Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107
Contents lists available at ScienceDirect
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science
journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa
The metaphor of epigenesis: Kant, Blumenbach and Herder
Daniela Helbig a, Dalia Nassar b, *
a
b
Unit for the History and Philosophy of Science, The University of Sydney, NSW 2006, Australia
Philosophy Department, The University of Sydney, NSW 2006, Australia
a r t i c l e i n f o
a b s t r a c t
Article history:
Available online 6 July 2016
Over the last few decades, the meaning of the scientific theory of epigenesis and its significance for
Kant’s critical philosophy have become increasingly central questions. Most recently, scholars have
argued that epigenesis is a key factor in the development of Kant’s understanding of reason as selfgrounding and self-generating. Building on this work, our claim is that Kant appealed to not just any
epigenetic theory, but specifically Johann Friedrich Blumenbach’s account of generation, and that this
appeal must be understood not only in terms of self-organization, but also in terms of the demarcation of
a specific domain of inquiry: for Blumenbach, the study of life; for Kant, the study of reason. We argue
that Kant adopted this specific epigenetic model as a result of his dispute with Herder regarding the
independence of reason from nature. Blumenbach’s conception of epigenesis and his separation of a
domain of the living from the non-living lent Kant the tools to demarcate metaphysics, and to guard
reason against Herder’s attempts to naturalize it.
Ó 2016 Published by Elsevier Ltd.
Keywords:
Kant;
Epigenesis;
Metaphor;
Analogy;
Biology;
Blumenbach;
Herder;
Transcendental deduction
Over the last few decades, Kant’s interest in the life sciences and
the role of the life sciences in the development of his critical philosophy have attracted greater scholarly attention. One strand of
investigation, opened up by Timothy Lenoir in 1982, examines the
crucial role of the life sciences in the Critique of Judgment and the
influence of Kant’s views on the life sciences themselves.1 A second
strand has argued that key ideas from the life sciences played
pivotal roles in the development of Kant’s earlier writings, especially the Critique of Pure Reason.2 Kant’s interest in the competing
theories of generationdpreformation and epigenesisdis regarded
as an especially significant interpretative tool for understanding the
origin, meaning, and role of the pure concepts of the understanding. Thus, Kant’s statements about the “birth place” of the pure
concepts, and his correlative use of terms such as Keime (seeds) and
Anlagen (predispositions)3 to describe their development, have led
some interpreters to suggest that Kant used the preformationist
model of generation in order to explicate the generation of the pure
* Corresponding author.
E-mail addresses:
[email protected] (D. Helbig), dalia.nassar@sydney.
edu.au (D. Nassar).
1
Lenoir (1982).
2
See Sloan (2002), Zöller (1988), and especially Mensch (2013), whose booklength study of the topic of epigenesis in the pre-critical writings and the first
Critique has generated new interest in Kant’s use of the term.
3
Kant (1781/1787), A66/B90-91.
4
Sloan (2002).
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2016.05.003
0039-3681/Ó 2016 Published by Elsevier Ltd.
concepts of the understanding.4 In the second edition of the
Critique of Pure Reason, however, Kant adds that the legitimacy of
the categories can only be established by thinking of them in terms
of “a system of the epigenesis of pure reason.”5 Accordingly, other
commentators have claimed that by 1787 Kant rejected the metaphor of preformation, and instead introduced that of epigenesis to
explicate the non-empirical and non-arbitrary character of the
categories.6
While the disagreement over Kant’s favored biological model is
explicit, his metaphorical use of these models in the context of the
generation of the pure concepts of the understanding has gone
largely unproblematized. According to Phillip Sloan, biological
models of explanation “ground”7 Kant’s cognitive theory; they
constitute its “scientific foundation.”8 Taking the primacy of scientific investigation as a given, Sloan sees Kant as altering his
theory of reason when this foundation shifts. Günter Zöller, by
contrast, regards the purpose of the use of the terms preformation
and epigenesis as more decorative than functional: doctrines of
5
Kant (1781/1787), B167.
