PDFaid.Com
#1 Pdf Solutions
We Have Never Been Schreber
Paranoia, Medieval and Modern
erin labbie and michael uebel
In place of Lancelot, we have Judge Schreber.—Michel Foucault
It is a rhetorical topos to note that Daniel Paul Schreber is the most
frequently quoted psychiatric patient in the history of mental health.∞ The
remarkable fame of Schreber’s autobiographical book, Denkwürdigkeiten
eines Nervenkranken (1903; Memoirs of My Nervous Illness),≤ rests upon its
status as an extraordinarily rich narration of the prototypical form of
madness, psychosis. From the time of his death in 1911 in a state asylum—
Schreber had spent about half of the last twenty-seven years of his life in
mental institutions—he became recognized as the iconic madman, with
his Memoirs shaping psychoanalytic conceptions, first articulated around
deformations of desire in the only case study Freud wrote concerning a
psychotic patient, his famous ‘‘Psychoanalytic Notes upon an Autobiographical Account of a Case of Paranoia (Dementia Paranoides)’’ of 1911.≥
Elias Canetti’s estimation of the Memoirs as ‘‘the most important document in psychiatric literature,’’ whose author is thus the most influential
patient in the history of psychiatry, is perfectly justified, given the enduring iconic status of Schreber’s self-described symptoms in the history of
descriptive psychiatry.∂ As a textbook for how to read lapidary psychosis,
and, as we will suggest, how to interpret religious, scientific, and poetic
relays from the medieval to the modern (and back again and forward to
the contemporary), the Memoirs have achieved precisely the status that
Schreber believed they would.
the legitimacy of schreber
One of our principal interests in this essay is to highlight the special and
extreme sensitivity of the psychotic to his cultural environment, to history,
and to future possibility. The psychotic’s multiple and complex relation to
present, past, and future is for us a register of how psychosis rebuilds the
world, where the delusional system amounts finally to a quasi-heroic
‘‘reconstruction after the catastrophe.’’∑ In a key passage in Discipline and
Punish, Foucault marks the transition from the medieval to the modern
disciplinary-scientific society:
And if from the early Middle Ages to the present day the ‘‘adventure’’ is an
account of individuality, the passage from the epic to the novel, from the noble
deed to the secret singularity, from long exiles to the internal search for childhood, from combats to phantasies, it is also inscribed in the formation of a
disciplinary society. The adventure of our childhood no longer finds expression in
‘‘le bon petit Henri,’’ but in the misfortunes of ‘‘little Hans.’’ The Romance of the
Rose is written today by Mary Barnes; in place of Lancelot, we have Judge
Schreber.∏
Citing two famous case studies by Freud concerning phobic little Hans and
paranoid Schreber, and another text by a schizophrenic artist,π Foucault
suggests that the maturation of the disciplinary society is reflected in
transitions marked by iconographic heroic and creative ideals. These ideals
have altered from a perception offered by medieval treatments of them to
their modern diagnosable counterparts. Although, in this passage, Foucault
finds the presence of these pasts in the dominant cultural schema of a
disciplinary modernity, the pasts are also overtaken by their negative and
disenfranchised counterparts as dramatized in the shift, for instance, from
Lancelot to Schreber. This shift from the fantasized heroic knight to the
paranoiac signals a telling transition in the construction of the past itself. In
this scene of cultural history, the mythologies that govern the perception of
the medieval past as ideal, by which a certain nostalgia for misperceived
simplicity or innocence is derived and performed, are in fact offered and
created by the modern moment that distinguishes itself from the past.
Thus, given the replacement of medieval heroism by private fantasies
generated in the context of new technologies of power and knowledge
(e.g., the judicial system and the then new science of psychoanalysis), it is
128
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
not surprising that Schreber, having imagined a world-historical catastrophe, undertook to legitimate his own solitary mission as redeemer of
mankind, a kind of crusader fighting on God’s side and ‘‘a champion’’ for
the German people.∫ Certain that the world around him had been subject
to plagues (‘‘holy diseases’’) and that he was surrounded by only reanimated corpses (‘‘fleeting-improvised-men’’),Ω Schreber inserts himself into
a medieval history of ‘‘holy times,’’ refusing to dismiss visionary experiences, such as his own communications with souls and God through
‘‘rays,’’ as fabulous inventions:
To avoid going back as far as biblical events, I consider it very likely that in the
cases of the Maid of Orleans, of the Crusaders in search of the Holy Lance at
Antioch, or of the Emperor Constantine’s well-known vision in hoc signo vinces
which was decisive for the victory of Christianity: that in all these cases a transitory communication with rays was established, or there was transitory divine
inspiration. The same may also be assumed in some cases of stigmatization of
virgins; the legends and poetry of all peoples literally swarm with the activities of
ghosts, elves, goblins, etc., and it seems to me nonsensical to assume that in all of
them one is dealing simply with deliberate inventions of human imagination
without any foundation in real fact.∞≠
Schreber’s certainty about spirituality’s deep roots in divine communication necessitates a return to the mixture of heroic strength and innocence
that Foucault characterizes as departure points for modernity. Judge
Schreber, as modern Lancelot, did the precise opposite of what Hans
Blumenberg considered characteristic of modern culture, that is, to fill
traditional spiritual forms with a modern secular content. He conveyed to
the modern Weltanschauung (worldview) a traditional religious content,
one remarkably consistent with medieval aesthetic theory and practice as
realized, for instance, in the mystical aims of Gothic architecture. The
Gothic cathedral, such as that of St.-Denis, embodied a Neoplatonic vision, based upon analogies between Dionysian light-ray metaphysics and
Gothic luminosity.∞∞ Within Schreber’s Gothic vision, the rays, or souls, by
which he felt himself connected to the divine, were ‘‘proof of God’s miraculous creative power which is directed to earth.’’ His supporting evidence
reflects the intimacy common to the mystic: ‘‘the fact that the sun has for
years spoken with me in human words and thereby reveals herself as a
living being or as the organ of a still higher being behind her.’’∞≤
We Have Never Been Schreber 129
Despite his identification with forms of medieval heroism, Schreber’s
will to power, what Freud saw as his megalomania, was never remotely as
strong as his will to truth.∞≥ Schreber was more mystic than knight. ‘‘I
lived,’’ Schreber writes, ‘‘in the belief—and it is still my conviction that this
is the truth—that I had to solve one of the most intricate problems ever set
for man and that I had to fight a sacred battle for the greatest good of
mankind.’’∞∂ Certain that truth, as communicated to human beings from
the divine, was being interrupted and perverted and that his own will was
subject to the influence of others (a condition he called ‘‘soul murder’’),
Schreber attempted to create his own private world shaped and unshaped
by metaphysical truths and supernatural events that he deemed resistant
to human language and beyond understanding.∞∑ To preserve the world as
sacral became Schreber’s preeminent concern, and his chief obstacles to
this were condensed in the figure of his first psychiatrist, the chair of
psychiatry at Leipzig University, Dr. Paul Emil Flechsig, in whose Irrenklinik (mental hospital) Schreber voluntarily placed himself on two different occasions following mental breakdowns. Schreber’s new place at the
margins of the social order, his ‘‘disappearance’’ from the center where he
had held one of the higher positions in the German court system with the
title of Senatspräsident, or presiding judge, of the Supreme Court of Appeals, signified for him that he had been replaced: ‘‘I further thought it
possible that news had spread that in the modern world something in the
nature of a wizard had suddenly appeared in the person of Professor
Flechsig and that I myself, after all a person known in wider circles, had
suddenly disappeared; this had spread terror and fear amongst the people,
destroying the bases of religion and causing general nervousness and
immorality. In its train devastating epidemics had broken upon mankind.’’∞∏ In Freud’s reading of Schreber, emphasis was placed on the persecution complex in which Schreber’s physician was understood as God/
Father. Schreber’s paranoid system was naturally assumed to rest on universal, Oedipal tension∞π; yet this interpretation, which takes the religious
dimension of his paranoid system as a secondary rather than primary
aspect of its construction,∞∫ does not adequately account for belief in a
wizard demolishing the foundations of religion and thereby triggering
mental disorder and corruption.
Seelenmord, the murder of souls, was Schreber’s strongest term for
describing the catastrophes affecting him and his world. Schreber did not
130
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
invent the term—he might have picked it up from any number of sources,
including the playwrights Henrik Ibsen (John Gabriel Borkman, 1896) and
August Strindberg (discussing Ibsen’s Rosmersholm in 1887), Ellen Key’s
international best seller The Century of the Child (1900), or another popular book by Anselm von Feuerbach, a well-known German judge, whose
volume of 1832 on the Kaspar Hauser case was likely known to Schreber.∞Ω
He did, however, introduce the term into the psychiatric literature, defining it as a kind of demonic bond with one person absorbing the life of
another, wherein the victim’s identity is forfeited in such a way that
he is unable to reason about what has happened. In the most basic sense,
soul murder is a crime, a violation of selfhood that may, as in the case
of Schreber, cross multiple existential areas, including the sexual (his famous ‘‘unmanning’’), the spiritual and moral, and the political, including
the racial.≤≠
Dr. Paul Flechsig, soul murderer, was appointed außerordentlicher Professor (also known as Extraordinarius, or a university professor not holding
his own chair) of psychiatry and was promised to be made head of the
psychiatric hospital to be opened at Leipzig University. The Irrenklinik was
opened in 1882, and it included a brain-anatomical laboratory specially
designed by him. In 1884, with the psychiatry chair having been vacant
since Johann Christian August Heinroth’s death in 1843, Flechsig was
appointed chair, or ordentlicher Professor (also known as Ordinarius).
