Winter 1999
411
The Virtues of Stewardship
Jennifer Welchman*
What virtues do good stewards typically have and can these virtues move people
to be good stewards of nature? Why focus on the virtues of stewards rather than
on trying to construct and defend morally obligatory rules to govern human behavior?
I argue that benevolence and loyalty are crucial for good stewardship and these
virtues can and do motivate people to act as good stewards of nature. Moreover,
since it is a matter of dispute whether rational considerations can move us to
perform a given act in the absence of disposition to do so, I argue we should try to
determine which moral dispositions (if any) will motivate people to be concerned for
the environment so that the development of environmentally sensitive character
may be encouraged.
Where a passion is neither founded on false suppositions, nor chooses means
insufficient for the end, the understanding can neither justify nor condemn it. It is
not against reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching
of my finger.
—D AVID H UME1
I. INTRODUCTION
Much recent work in environmental ethics has aimed to construct and justify
nonanthropocentric theories of value2 that would make preservation of the
natural world morally obligatory.3 The ecocentric, biocentric, deep ecological,
and related theories produced vary in their normative content but generally
coincide in an “externalist” view of the relation of moral considerations to our
* Department of Philosophy, 4-108 Humanities Centre, University of Alberta, Canada T6G 2E5.
Welchman is the author of Dewey’s Ethical Theory (Ithaca:Cornell University Press, 1995).
1 David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2d ed. (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1978), p. 416 (emphasis added).
2 The term anthropocentric is sometimes used simply to indicate a human-centered point of
view (in parallel with terms such as ethnocentric and egocentric) which has the effect of making
human interests and values most prominent or striking. Some also use it in a narrower sense, to
indicate interests or commitments to benefit whatever one puts at the center of one’s point of
view, to the exclusion of others. I believe the former use is the more common and so follow it here
and propose speciesist as an alternative to cover the narrower category of preferences or
principled commitments to put human interests before those of other species.
3 On the desirability of developing such ethical theories/theories of value, see, e.g., Richard
Routley [Sylvan], “Is There a Need for a New, an Environmental Ethic?” Proceedings of the XV
World Congress of Philosophy, vol. 1 (1973): 205–10; Holmes Rolston, III, “Environmental
Ethics: Values in and Duties to the Natural World,” in F. Herbert Bormann and Stephen R. Kellert,
eds., The Broken Circle: Ecology, Economics, and Ethics (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1991); Arne Naess, “The Deep Ecological Movement: Some Philosophical Aspects, Philosophi411
412
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
Vol. 21
motivation to act upon them. That is, they generally agree that we will be
motivated to comply with a moral principle of action if it can be shown to be
justified by a defensible moral theory. It need not also be shown that there is
internal to our character some antecedent desire for or interest in whatever
conduct is being morally prescribed in order for us to act upon the prescription.4
Thus, to dissuade us from environmentally destructive practices, externalists seek
to develop defensible nonanthropocentric normative principles with which
those practices are inconsistent. Aldo Leopold is sometimes thought to have
advocated an externalist approach in calling for what he refers to as a “land
ethic [that] simply enlarges the boundaries of the community to include soils,
waters, plants, and animals, or collectively, the land.”5
But the externalist view of the relation of moral considerations to our motivation to act upon them is not universally accepted. Internalists, such as David
Hume, have held that theoretical justifications will not motivate an agent to act
independent of interests, wants, or needs internal to the agent’s character
whose satisfaction depends upon realizing the objectives of a given theory.
Consequently, internalists are more strongly inclined to approach a subject
such as human behavior toward the natural world via moral psychology, to
determine which dispositions appear to play the most significant roles in
shaping human responses to the environment in order to discover what sorts of
environmental policies we can be motivated to approve and adopt.
Internalist approaches to environmental ethics have generated less excitement thus far because the results they promise are necessarily more modest.
