THE ANALYSIS OF KNOWLEDGE-HOW
An Anti-Intellectualist Manifesto
ABSTRACT: Intellectualism—viz., the thesis that knowledge-how is a species of
knowledge-that—bears straightforward relevance in epistemology and has received
rigorous development in recent years (e.g., Stanley and Williamson 2001; Brogaard 2008,
2009, 2011; Stanley 2011; Pavese 2015, 2017). By contrast, anti-intellectualism—construed
as a positive theory of knowledge-how—is hardly in a more developed state today than
Ryle left it in the middle of the 20th century. We hope to change this trend, and to
prepare the ground for a positive anti-intellectualist epistemology of knowledge-how,
one that goes beyond the inchoate suggestion that knowledge-how is, or involves,
abilities or dispositions. Our primary goal is to propose a tripartite analysis of
knowledge-how that is broadly analogous to the JTB analysis of knowledge-that in that
it offers a parallel set of conditions related to agents’ powers and capacities (mastery,
success and ability). This objective is principally programmatic; we do not try here to solve
but to map in a novel way a range of new epistemological problems such an analysis
would raise, and to show thereby that anti-intellectualist epistemology could be as
fruitful, engaging, and interestingly controversial as the epistemology of knowledgethat, even if it preserves the core Rylean idea that knowledge-how is nonrepresentational, non-truth-directed and non-propositional.
Keywords: knowledge-how; knowledge-that; anti-intellectualism; the analysis of
knowledge
1. Introduction
Around the middle of the 20th century, Gilbert Ryle influentially argued that knowledge-how
is not a representational, truth-directed and propositional phenomenon—an antiintellectualist view that interpreters have since glossed as the claim that knowledge-how is
something akin to ‘ability knowledge’. As it’s happened—and perhaps precisely due to the
prevalence of this view—the topic of knowledge-how has been absent altogether in
influential standard epistemology textbooks, anthologies and readers from Ryle to the
present day. The fact that know-how, on a Rylean model, seems to lack intellectual properties
relegated the view to the outskirts of epistemology 1.
1
The reader may find such a claim exaggerated. But here are just a few examples: Sosa, Kim, Fantl and
McGrath’s (2008) collection of texts in their Epistemology: an Anthology has 60 chapters. None is devoted to
knowledge-how, which is not even in the index. The same is the case with Greco & Sosa’s (1999) Blackwell
Guide to Epistemology (17 chapters), or with Huemer’s (2002) selection of 51 classic and recent papers in his
Routledge Epistemology Contemporary Readings and Bernecker and Pritchard’s (2011) Routledge Companion to
Epistemology (78 chapters). The situation is similar in the case of introductory texts. For instance, neither
Dancy (1985), Audi (2011) nor Pritchard (2016) mention knowledge-how. In the cases where knowledge-
1
But is such an exclusion fitting? If we take Ryle’s assessment of knowledge-how at face value,
then it is confessedly difficult to envisage how knowledge-how should ever be subject to
typical forms of epistemic evaluation. It will not be answerable to norms governing rational
and responsible belief. Nor will it be straightforwardly evaluable along, as Alvin Goldman
(1999) puts it, the kind of ‘truth-linked dimensions’ that are often taken to distinguish
epistemological from moral, aesthetic, political and other kinds of assessments2. Some may think
that the only way to recover knowledge-how as a proper topic in epistemology is to simply
challenge Ryle’s point by defending intellectualism—and thus to link know-how with truth in
a way that is epistemologically interesting. All the worse, then, for those who take Ryle to
have been on the right track.
Prior to about the turn of the 21st century, there had been a few unstructured strands of
challenge to Ryle’s anti-intellectualism3. However, no systematic expression of a positive
intellectualist alternative appeared until Stanley and Williamson (2001)’s landmark paper
‘Knowing How’. That paper offered a programmatic agenda for intellectualists to pursue an
account of knowledge-how in epistemologically friendly propositional terms. Soon after,
many other intellectualist approaches to knowledge-how have been proposed (for instance,
Bengson and Moffet 2011; Brogaard 2008; 2009; 2011; Snowdon 2004; Glick 2012; Stanley
2011; Pavese 2015; 2017; Stanley and Williamson 2017).
Although anti-intellectualists of various stripes (in different degrees of sympathy with Ryle)
have put up a fight, mostly in response to Stanley and Williamson-style intellectualism, the
current trend amongst anti-intellectualists has featured a greater enthusiasm in attacking their
adversaries’ views than in developing their own. In the rare cases where anti-intellectualists
have submitted positive theses about the nature of knowledge how, these theses have (with
the exception of Carr 1981 and Williams 2008, whose views we will return to) been at best
vague—viz., that knowledge-how must be something like, or involve, or be grounded in,
‘ability’, or at least some relevant counterfactual success on the part of the agent (e.g., Hawley
2003). And such proposals have moreover made no case for inclusion in the theory of
knowledge—epistemology—as opposed to merely the theory of action.
In sum, contemporary anti-intellectualism—as a positive alternative to intellectualism—is
hardly in a more developed state than Ryle left it in the middle of the 20th century.
Contemporary varieties of intellectualism, by contrast, offer clearly formulated accounts of
knowledge-how with straightforward relevance in epistemology. We hope to change this
trend, and to prepare the ground for a positive anti-intellectualist epistemology of
knowledge-how, one that goes beyond the inchoate suggestion that knowledge-how is, or
involves, ability or dispositions. In contrast with the post-Stanley and Williamson (2001)
trend of merely negative anti-intellectualism (our own included), our aim in this paper is
straightforwardly positive. That is: instead of challenging intellectualism, our objective is to
advance a positive alternative proposal: a tripartite analysis of knowledge-how that is broadly
analogous to the JTB analysis of knowledge-that, but where, in short, (i) ability stands for
belief, (ii) success stands for truth and (ii) mastery stands for justification. The structure of the
analysis would thus be analogous, in ways to be specified, to the classic tripartite analysis,
how is mentioned in introductory texts, the context is simply to discard the topic as not falling within the
proper scope of the textbook (e.g., Pritchard 2014, 4; Martin (2010, 3-4).
2
See, for example, Pritchard (2017), David (2001) and Alston (2005).
3
See, in particular, Ginet (1975) and Carr (1979).
2
and this analogy—as will be shown—will ensure that we are putting forward a genuinely
epistemological proposal.
This objective is principally programmatic; we do not try here to solve but to map a range of
new epistemological problems such an analysis would raise, and to show thereby that antiintellectualist epistemology could be as fruitful, engaging, and interestingly controversial as
the epistemology of knowledge-that, even if it preserves the Rylean idea that knowledge-how
is non-representational, non-truth-directed and non-propositional.
2. The Structure of the Analysis
2.1. THE CLASSICAL TRIPARTITE ANALYSIS
Epistemologists traditionally take as a starting point when theorising about the nature of
knowledge, the classical tripartite analysis:
JTB TRIPARTITE ANALYSIS OF KNOWLEDGE-THAT
For all S, S knows some proposition, p, if and only if
(1) S believes p,
(2) S is justified in believing p, and
(3) p is true.
We will here assume, for the sake of the argument, that this is a more or less (with some
well-known caveats) an acceptable template account of propositional knowledge 4. Of course,
particular substantive JTB-style proposals have been notoriously fraught, and a recent trend,
championed by Timothy Williamson (2000), notably regards JTB approaches as categorically
beyond repair5—a point that remains controversial though, particularly in light of recent
efforts since the publication of Knowledge and its Limits (2000) on behalf of various strands of
virtue epistemology6. But setting aside the material adequacy of extant JTB accounts, there
are good meta-theoretical reasons (which we will explore in some detail) for the antiintellectualist to take as a starting point the template structure of the JTB analysis as a way to
move past the inchoate claim that know-how is ‘ability knowledge’.
2.2 MATERIAL, FORMAL AND FINAL CONDITIONS: AN ARISTOTELIAN ANALOGY
Our first step will be to identify and sharpen the key questions to which ‘justification’, ‘truth’
and ‘belief’ may be understood as possible answers; this is because, as will be shown, each of
4
Of course, since Gettier (1963), the prospects of putting forward a materially adequate JTB analysis of
knowledge have been appreciated as (at best) very difficult (see, for example, Shope (1983)). For an
overview of the traditional project of analysing knowledge in terms of constitutive components such as
justification, truth and belief, see Ichikawa and Steup (2014).
One principal reason for doing so is Williamson’s ‘track record’ argument (see Ch. 1 of his 2000). Though
the soundness of this line of reason has been disputed. For some recent critical attention to this point, see
AuthorA & Co-Authors (eds.), (2017).
5
6
For some recent proposed solutions to the Gettier Problem on behalf of virtue epistemologists, see
Turri 2011; D. Pritchard 2012; Sosa 2009; Greco 2010; AuthorA 2014; Kelp 2012; AuthorB 2015;
Zagzebski 1996).