Heinroth, a Psychiker, worked in the tradition of soul psychiatrists, a
humanistic tradition dominating the German psychiatric scene at the
beginning of the nineteenth century. Flechsig’s inaugural speech, in clear
opposition to his predecessor, was entitled ‘‘On the Physical Basis of
Mental Diseases,’’≤∞ establishing his position as Somatiker and supporter of
a scientific paradigm given the title Hirnmythologie (‘‘brain mythology’’)
by the neuropathologist Franz Nissl (1860–1919).≤≤
Zvi Lothane has emphasized the extent to which brain mythology is an
ideology and not a methodology. Anchored in philosophical reductionism, it views the mind as caused by the brain, rather than the mind acting
in the brain, at the same time that it ignores the reality of the tertium quid,
or the person.≤≥ There is thus a sense in which brain mythology was itself
a paranoid system, operating through depersonalization and with a sense
of absolute certainty that the realities of the mind are to be replaced with
the realities of the physical body. The replacement of Heinroth by Flechsig
We Have Never Been Schreber 131
as chair of psychiatry at Leipzig University marked a transition, as Flechsig
announced in his inaugural lecture, from the ‘‘mistaken doctrine’’ of mental disorders understood as guilt- and sin-based to an understanding of
mental disorders as information- and experiment-based.≤∂ That is, a
‘‘chasm . . . gaped’’ between him and Heinroth, one ‘‘no less deep and wide
than the chasm between medieval medicine’’ and modern science.≤∑ Heinroth, the Somatiker claimed, had regressed psychiatry to medieval exorcism rather than advanced it forward into modern science. Flechsig, as a
neuroanatomist renowned for his work on the myelination of nerve fibers
and the localization of nervous diseases in the brain, ‘‘ushered in a new
epoch,’’ claimed Freud.≤∏ ‘‘In one fell swoop,’’ writes Lothane, ‘‘the tradition of the soul ended and the reign of the brain began.’’≤π Medieval
psychological understanding had been murdered, only to be psychotically
resurrected.
Schreber’s concept of ‘‘soul murder’’ should thus be seen as a dialectical
comment on Flechsig’s neurobiological paradigm. Schreber’s paranoid
alienation was historically inflected—‘‘I felt,’’ he writes, ‘‘like a marble
guest who had returned from times long past into a strange world.’’≤∫ This
strange world, however, was fast becoming one populated with subjects
who, just like Schreber, began to record their mental illnesses for an
enthusiastic modernist audience. Walter Benjamin expressed his joy at
finding a copy of the Memoirs in a used bookshop in Berne in 1918,≤Ω and
his shelf of ‘‘books by the mentally ill,’’ while formerly it might have been
‘‘disconcerting,’’ even ‘‘terrifying,’’ ‘‘nowadays . . . the situation is different.
Interest in the manifestations of madness is as universal as ever . . . more
fruitful and legitimate.’’≥≠ The publication of texts by mentally ill persons,
we suggest, is a marker of modernity. Both professionals and laypersons
noted their appearance with greater frequency by the turn of the twentieth
century. Examples include the Moscow physician Viktor Kandinsky, who
in 1880 described his psychopathological symptoms under the term ‘‘mental automatism’’ (telepathy, reading and broadcasting thoughts, and enforced speaking and motor movements).≥∞ Karl Rychlinski, of the Warsaw
psychiatric clinic, presented a case of hallucinatory psychosis.≥≤ One of the
most widely read and discussed accounts, in this case of mania, was that of
Auguste Forel, a retired professor of psychiatry in Zurich, published in
1901.≥≥ By 1906, such texts were available in popular German literary
periodicals.≥∂
132
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
In the texts of psychotics, then, a modernity was inaugurated in which
science, poetics, and religion attempt to legitimize themselves in relation
to the Middle Ages in two simultaneous and contradictory ways. On the
one hand, modernity contrasts itself to the barbarism (and innocence)
and presumed illegitimacy of the Middle Ages. In this case the idealization
of science asserts the supremacy of the technological progress of modernity over what is seen to be an archaic premodern scientific culture. On
the other hand, modernity is precisely dependent on the citation of the
past as a site of authority, therefore marking the Middle Ages as a legitimizing power in which a reliance on the theological foundations provided
by scholasticism provides a cultural grounding for potential knowledge. In
both of these contradictory approaches to the Middle Ages, the juxtapositions of science and religion are primary fields by which modernity justifies itself in relation to the past, and in both cases a relationship between
the present and the past takes the form of paranoia. Thus, we will argue,
the case of Judge Schreber is a complex embodiment of the medieval
within the modern.
scholastic schreber
Schreber’s Memoirs of My Nervous Illness, through a focus on language as a
primary element dictating the subject’s relationship to reality and to the
theological potential to explore the limits of knowledge, illustrates the
medieval foundations upholding the modernist crisis in representation, a
crisis that informs science, aesthetics, theology, and the field of psychoanalysis. Because paranoia is in part a linguistic disorder, it also calls into
question the very possibility of writing history. As Michel de Certeau
asserts, the writing of history has much to learn from the writing of the
psyche, and both history and psychoanalysis are informed by what is
considered to be a premodern sensibility.≥∑ Additionally, our concept of
the Middle Ages is dependent upon, and constructed by, a modernist
academic agenda.≥∏ The idealization of the past as a source for developing
nationalist identities led the modernist medievalists to couch their literary
criticism in scientific terms.≥π Schreber’s memoirs, then, perform a complex layering of the modern onto the medieval that illustrates a nonlinear
continuity between the Middle Ages and modernity. Indeed, the construction of the Middle Ages is grounded in what we call modernity.≥∫
We Have Never Been Schreber 133
The links between science and legitimacy have been addressed widely
in light of the ‘‘two cultures’’ debates and the idealization of a positivism
that is promised by scientific discourse. Fredric Jameson, in his foreword
to Jean-François Lyotard’s The Postmodern Condition, succinctly states,
‘‘ ‘Doing science’ involves its own kind of legitimation.’’≥Ω For Lyotard, this
indicates a particular legitimacy at stake in the legislature of scientific
discourse such that ‘‘the question of the legitimacy of science has been
indissociably linked to that of the legitimation of the legislator since the
time of Plato.’’∂≠ Science relies on the ‘‘game’’ of language; the narrative
structure of science calls for the observer to turn a scrutinizing gaze
toward the question of the legitimacy of language as a mediator.∂∞ In his
quest for truth and his desire to offer a contribution to scientific discourse,
Schreber’s memoirs narrate and document the multifarious dynamics at
stake in the experience of psychosis.
Offering his autobiography as a contribution to medieval scholastic
debates, Schreber participates in the dynamics of dialectical thinking.
Paranoia resembles the conventional dialectical process of thesis, antithesis, synthesis; however, there is no synthesis in the paranoiac field. Presenting as parallel the disciplines of science as an assertion of truth (thesis), poetics as an interrogation or negation of this positivist assertion
(antithesis), and religion as a promise for hope and an awareness of the
real (synthesis) allows an understanding of paranoia that explains why it is
one of the central questions at stake in psychoanalysis as well as in the
study of modernity.
1 Science (Thesis)
One of Schreber’s purposes in the writing of his Memoirs involves the
explicit desire to contribute to the discourse of science. Offering himself as
a case study—indeed, as a living corpse for the members of the scientific
establishment to examine—Schreber contributes to the formation of a
peculiarly legitimate form of knowledge at the limits of knowability.∂≤
Schreber claims that God is capable of relating only to corpses: ‘‘A fundamental misunderstanding obtained however, which has since run like a red
thread through my entire life. It is based upon the fact that, within the
Order of the World, God did not really understand the living human being and
had no need to understand him, because, according to the Order of the
World, He dealt only with corpses.’’∂≥ Needing to present himself as al134
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
ready dead, Schreber makes his body into an object of scrutiny. In Schreber’s view, the scientific and theological systems become elided such that
Flechsig is another god who can relate to him only through a ‘‘policy of
vacillation in which attempts to cure my nervous illness alternated with
efforts to annihilate me as a human being who, because of his everincreasing nervousness, had become a danger to God Himself.’’∂∂ As a
scribe recording his own ontotheological experiences and hallucinations,
Schreber seeks to attain the legitimacy that he associates with scientific
discourse and systematicity, and, despite his avowed agnosticism and
skepticism, he longs for the legitimacy that he also associates with God,
who has the power to recognize Schreber.
With Schreber as theoretical touchstone, the analysis of psychosis pervades the work of Jacques Lacan. Even before the completion of his 1932
doctoral thesis on paranoia, Lacan translated Freud’s paper ‘‘On Some
Neurotic Mechanisms in Jealousy, Paranoia and Homosexuality’’ and published ‘‘Structure des psychoses paranoïaques’’ (The structure of paranoid
psychosis) in 1931.∂∑ Although these early papers seek to distinguish between psychosis and the ‘‘normalcy’’ of neurosis, by the end of his career in
1975 Lacan would conclude that we are all paranoiacs and that personality
is premised on paranoia. The very structure of desire, dependent as it is on
the desire of the Other (the Che Vuoi?), is paranoid. As an ‘‘expert’’ in
paranoia, then, Lacan spends the third seminar (The Psychoses) reading
the case of Schreber in order to devise a line between psychosis and
neurosis.∂∏ Such a line is never in fact drawn, but in his effort to determine
the fragile and elusive difference between the two, Lacan diagnostically
marks the speech of the psychotic by way of its detachment from signification. Despite his alienation from the external world, the urges to participate in a social order and to be recognized by God lead Schreber to assert
his voice in the form of idealized scientific discourse. The fantasmatic
desire to be recognized compensates for the impossibility that the solipsistic paranoid will ever be able to participate in a social community. Scientific discourse, then, accommodates, while it symptomatically displays,
Schreber’s desire for legitimation.