One can at least hope to contruct a defensible theory of value that would
generate normative principles making preservation of the natural world absolutely and universally morally obligatory. One cannot similarly hope to discover
human dispositions that can be expected absolutely and universally to motivate
humans to act to preserve nature. Thomas E. Hill, Jr.’s paper, “Ideals of Human
Excellence and the Natural Environment,”6 is perhaps the best-known example
cal Inquiry 8 (1983): 10–31; J. Baird Callicott, In Defense of the Land Ethic: Essays in Environmental Philosophy (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1989); Paul W. Taylor, Respect
for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986); Eric
Katz, Nature as Subject: Human Obligation and Natural Community (Lanham: Rowman and
Littlefield, 1997); and Laura Westra, “Why Norton’s Approach is Insufficient for Environmental
Ethics,” Environmental Ethics 19 (1997): 279–97.
4
This is a somewhat loose definition which I take to be adequate for the purpose at hand. For
a fuller discussion see, John Robertson and Michael Stocker, “Externalism and Internalism,” in
Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, eds., Encyclopedia of Ethics, vol. 1 (New York:
Garland Publishing, 1992), pp. 352–54.
5
Aldo Leopold, A Sand County Almanac, and Sketches Here and There, (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1987), p. 204. Interestingly, J. Baird Callicott has argued there are both internalist
and externalist dimensions to Leopold’s position. See his In Defense of the Land Ethic.
6
Thomas E. Hill, Jr., “Ideals of Human Excellence and Preserving Natural Environments,”
Environmental Ethics 5 (1983): 211–24.
Winter 1999
THE VIRTUES OF STEWARDSHIP
413
of such an approach. In this paper, Hill offers a thoughtful analysis of the
motivations underlying a decision to destroy a garden, and then argues that
these motivations are incompatible with other, virtuous dispositions that are
integral to any one’s social and personal projects. However, he necessarily
stops short of offering any universal condemnation of such an act as immoral.7
Hill’s results also illustrate what many take to be a second unfortunate consequence of internalist approaches to environmental ethics: that they will yield
at most an enlightened anthropocentricism. If we are to accept the testimony
of human history, we are characteristically (in descending order) egocentric,
ethnocentric, and anthropocentric in our dispositions to act. Of course, we are
not exclusively egoistic nor ethnocentric. Moreover, we are capable of giving
serious consideration to the interests of at least some other species. However,
the more distant the benefits are of the sacrifices we must first make, the more
difficult it is to engage interests or sympathies that will move us to make those
sacrifices.8 As Mark Sagoff once remarked of himself, “I have an Ecology Now
sticker on the bumper of a car that leaks oil everywhere it’s parked.”9 Largescale environmental problems such as global warming, loss of biodiversity,
and depletion of nonrenewable resources can be resolved only by long-term
commitments by individuals who cannot expect any direct benefit to themselves or their communities as a result. If we are to rise to these sorts of
challenges, one may ask, will enlightened anthropocentrism be enough? Is
enlightened anthropocentrism sufficient to make us effective stewards of the
natural world?
Following Hume, my answer is that it had better be, because I do not believe
that we can be motivated to act to preserve values fundamentally inconsistent
with our predominant dispositions to action. No amount of argumentation,
however well intentioned, will move people to act for the sake of “values”
about which they do not care. Since the externalist/internalist debate is a matter
for metaethics, I do not attempt to defend my allegiance here. For the moment,
7 Of course, Hill’s paper is the not only contribution. For some more recent examples, see
Geoffrey B. Frasz, “Environmental Virtue Ethics: A New Direction for Environmental Ethics,”
Environmental Ethics 15 (1993): 259–74; Philip Cafaro, “Thoreauvian Patriotism as an Environmental Virtue,” Philosophy in the Contemporary World 2 (1995): 1–7; Bill Shaw, “A Virtue Ethics
Approach to Aldo Leopold’s Land Ethic,” Environmental Ethics 19 (1997): 53–67.
8 Recently, it has been suggested that we may find healthy environmental conditions agreeable
for their own sake. While no one could argue that people find environments, healthy and unhealthy,
aesthetically pleasing, it is a matter of great controversy whether we have a propensity to find
healthy environments inherently agreeable. The testimony of human history does not appear to
support the suggestion. Consequently, I do not follow up such suggestions in this paper. For a
sympathetic critique, see Ernest Partridge, “Ecological Morality and Nonmoral Sentiments,”
Environmental Ethics 18 (1996): 149–63.