3
the three tripartite conditions may be appreciated as distinct solutions to different challenges
in the theory of knowledge7. This will be the objective of the remainder of §2.2. We will then
explore in depth in §§3-5 how an anti-intellectualist epistemology of knowledge-how may
respond to those same challenges in a different way.
An epistemological analogy with the Aristotelian model of causes will be a fruitful starting
point. In Physics II 3 and Metaphysics V 2, Aristotle outlined four principal kinds of causes8: (i)
efficient; (ii) material; (iii) formal; and (iv) final. Each, he thought, corresponded with a
different why question. Take, for example, a bronze statue. We might seek an explanation as
to whom or what produced the statue—its efficient cause—which is the bronze caster. But
this explanation does not tell us everything about the statue. We might wonder what it is out
of which the statue was made—its material cause—in this case, bronze. Likewise, we might
inquire into the particulars of the shape in which the bronze was crafted, its formal cause. And
lastly, we might want to know about its aim—that for the sake of which the statue was made,
its final cause.
Our analogy is that, in the case of propositional knowledge, the JTB analysis provides
answers to three of the four Aristotelian questions about the nature of knowledge: material,
formal and final—setting for now the matter of the efficient cause aside9. Let us now look at
this analogy more closely.
2.2.1 The material condition
The belief condition of the JTB analysis is, repositioned in Aristotle’s terms, a material
condition: a belief is what a thinker has, or the kind of state she is in, when it is true of her that
she knows a proposition to be true. It is—at least, against a background supposition of some
form of meta-epistemological realism10—a metaphysical basis; it is that out of which knowledge
is made. Consider that, absent such a basis, knowledge-that attributions would be as they are
understood by anti-realist error-theorists and fictionalists: there would not be on such
construals something in the world that could serve to make it true that the agent knows that
p when she does—namely, her state of belief that p is the case11.
2.2.2 The formal condition
7
For some helpful discussion on this point, see Butchvarov (1970, 44).
8
For an overview, see Falcon (2015).
9
We believe that the efficient cause may also be an interesting question, and will come back to this in the
final section. If we think of knowledge as a production, the efficient cause of any instance of knowledge is
arguably the knower herself, viz., the producer of the relevant knowledge, which motivates an analysis of
knowledge in the vein of virtue epistemology (Phys. 195 a 6-8. Cf. Metaph. 1013 b 6–9).
10
Following Miller (2012), we may suppose that meta-epistemological realism, like meta-ethical realism,
involves a commitment to the existence of epistemic facts. And this involves a commitment to thinking
that at least some paradigmatically epistemic properties are actually instantiated. An additional
commitment of realism is that the instantiation of such properties is non-trivially mind-independent. See
Author A (2016 Ch. 1). We are, in this paper, going to remain agnostic about the truth of metaepistemological realism, since each of us have different views on the matter. It is at any rate a common
background against which epistemological theorising takes place and one with reference to which we
can naturally think about belief, within the JTB account, as a material condition along Aristotelian lines.
11
For some recent challenges to the orthodox belief requirement on propositional knowledge, see MyersSchulz and Schwitzgebel (2013) and Farkas (2015).
4
With respect to the ‘justification’ condition within the JTB account, it is, in Aristotle’s terms,
a formal condition, in the sense that it indicates the way the state (belief) is held by the person,
in light of some normative standard. For instance, as one traditional line of thinking goes,
justification is ‘parasitical on certain logical relations among propositions’.12 When
understood specifically along internalist lines, justification would be a function of the way
the belief is related to other states of the same kind (e.g., in relations of logical dependence);
if certain versions of foundationalism are correct, at least some beliefs would not be justified
by their logical relations to other beliefs but, perhaps, directly by their relation to other states
that are not propositional, e.g., experiences.13 But in any case, the status of being justified
would emerge from internal relations with other aspects of the individual’s cognitive system.
Or perhaps, along externalist lines, it is the way that beliefs are related to certain facts (i.e.,
facts about reliability, aetiology, etc.) that determine their status as justified. One way or the
other, the property of being justified is relational in the sense that it indicates the way the state
in question must be held by its possessor in relation to other states and properties. Being
justified (the formal condition) is, in sum, a status a given belief, qua material condition, has
or lacks, earns or loses, in virtue of how it is related to other elements, as opposed to a feature
that affects the individuation of the belief itself.
2.2.3 The final condition
And finally, the ‘truth’ condition of the traditional JTB analysis is, to continue the Aristotelian
analogy, a final condition; it indicates the goal or aim of the state, that to which the state aspires
to and with reference to which the belief is said to be correct or incorrect. A certain
movement of the arms and hands with a ball is a basketball shot—rather than a different
kind of shot (say, a volleyball serve)—when its correctness is a matter of its going through
the hoop. Belief is plausibly analogously related to truth—it is a kind of, as Sosa puts it,
‘epistemic performance’ (Sosa 2009; 2010; 2015, passim) with an aim that specifies its success
conditions, even if we don’t explicitly reflect on this aim when believing. That truth is the
aim of belief, its goal, distinguishes belief as a belief, rather than something else, such as a
wish or a hope. At least, this is one gloss on the idea that belief aims at truth, one embraced
by normativists, and one that we find plausible14. The Aristotelian analogy however doesn’t
depend on normativism; the point that—in the JTB analysis at any rate—truth is that toward
which a belief aims, its goal, may be defended even by those (such as Sosa) who lack any
commitment to the stronger constitutive norm claim—viz., that belief is distinguished from
other attitudes by its admitting of this particular standard of correctness 15.
To sum up: whatever else might be said for or against each component of the JTB analysis
as a possible response to each of these requirements, our claim is that the structure of these
requirements is fruitful and instructive with respect to understanding different theoretically
important aspects of its analysans, namely:
(i)
its material condition (what the analysans is, its metaphysical nature or basis),
Sosa (1980, 8). Sosa is here describing what he calls the ‘Intellectualist Model of Justification’, a model
that he takes to have been embraced by some kinds of foundationalism as well as their coherentist
critics.
12
13
For a notable expression of this point, see Sosa (1980, 20–23).
14
See, for example, Shah & Velleman 2005; Shah 2003; Wedgwood 2002.
15
Likewise, one might (within the framework of a JTB) account defend truth as the goal of belief along
the lines that Marian David does (2014, 363-76). Cf., Kvanvig (2014).
5
(ii)
(iii)
its formal condition (the way it ought to be held by the agent, in relation to her other
states and/or experiences), and
its final condition (what the state essentially or constitutively aims to, what its
defining goal is)16.
Against this background, we now want to investigate analogous questions in the case of
knowledge-how.
3. Our analysis
We have identified three epistemological questions any analysis of knowledge should attempt
to answer: what kind of state is knowledge, how must that state be held by the agent and to
what end does the agent have that state. Each corresponds with a request for a certain condition
on knowledge—material, formal or final—that our account of knowledge-how will have to
meet. Our challenge, then, is to answer the following: how should each of these requirements
be met in the case of knowledge-how, for the anti-intellectualist who resists entirely the thesis
that knowledge-how is a matter of possessing justified true beliefs? What kind of ‘conditions’
should we fill in as the material, formal and final conditions?
The structure of our proposed anti-intellectualist parallel to the JTB account is what we will
call the mastery/success/ability (MSA) analysis, and it takes the following shape:
MASTERY-SUCCESS-ABILITY (MSA) ANALYSIS OF KNOWLEDGE-HOW:
For all S, φ, S knows how to φ if, and only if,
(1) S has the ability to φ,
(2) S has mastery of φ-ing, and
(3) S would be successful in φ-ing.
In the following three sections, we will develop our MSA tripartite account with respect to
the material-condition, the formal-condition and the final-condition desiderata, respectively.
In §8 we will contrast the whole proposal with some precedents and show why ours is better
positioned than these precedents to foster future research in the epistemology of knowledgehow. We will conclude in §9 with some suggestions for new directions of research.
4. The Material Condition: Ability
4.1 ARTICULATING THE CONDITION
The material condition (as outlined in §3) in an analysis of a knowledge state involves some
informative description of what that knowledge-state is. In contrast to the other conditions,
which indicate either the way in which the state is held by the agent (formal condition) or
the constitutive reason why the agent has it (final condition) the material condition is
substantial, in the sense that it indicates what the knowledge-that state is made of, it’s
metaphysical basis.
Our candidate condition in the case of knowledge-how is ability: whenever an agent knows
how to , she must have an ability—viz., a capacity or a power—to by herself. We will
16
As was suggested previously, perhaps such an analysis should complemented by a fourth requirement,
related to its efficient cause (its aetiology in the virtues and faculties of the agent).
6
now qualify our view by embracing the following three claims: (i) dispositionalism, (ii) nonrepresentationalism and (iii) intentionalism.