Yet, in Lacan’s terms, science is itself akin to psychosis; science exceeds
the lines of the discursive structures at stake in ideological systems. In a
discussion of these fragile boundaries in Television, Lacan suggests that the
discourse of science is akin to that of the hysteric.∂π The discourse of the
We Have Never Been Schreber 135
hysteric, like that articulated by Schreber, replaces the empty subject with
the illusion of mastery and believes that jouissance is the truth of the
product of knowledge. The discourse of science appeals to the hyperbolic
vigilance that seeks to record its own desire.∂∫ Schreber’s appeal to the
fetishized discourse of science foregrounds the very status of psychoanalysis as a pseudoscience. Based, as it is, on linguistic narrative, the
‘‘talking cure’’ becomes the discursive product that, by calling into question the ability to narrate perceptual reality, enables an articulation of the
subject in the field of history.
Schreber’s recognition of the imbrication of science and what will be
called juridical discourse is tied to his professional status. A powerful
figure in the Senatspräsident of the Supreme Court, yet the youngest to
take this position among other ‘‘legitimate’’ patriarchs, his precarious relationship to the law in fact appears to catalyze his second psychotic break.∂Ω
Discussing the legitimacy of Schreber and his exclusion from the law, Janet
Lucas speculates that ‘‘there is no legitimate place for him in the Law.’’∑≠ This
exclusion is, according to Lucas, due to the split between the Name-of-theFather and Schreber’s system of knowledge. Schreber does not have access
to the signifier of the Name-of-the-Father because his psychic system of
replacement has created wholeness where there is lack. Schreber therefore
imagines that he is in a constant state of illegitimacy (and that this is true
despite his juridical success). Concluding that this illegitimacy is the
‘‘trigger’’ to his psychosis, Lucas then agrees with many scholars who
perceive the oppression of ideology at play in Schreber’s participation in
the disciplinary structure of the hegemonic system that, prior to his incarceration, he helped to organize and lead.∑∞ As a means of addressing and
approaching a form of truth, Schreber’s desire to participate in scientific
discourse (itself a form of replacement for a lack in language) reflects the
illegitimacy of the law itself by way of the foreclosure of the Father. Since
there is a protective barrier against the concept and the signifier of the
Father, there is no access to the Law of the Father in its proper form; the
Name and the Law of the Father are absent from the first then, and this is
reflected by Lacan’s ‘‘absent’’ seminar on the Name-of-the-Father.∑≤
In the analytic scene, however, joining science is structurally prohibited. In Serge Leclaire’s view of psychoanalysis as a discipline that is utterly
dependent on the letter, the signifier is materialized in its very abstraction.
136
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
This paradoxical view of language is most evident in the linguistic field of
the paranoid schizophrenic: ‘‘The materiality of the letter manipulated by
the schizophrenic seems to be in fact doubly abstracted from any corporeal reference, so that it is nothing more, finally, than the shadow of a
letter, that is, a materiality that refers to nothing other than the materiality
of any and all letters.’’∑≥ The fantasy of a pure scientific discourse becomes
impossible for the paranoiac to achieve because scientific narrative is
bound to the poetic qualities of language.
Before allowing the shadowy signifier to take us into a discussion of
poetics, we will address the element of the visual as a scene of pseudoscientific proof. In the performance of his subjectivity and the desire to seduce
God (as well as his other Father figures including but not limited to
Flechsig and Guido Weber∑∂), and in his concomitant desire to ward off the
voices that barrage him with persecutory messages, Schreber engages in
what he calls picturing. Seeking a means of maintaining a self-presentation
that confirms his imago, Schreber relies on picturing as a visual contribution to the scientific discourse he attempts to achieve with his text. Picturing is crucial in Schreber’s production of the proof of his experience.
Through it, he presents himself as evidence offered up as a sacrifice for the
examination of the scrutinizing eyes of God, Flechsig, the rays, and the
multiple father figures that persecute him.
Imagining, or believing, that he is being constantly watched, Schreber
performs for the gaze of the Other. He dresses up as a woman in order to
make himself available to God’s advances, and in his transvestism he
makes his external appearance conform to his internal image of himself.
Picturing constitutes one of the chief strategies that Schreber devises in
order to ward off the constant influx of voices and rays. In his own words,
‘‘ ‘Picturing’ in this sense may therefore be called a reversed miracle. In the
same way as rays throw on to my nerves pictures they would like to see
especially in dreams, I in turn produce pictures for the rays which I want
them to see.’’∑∑ Despite his awareness of its illusory nature, Schreber relies
on picturing as a defense mechanism by which he tests his reality.∑∏ The
endurance of Schreber’s picturing is a testimony to its efficacy as well. At
the end of treatment, his picturing remains a stable defense mechanism
that allows him to negotiate the social order of the world.
The externalized or projected visibility of Schreber’s internal psyche
calls attention to the public character of paranoia. In addition to its
We Have Never Been Schreber 137
obvious connections to the rise in technological advancements that accompany modernity, the function of picturing participates in the scopic
drive toward knowledge and truth that was dominant during the Enlightenment.∑π Picturing also places Schreber within the present moment.
Considering the location of knowledge within a historical moment, JeanClaude Milner understands Alexandre Koyré’s thesis regarding the intersection of modernity and mysticism to indicate that ‘‘science means only
modern science.’’∑∫ If this is the case, then by considering his own discourse to be scientific, Schreber marks his experience as immanent presence
and as an expansion of the horizon of the present.
Schreber’s concern with the self as a subject who exists in history is
evident in his drive to record his experiences. Working toward an understanding of the centrality of the trace as a means of understanding the
subject, the historian comes to resemble the psychoanalyst. Indeed, the
very process of narrating history is at the core of the discourse of psychoanalysis, and the process of interpretation leads the subject to imagine the
Other as an inquisitive audience. Narration, like desire, is then caught
within the discourse of the desire of the Other, and the process of constructing the self as present is fraught with the fantasy of the Other’s
desire. The precise narration of history, then, as a drive toward the construction of a properly scientific record of experience, is also paranoid. In
Bruno Latour’s characterization of history we are able to perceive the
function of this discursive paranoia as it translates to personal and political
matters:
Historians reconstitute the past, detail by detail, all the more carefully inasmuch
as it has been swallowed up for ever. But are we as far removed from our past as we
want to think we are? No, because modern temporality does not have much effect
on the passage of time. The past remains, therefore, and even returns. Now this
resurgence is incomprehensible to the moderns. Thus they treat it as the return of
the repressed. They view it as an archaism. ‘‘If we aren’t careful,’’ they think, ‘‘we’re
going to return to the past; we’re going to fall back into the Dark Ages.’’ Historical
reconstitution and archaism are two symptoms of the moderns’ incapacity to
eliminate what they nevertheless have to eliminate in order to retain the impression that time passes.∑Ω
The repetition and return of the image of the Middle Ages as a promise or
a threat further reinforces the power dynamic at the heart of the narrative
138
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
process as it relates to the desire of the Other. The very treatment of the
past as the eruption of the repressed intensifies the desire to further
repress, revealing, symptomatically, the desire to perceive time as a force of
progression. The paranoid tendency to construct walls between the present and the past is manifested, in part, through the desire for science and
reason in the form of historical documentation.
As a model of this form of the historical play between modernity and
the Middle Ages, Schreber’s self-documentation appeals to history as a
rational expression that will save him from a lapse into the unreason
associated with the Middle Ages. Attempting to repress that which does
not fit into a logical system or order, Schreber asserts a hyperrationality
that is affiliated with modernity and relies on the logic of scholasticism.
Rationality must be conceived of in a historicized context;∏≠ notably, this is
not the same as saying that rationality must be contextualized historically.
Latour and Schreber both demonstrate the impossibility of epochal distinctions as temporality shifts, eliding that which is called medieval and
that which is called modernity.
In accord with a sympathetic reading of the paranoiac, many critics
have suggested that Schreber’s deity is the Judeo-Christian God. As such
He is also the contingent God of modernity and classical antiquity that
Niklas Luhmann describes in his analysis of Aristotelian observation. This
God induces and produces paranoia. Everyone who believes in God,
Luhmann writes, ‘‘knows that he is being observed, not only in violation of
his private space, that is, with data security, but also in everything that
surrounds and motivates him. God knows now, even before now, when we
are in error—and leave it be! Therefore, He also knows the ‘futura contingentia.’ ’’∏∞ Thomas Aquinas’s concept of contingency (which is central
to Luhmann’s argument regarding observation) signifies the precise manner in which the paranoid subject relates to and conjures the Other.
Scholasticism is thus historically bound to a concept of paranoia.
Schreber’s paranoid relationship with God is indeed secured by technological Otherness to the extent that ‘‘private space’’ is not at all private.