9 Mark Sagoff, “At the Shrine of Our Lady of Fatima, or Why Political Questions are not All
Economic,” Arizona Law Review 23 (1981): 1283–98, reprinted in James P. Sterba, ed., Earth
Ethics (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall, 1995), p. 374.
414
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
Vol. 21
I simply note that in a world where many have yet to adopt and act upon widely
promulgated and well-defended theories of universal human rights, equality,
and universal duties of impartiality and justice, to throw all one’s efforts into
the development of newer and better normative principles would be misguided.
We need to balance such research with careful attention to resources traditional
human-centered virtues of character may yet provide for the motivation of
environmentally responsible behavior.
My discussion here is intended to be a contribution to the small but growing
field of environmental virtue ethics. In environmental ethics (as in recent ethics
generally), virtue ethics is regularly taken to be synonymous with Aristotelian
eudaimonism—i.e., the theory that evaluates human character and habits of
action by their contribution to the agent’s achievement of eudaimonia through
the realization of his or her unique human telos or end. If there is a unique
human telos on which our realization of the good life depends, then the problem
of our motivation to act as morality requires is resolved. But is there a human
telos? How can we know what it is or whether specific dispositions to action,
say concern for nature, are among the dispositions through which we can
realize our telos? The difficulty of answering such questions encouraged later
theorists to develop means of evaluating human dispositions without reference
to such a standard. Hume is one of this group.
Virtues, Hume held,10 are those dispositions to action that are either useful
or agreeable in themselves to human beings. A virtue ethics approach to
questions of whether we should preserve natural landscapes or biodiversity,
conducted on Humean lines, examines what could motivate us to preserve
nature and whether the dispositions involved are likely to be generally approved as inherently agreeable or agreeable for their utility in serving human
desires for happiness, peace, security, beauty, and so forth. In other words, we
would want to know what (if anything) motivates people to function effectively
as voluntary stewards of the natural world. Thus, the dispositions in which I am
interested are those that typically dispose us voluntarily to act as stewards of
the natural world in our species’ long-run interests in the preservation of natural
beauty, biodiversity, renewable and nonrenewable resources, and so forth.
In what follows, I discuss loyalty and benevolence, two traditionally virtuous dispositions that seem central to the character of stewards. In order to assess
the extent to which these dispositions can motivate us to sacrifice personal
convenience to preserve the environment, I test these virtues in a type of “last
man” scenario (discussed below). I argue that even in such an extreme situation,
an individual whose stewardship of nature is grounded in enlightened anthropocentrism could be morally motivated to resist the destruction of the world. I
do not claim that the virtues involved are always sufficient to lead people to
behave in environmentally friendly ways. However, I believe they are suffi10 This definition of virtue is developed in Hume’s An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of
Morals, ed. J. B. Schneewind (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983).
Winter 1999
THE VIRTUES OF STEWARDSHIP
415
cient, when coupled with the right background information and experiences, to
lead most people to devote more than nominal concern and attention to environmental preservation. Thus, encouraging the development of such virtues should
be among the objectives of anyone interested in the development of environmentally responsible moral character.
II. STEWARDSHIP
One swallow does not make a summer, nor one act a steward. Stewardship is
a social role individuals adopt toward some other, a role sustained over time. To
be a steward is to devote a substantial percentage of one’s thoughts and efforts
to maintaining or enhancing the condition of some thing(s) or person(s), not
primarily for the steward’s own sake. What stewards care for may or not be the
person or institution they steward. Museum curators are stewards preserving
historical or art objects for the public good; regents are stewards of kingdoms
administered for their monarchs, while parents are stewards of children reared
for their own sake. Environmental stewards would be persons who consistently
devote a substantial amount of thought and effort to preserving the natural
world, not primarily for their own benefit. They may or may not be paid for
some of the actions they undertake. Being paid should not bar us from seeing
them as stewards of nature so long as their salaries are not their primary or only
incentive, and their environmental concern is not limited to their working hours.
To be capable of appointing oneself and functioning as a steward in this
sense, one would seem to need a character strongly marked by dispositions to
benevolence or loyalty or both. Stewards may be motivated by future-oriented
or backward-looking motivations in different cases. For example, an abandoned kitten at my door may stimulate a benevolent stewardship of the animal.