Dispositionalism is the view that, insofar as the metaphysical basis of knowledge-how states
are abilities, and abilities are a particular kind of dispositional state, knowledge-how is itself
a dispositional state. Interestingly, and perhaps despite initial impressions, this idea is not
different in kind from what we find in traditional epistemology. It is almost entirely
uncontroversial that the material condition of knowledge-that, belief, is also dispositional in
character.17 This is so even though belief admits of occurrent modes where one is engaging
propositional content; likewise, abilities may be exercised, but they are in the default case
non-occurrently exercised dispositional properties of agents. At any rate, the dispositional
character of ability should not be distinctively problematic qua candidate for the material
condition on knowledge-how any more than the dispositional character of belief is
problematic when in this role in the theory of knowledge-that.
Non-representationalism, on the contrary, marks a difference with the parity condition in the
analysis of knowledge-that because, in contast to belief, ability is not a representational state.
There is no intentionality, in the sense of aboutness, as there is with belief. Abilities are not
contentful because, properly speaking, they are not about anything in particular. They are
individuated with respect to what the agent is able to do and not by states of affairs the agent
represents. It may be adduced that, in order to be able to perform some deed, the agent must
somehow be capable of representing its outcome. However, it is important to realise that
this idea results from a possible theoretical account of abilities, i.e., from an attempt to
explain how they function, but not from a description of what they are. Being
representational, or being capable of representing, is not a property that defines abilities
themselves but, in any case, a trait some authors suppose agents must have in order to have
abilities.18
Thirdly, intentionalism says that abilities—at least, the sort apposite to knowledge-how—must
be satisfactorily situated within the agent’s command19. An ability to do something is an
ability to perform not any old way, but to perform intentionally20. Intentionalism takes abilities
to be rooted in the nature of agents. Thus, not just any disposition—the fragility of glass, the
stomach’s disposition to digest, etc.,—instantiates know-how; only agents who are able to
do, and to do intentionally, may know how to do things.
Beyond dispositionalism, non-representationalism and intentionalism, deeper questions
linger. How may abilities themselves be identified? Under what conditions, exactly, must the
agent be able to succeed intentionally by herself? Answering such questions is relevant to
saying, in a suitably informative way, what a given ability is. Just as, in a similar way, a
specification of a given belief’s truth conditions is relevant to specifying of a given belief,
17
This dominant view has been contested by so-called presentism, according to which there are no
dispositional beliefs and we can only believe, and thereby know, things in the present. For a recent
defence of epistemic presentism, see Palermos (forthcoming).
18
Perhaps not all intelligent behaviour must be supported by representational processes. For an account
of basic cognition deprived of representations, see Hutto and Myin (2012). We expect our epistemology
of knowledge-how to be compatible with such a possibility.
19
See Hyman (2015, Ch. 4) for a helpful discussion on the issue of intention and voluntariness in
connection with action.
We are considering here “intentional” in the sense of intentional action, not in the sense of intentionality
as aboutness. See AuthorB (2017) for this distinction.
20
7
that it is that belief. But still, the conditions for an agent’s having a given belief are not
coextensive with the conditions for that given belief’s being true. By the same token, we may
expect different conditions, in the theory of knowledge-how, for (i) a subject’s having the
ability; and (ii) that ability being successfully exercised.
Over the past fifteen years, the claim that agents’ know-how consists in some relevant kind
of ability possession has been contested, and in particular on the basis of various kinds of
disabled agent cases. Such cases involve agents who apparently have both
(i)
lost previously possessed abilities; but
(ii)
retained their knowledge-how.
Intellectualists have made use of cases with the above structure in the service of arguing that
knowledge-how may be retained through the possession of beliefs stored in memory even
when the kinds of powers or capacities the anti-intellectualist adverts to are lost. Notable
examples of such cases include Carl Ginet’s (1975) unfortunate pianist who lost her hands
in a tragic car accident but still intuitively knows how to play the piano; Paul Snowdon
(2004)’s chef who still intuitively knows how to cook his famous omelette despite having
lost his right arm; and Stanley and Williamson (2001)’s ski instructor who still intuitively
knows how to ski despite debilitating arthritis.
Dispositionalism, intentionalism and non-representationalism do not by themselves offer
the resources to handle such cases. Thus, further explanation is needed. We think that the
most effective way to respond to these kinds of cases by the anti-intellectualist, who takes
ability possession to be necessary for knowledge-how, will involve putting three ideas
together21.
Firstly, that abilities, just like all dispositional states more generally, are always related to
some conditions of manifestation that may—and oftentimes, do—differ from the
conditions the agent is in at the time of the attribution. Secondly, disabling conditions may
have very different origins, and they may affect the agent in very different ways, even
permanently. And thirdly, in connection with this point, it will be helpful to review Ernest
Sosa’s (e.g., 2015) ‘triple S’ analysis of competences (which will help us to tie the previous
two points together):
Competences are a special case of dispositions, that in which the host is disposed to
succeed when she tries, or that in which the host seats a relevant skill, and is in the
proper shape and situation, such that she tries in close enough worlds, and in the
close enough worlds where she tries, she reliably enough succeeds. But this must be
so in the right way (Sosa 2015, 23).
Pianists with no piano available, chefs fresh out of ingredients, and skiers in the Caribbean
islands are not in the proper situation to manifest their abilities, but those who are amputated
or have arthritis cannot manifest them because they are not—in Sosa’s parlance—in proper
shape. Nevertheless, it may be argued that all of them preserve the relevant skill provided it’s
true that, if they were in proper shape and properly situated, they would be able to manifest that skill.
As Sosa (2015) puts it:
Drop the situation and you still have an inner SS competence. Drop both shape and
situation and you still have an innermost S competence: that is, the basic driving skill
21
For additional discussion related to these points, see AuthorA & AuthorB (2017).
8
retained even when asleep (in unfortunate shape) in bed (in an inappropriate
situation) (Sosa 2015: 26).
The limits between skill, shape and situation are anything but clear, and philosophers working
on situated cognition would have valuable input here. Perhaps the skill is extended to the
limbs of the agent (embodiment) 22, or perhaps some aspects of the situation are part of the
agent’s cognitive system (extended cognition) 23, but, in any case, it’s evident that attributions
of abilities or competences are always made with a working idea of right circumstances of
manifestation in mind, where SSS conditions are met.
Against this background, let’s return now to our specific disabling cases offered by Ginet,
Snowdon and Williamson & Stanley, respectively: it is still true about the subjects in these
cases that, if they were in the right situation, that is, if they had their arms or limbs, or they
were not affected by arthritis, they would then be able to play the piano, cook the omelette
or ski the mountain. These counterfactual claims are true of each of these agents even in the
disabling conditions described. Accordingly, not having a piano available, not having eggs in
the fridge, or being in the middle of the summer is not essentially different from having had
one’s hands amputated, or being affected by arthritis, no matter how dramatic the latter
situations may be.
We may now refine our position: we propose that dispositions, as—in Sosa’s sense—the
innermost seat of the agent’s skills, are retained even when one is not in the right conditions to
manifest them, which makes a dispositional state (viz.., ability) a good candidate for the
material condition of knowledge-how. Note that such a condition is still met in Ginet’s,
Snowdon’s and Willliamson & Stanley’s disabled agent cases. Moreover, we hold that the
notion of ability, as a particular kind of disposition, satisfactorily fills this role in that it fulfils
the requirement of intentionalism without implying representationalism (which is just a particular
way of accounting for our capacity for intentional action).
4.2. HAWLEY ON ABILITY AND COUNTERFACTUAL SUCCESS
Our account has much in common with Katherine Hawley’s (2003) defence of
counterfactual success as the essential feature of knowledge-how, although she is reluctant
to express her own proposal in terms of abilities. We think her reasons for scepticism on this
score can, after some careful consideration, be defused.
Hawley’s argument against abilities draws from several connected ideas. Firstly, abilities are
(or involve) dispositions24 (i.e., dispositionalism). Secondly, in some circumstances, dispositions
can be ‘finkish’—viz., like an otherwise fragile vase that is caused to not be fragile just when
being dropped (this is why straight counterfactual analyses of dispositions are typically
thought to fail25). Thirdly, we needn’t accept that knowledge-how is ever finkish. With these
three ideas in play, Hawley offers the following case:
22
See Noë (2005) for similar claims.
23
For the classic defence of this view, see Clark and Chalmers (1998). Cf., Carter and Czarnecki (2015)
for a limited defence of extended abilities, as relevant to knowledge-how on an anti-intellectualist
construal.
24
A straightforward defence of this claim is advanced by Michael Fara (2008, 848).
25
For the classic presentation of finkish dispositions, see (Maier 2010). The issues raised involving finks
apply mutatis mutandis for mimics and masks. See Choi (2008) for discussion.
9
SYLVIA: Silvia is ordinarily able to get home from the city centre, a journey she has
made hundreds of times. But, due to strange social and psychological features of the
city centre’s crowd which are currently present, if Sylvia were actually to go to the
city centre, she would have a panic attack and the panic attack would cause her to
forget how to get home26.