In the cosmology of the paranoiac, there is no such thing as private
space.∏≤ Similarly, we are introduced to a perspective of ourselves as the
Other when we locate our own position as observer in the scene of
Schreber’s self-display. As his readers, we stand in for the gods for whom
he dresses his language; we are the Others he is seducing—Schrebers are
We Have Never Been Schreber 139
we. Since God is purely reasonable, He is in control of His passions.∏≥
Therefore, the question of rationality in regard to the perception of the
impossible knowledge of God shifts to one of our potential to observe
God. Luhmann characterizes this dynamic by recalling the very problem
at stake in both premodern and postmodern understandings of the unknown: ‘‘In engaging in the same task of observing the observation of
God, theologians come dangerously close to the devil and must therefore
maintain their distance. This occurs within the values of the nobility by
distinguishing between agitation and humility; through a sense of social
standing, or in folk variants through a demonization of the devil—in short,
through an observation of the observer of the observation of God.’’∏∂ The
meta-level upon which the subject is observed situates the paranoid subject as one who logically and rationally offers himself to the view of the
Other. In this manner, the subject who is paranoid is in fact ahead of the
game. He is not within the scene of social order, yet he leads the drive of
the social sphere to form a community. As the legal norms of the Enlightenment privileged the spoken over the written, the testimony of the illiterate was equated with that of the literate, thus placing the element of
picturing within the statist view of legal testimony.∏∑
Schreber’s picturing, however, evinces a complex scientific gaze that
accounts for both visually ‘‘proven’’ empiricism and linguistically driven
narrative. In his reading of Rembrandt’s painting The Anatomy Lesson
(1630), Francis Barker demonstrates that the lines of the gaze are focused
on the text, not on the body at stake in the image. The scientific gaze is
blind to what becomes the invisible body, and it aims its trajectory instead
at the textualization of evidence: ‘‘thus reduced, the body has ceased to
mean in any but residual ways, sinking away from vision into the past.’’∏∏
The scientific gaze that becomes the textualized gaze is situated on a
threshold of visibility and a horizon of perception. It refers back to the
practice of scholastic medieval anatomy and simultaneously ‘‘points forward to the modern aversionary textualization of the flesh.’’∏π In this manner, the scientific gaze gives way to the textual gaze of poetics. As Friedrich
Kittler states, ‘‘Only when sciences localize madness in ‘language itself ’
does its literary simulation become possible and important.’’∏∫ Or, in
Lacan’s view, ‘‘science is a collusion with hyperreality’’ and as such is
overtaken by poetics.∏Ω
140
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
2 Poetics (Antithesis)
According to Lacan, Schreber has no claim to being a poet.π≠ Yet, like
Lacan’s own expression of neologism, euphemism, and metaphor, and like
Freud’s literary case studies, Schreber’s Memoirs consistently expresses a
drive toward poetics and a recourse to metaphor and metonymy. From the
outset of his autobiography, Schreber confesses that his discursive register
is a poetic one:
To make myself at least somewhat comprehensible I shall have to speak much in
images and similes, which may at times perhaps be only approximately correct; for
the only way a human being can make supernatural matters, which in their
essence must always remain incomprehensible, understandable to a certain degree is by comparing them with known faces of human experience. Where intellectual understanding ends, the domain of belief begins; man must reconcile
himself to the fact that things exist which are true although he cannot understand
them.π∞
The limits of knowledge find their expression in the poetic register. Gesturing toward the shift from proof to belief, poetics are asserted as a
counter to scientific discourse.
For Julia Kristeva, this poetic dilemma is linked precisely to the nominalist function in which language constructs reality: ‘‘the subject of poetic
language continually but never definitively assumes the thetic function of
naming, establishing meaning and signification, which the paternal function represents within reproductive relation. Son permanently at war with
father, not in order to take his place, nor even to endure it, erased from
reality, as a symbolic, divine menace and salvation in the manner of
Senatspräsident Schreber.’’π≤ The generational conflict at stake in the historical recording of the poetic experience links Schreber’s internal tragedy
to a transcendent reality. Through poetics, he is able to produce that
which he cannot physically produce in life. And, though, like the demonically possessed early modern painter Christof Haizmann, Schreber risks
losing his soul, he maintains it through the poetic register which conquers
discourse itself.π≥ As Kittler neatly summarizes it, ‘‘All of Freud’s case
histories demonstrate that the romanticism of the soul has yielded to a
materialism of written signs.’’π∂ Poetics remain central to the move toward
the necessary technological inquiry of the influencing machines that domWe Have Never Been Schreber 141
inate the embodiment of schizophrenia. Avital Ronell identifies Lyotard’s
recourse to poetics: ‘‘The electric flow installs the paradigm for a language
opposed to a signifier that strangles and overcodes the flows and in which
no flow is privileged, ‘which remains indifferent to its substance or support, inasmuch as the latter is an amorphous continuum.’ The electric flow
serves to illustrate ‘the realization of such a flow that is indeterminate as
such.’ In this regard, consider also Lyotard’s generalized critique of the
signifier in which the signifier’s coded gaps are short-circuited by the
‘figural.’ ’’π∑ The poetic determination of language as an organizing force
within the psyche then also determines the somatic display. The letter
indeed becomes materialized.
Even Schreber’s grammatical structure is poetic, depending on emotion
to inflect and direct his logic. As Freud defines paranoia in his case study
of Schreber, the paranoid turns the statement ‘‘I love him’’ into ‘‘He hates
me.’’ By way of transition and projection, the paranoiac defies his own
desire to claim, ‘‘I do not love him—I hate him, because he persecutes
me.’’π∏ Freud thus institutes a grammatical structure of emotion that is
supported by a concern regarding poetics. Paralleling this connection
between language and feeling is the grammatical structure of melancholy.
According to Kristeva, the malady is emphasized linguistically by way of
introjection: ‘‘ ‘I love that object,’ is what that person seems to say about
the lost object, ‘but even more so I hate it; because I love it, and in order
not to lose it, I imbed it in myself; but because I hate it, that other within
myself is a bad self, I am bad, I am nonexistent, I shall kill myself.’ ’’ππ
Kristeva’s explication of melancholy precisely describes Schreber’s relationship to God and to the poetic expression of the self. As a scholarly
malady, poetics is precisely linked to melancholy.π∫ On the one hand,
Schreber wants to be able to claim that God persecutes him, and, on the
other hand, he wants to take control of this persecution so that he punishes himself for his ill will toward his oppressor. Ultimately, we find
ourselves in a scene of cynicism. This dynamic also characterizes and is
characterized by modernity’s relationship to the Middle Ages. We view the
past only with the eyes of a paranoiac.
We cannot find a way out of the paranoid system, because language
itself is founded on the structure of lack and alienation. François Roustang
calls attention to this primacy of paranoia within language when he declares, ‘‘Language is at the center because it must confront that which is its
142 Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
enemy, that which threatens to dissolve it, and because it owes its salvation
solely to the fact that it becomes the servant of what is foreign to it.’’πΩ
Psychosis is entrenched within language and the gaps in signification that
are rendered when the subject speaks.
The fantasmatic structure of language as a mediator renders it a replacement or supplement for the ideal form.∫≠ In Friedrich Nietzsche’s
terms, this means that we exist in a world of illusion. Further, we must give
ourselves over to the illusion in order to pretend as though reality is
sedimented through perception. In this way, we delude ourselves, and we
doubly delude ourselves when we necessarily forget that we have in fact
deluded ourselves. Nietzsche articulates this process in ‘‘Truth and Lies in
a Nonmoral Sense,’’ where we find that language is always already metaphorical and metonymical.∫∞
In the expression of his desire to contribute to the scholastic debates
known as the quarrel of the universals, Schreber articulates the wish to be
a poet. Self-conscious of his own play with language and his discursive
construction of his reality, he idealizes the role of the poet as one who
is able to convey significance by way of metaphor and metonymy, even
while offering a unique fusion of expression and meaning. The automatic
elimination of nonsense rendering signification everywhere and nowhere,
evident in Schreber’s statement that ‘‘all nonsense cancels itself out,’’ calls
into question the potential for meaning in the perceptual reality of the
paranoiac.
Schreber’s search for a Grundsprache, a basic language or a root language, is manifested in a focus on the sounds and voices of the ‘‘miraculously created birds’’ he imagines. Organic in nature, Schreber does not
know the ‘‘mechanical’’ language of the birds, but he nonetheless understands their utterances despite their emptiness. Knowing their significance
by rote or parroting, Schreber is able to communicate with them. Indeed,
he claims that the birds themselves do not know the sense of their song.
Rather, they have a ‘‘natural sensitivity for the similarity of sounds.’’∫≤ Schreber records:
It has already been said that the sounds need not be completely identical; a
similarity suffices, as in any case the birds do not understand the sense of the
words; therefore it matters little to them—in order to give some examples–
whether one speaks of
We Have Never Been Schreber 143
‘‘Santiago’’ or ‘‘Cathargo’’
‘‘Chinesentum’’ or ‘‘Jesum Christum’’
‘‘Abendroth’’ or ‘‘Athemnoth’’
‘‘Ariman’’ or ‘‘Ackermann’’
‘‘Briefbeschwerer’’ or ‘‘Herr prufer schwört,’’ etc., etc.∫≥
Taking the birds as a challenge to create unity of sound, Schreber seeks to
fulfill the order toward homogeneity that he imagines to derive from God.