The death of a colleague, on the other hand, provides an opportunity for an
expression of loyalty to shared commitments, which may result in stewardship
of her posthumous papers or literary legacy. Other situations prompt stewardship motivated by both sorts of dispositions. Children, for instance, invite both
benevolent and loyal stewardship of their development and well-being. To be
a good steward, one also needs a host of other virtues, such as patience, selfdiscipline, courage, and/or thrift. No one could be a good steward who lacked
any of these other virtues. But no one would be a steward who had only these
virtues. To willingly act as steward for another one must care about the person(s)
whose interests are thus served. In what follows, I focus on the virtues of
benevolence and loyalty, which I take to be central to the character of most
willing stewards.11
Why bother, a critic may ask, since environmental stewardship motivated by
11 I do not deny that some other traditional virtues can motivate individuals to act as stewards
of things or persons on another’s behalf in particular cases. Respect for the purposes or labors of
a divine Creator where this respect is distinct from benevolence toward such a being or loyalty
416
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
Vol. 21
such human-centered virtues will inevitably prove incapable of motivating the
sort of large-scale environmental actions needed to preserve what remains of
the natural world? To illustrate, the critic might use a sort of latter-day version
of Hume’s example quoted above. If for an anthropocentrist such as Hume,
virtues are dispositions valued for their agreeableness or utility to persons, then
causing the destruction of the world is not against reason or virtue, so long as
no person is harmed thereby. Imagine that a series of natural catastrophes has
struck the human race, reducing it to a single individual—a last man.12 Unwilling
to permit lower species to inherit the Earth, he plans to annihilate the remaining
biosphere with the aid of nuclear weapons now at his disposal. Would it be
inconsistent with the anthropocentric virtues of an environmental steward to
destroy the world? No, the critic will argue. Yet such an act is surely immoral
whether or not human interests are significantly affected. Because enlightened
anthropocentrism cannot explain or justify our condemnation of the last man’s
act, enlightened anthropocentrism and its virtues must be rejected as a basis for
environmentally responsible moral agency.
This rejection would be a rather abrupt dismissal of a virtue that has probably
motivated more ordinary people to lobby, vote, organize for, and otherwise
support environmental preservation than any other. Benevolent interest in our
own descendants is a powerful motivator—one to which politicians and
lobbyists are quick to appeal, when possible, in support of policy initiatives
designed to maintain or improve environmental quality. Still, the critic has a
point. The last man scenario has its analogies in our own lives. Rare species
whose loss are unlikely to affect future generations are threatened with
extinction. Uniquely beautiful river vistas, which our descendants may not
even know have been lost, are threatened with destruction to provide reservoirs
and hydroelectric plants for existing human beings. Benevolence to our kind
does not provide us with strong incentives to oppose such changes to our environment. If, nonetheless, we are strongly inclined to oppose them, we will have to
appeal to dispositions other than benevolence for an explanation.
Of course, a merely benevolent steward could find destruction of the biosphere
distasteful on account of the suffering caused to other sentient creatures in the
process. Benevolence moves us to concern ourselves with the pains and pleasures
of others. Since these experiences are not restricted to human beings, a benevolent last man could be strongly moved to spare the biosphere. However, the
critic can revise the scenario to strengthen the case against benevolence by
stipulating that the catastrophes responsible for human extinction have also
to the being’s ideals, values, or purposes is perhaps the most compelling example of such a
disposition. Because I consider in general the secular moral virtues of benevolence and loyalty
typically to be the predominantly compelling virtues, I focus on them.
12 Traditionally, the “last” individual in these scenarios is male (see Routley, “Is There a Need
for a New, an Environmental Ethic?”). There is, moreover, a practical reason for following tradition—
it neatly precludes the possibility of pregnancy.
Winter 1999
THE VIRTUES OF STEWARDSHIP
417
annihilated all other forms of vertebrate and higher invertebrate life. The last
man’s destruction of the biosphere would thus have no impact upon any sentient
creature other than himself. Again, we must look beyond benevolence if we are
to explain our repugnance for seeing the biosphere go bang.
Fortunately for the biosphere, stewards are often stewards out of loyalty as
well as benevolence. For individuals voluntarily assuming the role of a steward
of nature out of loyalty, the existence or nonexistence of future generations
does not determine whether or not that stewardship can meaningfully continue.