The key question here is whether Sylvia knows how to get home from the city centre. Hawley
thinks her own favoured account—which appeals to a counterfactual success condition but
not a disposition condition—is in a better position to answer the question without incurring
unwanted theoretical costs. The reason is that a counterfactual success account is (unlike a
dispositional account in terms of abilities) not at all pressured to diagnose Sylvia as having
‘finkish’ knowledge-how, which would plausibly be the case were dispositions or abilities to
be what is identified as the material condition of knowledge-how. As Hawley (2003) writes:
It is uncontentious that ordinary dispositions may be finkish and thus that straight
counterfactual analyses of dispositions fail. But we need not accept that knowledge how may
be finkish. Sylvia’s knowledge-how matches her counterfactual success. Sylvia does not know
how to get home from the city center under the circumstances of being prone to panic
attacks. She does know how to get home from the city center under circumstances which
are normal for most people, but she also satisfies the counterfactual success condition for
this task: if she were to try under such circumstances, she would succeed in getting home
(2003, 25).
Hawley then adds:
[…] replacing the straight counterfactual success condition with a dispositional success
condition does not seem to offer any advantages, and it raises additional questions about the
nature of disposition (2003, 25).
Of course, if knowledge-how could really be under some circumstances finkish, then it is no
theoretical cost to be committed to this possibility. And furthermore, there would be no
reason to think, on the basis of cases such as that of Sylvia, that a straight counterfactual
success account fares better than one that identifies an ability or disposition as the material
condition of knowledge-how.
We want to respond to Hawley’s line of argument by showing that it is very plausibly a virtue,
not a vice, of our account that it allows for the possibility that knowledge-how, at least in
certain kinds of cases, may be finkish; correlatively, we suggest that this is a feature that
know-how would share with knowledge-that, given some relatively uncontroversial
assumptions about the mechanisms of epistemic defeat27.
Here is an example of finked knowledge-that: suppose Moddy knows that he is modest (he
has, suppose, reliable testimony from many trusted peers on this point, and no reason to
think they are mistaken). But whenever Moddy thinks that he is modest, this generates for
him, at least temporarily, a psychological (or, alternatively, a mental-state) defeater—viz.,
suppose Moddy believes (whether rightly or wrongly) that modest people do not believe they
are modest—and this defeater suffices to temporarily defeat his previous knowledge that he
26
This is an adapted version of Hawley’s case, as outlined in Hawley (2003, 25).
27
For a detailed account of defeaters for knowledge-how, see AuthorA & AuthorB (2017).
10
is modest. The defeater can be neutralised however by Moddy’s refraining from occurrently
entertaining this thought 28.
We believe that (in light of examples like the modesty case just described) any viable account
of knowledge-that should not foreclose the possibility that knowledge-that might, at least in
certain situations, be finkish. But if that’s right, then the presumption should be in favour of
supposing that it’s a virtue of an account of knowledge-how that it be open to such an
analogous possibility (i.e., as in the case of Sylvia) rather than to be, as Hawley’s straight
counterfactual account is, closed to such a possibility.
If we were to assume that it is a vice of an account of knowledge-how that it avails itself to
dispositions which can themselves be finkish (as well as subject to mimics and masks29), then
this objection would overgeneralise so as to apply also to beliefs in the epistemology of
knowledge-that, beliefs which are also dispositional in character.
5. The Final Condition: Success
What stands in relation to ability as truth stands in relation to belief? The most obvious way
to fill in the blank here is ‘success’30. This point can be made with reference to (i) the
constitutive aim of these state types; and relatedly with reference to (ii) the identity conditions
for the relevant state tokens. In the former case, with respect to knowledge-that, we might
say—as the normativists do—that what distinguishes beliefs from other kinds of
propositional states is its constitutive aim; belief, as such, aims at truth, and that’s what makes
it, qua attitude, a belief rather than something else (e.g., a hope or a desire). As Velleman
(2000) puts it:
The concept of belief just is the concept of an attitude for which there is such a thing
as correctness or incorrectness, consisting in truth or falsity. For a propositional
attitude to be a belief just is, in part, for it to be capable of going right or wrong by
being true or false (Velleman, 2000, 16)
Likewise, we might say that the concept of ability just is the concept of a success-aimed
dispositional state. It seems paradoxical to assert: “I have an ability but there is nothing I
have an ability to do successfully.” Just as (à la Velleman) for a propositional attitude to be a
belief just is, in part, for it to be capable of going right or wrong by being true or false with
a mind-to-world direction of fit, to be an ability is to be capable of going right or wrong by
being successful or unsuccessful, with a world-to-mind direction of fit.
Moreover, the analogy that belief is to truth as ability is to success also gains support from
considerations to do with the identity conditions for the relevant state tokens. The belief <The
well is dry> is a different belief token from the belief <A tiger is in the brush> because the
truth conditions of the two belief tokens are different. Analogously, the ability to ride a bike
is different from the ability to rule a company because they aim at different kinds of outcomes
28
For a discussion of the difference between psychological and normative defeaters, see for example
Sudduth (2008), Pollock (1986) Lackey (1999) and AuthorA & AuthorB (2017).
29
See Choi and Fara (2016) for an overview.
30
See Sosa (2015, Ch. 1) and Williamson (2015) for some related analogies between belief, ability and
action and their related success conditions.
11
that count as successful manifestations of each. Riding a bike is different from ruling a
company.
Interestingly, for our purposes, Aristotle defines ‘final cause’ twice over (e.g., Physics II 3,8
and Metaphysics V 2), in terms of aim or end, and in terms of that for the sake of which something
was done. The preceding considerations speak to the belief/ability parallel (vis-à-vis the final
condition on knowledge-how) with truth/success, with respect to respective aims. And we
may also develop this analogy in terms of that for the sake of which each is done: by
connecting belief and truth in the context of seeking knowledge-that for its own sake, and
ability and success in the context of seeking knowledge-how for its own sake.
First, a clarificatory point. We are sympathetic with those who claim that inquiry itself (and
not merely the state of belief) aims at truth—viz., that the practice of believing should be
pursued out of a love of truth31. Hilary Kornblith (1983, 34), for instance, captures this point
in terms of epistemic responsibility: ‘An epistemically responsible agent desires to have true
beliefs, and thus desires to have his beliefs produced by processes which lead to true beliefs;
his actions are guided by these desires’. Likewise, James Montmarquet (1993) connects
intellectual virtue possession with the desire for truth, claiming that such virtues are qualities
a person who wants the truth would want to acquire. However, as Zagzebski (1996, §4.2.1)
has suggested, the core thrust of these proposals can be captured in terms of desire for
knowledge32. And indeed, the knowledge view has additional considerations to recommend it
(not least because, as we’ll explain further, being aimed at truth may not be characteristic of
all kinds of knowledge.)
This point has been captured helpfully in Sosa’s (2015, e.g., Ch. 3) recent work on the
epistemology of judgment: in judging something to be so, we are (unless we are simply
guessing) affirming in a way that is not merely aimed at truth, an aim we might hit when (for
example) we affirm with no concern for risk, as we do when guessing the lower letters in an
eye exam (2015, 74-5). Our typical judgments, unlike guesses, are not so riskily aimed, but
aimed at acquiring the truth in a way that delimits risk. In this respect, our epistemic aim in
affirming, knowledge, is more like the aim of a basketball player who takes a shot under
conditions of good risk management than the aim of a basketball player who aims at the
basket while disregarding risk altogether while nonetheless trying to get the ball in the hoop33.
Unless we already assume intellectualism, achieving the truth of our beliefs—viz., gaining the
truth in the right way—would be just one way, of potentially multifarious ways, of achieving a
given knowledge state. If such a pluralist view is correct, then we may envisage genuinely
epistemic goals for knowledge-how, even constitutive or, at least, necessary ones, other than
truth. For example, one may want to know how to φ without any particular interest in φ-ing
beyond attaining this knowledge—viz., with no interest in obtaining any benefits from this
knowledge: just for the sake of knowledge. In such a case, one’s goal is genuinely epistemic, but
not because one wants to know how to φ just for the sake of truth, but because one wants to
know how to φ just for the sake of knowledge (viz., one wants to know how to φ just because one
31 This point, of course, may complement an appreciation of a plurality of kinds of knowledge, including
kinds not reducible to knowledge-that.
32
See for example, Kappel 2010, Kelp 2011;2017 2014; Rysiew 2012; Engel 2009.
33
For further discussion on this point, see Carter (2016) and Kelp et al. (2017).
12
want to learn, for curiosity, how to do it, but not for any particular non-epistemic benefit—
not even doing it itself)34.
Conversely, non-genuinely epistemic goals ought to be distinguished from non-knowledge
conducive motivations. For instance: we may be interested in a certain proposition’s being
true, without any corresponding interest in holding a corresponding true belief (we would
then have a practical, but not epistemological interest in p)35. By the same token, for
knowledge-how, it could be the case that one is interested in obtaining the products or
practical benefits of φ-ing without being really interested in knowing how to φ oneself. We
would have then a practical, but not particularly epistemological interest in knowing how to
perform the activity in question—an interest that could in fact be satisfied simply by having
the activity in question done by somebody else.