The precise significance of the sounds is unimportant given the extreme
auditory identification that enables Schreber and the birds to understand
each other. Neither his language nor theirs requires translation. Instead,
the full significance of the utterances rests in the lack of a need for
translation. In fact, this communication with the birds then represents a
scene in which transference has the potential to succeed in a case of
psychosis.
By displacing his own sense of the difference between words that sound
the same but have different meaning, Schreber unites language, making it
a system based on sameness and identification rather than on difference.
He becomes one with all he hears. This unity, however, is achieved only by
dispossessing himself of his own knowledge and awareness that the words
that sound similar and therefore seem to have similar signification, such as
‘‘Santiago’’ and ‘‘Cathargo,’’ nonetheless remain separate and different. In a
desperate attempt to preserve and prove his rationality, Schreber must
sacrifice his sense of linguistic logic in order to identify with God and
achieve mystical unity.
At the limits of understanding, Schreber offers a mystical unity that
promises a union between belief and proof. His concept of eternity as that
which cannot be precisely proven but which must be taken on faith is a
primary example of that which must be believed yet not understood. In his
mystical experience of these transrational moments, Schreber seeks to
articulate that which exceeds the capacity of language and human understanding. If understanding is perfectly bound to language, then we are stuck
in the realm of paranoia by way of nominalism. Language determines the
way in which we know the world, and so we enter a constructionist
mentality. Schreber’s desire to articulate the inarticulable is in fact an
indication of his poetic drives, even as he seeks to systematize his experience. In the course of his discursive strategy to seduce God and to defend
144
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
himself against the multitude of persecutory voices he hears, Schreber also
claims a particularly complex relationship with language. He relies heavily
on metaphor and metonymy in his quest to communicate his personal
Weltanschauung as he determines the Order of the World. Poetics take over
the role of epistemological activity in this scenario.
Schreber’s desire to understand the order of the world and the unknowable elements of the cosmos find limits similar to those located within the
poetic. When he says that ‘‘an intimate relation exists between God and
the starry sky,’’ he notes that ‘‘such things are also known to our poets ‘Far
above the starry sky, surely dwells a kindly father,’ etc.’’∫∂ Schreber’s frequent citations of poets, including this passage by Johann Wolfgang von
Goethe and other references to Tannhäuser and Richard Wagner, situate
his poetic knowledge as a discursive register of authority that is akin to,
and the inverse of, the scientific register he emulates. Unlike science,
which cannot prove the existence of eternity, poetry has the potential to
assert the immanence of being and the presence of souls across time.∫∑
3 Religion (Synthesis)
As he states in his open letter to Professor Flechsig of March 1903,
Schreber’s explicit goal in the writing of his autobiography is ‘‘solely to
further knowledge of truth in a vital field, that of religion.’’∫∏ Scholasticism
contributed to philosophical theology what Louis Dupré characterizes as
‘‘a science of God based exclusively on rational arguments.’’∫π Seeking the
proof of God’s existence and his availability to human interaction, Schreber hopes to posit a scholastic theory. He claims that his examples of
God’s knowledge ‘‘illustrate exactly the way in which for centuries scholastic philosophy of the Middle Ages treated predestination and related
questions.’’∫∫ Speculating about God’s potential to know the future and to
‘‘determine the number which is to win in the lottery,’’∫Ω Schreber imagines
that God in fact is the tuché, the encounter with the real. However, by way
of his certainty and his omniscience, God precisely takes chance out of the
tuché and inserts a constant state of the fantasy that marks the real.Ω≠ The
very impossibility of properly knowing God insures that this fantasy is in
fact a brush with the real. Schreber articulates God’s knowledge in light of
scholastic concerns. Moving from a concern with human life to flies in the
spider’s web to the numbers in the lottery to a political assertion of global
conflict, the particularities and the generalities of God’s omniscience renWe Have Never Been Schreber 145
der moot any concern with causality, as God dominates cause itself. Causality is premised on fragmentation and schizophrenia. As Étienne Gilson
explains, ‘‘That we may have causality in the strict sense of the term means
that we must have two beings and that something of the being of the cause
passes into the being of that which undergoes the effect;’’ thus ‘‘being is
the ultimate root of causality.’’Ω∞
Not content with a split between the soul and the body, and resisting
the alliances with Cartesian vigilance and the state of constant thinking
that barrages his mind, Schreber imagines that his union with God will
occur by way of copulation. The proof of God’s existence, then, will be
materialized in the form of the maternal Schreber’s children. In this way,
Schreber inverts not only the trajectory of desire (shifting an expression of
love into a threat of persecution), but also the dynamic by which we have
come to know the power of the phallic mother. His picturing is precisely
linked to his need to become the mother of the new world order and, as
such, binds him to representation. Lacan reflects on this connection when
he wonders, ‘‘Could we not say that desire itself is an effect of representation, of the bringing-to-presence, and that insofar as desire is always desire
for something (something that would be God or a representation thereof ), it is bound up with the teleological thought of meaning?’’Ω≤ The
neurotic block preventing representation becomes the psychotic flow in
which representation abounds by way of Schreber’s desire to disseminate
his experience through the Memoirs.
This scene of representation calls attention to the relationship between
belief and proof. As David Tracy points out, ‘‘God, religiously construed, is
not primarily the problem of consciousness but the question of the unconscious. Mystics (and Jacques Lacan) know this.’’Ω≥ It is precisely the gap
between the signifier and the signified that establishes the foundation on
which the paranoiac builds his airy castle. This is one of the paradoxical
elements of paranoia: heterogeneity fails the subject by reminding him of
the difference between the signifier and the signified; yet homogeneity
fails the subject by eliding difference and denying crucial subjective distinctions among words, things, objects, and beings. If both realism and
nominalism are paranoid—if, in fact, the quarrel of the universals is paranoid—how do we know God?Ω∂ Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari perceive
an aporetic structure of schizophrenia such that the assertion and its
simultaneous negation, ‘‘I am God I am not God, I am God I am Man,’’ do
146 Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
not synthesize but remain parallel, ambivalent statements and beliefs. For
them, this failure to synthesize is the reason that ‘‘the schizophrenic God
has so little to do with the God of religion.’’Ω∑ Alon Kantor reframes this
question when, in ‘‘Ethics and Simulacrum,’’ he asks, ‘‘Can God be ‘known’
otherwise than in Schreber’s way?’’Ω∏ Schreber synthesizes poetics and
science to imitate Meister Eckhart’s paradoxical prayer, ‘‘I pray to God to
save me from God.’’Ωπ
Schreber achieves his goal of contributing to the fields of scholasticism,
religious knowledge, and scientific knowledge by illustrating that in the
field of psychosis the distinctions between realism and nominalism collapse. The articulation of the fantasized relationship between the word
and the thing itself, in which the solipsistic reality of the speaking subject
perceives a unity of internal thought and external reality, suggests a dialectical synthesis of the nominalist and the realist epistemic systems. In this
manner, Schreber’s cosmology gestures toward a fantasmatic state of
omniscience akin to that epistemic system projected onto, or imagined
in, God. As such, his mystical approach to knowledge and language
fuses belief and proof, religion and science, and realism and nominalism in a manner that indeed contributes a unique theological imaginary
to the scholastic debates and to psychiatry—the so-called science of
the soul.Ω∫
we (synthesis ii)
We are all budding paranoids.—François Roustang
With schizoids anything is possible.—Peter Sloterdijk
The psychotic appears as the antithesis—or is it antidote?—to the Enlightenment. ‘‘Enlightenment,’’ writes Sloterdijk, ‘‘means to affirm all antischizophrenic movements.’’ΩΩ The same can be said for modernity and its
inveterate practice of marking off the lines between self and not-self, sane
and insane, treatable and untreatable. Schreber was a kind of lightning rod
for the modern psychiatric power of defining madness as something containable within categories of affect, behavior, and thought, which are taken
to symbolize pathological difference. Schreber both saw himself in terms
of that psychiatric discourse, consulting, for example, the sixth edition of
Emil Kraepelin’s Lehrbuch der Psychiatrie in order to compare his halluciWe Have Never Been Schreber 147
nations with those described in the textbook, and saw himself as an
exception to such a ‘‘rationalistic and purely materialistic’’ way of describing what for him were certainly ‘‘supernatural’’ phenomena.∞≠≠ Indeed, it
was precisely by sifting through a psychiatric textbook, determining what
‘‘fit’’ and what did not, that Schreber unsettled the older metaphysical
dualism of sanity and insanity through the new empiricism. He experiments with the possibility of a supernatural subjectivity, offering his readers a sense of how it would be to live simultaneously at the very heights of
connectedness to the divine and at the very depths of social isolation and
psychic pain brought by malevolent others. In this sense, Schreber truly is
our modern Lancelot, split between radically different worlds that are only
superficially so.