Loyalty, unlike benevolence, is not an inherently forward-looking disposition.
That is, it is not the objective of loyalty to alter current or future human affairs
for the better. Loyalty is backward looking, a response to the past behavior of
others.
III. LOYAL STEWARDSHIP
Loyalty, like gratitude, is a virtue of beneficiaries. Loyalty may be distinguished from gratitude by the nature of the services that regularly prompt
loyalty in response. I may be grateful for a loan, for a lifesaving organtransplant, or for friendly forbearance of my less likeable habits. But I am not
likely to be loyal to my bank manager, my doctor, or my colleagues unless other
conditions besides the receipt of a favor are also met. A clue to the nature of
those further conditions may be found in the language we use to describe our
relation to individuals, groups, or institutions to whom or which we are loyal.
Loyal agents are frequently described and self-described as identifying with
those to whom they are loyal. This talk indicates the peculiar kind of service
for which loyalty is the response—service to the formation of our characters,
central life projects, or if you will, our identities. Our personal identities take
shape through the emulation of and identification with the ideals, practices,
values, and character of others. Loyalty is the acknowledgment of such a
continuing gift. We are (or should be) loyal to those who have served as our
templates—for it is by our identification with and participation in their practices
and projects that we have developed the character traits and values in which we
take pride.13 So understood, loyalty is integral to one’s moral integrity. Disloyalty, by contrast, always imperils personal integrity by its false accounting of our
most significant relationships, a false accounting which involves self-deception in its least malign forms, cruelty in its worst.
We each have many loyalties that sometimes conflict. In this respect, loyalty
is no different from benevolence or charity. If, to take an old example, I must
choose whether to betray my country or my friend (assuming it is somehow
merely a question of loyalty), then the greater loyalty will go to the one to
13 Moral lessons learned from negative example of others do not involve identification with or
loyalty to the person providing the negative example. Thus, they do not give rise to loyalty.
418
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
Vol. 21
whom I owe the most for the personal values, goals, or ideals I now hold dear.14
It should not be surprising that the varying life experiences of different persons
lead them to different resolutions of such a problem.
That there will be no future generations of human life is no obstacle to a last
man’s stewardship of the natural world, if he had appointed himself to the role
at least partly from loyalty. Loyalties often dispose us to look out for future
generations—though not primarily out of a benevolent interest in their welfare
but as a means of responding to our benefactors. For example, many of us keep
inherited books, keepsakes, or toys to pass on to our children or grandchildren.
We are not merely being thrifty when we do. We preserve these objects out of
loyalty to individuals and communities through identification with which our
values, virtues, and ideals have been formed—with the intention of using these
objects to influence the characters of our progeny.
Through such objects, we give a variety of expressions to our loyalties. We
keep their previous owners and their characters fresh in our minds, reinforcing
our identification with them, helping to maintain the integrity of our characters. In addition, we extend the influence of those to whom we are loyal to
another generation. With these objects, we recreate our predecessors’ rituals,
retell their tales, or recount their doings. By these means, we seek to make their
characters, their rituals, and their values real and accessible to our descendants
or students.
However, even if we never had nor ever could have descendants, and even
if our own identification with our predecessors’ traits, values, or ideals could
not benefit from reinforcement, our preservation of those objects could still be
a meaningful expression of loyalty. The acknowledgment that loyalty moves
us to give of another person’s or group’s contributions to our characters need
not involve third parties. It is enough if we act in such a way as to indicate our
ongoing appreciation of the peculiar service we have received. Perhaps the best
and most consistent way to acknowledge shared values, shared commitments,
or shared ideals is to continue with them even after those with whom we shared
them are gone.
For many of us, natural landscapes are chief among the relics through which
we honor and renew our identification with past generations and attempt to
extend their influence into the future. For most of us, walks in the woods or
along the coast, bird-watching, berry-picking, camping, fishing, hunting, and
other such experiences with friends and family have been rituals or practices
through which important values were enacted or illustrated for us, as well as
supplying opportunities to share in and emulate those rituals, practices, and
14 Consequently, I find it difficult to believe that the supposed hobgoblin of arguments for
loyalty, the “loyal Nazi” really poses a serious threat. I do not believe that a Nazi’s reprehensible
actions undertaken in the name of party loyalty can be justified by that appeal, since it is unlikely
that any individual Nazi can have owed more to the party than to the many institutions and persons
which the party threatened.