This is the key claim made by Zöller (1988). Although Mensch (2013) agrees
with Zöller’s understanding of the significance of the metaphor of epigenesis, she
demonstrates that Kant’s turn to epigenesis came much earlier than 1787. She does
not, however, explicitly address the question of whether there was a transition in
Kant’s thinking between 1781 and 1787.
7
Sloan (2002), 22.
8
Sloan (2002), 24.
6
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107
reason are “illustrate[d] by means of an analogy,” or “figuratively
represented” by them.9 Neither approach, however, captures the
significance of the appearance of language borrowed from the life
sciences in crucial parts of the Critique of Pure Reason, whether in
the Transcendental Analytic or the Transcendental Deduction.
The first aim of this paper is to clarify the role of the metaphors
of generation in the critical philosophy. We argue that Kant’s 1787
reference is to a specific epigenetic theory, that of Johann Friedrich
Blumenbach rather than Caspar Friedrich Wolff, and that its
metaphorical use in the context of Kant’s theory of cognition carries
wider programmatic connotations, which cannot be grasped by
taking the analogy with biological generation to be either a naturalistic blueprint, or a mere illustration. Blumenbach’s vitalistic
theory of epigenesis, and its central notion of Bildungstrieb, functioned as one of the emerging demarcations of the subject area of
the life sciences, thereby clearly distinguishing it from the physical
sciences. In various contexts, Kant warned against the confusion of
the problems of metaphysics with those of the special sciences, and
he had a keen interest in mapping the boundaries of those special
disciplines.10 His use of Blumenbach’s theory as a metaphor in the
context of his conception of reason must therefore be understood
not simply in terms of the self-organization or spontaneity of
reason,11 but also in terms of the demarcation of a specific domain
of inquiry: for Blumenbach, that of the study of life; for Kant, that of
the study of reason.
More specifically, we argue that Kant introduced the metaphor
of epigenesis into his theory of reason in 1787 as a result of his
dispute with Herder about the independence of reason from nature,
followed by his explicit adoption of epigenesis as a scientific theory
of generation in the Critique of Judgment in 1790. Blumenbach’s
separation of a domain of the living from the non-living in terms of
his notion of Bildungstrieb lent Kant the conceptual tools by which
to demarcate metaphysics as the study of reason, and thus to guard
the domain of reason against Herder’s attempts to naturalize it. We
show that it was following his review of Herder’s Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit (1784e5) that Kant felt the
need to emphasize both the independence of reason from nature
and the distinctiveness of the study of reason from the study of
nature, i.e., to distinguish reason as an object that cannot be studied
by means of the natural sciences or anthropology. It was on account
of this, we contend, that the specific articulation of epigenesis put
forward by Blumenbach became central in the second edition of the
first Critique.
Our re-contextualization of Kant’s employment of the metaphor
of epigenesis does not, however, imply that he did not make critical
use of the term in the Transcendental Deduction. Rather, and in
concert with research that draws on the idea of epigenesis to understand the activity of reason, we argue that by comparing Kant’s
first published use of the termdin his review of Herder’s Ideendwith the parenthetical remark he makes in the Deduction, it becomes clear that the “epigenesis of pure reason” involves the
limitation of what is and what is not possible in experience, analogous to the limitation that Kant regards as necessary in natural
generation, and which he formulates in response to Herder. It is
through the notion of epigenesis as a form of limitation (on possible
9
Zöller (1988), 88.
As Kant puts it in his essay on the use of teleological judgment: “I have become
totally convinced that through the mere separation of what is heterogeneous and
what previously had been left in a mixed state, often a new light is cast upon the
science . which opens up many authentic sources of cognition where one would
not at all have expected them .” (Kant (1788), AA 8, 162). The aim of the scientist,
he continues, must be to challenge “the carelessness of letting the boundaries of the
sciences run into each other.”
11
Zöller (1988); Mensch (2013).