The ‘‘legitimation crisis’’ that, according to Jürgen Habermas, represents political modernity and, according to Eric Santner, calls upon Schreber to negotiate a world that is worthy both of paranoia and more so of
trust and solidarity, radically alters the conditions in which something like
enlightenment may have any meaning at all.∞≠∞ The stage has been set for a
kind of schizoid ‘‘free-for-all’’ wherein strategies such as cynicism and
paranoia become appropriate for functioning in a morally ambiguous
world. Sloterdijk’s cynic behaves like Freud’s paranoiac:
By day, colonizer, at night, colonized; by occupation, valorizer and administered;
officially a cynical functionary, privately a sensitive soul; at the office a giver of
orders, ideologically a discussant; outwardly a follower of the reality principle,
inwardly a subject oriented toward pleasure; functionally an agent of capital,
intentionally a democrat; with respect to the system a functionary of reification,
with respect to the Lebenswelt (lifeworld), someone who achieves self-realization;
objectively a strategist of destruction, subjectively a pacifist; basically someone
who triggers catastrophes, in one’s own view, innocence personified.∞≠≤
A delusional system supports this ethical concoction; knowledge is fragmented, and the paranoiac, like the cynic, uses disavowal strategically, carving out a quasi-utopian space, even if it never objectively seems to be one.
Despite its sociocultural pervasiveness, a schizoid position is hard to maintain for the simple reason that it ultimately issues in the violence of depersonalization, self-destructing in the process, only to begin another cycle.∞≠≥
R. D. Laing once observed that, phenomenologically speaking, nothing
separates the scientist or physician, who turns persons into objects of
148
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
study, from the psychotic patient, since both engage in acts of intentional
depersonalization.∞≠∂ Laing was a powerful advocate for psychotic subjectivity, carefully placing it in the context of how, given untenable circumstances, a ‘‘rational’’ person might act. ‘‘Without exception,’’ Laing notes,
‘‘the experience and behavior that gets labeled schizophrenic is a special
strategy that a person invents in order to live in an unlivable situation.’’∞≠∑
Citing Schreber’s preoccupation with soul murder as an example of strategic self-murder in order to survive, Laing notes that all types of psychosis
share a formal feature, namely, ‘‘the denial of being, as a means of preserving being.’’∞≠∏ The strategy is essentially masochistic, though Laing does
not use that term, and is consistent with everyday neurotic and perverse
formations of subjectivity that convert passivity into activity in order to
achieve what the master theorist of masochism, Theodor Reik, neatly
summarized as ‘‘victory through defeat.’’∞≠π
This masochism has the power to temper somewhat the violence of
depersonalization. For the most part, Schreber’s violence is linguistic,
consisting in specific speech acts such as bellowing, hearing voices denouncing him as ‘‘Luder!’’ (filthy whore), or experiencing himself ‘‘represented’’ as a soul murderer just like Flechsig. Indeed, acts of being represented are most acutely felt by Schreber as attacks against his innermost
self; in short, his identity is up for grabs.∞≠∫ In an important footnote
elaborating upon the notion of representing, defined as ‘‘giving to a thing or
a person a semblance different from its real nature,’’ Schreber emphasizes
that the familiarity of souls and God with human beings is based only upon
the singularity of a momentary impression through nerve contact.∞≠Ω This
fleeting contact, owing to the interference of Flechsig’s ‘‘tested soul,’’ prevents an understanding of ‘‘living man as an organism.’’ Schreber then
reasons that even though one may be acted upon according to impressions,
or represented, such treatment ultimately amounts to a ‘‘self-deception
quite useless in practice’’ since ‘‘a human being naturally has in his actual
behavior, and particularly in the (human) language, the means of establishing his true nature against intended ‘representing.’ ’’∞∞≠
Schreber’s paranoia finds its own antidote in the symbolic realm where
the rift between signifier and signified can be healed. The trace of the rift
must, however, remain within the paranoid system; to close it forever
would be to take up the position of the neuroanatomist Flechsig, for whom
no gap can be admitted since the physiology of the brain or body is the preWe Have Never Been Schreber 149
eminent site where signifier and signified become indistinguishable. Schreber’s catalog of ‘‘miracles,’’ including the excruciating ‘‘chest-compression
miracle’’ and the miracle of the little men, or ‘‘little devils,’’ who assemble on
his head and pull his eyelids up and down, is to be understood then as that
which ‘‘represents’’ him as psychotic. Yet precisely because they represent
him, the miracles in effect protect him by demonstrating that there is a gap
between how he is made to appear and what he is.∞∞∞ To dismiss the whole
system of knowledge at work here as delusional would be to miss the
central, indeed the only, issue for the paranoiac, namely, as Lacan has
identified it, knowing in relation to certainty, not in relation to reality.∞∞≤
Put simply, what marks Schreber as different from putatively sane persons is
not a failure to distinguish reality from unreality—that the judge can do—but
his radical certainty. ‘‘The very nature of what he is certain of,’’ argues Lacan,
‘‘can quite easily remain completely ambiguous, covering the entire range
from malevolence to benevolence. But it means something unshakable for
him.’’∞∞≥ If the litmus test for madness is, therefore, not whether one can
distinguish reality from unreality, but instead where—the inner world or the
outer world—and the intensity with which one directs certainty, then clinical
descriptions of paranoia, including those by Freud, can easily be confused
with ‘‘the most wonderful descriptions of the behavior of everyone.’’∞∞∂
The nonpsychotic relates to the world with a firm sense of reality
precisely because he or she lacks absolute certainty. The inverse relation
between reality-sense and certainty may at first be counterintuitive until it
is recognized as underpinning the aims of analysis and, we suggest, as
grounding contemporary subjectivity. ‘‘What guarantees,’’ Mikkel BorchJacobsen asks, echoing Lacan, ‘‘that the so-called normal personality is not
fundamentally paranoid?’’∞∞∑ The answer, as far as Lacan is concerned, is
little. Indeed, a form of paranoia marks the emergence of human subjectivity and constitutes the aim of analysis.∞∞∏ Apropos forms of ‘‘paranoiac
knowledge,’’ Lacan suggests in ‘‘Aggressiveness in Psychoanalysis’’ that the
‘‘highly systematized, in some sense filtered, and properly checked’’ mechanism of analysis aims at ‘‘inducing in the subject a guided paranoia.’’∞∞π
But outside the analytic setting, persons routinely reject certainty in order,
it seems, to cope with the possibility that reality is worse than it appears.
Lacan’s illuminating summary of ordinary avoidances of seriousness returns us to the problem of cynicism:
150
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
What characterizes a normal subject is precisely that he never takes seriously
certain realities that he recognizes exist. You are surrounded by all sorts of realities
about which you are in doubt, some of which are particularly threatening, but you
don’t take them fully seriously, for you think . . . that the worst is not always
certain, and maintain yourselves in an average, basic—in the sense of relating to
the base—state of blissful uncertainty, which makes possible for you a sufficiently
relaxed existence. Surely, certainty is the rarest of things for the normal subject.∞∞∫
The ethical and political consequences of ‘‘blissful uncertainty’’ should be
clear, even certain. In the name of existential calm we avoid conclusive
relations to the threatening realities everywhere around us. Likewise, in the
name of consumption, we surrender to the seductions of the capitalist sensurround without the paranoia often required to resist, and ultimately replace, our reality. One of Jean Baudrillard’s keenest insights is that seduction
is stronger than production; that is, if capitalism worked by direct force rather
than by techniques of pampering, stupefaction, and the debasement of
minds, it would not be nearly as effective as it is.∞∞Ω Realities of force typically
engender reactions associated with trauma-related psychic sequelae, including a spectrum of increasingly prevalent mental defense conditions such as
post-traumatic stress disorder (ptsd), depression, substance abuse, somatic disorders, dissociation, and anxiety.∞≤≠ Seduction and, concomitantly, alienation engender psychotic (schizoid and paranoid) defense
reactions. The question we would-be Schrebers may ask is: Are we willing
to forfeit our reality-sense, such as it is, for the certainties that may alter it
forever and perhaps for the better? Or, put another way, will we choose,
with Schreber, how we wish to be represented?
Paranoia, then, as florid sign of cultural health: Benjamin had already
pointed us here in his 1928 reflection on the new ‘‘fruitful . . . legitimate’’
quality of books by the mentally ill.∞≤∞ Reading and, as we have suggested,
writing paranoia are important markers of modernity, and living (our)
paranoia has emerged as another such indicator, one posing a wide range
of sociological questions that transcend individual psychopathology and
private morality.∞≤≤ Engaging the meditations on schizo-existence by Gregory Bateson, R. D. Laing, David Cooper, Thomas Szasz, Franco Basaglia,
Joseph Gabel, and Deleuze and Guattari, one is led to the conclusion that
we are already enjoying our symptoms, perhaps a bit too much in the
sense that we have become prisoners of a reality that largely forecloses
We Have Never Been Schreber 151
dissociation and, with it, a sense of the possible. Gabel called this existential condition ‘‘morbid authenticity,’’ a state of being in which, we might
say, one is not paranoid enough to be able to lie.∞≤≥ Schreber was an
astonishing liar who was able to deduce possibilities, of which he was
certain, from realities of which he was profoundly uncertain. That he
could trade on the Middle Ages in order to produce something new
appears to be less than we can hope for and more than we can bear.
notes
The authors would like to acknowledge the consultations and/or inspirations of the
following persons: Andrew Cole, Zvi Lothane, Wolfgang Natter, and Stephen Sonnenberg.
1 For example, the translators Macalpine and Hunter, in the 1988 edition of the
Memoirs, note that ‘‘Schreber is now the most frequently quoted patient in
psychiatry’’ and that he is mentioned in nearly all textbooks of mental disorders,
including the Casebook accompanying the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of
Mental Disorders (DSM-III-R); see Schreber, Memoirs of My Nervous Illness (1988
edition), 8; 11.