Winter 1999
THE VIRTUES OF STEWARDSHIP
419
values. As parents, grandparents, aunts, or friends, we seek out the same sorts
of locales in which to recreate these experiences for our own children, friends,
or other loved ones. Loyalty to those who have taught us in and through such
natural landscapes, entities, and processes makes us desire their preservation
and deplore their degradation.
Moreover, the predecessors in whose memory we preserve a natural landscape
need not be directly related to us. They may be members of distant generations
responsible for establishing our culture or distinctive ways of life. As Leopold
notes, “the rich diversity of the world’s cultures reflects a corresponding diversity
in the wilds that gave them birth.”15 On these grounds, Leopold argues for the
preservation of portions of the American prairie and other relatively “natural”
areas as a living, interactive memorial to honor the courage, hardiness, and
other pioneering virtues of earlier inhabitants—“for the edification of those
who one day may wish to see, feel, or study the origins of their cultural
inheritance” or who wish others to be able to do so.16 In “Wildlife in American
Culture,” Leopold writes, “there is value in any experience, that reminds us of
our distinctive national origins and evolution, i.e. that stimulates awareness of
history. Such awareness is nationalism in its best sense.”17 North Americans
(whether of European, Asian, African, or native descent) need wilderness, he
thought, to imaginatively recreate or reinforce the more desirable cultural
legacies of the past. Loss of the opportunity for such experiences will not
prevent people from trying to have them, but will distort the lessons learned.
Using hunting as an example of a way individuals may try to rehearse their
predecessors’ thrift, self-reliance, and sensitivity to their environments, Leopold
demonstrates how distortions can arise.
Consider the duck hunter, sitting in a steel boat behind composition decoys. A
put-put motor has brought him to the blind without exercise. Canned heat stands
by to warm him in case of a chilling wind. He talks to passing flocks on a factory
caller, in what he hopes are seductive tones; home lessons from a phonograph
record have taught him how the decoys work, despite the caller; a flock circles in.
It must be shot at before it circles twice, for the marsh bristles with other
sportsmen, similarly accoutered, who might shoot first. He opens up at 70 yards.
. . . The flock flares. A couple of cripples scale off to die elsewhere. Is this
sportsman absorbing cultural value? or is he just feeding minks?” 18
Cultures are adaptations to a group’s circumstances—especially its environment. Faithful transmission and reinvigoration of values and virtues across
generations requires the preservation of some of that natural landscape and its
fauna reasonably intact and not merely the conservation of recreational “green
15
16
17
18
Leopold, A Sand County Almanac, p. 188.
See “Wilderness,” in Leopold, A Sand County Almanac, pp. 188–200.
Leopold, A Sand County Almanac, p. 177.
Ibid., p. 180.
420
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
Vol. 21
spaces” denuded of their original features out of concern for modern sensibilities. Of course, since not everyone who identifies with and means to emulate
his or her predecessors’ virtues or values or ideals will take up duck hunting,
mountaineering, harvesting wild rice by hand, or spear fishing, places for these
activities need not be provided for all possible members of each generation.
However, enough must be preserved so that members of future generations
who wish can revisit and/or redescribe them in terms (or other media) that their
contemporaries can use to acknowledge and reinforce important cultural values.
If the last man had adopted the outlook of a steward upon the natural world
out of loyalty to values shared with family, friends, or the founders of his
culture, his impulse to deny other organisms the chance to “succeed” humanity
would not be unopposed by his other virtues. Loyalty would press for the
acknowledgment of shared commitments, ideals, and values, preferably by
continuing in them whenever possible, paying honor to them when it is not.
While the last man might (bizarrely) be loyal to others for their shared commitment to sheer destructiveness (in which case he would never have elected to act
as a steward of nature), it is unlikely that destruction of the biosphere would be
a reasonable way of continuing or honoring the values or projects of those to
whom his loyalties were directed. In such a situation, relatively few of the
projects and values one once shared with others can be sustained. Among those
which can are the practices and projects to which interaction with natural landscapes are integral—i.e., watching sunsets, camping, fishing, hiking, or harvesting wild rice by hand. Since the natural landscapes integral to those
activities include sentient life, loyalty would oppose the destruction of the
biosphere—just as in our own lives loyalty to our own predecessors often
stands in the way of the destruction of historic buildings, battlefields, and
groves.