In connection with this point, it will be helpful to consider following case:
FIGHTER PILOT: Will is an 80-year-old war pilot who flew a twin-engined torpedo
bomber in World War II. He has, in the twilight of his life, acquired a keen interest
in modern fighter aircrafts and wants to learn as much as he can about them. Will
develops not only an interest for facts related to those modern aircrafts (i.e., size,
manufacturer, capabilities, etc.) but for how one could actually pilot them. For
example, he wants to understand the differences between the kinds of abilities he
developed back in the 1940s and which he would have to employ today in order to
pilot the brand-new fighter planes.
We may imagine that Will—appreciating his own limitations—does not intend to become a
pilot in the future, and he could hardly have an interest to impress others with his abilities.
At his age, his interest is just in learning how to pilot those aircrafts for the sake of knowledge,
out of pure epistemic interest, even while conceding that he will never have again the
opportunity to sit in a cockpit, or earn anything from this knowledge besides knowledge
itself.
Just like the genuinely epistemological goal that drives traditional epistemology, concerned
with knowledge-that, is (arguably) knowledge (for its own sake), the genuinely
epistemological goal within a promising anti-intellectualist theory of knowledge-how is
likewise knowledge (for its own sake). When that goal is achieved for knowledge-that, the
agent who knows that her belief that p has reached the truth of p. Similarly, when that goal is
achieved for knowledge-how, the agent who learns how to φ has acquired the ability to φ
herself successfully, i.e. the power to achieve the occurrence of that act of φ-ing—if only she
were in the right (in Sosa’s terms) shape and situation, (and even the relevant shape and situational
aspects are presently inaccessible), and, what is more, even if she does not have—and may
never actually have—the desire to obtain that outcome. Put another way: the strictly
Compare here with Kvanvig’s (2014) characterisation of epistemology: ‘In slogan form, my
characterization of epistemology is that it is the study of purely theoretical cognitive success, where the
notion of what is purely theoretical is understood […] in terms of abstraction from the causal consequences of the
success in question’ (2014, 353). In a similar vein, purely theoretical knowledge-how would be a kind of
knowledge abstracted from the consequences of the success in question.
34
35
For example, concern about the future suffering of a loved one is best articulated in terms of an interest
that the individual’s suffering subsides, not necessarily connected to any salient concern about one’s own
epistemic standings, which is obvious because this sort of concern typically extends beyond the agent’s
own life.
13
epistemological goal of knowledge-how is to acquire potentially reliable creditable success
for its own sake—viz., just for the sake of knowledge.
6. The Formal Condition: Mastery
The problem of the value of knowledge is, in short, to uncover what kind of cognitive gain
one makes when one moves from mere true belief to knowledge, so as to account for why
the value of the latter exceeds the value of the former36. As we know from Plato’s Meno, this
problem is initially at least a perplexing one; mere true beliefs, as Meno and Socrates agree
(§§96-100), seems to aid us in our practical objectives as well as knowing; a person with a
true belief about how to get to Larissa is as good a guide as one who knows the way.
In an analogous vein, we may ask: what it is that makes knowledge-how more valuable than
mere successful ability; Meno might have suggested, by parity of reasoning, that a successful
ability to get to Larissa gets us there just the same as know-how. So why then should we
prefer the latter to the former?
Plato’s analogy in the Meno of the statues of Daedalus may be of help here: just as we want
not merely to possess the truth any old way, but to have it safely tethered down, we do not
want merely to succeed, but to have the capacity for such success at our command37. We
want to attain mastery, to be good at what we do (and not just to do good)—to achieve
excellence.
Justification and mastery are thus, in our view, the formal conditions on knowledge-that and
knowledge-how respectively. They are formal conditions because they say something
essential about the way in which the relevant state (belief, ability) must be held by the agent.
The formal condition may be satisfied when the state is properly connected to other states
of the agent, of the same or different kinds, but won’t be satisfied simply by adding more
states—viz., by the provision of additional material conditions (e.g., more beliefs into the
belief system, or more abilities and powers). Consider that if a thinker possesses or acquires
additional beliefs that remain inferentially detached from one other (as happens in Lewis
Carroll’s (1895) famous paradox of Achilles and the Tortoise), we do not say that the agent
is thereby more justified in believing the target proposition, simply in virtue of possessing
such additional inferentially detached beliefs 38. By the same token, an agent may come to
possess additional abilities or powers, but such abilities may themselves be disconnected
from one another, in such a way that, in general, she is a poor or at best lucky performer.
(This, at any rate, seems to be what we find in Bengson and Moffett’s (2011a) well-known
case of ‘Irina’, whose figure skating abilities are disintegrated from the neurological
abnormality that causes her to perform a salchow).
What this formal condition requires thus is not merely more states, more material bases, but
rather that those states be connected in the right way. It requires them to be held by the
agent in the right manner, by the lights of a plausibly specified normative standard. We
36 See, for example, Kvanvig 2003; Pritchard 2011; Haddock, Millar, and Pritchard 2010. For an
overview, see AuthorA & Co-Authors (2017).
37
For a more contemporary expression of the Daedelus metaphor in terms of stability, see Olsson
(2007).
Compare: we do not elevate one’s doxastic justification by simply increasing the level to which an
individual is propositionally justified.
38
14
submit that the fact that genuine knowledge-how requires mastery, or at least some level of
it, accounts for its normative character, as a state subjected to standards of normative
evaluation. This feature (which was crucial in Ryle’s original approach to the topic) has been
obscured in the debate about the nature of knowledge-how, which too often focuses on
simple and easy tasks, such as opening a door or breaking a glass, activities with respect to
which there is not much difference between (i) having a mere ability to successfully execute
the task and (ii) really knowing how to do it.
However, the concept of knowledge-how is revealed to be much richer—and comparatively
more epistemologically interesting—when applied to activities that are complex, multifaceted
and demanding—viz., activities which require longer learning processes, where
performances may be criticised and assessed from different perspectives, that require
intelligence and refinement, from cooking to driving, from designing a missile to giving a
lecture, from dancing flamenco to raising a child. When complex activities such as these are
under consideration, normative constrains and sophisticated and often demanding criteria of
assessment come to the foreground. It is (for instance) when assessing who knows how to
play tennis better, Federer or Nadal, that the concept of knowledge-how really comes apart
from mere ability possession, or when we wonder whether it was Russell or Heidegger who
knew how to better approach a philosophical problem 39. It is complex practices of this sort
that in the main attracted Ryle’s attention to the topic of knowledge-how—viz., activities
that require intelligence, prudence, and wisdom, where the component of mastery comes to
the fore. In a similar vein, in the epistemology of knowledge-that, justification is rarely—or
perhaps, pointlessly—requested when the propositional knowledge at issue is simple and
intellectually undemanding—viz., that one’s hand is in front of one’s face 40. More
epistemologically interesting are our justifications for complex claims, where balancing the
relevant evidence requires some intellectual sophistication. In such cases, the gap between
mere true opinions and justified true opinions, or knowledge-that, is comparatively more
intellectually striking.
The topic of mastery makes salient one well known difference between knowledge-that and
knowledge-how, which we have not yet discussed: the gradability of the latter. In contrast to
knowledge-that, which is almost unanimously taken to be an ‘on/off’ attitude41 (either you
know that p or you don’t), the possession of knowledge-how is paradigmatically a matter of
degree. Some people know-how to much better than others, which does not mean that
those that are less knowledgeable do not know anything at all—viz., that they don’t at all
know how to . In contrast, we do not say that some people know-that p better than others,
or for that matter that one know that p ‘less’ when in the possession of some undefeated
epistemic defeater42. The gradability of knowledge-how is best explained, in our view, as a
feature of mastery: we become better performers by means of education and practice, in so
39
For an account of philosophical practices in terms of knowledge-how, see AuthorB (2017 ch. 8 and
passim).
40 It is among Wittgenstein’s (1969) central objectives in On Certainty to call into doubt the rationality of
the practice of requesting justification in such circumstances. See, for example, OC §77, §93, §111, §125,
§138, §210, §243, §250, §282, §307.
41
For a dissenting view, see Hetherington (2011).
42
On the relationship between the gradability of knowledge-how, on an anti-intellectualist construal,
and defeasibility, see AuthorA & AuthorB (2017). For a recent voice of opposition on this point, see
Pavese (2017).
15
far as we perform better (or at least would do better if we actually intended to perform, or
were in the right SSS conditions)43.