10
99
experience, on natural development) that the metaphor can be
regarded as playing a crucial role in the Transcendental
Deduction.12
Our aims are thus twofold. In the first instance, we seek to offer a
new perspective on Kant’s interest in Blumenbach, via Herder, and
to show how Kant’s use of biological metaphors should be understood neither as naturalistically nor as illustratively, but as both a
reflection and instrumentalization of emerging disciplinary distinctions in the natural sciences. In the second, we suggest a new
way by which the metaphor of epigenesis can help us to better
understand the Transcendental Deduction. Our reinterpretation is
based on a clear distinction between Wolff’s and Blumenbach’s
versions of epigenesis. On that basis, Kant’s use of epigenesis to
describe his conception of the mind speaks not only to the
deduction of the categories, but also to long-standing questions
regarding Kant’s understanding of the unity of reason.
1. Kant on scientific theories of generation prior to the
Critique of Pure Reason
Long before his much-cited endorsement of Blumenbach’s
formulation of an epigenetic theory, Kant occasionally discussed
the competing theories of generation, epigenesis and preformation.
However, these discussions occur in a number of different contexts.
They weigh the various problems Kant sees with both of the theories, but their primary goal is neither to espouse one theory over
the other as a scientific explanation of the generation of living
beings, nor to use them metaphorically to explicate problems
outside the life sciences.13 Against this background, the shift in the
Critique of Judgment in 1790 is significant. In this latter work, Kant
explicitly distinguishes two different contexts in which theories of
generation are relevant to him, and endorses epigenesis in both.
Firstly, he declares Blumenbach’s epigenetic theory to provide an
appropriate scientific explanation for generation, having a “great
advantage . on experiential grounds” over preformation.14 Secondly, Kant emphasizes the theory’s cognitive appeal in stating that
reason is “favorably disposed to this [epigenetic] explanation.” This
second aspect is independent of the first. It would hold “even if one
did not recognize” the alleged experiential superiority.15
The endorsement of a specific explanatory model in the life
sciences thus coincides with a claim about reason’s dispositions. A
brief review of Kant’s discussion of epigenetic and preformationist
theories in the years leading up to the use of metaphors of generation in the Transcendental Analytic at A66/B90-1 may serve to
demonstrate the absence of his commitment to either theory as a
scientific explanation of generation. Such a commitment only
comes, as we will argue, when it coincides with a specific rearticulation of the role of reason in Kant’s systematic philosophy.
Kant discusses the generation of plants and animals as early as
1763 in The Only Possible Argument in Support of a Demonstration of
the Existence of God. Here he distinguishes broadly between a view
12
We thus aim to elaborate and expand upon the work of Zöller (1988) and
Mensch (2013) on the significance of the notion of epigenesis for the Transcendental Deduction.
13
Our conclusion is in line with Reinhard Löw’s, who argues that Kant “did not
take a consistent position on these questions” (Löw, 1980, 168). In particular, we
agree with his problematisation of Kant’s endorsement of epigenesis. However, our
intention here is different from Löw’s: we do not seek to determine Kant’s position
regarding epigenesis and preformation, but to emphasize that he saw no need to
take such a position on the problem of generation as a scientific problem prior to
1790.
14
Kant (1790), AA 5, 424.
15
Kant (1790), AA 5, 424. See McLaughlin’s (1982) critical contextualization of this
claim, placing it in the context of bourgeois theories of society in the 17th and 18th
centuries (371).
100
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107
of ontogeny as the quantitative evolution (Auswickelung) of a supernaturally given form, and a view which grants individuals the
capacity of qualitatively generating rather than merely unfolding
their structural form.16 Although Kant does not name them as such,
the former view corresponds to the theory of preformation, prevailing through the first half of the 18th century and prominently
represented by Albrecht von Haller and Charles Bonnet.17 The latter
view can, in turn, be described as “epigenetic,” and its first 18thcentury representative was Caspar Friedrich Wolff (whom Kant
does not mention). It was, however, preceded by antipreformationist views as articulated by Pierre Louis de Maupertuis, and the Comte de Buffon (whom Kant does mention).18
Both preformationist and anti-preformationist views, Kant
contends, are deeply problematic in that they each contain an
arbitrary (willkürlich) element.19 He finds sarcastic words for both.