Thus, the human-centered virtues integral to voluntary stewardship, benevolence and loyalty can motivate human beings with reasons to make sacrifices
of personal resources and convenience in order to preserve natural landscapes,
air and water quality, and biodiversity, for the sake of both future and past
generations. For individuals actually to see stewardship as an appropriate role
to adopt toward the natural world, extensive education in environmental processes
is needed. They must understand not only how current human management of the
natural world may effect their descendants quality of life, but also how specific
natural landscapes and natural events have shaped human history and human
traditions. At present in North America, little ecological science or history is
mandated as part of general education. Unless this situation changes, the
number of individuals who will voluntarily adopt the role of stewards of their
environments will be fewer than they could be or should be. But the problem,
from a Humean perspective, is not that people care too much for the welfare,
values, or fate of humanity. It is that they care too little, because they do not
understand how much care is needed. Thus, ignorance rather than anthropo-
Winter 1999
THE VIRTUES OF STEWARDSHIP
421
centrism is the obstacle. It impossible for environmentally responsible conduct to
occur without improved understanding of the fragility of natural systems and
processes and the importance of maintaining them for human cultural and
physical survival.
IV. OBJECTIONS
A number of objections may be raised to the suggestions I have made. First,
it may be argued that even if individuals were educated so as to encourage
benevolent and loyal stewardship of nature, the results would fall short of what
we should desire. There are rare species and isolated ecosystems that have
played no important role in any existing culture’s development and whose loss
is unlikely to affect the welfare of any future generation. Merely enlightened
anthropocentrists could tolerate their destruction out of a benevolent concern
for the well-being of existing human beings or their near descendants. Second,
it may be argued that, overall, loyalty is a vice rather than a virtue in human
affairs. Because it is not consistent with anthropocentrism to encourage character
traits that reduce human flourishing by promoting disagreement and disorder,
they should not encourage loyal as well as benevolent stewardship of nature.
Concerning the first objection, I agree that inculcating the virtues central to
stewardship together with the environmental understanding required to motivate stewardship of nature will not preclude the adoption of policies destructive of or deleterious to wildlife or landscapes. As one who aspires to no more
than enlightened anthropocentrism, I am, of course, unapologetic about this point.
If species or entities about which virtually no one cares, has cared, or are ever
likely to care can be saved from extinction only by demanding enormous
sacrifices of things for which many people have cared, do care, and will continue
to care, then we can and perhaps must permit their destruction. As a rule,
uncertainty about our understanding of the natural systems involved favors
preservation. However, in those instances where both our certainty and the
costs are very high, I cannot see why we must accept the costs.
The second objection raises more complicated issues. First, some would
argue that loyalty is simply another name for ethnocentrism, an uncritical
prejudice in favor of one’s own group’s or culture’s practices. Ethnocentrism
has often proved disadvantageous by complicating relations between societies
and between groups within multicultural societies, to the detriment of social
order and cooperation. Thus, loyalty is not a virtue but a vice. Second, others
have argued that loyalty is inherently exploitive. For example, Marcia Baron
has remarked, “one may wonder whether loyalty and related virtues are virtues
only in the context of . . . hierarchical role relationships, for example, a society
in which a wife is to serve her husband, a servant is to serve his or her master,
and so on. (It is noteworthy that while the loyalty of dogs . . . [and] of servants
. . . is extolled, we almost never hear of a master being praised for his loyalty
422
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
Vol. 21
to his dog or to his servant).”19 On this view, loyalty is an acknowledgment of
restraint shown by moral and/or social superiors toward inferiors—which reason
can show to be irrational, since the inferiors’ interests would invariably be
better served by rejection of hierarchical social arrangements. Thus, loyalty
decreases utility for the loyal agent and his or her kind.