On such a scale, the highest peaks of knowledge-how are those attained by masters. They
achieve excellence, which is not merely success resulting from the exercise of specific
abilities, but in general when performing in activities that include the exercise of multiple
inter-connected abilities. Success in the exercise of basic abilities may be sufficiently
explained by strength or good reflexes; the mastery dimension of knowledge-how is idle in
such cases. However, in cases where agents have to exhibit fine-grained integration between
multiple capacities and powers, their abilities cannot be detached from each other, but must
be integrated, nested, available on demand, sensible to features of a changing environment,
and so on. That is the point at which know-how plays a distinctive function in the social
assessment of performances. Think about an excellent tennis player, and how a multitude of
physical capacities (to run, to hit a drive or a backhand, to turn around oneself) are integrated
with further psychological capacities (to remain motivated, focussed, aware of the strategy
chosen) in such a way that elevates the subject’s skill. Or think about what a good business
administrator does to run her company. Just as justification leads intelligent agents to truth,
and helps to, as Socrates says, keep that truth well-fastened and tethered down, mastery leads
prudent agents to success, making them ever more capable and better equipped to deal with
practical challenges and adversity.
There is a further and important point about mastery which should be clarified. It would
perhaps be natural to suppose that the achievement of mastery, in some domain of
performance, is something one attains by first securing in some way an excellent method,
replete with a diverse and rich set of regulatory rules or algorithms, and then by consulting
this method, algorithm or set of rules in a reliable and effective way when executing the
relevant kinds of performances. In our view, such an approach would be utterly misguided.
Mastery is attained by agents, and assessed by critics, with respect to normative standards of
success, not by the fact of following procedures, recipes or regulative propositions. The latter
are clues, tips or advice we try to extract from excellent practice, not necessarily what governs
it. The master chef, for instance, is not the one that follows complex recipes perfectly, but
the one that can create them, who can in the right circumstances skilfully break the kinds of
rules and conventions that others must consult when attempting to ameliorate their
capacities. Likewise, the magnificent tennis player is not the one that has learnt by heart
tennis manuals, but the one on whom those manuals are based, and who doesn’t need anymore
to think about the kinds of rules and guidance that are indispensable to learning tennis, and
to improving once one has learned. In short, the standards of mastery are ruled by excellence
in performance, not the other way around. Let’s not confound mastery itself with pieces of
advice we may extract from the observation of masters, advice masters themselves need not
rely on. We believe that was one of Ryle’s original intuitions that should be guiding future
research in the epistemology of knowledge-how44.
43
Justification is also a gradable property, which is also a good motivation to propose mastery as the
requirement that mirrors it as a formal condition. And just as the degree of justification required for
knowledge-that may be sensible to practical features of the environment, as contextualists hold, so may
be the degree of mastery that is required for knowledge-how.
44
This point stands in stark contrast with the over-regulated and utterly counter-productive tendency
that we find nowadays in many professional activities (education being one of them), where
bureaucratically driven performance assessment standards have de facto usurped other ways of assessing
performances, and with devastating consequences.
16
7. Precedents
We are not the first to propose an anti-intellectualist tripartite analysis for knowledge-how.
We are aware of at least two such precedents, one due to David Carr (1981) and the other to
John N. Williams (2008). These proposals can be summarised as follows:
CARR’S (1981) ACCOUNT:
For all S, φ, S knows how to φ if, and only if
(i) S may entertain φ-ing as a purpose.
(ii) S is acquainted with a set of practical procedures necessary for successful φ-ing.
(iii) S exhibits recognizable success at φ-ing.
WILLIAMS’ (2008) ACCOUNT:
For all S, φ, C, S knows how to φ in C only if45
(i) If S were to try to φ, under C, then S would usually succeed in φ-ing because
(ii) S has a reliable method of φ-ing, under C, that
(iii) S is entitled to believe will usually result in φ-ing.
Carr’s and Williams’ analyses are not explicitly related to each other 46. Interestingly enough,
both of the above two analyses are introduced as non-Rylean anti-intellectualist accounts of
knowledge-how. They purport to be non-Rylean because neither introduces abilities in their
analysans, in contrast with our own proposal. In the case of Williams, reluctance to introduce
abilities in the analysans is explained by arguments introduced by Hawley (2003), which we
have addressed in §4.2, where we argued that certain principled considerations against
positing ability as the material condition of knowledge-how are unmotivated. Our proposal,
we want to now suggest, fares favourably in comparison with each of these precedents.
7.1. CARR’S TRIPARTITE ANALYSIS
Carr’s first condition faces (as a necessary requirement on knowledge-how) some troubling
counterexamples. In short: there are many things agents plausibly know how to do even if
they may never entertain them as purposes. For example, a master locksmith, ‘Alex’, may
plausibly count as knowing how to pick a warded lock even though he may never entertain
doing this as a purpose precisely because it is too easy. He nonetheless easily would be able to
easily pick the lock if he tried. We may have powers we may never exercise, but that does
not mean that we don’t have them. Most everyone knows how to jump from a dangerously
steep cliff, but few would entertain that as a purpose. In short, lack of motivation or
pragmatic constraints needn’t limit our powers. Carr’s first condition misses this point.
Carr’s second condition is, recall, that S is acquainted with a set of practical procedures
necessary for successful φ-ing. This condition contrasts with our requirement of mastery, as
a (gradual) condition on knowledge-how. As we’ve suggested in §6, mastery is to be
determined by excellence in performance, not by the act of following procedures, recipes or
regulative propositions of the sort we are likely to derive by observing the skilled performer.
We do not assess know-how by the way agents follow recipes, but by the excellence in their
Williams’ analysis aims to offer strong necessary conditions which he does not claim are jointly
sufficient, thus, he does not maintain ‘if, and only if’ in his formulation.
45
46
Williams (2008) does not make any reference to Carr (1981), but just to Carr (1979) wherein the above
analysis had not yet been proposed.
17
outcomes. Recipes may be useful as an attempt to imitate mastery, or to attain it when we
are at lower levels of excellence, but are not such that the consultation of them is in any way
constitutive of the mastery itself. Carr’s second requirement inverses the cause and the effect,
and considers as a condition of knowledge-how what should better be understood as its
consequence or by-product.
As to Carr’s third condition, “(iii) S exhibits recognizable success at φ-ing”, it is very similar
to our final condition, but it errs in requiring the agent to actually exhibit that success, which
is not a viable necessary condition for knowing how. As we argued in §5, abilities are—and
this was a point that has been developed in detail in Sosa’s work—always related to relevant
conditions of manifestation (recall Sosa’s ‘shape’ and ‘situation’ conditions), which may be
unreachable for the agent, even in an irretrievable way. Our imagined fighter pilot Will, for
instance, may learn how to fly a modern fighter plane full well, even if, given his age and
associated practical limitations, he will never be able to actually do so successfully. Carr’s third
condition is in the right direction towards the correct formulation of a final condition, but it
is too strong in that respect.
7.2. WILLIAMS’S TRIPARTITE ANALYSE
Let’s consider now Williams’ (2008) proposal, according to which S knows how to φ in
circulstance C only if (i) If S were to try to φ, under C, then S would usually succeed in φing because (ii) S has a reliable method of φ-ing, under C, that (iii) S is entitled to believe
will usually result in φ-ing. We submit that Williams’ first condition is a correct formulation
of the final condition, i.e. success. However, the problem is that the account lacks anything
like a material condition, which is needed to explain why the relevant success is actually due
to the agent’s own abilities.
Williams’ first condition actually sounds a lot like a standard ability condition. After all, it
bears close similarities to some prominent variations on the conditional analyses of abilities
(e.g., Davidson 1980; Peacocke 1999)47. However, Williams cautions us that we should avoid
positing an ability condition for two reasons.
(i)
(ii)
The first reason is that, as Williams puts it, ‘it is possible that S still knows how
to perform a task she is newly unable ever again to perform’ (2008, 109).
The second reason Williams adduces has to do with the opacity of knowledgehow.
Neither of these reasons is convincing. Williams’ first point is made with reference to a
standard disabled agent case—though we’ve shown in §4.1 that such cases don’t pose a
problem for the kind of ability condition we are advancing.
Williams’ second line of reasoning, which has to do with the opacity of ability and
knowledge-how respectively, is more interesting. The argument proceeds as follows:
WILLIAMS’ ARGUMENT FROM OPACITY
(1) Knowledge-how is opaque.
(2) Abilities are not opaque.
(3) Therefore, knowledge-how is not ability.
47
The conditional analysis probably owes, originally, to Hume. For discussion of this analysis, and
responses to objections, see Maier (2010 §3).
18
Williams defends (1) by appealing to the case of Stan:
STAN: ‘Stan’s job involves selecting three equal lengths of wood and then gluing them
together to make equilateral triangles. Stan, who is not very bright, has the concept
of equal length but has no clue what an angle is. He may know how to make
equilateral triangles (by following the method above) yet not know how to make
equiangular triangles (he has no idea what these are), despite the fact that making
equilateral triangles is necessarily making equiangular triangles’ (2008, §2).
It’s at least controversial whether Stan does not know how to make equilateral triangles. It
could be argued, for instance, that what Stan lacks is knowledge that he knows how to make
them. And the requirement that one may only know how to φ if one knows that one knows
how to φ is anything but evident 48.