The arbitrariness of preformation consists in positing a supernatural origin of generation instead of admitting that this origin might
be scientifically explicable. Kant mocks this move by invoking the
reproduction of yeast: while as equally ill-understood as the
problem of explaining higher organisms, this problem does not
seem to prompt any explanatory recourse to alleged supernatural
causes. Buffon’s and Maupertuis’s non-preformationist theories, in
contrast, do not posit any such supernatural origins, but they too
contain arbitrary elements. Kant locates these in the attempts to
counter the difficulties in accounting for the origin of qualitatively
new structure according to mechanical laws. Maupertuis addresses
the problem of generating structure by the introduction of attractive forces and particles in the seminal fluid of the parents, whereas
Buffon posits the existence of a so-called moule intérieure, or internal mould, responsible for the formation of the newly generating
body. Kant criticizes both in one and the same breath, suggesting
that “the inner forms of Herr Buffon, which self-assemble according
to the opinion of Herr von Maupertuis”, are “either as incomprehensible as the thing itself, or [.] arbitrary inventions.”20
Thus facing a choice between preformation as a theory of supernaturally given, and anti-preformationism as a theory of arbitrarily invented form, Kant concludes that “it is perhaps impossible
to make out which difficulty is the greatest.”21 He is perfectly
explicit in stating the point of his discussion of the two theories of
generation: not to endorse one of them over the other as a scientific
(naturphilosophische) theory, but to sort out the “weightier metaphysical reasons” at stake in deciding between them.22 The
weightier reason for him, unsurprisingly, is to avoid any recourse to
the supernatural in the philosophy of nature.
However, this does not amount to an endorsement of the specific anti-preformationist theories of Maupertuis and Buffon, which
he has just ridiculed. Instead, it is a methodological demanddand
16
Kant (1763), AA 2, 114.
See Roe (1981), ch. 2, on Haller’s conversion from epigenesis to preformation in
the 1750s.
18
Kant’s omission of Wolff ’s name not just here but in any other of his writings
has been discussed at length; see Löw (1980), 176. Wolff and Blumenbach both
explicitly use the term ‘epigenesis’ to describe their respective, and different, theories (see below). Maupertuis and Buffon do not use this term, and it remains a
matter of debate whether or not it is appropriate to label their views as epigenetic.
Wolff and Blumenbach each postulate a force responsible for the generation of a
qualitatively new structure, whereas Buffon’s explanation of this new structure
relies on spatial arrangements of matter that preexist the newly generated organism. For Sloan (2002), this makes Maupertuis and Buffon “mechanistic” epigeneticists (6); for Mensch (2013), Buffon’s “internal mould” smells too strongly of
preformationism to count him among the epigeneticists (chapter 2).
19
Kant (1763), AA 2, 115.
20
Kant (1763), AA 2, 115.
21
Kant (1763), AA 2, 114.
22
Kant (1763), AA 2, 115.
17
only that, as Kant stressesdto rethink the possible action of forces
in living things23:
My intention here is only to show the necessity to grant the
things of nature more of a possibility than is commonly done to
produce their consequences according to general laws.24
It is worth noting that Wolff’s explicitly epigenetic theory (discussed below) in its reliance on a force, as opposed to Buffon’s and
Maupertuis’s anti-preformationist accounts, could bedalthough
Kant does not do sodinterpreted as an attempt to fulfill just such a
methodological demand in seeking to show how “general laws”
might account for the generation of high structural complexity.
In his first mention of the actual term ‘epigenesis’ in notes dated
1772e1776, Kant identifies it with the ‘organic’ as opposed to the
mechanical or chemical, and as such with the idea of an “an
animating spirit in plants and animals”:
The question is whether there is an organic formative nature
(epigenesis) or only one which produces form (bildet) mechanically and chemically. It seems: to that belongs a spirit
because of the unity of the relation of all parts, according to their
generation, to every single such part. But isn’t there a spiritually
animating essence in animals and plants too. In such a way one
would even have to assume an animating spirit in the primordial chaos in order to explain the various animals which can
now only reproduce.25
This usage of the term ‘epigenesis’ is sufficiently broad and yet
idiosyncratic to rule out the possibility that Kant is discussing the
contemporaneous epigenetic theory that had actually been put
forward by the time he was writing. Wolff ’s epigenetic Theoria
generationis from 1759 is decidedly anti-animistic in postulating a
vis essentialis that accounts for the structure of plants and animals
by the secretion of nutritive fluids; the functional unity of their
different parts is a by-product rather than the result of the action of
a soul or spirit.