To the first of these two attacks on the utility of loyalty, I argue that as we have
seen, loyalty need not be construed as a mere sentimental attachment to the
familiar. If someone demands loyal behavior from us, we expect that person to
have something more to appeal for support than mere familiarity. He or she
must be able to point to something he or she has done for us. Family relationships, for example, engender loyalty not because family members are familiar
but because they exchange services and share values. Community loyalties
arise in a similar fashion. Thus, we need not assume that loyalty is merely an
uncalculating prejudice in favor of our own traditional tastes or practices.
The second attack has a certain foundation in past usage which cannot be
denied. Throughout Western history the relation of benefactor to beneficiary
has overlapped with and indeed been conflated with the relationships of
superior to inferior. Thus, we find philosophers as diverse as Aristotle 20 and
Kant21 recommending self-sufficiency to the would-be moral agent to avoid
the inferiority they each believed was implicit in the acceptance of favors. In
hierarchical societies, of course, the two sorts of relationships often went hand
in hand. Children, servants, and vassals typically received important benefits
from their parents, employers, and liege lords—who happened also to be their
social superiors. Thus, it is easy to make the mistake of supposing that loyalty
to parents, employers, and lords must be a response to their superior status. But
clearly, superiority that is never exercised to the benefit of others is neither
necessary nor sufficient to make its possessor an object of gratitude or loyalty.
The parent, employer, or lord must actually have done the child, servant, or
vassal some good. Loyalty, as defined above, reinforces benevolence, not
domination. Thus, members of cooperative communities, even multicultural
communities, have reason to value loyalty.
Even so, loyalties can be sources of disorder within communities. Multicultural societies are made up of individuals whose loyalties sometimes prove
incompatible or require mutually exclusive social practices. We must expect
that stewards of nature will sometimes be motivated by differing loyalties
which lead them to promote competing and incompatible environmental
19 Marcia Baron, “Loyalty,” in Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, eds., Encyclopedia of Ethics, vol. 2 (New York: Garland Publishing, 1992), p. 753. John Ladd offered a similar
view in “Loyalty,” in Paul Edwards, ed., Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 5 (New York: Macmillan,
1967), pp. 97–98.
20 See, e.g., Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Terence Irwin (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1985).
21 See, e.g., Immanuel Kant, Lectures on Ethics, trans. Louis Infield (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1980.)
Winter 1999
THE VIRTUES OF STEWARDSHIP
423
policies.22 Unless the projects in question rest on false beliefs either about the
services which the loyal agent is acknowledging or about the efficacy of the
means adopted to do so, it may be impossible to judge one, morally speaking,
either better or worse or more or less significant than the other. The only
solution will be a compromise between the parties by appeal to other or higher
loyalties or values. This solution, of course, does not distinguish loyalty from
other virtues such as charity or mercy, which may likewise cause individuals
to pursue competing and mutually exclusive charitable or merciful projects.
V. THE UPSHOT
In a response to critics who argue that novel theories of natural values are
unnecessary because more creative cost-accounting provides sufficient reasons for preserving natural resources, Leopold remarks, “when the logic of
history hungers for bread and we hand out a stone, we are at pains to explain
how much the stone resembles bread.”23 In trying to focus attention on the
potential of traditional human-centered virtues to motivate effective stewardship of the environments we inhabit, I am not trying to make a stone pass for
bread. I do not claim, for instance, that the development of a character strongly
marked by benevolence and loyalty will always be sufficient to motivate us to
care for nature. To those who believe both that we need to embrace nonanthropocentric principles of value if we are ever to respond adequately to human
threats to the environment and that theoretical justification of such principles
can move us to act upon them, what I have to offer is certainly not the loaf they
desire. But for the reasons given above, I do not consider this limitation to be
a fatal flaw in my approach.
I agree with Leopold that effective environmental stewardship of the natural
world cannot occur if we see it only as a resource for maximizing economic
gains. We need instead to develop a greater sensitivity to the noneconomic
needs, values, and interests that natural entities and environments serve if we
are to develop enduring commitments to preserve them. We need, in other
words, more and better stewards of the natural world. And to develop more and
better stewards we need a better understanding of how our own self-love and
love for our kind can supply the motivation necessary for us to make the
sacrifices involved.
22
23
The debate over how to manage feral pigs in Hawaii gives us an example of such phenomena.
Leopold, A Sand County Almanac, p. 210.