But let’s set this point aside. The problem with (1) of the argument from opacity is that even
if we grant Williams’ diagnosis of the case of Stan, this is insufficient evidence for accepting
the conclusion. It might after all be that some cases of knowledge-how are not opaque, even
if others are, and thus that knowledge-how is not uniform with respect to whether it is
opaque.
It is at any rate incumbent on Williams to establish that if some cases of knowledge-how are
opaque, then all must be. Furthermore, it’s not clear why the anti-intellectualist cannot make
a similar move in the course of rejecting (2). Even if some abilities are not opaque, the burden
remains with Williams to account for why all abilities are not opaque.
The second condition in Williams’ analysis is misguided for same kinds of reasons as Carr’s
second condition was. Whereas Carr included as a requirement being acquainted with a set
of practical procedures, Williams requires the agent to “have a reliable method of φ-ing,
under C”. However, as we have shown, methods, regulative propositions and practical
procedures are not utilised by those who have sufficiently mastered their activities. We may
try to imitate masters by means of such methods which we infer by observing their
performances, but masters are not those who follow methods, even if they inadvertently
develop them. If anything, possessing and following a reliable method is the way we may try
to achieve success precisely when we do not know how to do what we attempt to do.
Williams’ third condition is based on his second condition: the agent, according to this
condition, must be “entitled to believe” that her method “will usually result in φ-ing”. Setting
aside the reasons to reject that condition that are already implied by our reasons just noted
for rejecting the second condition, we also submit that the addition of belief in this condition
leaves Williams’ himself with a view that embraces an aspect of the very kind of intellectualist
view his proposal was meant to be an alternative to.
In sum, both Carr’s and Williams’ proposals fails to provide a defensible material condition
in their respective analyses of knowledge-how. Their reluctance to introduce abilities leads
them to advert to conditionals and possibilities, but not to the kinds of dispositions that
could be grounded in the agent’s nature. We grant that both accounts include success in their
conditions, which puts them in the right direction to meet a final condition (although Carr
formulates the requirement too strongly, requiring actual success). However, above all, both
accounts fail to locate the normativity of knowledge-how, which is not to do with procedures
or methods, but in the mastery of the task, as when the agent’s capacities and powers are
related in the right way, with fluency and flexibility. Normativity, in short, is parasitic on excellence
48
See AuthorA & AuthorB (2017) for discussion.
19
in practice, not on whatever conscientiousness may be exercised in the application of previously determined
regulations. Norms, regulations, methods, manuals and recipes are instruments that allow us
to imitate excellence, but following them is not what makes those results valuable. Carr and
Williams, thus, are not in a position to satisfactorily respond to the Meno question,
repositioned as a question about knowledge-how: why should we prefer knowledge-that to
mere true opinion, knowing how to do something to merely being able to successfully do it?
8. Concluding remarks and further applications
The principal problem we’ve attempted to address in this paper is this: if know-how is
afforded the traditional anti-intellectualist spin of ‘ability knowledge’, it’s not especially clear
where the epistemology of knowledge-how is to begin, and it is perhaps even less clear how
traditional epistemological problems that have exercised those who think about the nature
and value of knowledge-that should be reconceived as problems apposite to knowledge-how.
Our goal has been accordingly to advance the prospects of an anti-intellectualist approach
to knowledge-how in epistemology by offering a positive anti-intellectualist view that goes
beyond mere ‘ability possession’. We’ve tried to show that the very questions which
undergird the JTB analysis in the epistemology of propositional knowledge have viable
analogues in the case of knowledge-how, and that this is so even when approached from
within the anti-intellectualist tradition. To this end, we’ve proposed and defended specific
candidate conditions: ability, mastery and success.
A benefit of the structure outlined is that traditional problems of knowledge-that may be
reconceived straightforwardly as problems we may explore for an anti-intellectualist account
of knowledge-how. We have shown this to be so in several respects thus far, and we will
conclude by sketching some additional examples that may foster some future research.
Firstly, we may ask whether knowledge-how, on an anti-intellectualist construal may be
Gettierized, and what an ‘anti-Gettier’ condition might look like. To be clear, there are
already extant discussions of knowledge-how and Gettier cases. However, such discussions
have categorically focused on intellectualist accounts of knowledge how 49, accounts on which
Gettier cases for know-how would inherit the structure of Gettier cases for knowledge-that.
On our tripartite anti-intellectualist account, the form is clear enough: such cases would
feature agents whose mastery of an activity is disconnected from the success such that the
success is lucky. In order to deal with such cases, perhaps we will need a fourth condition,
which would be equivalent to an Aristotelian efficient cause—one that remained unused in our
analogy. Something like this is what—in the epistemology of propositional knowledge—
robust virtue epistemology (e.g., Zagzebski 1996; Greco 2010, 2012; Sosa 2009) offers to
effect, at least in some of its versions: knowledge-that is justified true belief that results from
the agent’s aptness (as a performance where the agent is sufficiently creditable for the relevant
success). We may be inclined to impose on knowledge-how some equivalent further
requirement, in the sense that it must be to the credit of the subject of knowledge-how that
her success manifests her mastery.
Secondly, a promising line of research would be to model sceptical worries with respect to
know-how along anti-intellectualist lines, including radical sceptical worries engendered by
those who doubt whether we know how to do anything, or almost anything, despite being
apparently successful in many things we intend to do. Of course, at least one general version
49
See, for example, Poston (2009); Cath (2011); AuthorA & Co-Author (2015).
20
of radical scepticism for anti-intellectualism may trivially follow from a BIV scenario, one
that deprives us of propositional knowledge and knowledge-how alike (by causing not only
our beliefs to be false, but more relevantly for our purposes, our abilities to be illusory).
However, even so, the matter of how know-how might be vindicated in the face of such
challenges, remains to be spelled out. Moreover, there are additional kinds of sceptical
worries that would be endemic to knowledge-how and which our proposal can clearly
represent. Take, for example, Jonathan Schaffer’s (2010) ‘Debasing Demon’ which causes
beliefs to be produced on an improper basis and later for it to seem to one that they are
properly based. Analogously, we can envisage a demon that causes successes to be a matter
of luck, and later makes it seem to us that our success manifested a mastery creditable to us.
Furthermore, just as Pyrrhonian scepticism maintains that we could have true beliefs, or even
knowledge, but still never know if this is the case, perhaps along similar lines we may
investigate whether, if we do have knowledge-how, how are we even in a position to tell that
we do.
Yet another auspicious topic concerns the extent to which knowledge-how may be socially
distributed and extended into the environment. Once we have a principled understanding of
the structure of knowledge-how, we may ask: to what extent may agents be said to know
how to do things when they systematically and actively rely on external scaffolding, or on the
capacities of others? Theorising about the extension of knowledge-how into the
environment, on our view, will not be simply a matter of theorising about whether abilities
may supervene on extraorganismic features of the world. It would in addition involve
inquiring into the matter of whether and to what extent mastery itself may be outsourced
and offloaded systematically via the reliance and trust that we manifest in the capacities of
others. In fact, the social function of the concept of know-how, as label for reliable
performers that manifest mastery, may help shed light on the very content of such concept
—in a similar vein to how Craig (1990) famously claimed that the social function of
knowledge-that is to track reliable testifiers.
Finally, further topics for future research concern the mechanisms involved in the acquisition
and transmission of knowledge-how. For example:
•
•
•
•
50
Are there specific sources of knowledge-how, besides those canonically identified as
sources of knowledge-that (i.e., memory, testimony, inference, perception)? For
instance: trial and error, active mimicking, praise and criticism, and so on.
Are any such sources basic? If so, are we default entitled to trust such ‘basic abilities’
that would issue from such sources in action in a way that is broadly analogous to
the way we are plausibly default entitled to trust the deliverances of basic sources
(e.g., perception, memory) in the epistemology of knowledge-that?
How limited is the know-how we may acquire by sheer testimony, in contrast to
knowledge-that, which could in principle be acquired by such means without loss in
value?
Do transmission principles that plausibly govern the transmission of knowledge-that
hold, mutatis mutandis to knowledge-how? For example, if as Burge, McDowell and
others maintain, one cannot acquire knowledge-that from a speaker who lacks it50,
we may ask: can one acquire knowledge-how (replete with the mastery requirement)
from a teacher who lacks it? Nothing guarantees a priori that the answer here must
be the same.
For a notable counterexample to this kind of principle, see Lackey's (2008) ‘creationist teacher’ case.
21
The questions and problems that arise with our style of account in play are both new and
worthy of engagement. Our goal has not been to offer definitive solutions to any of these
problems. Rather, we hope to have shown that the epistemologically interesting character of
know-how is not parasitic upon, or derivative from, knowledge-how’s belonging to the
category of knowledge-that. There is room for an epistemology of knowledge-how that does
not traffic in justified true beliefs, but which may nonetheless face the same kinds of
challenges that that have de facto set the agenda in the theory of knowledge-that, and probably
still will for a long time yet.