2 Schreber, Memoirs of My Nervous Illness; all page references are to the 2000
edition except where noted. Zvi Lothane has suggested that a more accurate
translation of the title might be Great Thoughts of a Nervous Patient; see Lothane,
In Defense of Schreber, 1–2.
3 Freud, ‘‘Psychoanalytic Notes Upon an Autobiographical Account of a Case of
Paranoia (Dementia Paranoides),’’ in Standard Edition, 12:3–82.
4 Canetti, The Conscience of Words, 25. Important early psychiatric texts using
Schreber to illustrate schizophrenia include Bleuler, Dementia Praecox; Jaspers,
General Psychopathology; and Jung, Psychology of Dementia Praecox.
5 Freud, ‘‘Psychoanalytic Notes,’’ in Standard Edition, 12:71.
6 Foucault, Discipline and Punish, 193–94.
7 See Freud, ‘‘Analysis of a Phobia in a Five-Year-Old Boy’’ (1909), in Standard
Edition, 10:5–149; and Barnes, Mary Barnes: Two Accounts of a Journey Through
Madness. Barnes discovered her artistic talent after psychotherapeutic treatment
for schizophrenia with R. D. Laing.
8 See Schreber, Memoirs, 87. Notably, Schreber’s theological vision of history is
based on the medieval principle of translatio imperii (transference of empire);
see his historical ordering of ‘‘God’s chosen peoples,’’ which moves from East to
West, culminating with the Germans (Memoirs, 27).
9 Ibid., 94–95.
10 Ibid., 82.
11 See Simson, The Gothic Cathedral, 91–141. On the influence of Dionysian
152
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
thought on Suger’s aesthetic visions, see Suger, Abbot Suger on the Abbey Church
of St.-Denis.
Schreber, Memoirs, 22.
See Freud, ‘‘Psychoanalytic Notes,’’ in Standard Edition, 12:65; 72.
Schreber, Memoirs, 139.
See ibid., 16.
Ibid., 93.
See, for example, Freud, ‘‘Psychoanalytic Notes,’’ in Standard Edition, 12:47; 18.
In the years since Freud analyzed Schreber’s writing, the religious fantasies of
psychotic patients have been discussed in the psychoanalytic literature. See, for
example, Fairbairn, ‘‘Notes on the Religious Phantasies of a Female Patient,’’ and
Kaufman, ‘‘Religious Delusions in Schizophrenia.’’
See the discussion in Shengold, ‘‘Child Abuse and Deprivation Soul Murder’’
and Soul Murder. For the relevant discussion in Kaspar Hauser Feuerbach, see
Anselm von Feuerbach, Kaspar Hauser, 55–56. Feuerbach, Lost Prince, is a new
translation of the case by Jeffrey Moussaieff Masson.
See Shengold: ‘‘Soul murder has to do with crime: there is an inherent moral
protest in the term. Soul murder is a crime characterized by man’s inhumanity to
man. One man uses his power over another to crush his individuality, his dignity,
his capacity to feel deeply (to feel joy, love, and even hate); and, as implied in
von Feuerbach’s description, to stifle the victim’s use of his mind—his capacity to
think rationally and to test reality’’ (‘‘Child Abuse and Deprivation Soul Murder,’’
536). For the linkages of unmanning to soul murder, see Schreber, Memoirs, 67;
for morality, see ibid., 66. On the racial meanings of Schreber’s delusional system, see Gilman, Freud, Race, and Gender, 132–68.
Flechsig, Die körperlichen Grundlagen der Geistesstörungen. See also his Gehirn
und Seele.
Karl Jaspers notes that ‘‘even provisional anatomical constructs are preferable to
mere psychological investigation. These anatomical constructions, however, became quite fantastic (e.g., Meynert, Wernicke) and have rightly been called
‘Brain Mythologies’ ’’ (General Psychopathology, 1:18). On Franz Nissl as the first
to use the expression, see Bumke, ‘‘Fünfzig Jahre Psychiatrie,’’ 1141.
See Lothane, In Defense of Schreber.
Heinroth’s psychiatric concepts were preeminently guided by Protestant Christian doctrine; according to Heinroth, the etiology of mental disorders (Seelenstörungen, or disorders of the soul, by which he understood only the endogenous
disorders) was located in guilt caused by the mentally ill person himself. This
guilt was grounded in sin, a turning away from God and the commandments, as
exemplified in a life of physical or earthly satisfaction. See Heinroth, Lehrbuch
der Störungen. For an excellent discussion of Heinroth’s religious and ethical
conceptualization of sin, see Steinberg, ‘‘The Sin in the Aetiological Concept of
Johann Christian August Heinroth (1773–1843), Part 1’’ and ‘‘The Sin in the
Aetiological Concept of Johann Christian August Heinroth (1773–1843), Part 2.’’
We Have Never Been Schreber 153
25 Flechsig, Die körperlichen Grundlagen, 3–4.
26 Freud referred, in his 1893 obituary of Jean-Martin Charcot, to Flechsig’s scientific findings as having ‘‘ushered in a new epoch in our knowledge of the ‘localization of nervous diseases’ ’’ (Freud, ‘‘Charcot,’’ in Standard Edition, 3:15).
27 Lothane, In Defense of Schreber, 205; see also Santner, My Own Private Germany, 70.
28 Schreber, Memoirs, 92.
29 Benjamin was well acquainted with Schreber’s case, and kept the judge’s memoirs in his library on a special shelf reserved for works by the mentally ill. See
Benjamin, ‘‘Books by the Mentally Ill: From My Collection.’’ See also Scholem,
Walter Benjamin: The Story of a Friendship, 57; and Benjamin’s letter to Scholem
(July 21, 1925), in Benjamin, Correspondence of Walter Benjamin, 279. On the
‘‘strange similarity between the feminized posture of the translator (or translation), and Schreber, who attracted Benjamin’s interest,’’ see Clej, ‘‘The Debt of
the Translator,’’ 13.
30 Benjamin, ‘‘Books by the Mentally Ill,’’ 130.
31 This syndrome was later called the Kandinsky-Clerambault syndrome. See Kandinsky, ‘‘Zur Lehre von den Hallucinationen.’’
32 Rychlinski, ‘‘Ein Fall hallucinatorisch-periodischer Psychose.’’
33 Forel, ‘‘Selbst-Biographie eines Falles von Mania acuta.’’
34 See, for example, David, ‘‘Halluzinationen.’’
35 Certeau, The Writing of History. See also Freccero, ‘‘Toward a Psychoanalytics of
Historiography.’’
36 For thoughtful accounts of the various ways that modernity has constructed the
Middle Ages, see Bloch and Nichols, Medievalism and the Modernist Temper.
37 See Nichols, ‘‘Modernism and the Politics of Medieval Studies,’’ 29.
38 See Leupin, ‘‘What is Modernity?’’ Leupin’s discussion is central to this essay as a
means of addressing the secularization thesis at stake in the debate between
Blumenberg and Löwith. See Blumenberg, Legitimacy of the Modern Age; Löwith,
Meaning in History.
39 Fredric Jameson, foreword to Lyotard, Postmodern Condition, viii. See also Leupin, Lacan and the Human Sciences, and Glynos and Stavrakakis, Lacan and
Science. Erin Labbie has addressed Lacan’s idealization of the hard sciences and
the role of science within psychoanalysis in her Lacan’s Medievalism, 151–81.
40 Lyotard, Postmodern Condition, 8.
41 Ibid., 24–31. For an analysis of Schreber’s ‘‘language games,’’ see Wiethaus, ‘‘Cherchez la femme.’’
42 On Schreber as a body of writing, see Rickels, Aberrations of Mourning, 267;
Lukacher, ‘‘Schreber’s Juridical Opera’’; and Kittler, Discourse Networks, 194–95.
43 Schreber, Memoirs, 62.
44 Ibid.
45 Lacan, ‘‘Structure des psychoses paranoïaques.’’
46 Lacan, The Psychoses.
47 Lacan, Television, 19.
154
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
48 For a clear discussion of the role of discourse in the scene of schizophrenia, see
also Copjec, ‘‘The Anxiety of the Influencing Machine.’’ An important avenue of
inquiry that we are addressing in our extended work on Schreber is the role of
the idealization of science and the techne. As a disorder that is characterized
precisely by way of technological defense mechanisms, paranoid schizophrenia is
a disease of the subjective refusal to assimilate modernity and the technological
‘‘advances’’ that accompany it. For an argument along these lines, contextualized
in early Russian cinema, see Yampolsky, ‘‘Mask Face and Machine Face’’; and, for
ones contextualized in terms of cyberculture, see Roberts, ‘‘Wired,’’ and Marsden,
‘‘Cyberpsychosis.’’
49 See Lothane, In Defense of Schreber, and Israëls, Schreber: Father and Son.
50 Lucas, ‘‘The Semiotics of Schreber’s Memoirs’’ (emphasis in original).
51 Ibid. See also Santner, My Own Private Germany.
52 Jacques-Alain Miller discusses this lack in ‘‘The Names-of-the-Father.’’
53 Leclaire, Psychoanalyzing, 91.
54 Dr. Guido Weber was director of the Sonnenstein Asylum, where Schreber was
confined from June 1894 to December 1902. Weber was a forensic expert for the
court, and his reports on Schreber were submitted as documents adjudicating
the issue of Schreber’s guardianship and confinement. Schreber included these
reports as appendices to his own Memoirs, 327–48; 388–404.