If Kant’s usage of the term is not aligned with Wolff ’s, what
might his sources be? Maupertuis’s Systême de la nature. Essai sur la
formation des corps organisés (1751) claims the impossibility of accounting for an organism’s functional unity as a result of a “uniform
and blind force,” and posits a “principle of intelligence” to resolve
this problem, “similar to what we call desire, aversion, memory.”
However, and even if he may have left Kant unconvinced, Maupertuis insisted that there was a difference between his principle of
intelligence and an animating spirit in the sense of a “sensitive
soul.”26 Another potential source for Kant’s allusion to an animating
principle is Georg Ernst Stahl (from whom Wolff had distinguished
his views explicitly).27 In the Dreams of a spirit-seer, Kant had
defended Stahl’s “organic explanation” as being “often closer to the
truth” than
23
Thus we disagree with Claude Piché’s reading of this passage as an obvious
“adoption of the biological theory of epigenesis” (Piché [2001], 186). Firstly, we do
not see Kant endorsing the specific theories he sarcastically discusses as arbitrary;
we only see him arguing that bad non-preformationist theories are on safer
metaphysical grounds than preformationist ones. Secondly, applying the broad label ‘epigenetic’ to the specific non-preformationist theories Kant exposes here
erases the decisive difference with his later endorsement of Blumenbach’s epigenetic theory as based on not just a force, but a “drive”.
24
Kant (1763), AA 2, 115 (our translation).
25
Kant (1772e1776), AA 17, 591 (our translation).
26
Maupertuis (1984 [1751]), 146e147.
27
See Roe (1981), 109.
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107
. Hofmann, Boerhaave and others, who do not consider
immaterial forces, who stick to mechanical causes and in that,
follow a more philosophical method.28
Kant thus broadly aligns the term ‘epigenesis’ with an organic
process of formation that bears animistic connotations, and uses
the term to acknowledge the problem of the relation between the
organically formative on the one hand, and the mechanical on the
other. This is, however, neither a discussion of an actually existing
theory of epigenesis (Stahl did not offer such a theory), nor an
endorsement of the idiosyncratically animistic articulation of
epigenesis as a viable explanatory option in natural philosophy.
When he takes up the problem of epigenetic ontogeny again in
notes dated 1776e78, Kant still presents epigenesis as requiring the
assumption of a ‘soul’; however, this soul must understood as a
non-localized part of the intelligible world in order to avoid
animistic implications:
For epigenesis we have to assume that the soul belongs to the
intelligible world; that it does not have a location in space, that,
once an organized body has come into being through conception, it has in itself the condition to be ensouled (beseelt) by the
intelligible, vitalizing (belebend) principle; and that in this body
the soul is present not locally, but virtually.29
In his private remarks on Eberhard’s “Preparations for natural
theology,” and thus in a theological context, Kant discusses phylogeny rather than ontogeny with regard to the necessity of
assuming supernatural effects.30 Here, he now uses the term
‘epigenesis’ in a more conventional way:
The preservation of species can either be regarded as natural,
or it requires a supernatural influence. In the first case the
origin of species is to be regarded as natural too: for every
generation is to be regarded as a new origin insofar as there
are so many foreign causes which can modify or change the
formative force that, were it not for a counteracting principle
following general laws, the regularity of reproduction could
not be explained from a disposition once created. Particularly
if one assumes epigenesis.
A hypothetical endorsement of epigenesis thus renders a
natural origin of species more plausible insofar as the theory
purports to explain the generation of every single member of the
species as a renewed “origin” (Ursprung) without recourse to
supernatural causes, and thus provides a model for how the first
such origin could be conceived. Kant’s earlier metaphysical
argument in favor of non-preformationist theories is reiterated
here with explicit reference to epigenesis as a mode of explanation. And yet, this move only posits an epigenetic theory for
the sake of the theological argument, and does not amount to an
explicit espousal of epigenesis over other theories in the life
sciences.