22
References
AuthorA (2014; 2016)
AuthorA & AuthorB (2017)
AuthorA & Co-Author (2015).
AuthorB (2015).
Alston, William P. 2005. Beyond Justification: Dimensions of Epistemic Evaluation. Cambridge
University Press.
Bengson, John, and Marc Moffet. 2011. ‘Nonpropositional Intellectualism’. In Knowing
How: Essays on Knowledge, Mind, and Action, edited by John Bengson and Marc
Moffet, 161–195. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bengson, John, and Marc Moffett. 2011. ‘Two Conceptions of Mind and Action: Knowing
How and the Philosophical Theory of Intelligence’. In Knowing How: Essays on
Knowledge, Mind, and Action, edited by John Bengson and Marc Moffett, 3–55.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Brogaard, Berit. 2008. ‘Knowledge-the and Propositional Attitude Ascriptions’. Grazer
Philosophische Studien 77 (1):147–190.
———. 2009. ‘What Mary Did Yesterday: Reflections on Knowledge-Wh’. Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 78 (2):439–467.
———. 2011. ‘Knowledge-How: A Unified Account’. In Knowing How: Essays on Knowledge,
Mind, and Action, edited by J. Bengson and M. Moffett. Oxford University Press.
Butchvarov, Panayot. 1970. The Concept of Knowledge. Evanston: Northwestern University
Press.
Carr, David. 1979. ‘The Logic of Knowing How and Ability’. Mind 88 (351):394–409.
———. 1981. ‘Knowledge in Practice’. American Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1):53–61.
Carroll, Lewis. 1895. ‘What the Tortoise Said to Achilles’. Mind 4 (14):278–280.
Carter, J. Adam. 2016. ‘Sosa on Knowledge, Judgment and Guessing’. Synthese, 1–20.
Carter, J. Adam, and Duncan Pritchard. 2015. ‘Knowledge-How and Epistemic Luck’. Noûs
49 (3):440–453.
Carter, J.A. 2014. ‘Robust Virtue Epistemology as Anti-Luck Epistemology: A New
Solution’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 1–17.
Cath, Yuri. 2011. ‘Knowing How without Knowing That’. Knowing How: Essays on Knowledge,
Mind and Action, 113–35.
Choi, Sungho. 2008. ‘Dispositional Properties and Counterfactual Conditionals’. Mind 117
(468):795–841.
Choi, Sungho, and Michael Fara. 2016. ‘Dispositions’. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Spring 2016.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/dispositions/.
Craig, Edward. 1990. Knowledge and the State of Nature: An Essay in Conceptual Synthesis.
Oxford University Press.
David, Marian. 2001. ‘Truth as the Epistemic Goal’. In Knowledge, Truth and Duty: Essays on
Epistemic Justification, Responsibility and Virtue, edited by Matthias Steup, 151–69. New
York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Davidson, Donald. 1980. Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford University Press.
Falcon, Andrea. 2015. ‘Aristotle on Causality’. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
edited by Edward N. Zalta, Spring 2015.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/aristotle-causality/.
Fara, Michael. 2008. ‘Masked Abilities and Compatibilism’. Mind 117 (468):843–65.
https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzn078.
Farkas, Katalin. 2015. ‘Belief May Not Be a Necessary Condition for Knowledge’.
Erkenntnis 80 (1):185–200.
Ginet, Carl. 1975. Knowledge, Perception, and Memory. D. Reidel Pub. Co.
23
Glick, E. 2012. ‘Abilities and Knowledge-How Attributions’. In Knowledge Ascriptions, edited
by J. Brown and M. Gerken. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Greco, John. 2010. Achieving Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 2012. ‘A (Different) Virtue Epistemology’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
85:1–26.
Haddock, Adrian, Alan Millar, and Duncan Pritchard. 2010. The Nature and Value of
Knowledge: Three Investigations. Oxford University Press.
Hetherington, Stephen. 2011. How to Know: A Practicalist Conception of Knowledge. WileyBlackwell.
Hume, David. 1777. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding: A Critical Edition. Oxford
University Press.
Hutto, Daniel D., and Erik Myin. 2012. Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds Without Content.
MIT Press.
Hyman, John. 2015. Action, Knowledge, and Will. OUP Oxford.
https://books.google.co.uk/books?hl=en&lr=&id=bIJMCAAAQBAJ&oi=fnd&p
g=PP1&dq=action+knowledge+and+the+will+john+hyman&ots=mPvR3hbQic
&sig=gW_xznaif7_BYPkLd89QlVexpik.
Ichikawa, Jonathan Jenkins, and Matthias Steup. 2014. ‘The Analysis of Knowledge’. In The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta, Spring 2014.
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/knowledge-analysis/.
Kelp, Christoph. 2012. ‘Knowledge: The Safe-Apt View’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91
(2):265–78.
Kelp, Christoph, Cameron Boult, Fernando Broncano-Berrocal, Paul Dimmock, Harmen
Ghijsen, and Mona Simion. 2017. ‘Hoops and Barns: A New Dilemma for Sosa’.
Synthese, 1–16. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1461-5.
Kornblith, Hilary. 1983. ‘Justified Belief and Epistemically Responsible Action’. Philosophical
Review 92 (1):33–48.
Kvanvig, Jonathan L. 2003. The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Lackey, Jennifer. 1999. ‘Testimonial Knowledge and Transmission’. The Philosophical
Quarterly 49 (197):471–90. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9213.00154.
———. 2008. Learning from Words: Testimony as a Source of Knowledge. Oxford University
Press.
Lewis, David. 1997. ‘Finkish Disposition’. The Philosophical Quarterly 47.
Maier, John. 2010. ‘Abilities’. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Myers-Schulz, Blake, and Eric Schwitzgebel. 2013. ‘Knowing That P without Believing
That P’. Noûs 47 (2):371–384.
Olsson, E. J. 2007. ‘Reliabilism, Stability and the Value of Knowledge’. American
Philosophical Quarterly 44 (4):343–55.
Palermos, Orestis. Forthcoming. ‘Epistemic Presentism’. Philosophical Psychology.
Pavese, Carlotta. 2015. ‘Practical Senses’. Philosopher’s Imprint 15 (29).
http://hdl.handle.net/2027/spo.3521354.0015.029.
———. 2017. ‘Know-How and Gradability’. Philosophical Review 126 (3):345–383.
Peacocke, Christopher. 1999. Being Known. Oxford University Press.
Pollock, John L. 1986. Contemporary Theories of Knowledge. Rowman and Littlefield.
Poston, Ted. 2009. ‘Know-How to Be Gettiered?’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79
(3):743–47.
Pritchard, D. 2012. ‘Anti-Luck Virtue Epistemology’. Journal of Philosophy 109:247–79.
Pritchard, Duncan. 2011. ‘What Is the Swamping Problem’. In Reasons for Belief, edited by
Andrew Reisner and Asbjorn Steglich-Petersen. Cambridge: Cambridge Univeristy
Press.
24
———. 2017. ‘Epistemic Axiology’. Edited by Martin Grajner and Pablo Schmectig.
Epistemic Reasons, Epistemic Norms, and Epistemic Goals. Berlin: De Gruyter.
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2010. ‘The Debasing Demon’. Analysis 70 (2):228–237.
Shope, Robert K. 1983. An Analysis of Knowing: A Decade of Research. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Snowdon, Paul. 2004. ‘Knowing How and Knowing That: A Distinction Reconsidered’.
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 104 (1):1–29.
Sosa, Ernest. 1980. ‘The Raft and the Pyramid: Coherence versus Foundations in the
Theory of Knowledge’. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1):3–26.
———. 2009. A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge (Vol. 1). Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
———. 2015. Judgment and Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stanley, Jason. 2011. Know How. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stanley, Jason, and Timothy Williamson. 2001. ‘Knowing How’. Journal of Philosophy 98:411–
44.
———. 2017. ‘Skill’. Noûs 51 (4):713–726.
Sudduth, Michael. 2008. ‘Defeaters in Epistemology’. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
http://www.iep.utm.edu/ep-defea/.
Turri, John. 2011. ‘Manifest Failure: The Gettier Problem Solved’. Philosopher’s Imprint 11
(8):1–11.
Velleman, J. D. 2000. The Possibility of Practical Reason. USA: Oxford University Press.
Williams, John N. 2008. ‘Propositional Knowledge and Know-How’. Synthese 165 (1):107–
125.
Williamson, Timothy. 2015. ‘Acting on Knowledge’. Knowledge-First: Approaches in
Epistemology and Mind, Edited by J. Adam Carter, Emma Gordon, and Benjamin Jarvis.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, Forthcoming.
http://old.philosophy.ox.ac.uk/__data/assets/pdf_file/0005/35834/KfirstCarter.
pdf.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1969. On Certainty. Blackwell Oxford.
Zagzebski, Linda Trinkaus. 1996. Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and
the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge. Cambridge University Press.
25