55 Schreber, Memoirs, 181.
56 See also Labbie, Lacan’s Medievalism, 208–15.
57 These advancements include apparatuses such as the camera, which lent new
potential for empiricism (as well as fantasy) to culture by way of photography
and film. See Benjamin, ‘‘The Work of Art in the Age of Technological Reproducibility (Second Version),’’ in Selected Writings, 1935–1938, 101–33. And
consider that Frederick Engels mourns the obsession with the copy and the
object rather than the original and the signifier in Ludwig Feuerbach and the
Outcome of Classical German Philosophy.
58 Milner, ‘‘Lacan and the Ideal of Science,’’ 29. See also Koyré, Galileo Studies
(originally published as Études galiléennes, 1939).
59 Latour, We Have Never Been Modern, 69.
60 Luhmann, Observations on Modernity, 39.
61 Ibid., 51–52.
62 Schreber’s architectural sketches of his location in the asylum support a perception of his attempts at a social relationship. In sketching his physical position
within the asylum, Schreber demonstrates his need to draw the space in which
he dwells, providing us with an image of his atomic location within the panoptical view of the institution, of ideology, and of God as the Father and Other.
Additionally, Freud’s own account of his apartments mirrors Schreber’s paranoid
display. For a smart parallel between Freud and Schreber’s paranoid system, see
Farrell, Freud’s Paranoid Quest.
63 Luhmann, Observations on Modernity, 52.
We Have Never Been Schreber 155
64 Ibid., 53. See also Certeau, ‘‘The Gaze of Nicholas of Cusa.’’ Schreber’s hallucinations of the devil recall the famous case of Christof Haizmann, as studied by
Freud, ‘‘A Seventeenth-Century Demonological Neurosis,’’ in Standard Edition,
19:69–105; and Macalpine and Hunter, Schizophrenia 1677.
65 In fact, the spoken testimony of an illiterate witness took precedence over the
written testimony of a literate witness, as documented in Barker, Tremulous
Private Body.
66 Barker, Tremulous Private Body, 70.
67 Ibid., 73.
68 Kittler, Discourse Networks, 307.
69 Lacan, Freud’s Papers on Technique, 178.
70 Lacan, The Psychoses, 78.
71 Schreber, Memoirs, 16.
72 Kristeva, Desire in Language, 138.
73 Freud, ‘‘A Seventeenth-Century Demonological Neurosis’’ in Standard Edition,
19:69–105; Macalpine and Hunter, Schizophrenia 1677.
74 Kittler, Discourse Networks, 283.
75 Ronell, The Telephone Book, 454n147; Lyotard quotations from Discours, figure.
76 Freud, ‘‘Psychoanalytic Notes,’’ in Standard Edition, 12:63.
77 Kristeva, Black Sun, 11.
78 See Kittler, ‘‘The Scholar’s Tragedy: Prelude in the Theater,’’ in Discourse Networks, 3–24; Rickels, ‘‘Faust, Freud, and the Missing Entries into War.’’
79 Roustang, How to Make a Paranoid Laugh, 37.
80 In The Telephone Book, Ronell explains that the ‘‘always already’’ is different from
the a priori and that, as a temporal priority, the former refers to an ‘‘anteriority of
essence and presence’’ (430n89). This temporality is crucial for an understanding of the play of the medieval and the modern as dislocated concepts that are
not bound by time. See Uebel, ‘‘Opening Time.’’
81 Nietzsche, ‘‘On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense’’ (‘‘Über Wahrheit und Lüge
im außermoralischen Sinn,’’ 1873), in Philosophy and Truth, 79–91. Lacan’s classic
treatment of metaphor and metonymy is ‘‘The Instance of the Letter in the
Unconscious, or Reason since Freud,’’ in Écrits, 412–41.
82 Schreber, Memoirs, 192.
83 Ibid., 192–93.
84 Ibid., 21.
85 The poetics of the soul is in constant conflict with the end of time. Immanence is
poetic knowledge: ‘‘The soul of a child . . . might only have preserved it for the
same number of years it had lived’’ (ibid., 29).
86 Schreber, Memoirs, 7.
87 Dupré, Passage to Modernity, 178.
88 Schreber, Memoirs, 230.
89 Ibid., 231n104.
156
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
See Lacan, Four Fundamental Concepts of Psycho-Analysis.
Gilson, Spirit of Mediaeval Philosophy, 86.
Lacan, ‘‘Introduction to the Names-of-the-Father Seminar,’’ in Television, 90.
Tracy, ‘‘Mystics, Prophets, Rhetorics,’’ 260. See also Burke, The Rhetoric of Religion, and Harshorne, Man’s Vision of God. For Burke, human beings learn by
learning negatives (‘‘thou shalt not’’); this is important for an understanding of
the grammar and consciousness of the paranoiac. The shifting of a positive into a
negative functions to sediment a consciousness of God’s language.
See Plotnitsky, The Knowable and the Unknowable.
Deleuze and Guattari, Anti-Oedipus, 77. This volume and its companion, A
Thousand Plateaus, argue for the centrality of schizophrenia within culture. See
also Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, 192–95. Other thinkers positing a deep connection between modernity (or capitalism as modernity) and schizophrenia include
R. D. Laing, David Cooper, Joseph Gabel, Franco Basaglia, and Peter Sloterdijk.
Kantor, ‘‘Ethics and Simulacrum,’’ 488. Kantor also asserts that Schreber’s God is
the God of the Judeo-Christian tradition; see ibid., 487–88.
Tracy, ‘‘Mystics, Prophets, Rhetorics,’’ 270.
For a developed discussion of psychiatry as the science of the soul, as well as the
relationship between the soul and the brain, see Jung, The Psychogenesis of Mental
Disease, in Collected Works, 158–78. ‘‘Unfortunately only too often no further
knowledge reaches us of the things that are being played out on the dark side of
the soul, because all the bridges have broken down which connect that side with
this’’ (178).
Sloterdijk, Critique of Cynical Reason, 120.
Schreber, Memoirs, 269.
See Habermas, Legitimation Crisis, and Santner, My Own Private Germany, 145.
According to Santner, Schreber acts out and works through an ‘‘investiture crisis’’
(xii, 40, 143).
Sloterdijk, Critique of Cynical Reason, 113.
The characterization of contemporary culture as schizoid is most elegantly
articulated by Rollo May; see, for example, his Love and Will.
See Laing, Divided Self, 23
Laing, Politics of Experience, 78–79 (emphasis in original).
Laing, Divided Self, 161.
See Reik, Masochism in Modern Man.
See, for example, Schreber, Memoirs, 34; 124–25; 151.
Ibid., 124n62.
Ibid., 125n62.
The question of what the miracles protect Schreber from is a complex one, the full
answer to which exceeds the limits of this essay. Schreber had and has a lot to
defend himself against—from the cruelties of asylum life to misinterpretations
and mishandlings at the hands of psychiatrists and analysts continuing until the
We Have Never Been Schreber 157
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
present. For a complete ‘‘defense’’ of Schreber, see Lothane, In Defense of Schreber.
A good case for the ways Schreber defends himself against the dehumanizing
effects of mechanization can be made; for one such attempt, see Roberts, ‘‘Wired.’’
See Lacan, The Psychoses, 75–79.
Ibid., 75. Cf., on this point, Boothby, Freud as Philosopher, who reads Schreber’s
‘‘unshakeable sense of certainty’’ in the context of the loss of the sense of reality
(279). ‘‘Absolute certainty without reality’’ is thus a shorthand definition of
psychosis (ibid.).
Lacan, The Psychoses, 19.
Borch-Jacobsen, Lacan: The Absolute Master, 32.
Lacan sees paranoia as structurally necessary for the emergence of human subjectivity. The subject emerges when, in the mirror stage, the ego is constituted as
a specular Other and as an object of paranoid identification. The mimicry of the
mirror stage structures the ‘‘specular I,’’ which is turned, with the intrusion of the
symbolic, into the ‘‘social I.’’ Entry into the symbolic inevitably entails what
Lacan calls the ‘‘paranoiac alienation’’ of the subject (‘‘The Mirror Stage as
Formative of the I Function as Revealed in Psychoanalytic Experience,’’ in Écrits,
79). As Muller and Richardson comment, ‘‘captivation by the image of the other
in transitivism leads to paranoiac identification’’ (Lacan and Language, 40).
Lacan, ‘‘Aggressiveness in Psychoanalysis,’’ in Écrits, 91; 89.
Lacan, The Psychoses, 74.
See Baudrillard, Seduction.
For a fine study of trauma-related disorders from a mind-body perspective, see
Bremner, Does Stress Damage the Brain? For readings of the potentially positive
aftereffects of trauma on identity, see Wilson, Posttraumatic Self.
Benjamin, ‘‘Books by the Mentally Ill,’’ 130; see also note 29 in this essay.
One of the more important studies along these lines is Gabel, False Consciousness. Gabel sees false consciousness as a purer form of schizophrenia than clinically observable schizophrenia, due to false consciousness’s intense powers of
reification. However, he is clear about his adherence to a dualist conception of
schizophrenia in which paranoia (in contrast to schizophrenic false consciousness) does not de-dialecticize cognition or necessarily defeat praxis (Gabel, False
Consciousness, 209).
Ibid., 158–59; this is not a moral condition, but a failure to deduce the possible
from the actual. See also Cassirer, ‘‘Pathologie de la conscience symbolique.’’
158
Erin Labbie and Michael Uebel