By the late 1770s, then, Kant has publicly engaged with
epigenesis and preformation on a methodological meta-level, and
privately considers both the difficulties of epigenesis as an
explanatory strategy in ontogeny, and its phylogenetic implications.
However, when not working on a meta-level but engaging directly
and publicly with questions of phylogeny and heredity in his 1775
28
29
30
Kant (1766), AA 2, 331 (our translation).
Kant (1776e78), AA 18, 189/190.
Kant (1776e78), AA 18, 574.
101
“On the different human races,” Kant’s account of natural generation is a version of preformationism.31 The assumption of preformed germs (Keime) as well as predispositions (Anlagen) is the
only means, he argues, by which to explain both differences between species and heritable differences within species, i.e., adaptation. For insofar as “chance or general mechanical laws cannot
bring forth such adaptations,” e.g. to climate, it follows that
different species must have within them germs and natural predispositions which allow them both to maintain their species line
as well as adapt to new conditions.32 The original species is
equipped with the potential to adapt to any external condition, but
it is contingent upon these conditions which predisposition is
expressed (ausgewickelt). Sloan has characterized this view as a
combination of “preformation with environmentalism.”33
Against the background of these varied earlier discussions,
Kant’s usage of biological terms of generation in the 1781 edition of
the first Critique stands out as markedly different: in contrast to the
earlier methodological debates or attempts at developing a theory
of heredity, this usage is clearly metaphorical in character. Keime,
seeds, is the word Kant uses to describe both the generation of the
pure concepts of the understanding in the Transcendental Analytic,
and the development of the special sciences in the Architectonic of
Pure Reason.34 In the 1787 edition, Kant retains both passages, and
thus maintains the metaphorical vocabulary of categories as preformed seeds and dispositions, which develop on the occasion of
experience. However, in the Transcendental Deduction he adds a
competing metaphor from the life sciences: the now well-known
claim of the “epigenesis of pure reason.”35
Given this ambiguity within the B edition, it is perhaps not
surprising that commentators have reached contradictory answers
to the question which biological mode of explanation informs
Kant’s cognitive theory. After all, his many different earlier discussions of both epigenesis and preformation offer numerous
passages to support either argumentdtypically by emphasizing the
methodological support for epigenesis, or the usage of preformationism in the race essay, respectively.36 But it seems to us
that these arguments skate too lightly over the difference in context
and usage. Even if Kant had endorsed either theory as scientifically
superior prior to 1790, it would still remain unclear how an
endorsement of the scientific theory affects its metaphorical usage
in the theory of cognition. However, we have no such endorsement.
Furthermore, such a discussion does not do justice to Kant’s use of
biological language outside of its original context. To understand
what makes Kant’s employment of the metaphor of epigenesis
poignant, we turn to its usage in the contemporaneous life sciences
and to Kant’s first published discussion of the term in his review of
Herder.
31
McLaughlin (2007).
Kant (1775), AA 2, 435.
33
Sloan (2002), 240.
34
Thus, the aim of the Transcendental Analytic is “to pursue the pure concepts
into their first seeds (Keime) and predispositions (Anlagen) in the human understanding, where they lie ready (vorbereitet), until with the opportunity of experience, they are developed (entwickelt) and exhibited in their clarity by the very same
understanding liberated from empirical conditions attaching to them” (Kant (1781/
1787), A66/B91). And in the Architectonic: “No one attempts to bring about a science without a grounding idea for that science. However, in elaborating that idea
the schema, even the definition given to that science initially, rarely ever corresponds to that idea; because it lies like a seed (Keim) in reason, a seed in which all
parts are still very much wrapped up (eingewickelt) and lie hidden barely accessible
to microscopic observation” (Kant (1781/1787), B861; our translation).
35
Kant (1781/1787), B167.
36
Sloan (2002) and Zöller (1988), respectively.
32
102
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107
2. Blumenbach: Bildungstrieb and generic preformation
Both in his oft-cited letter from August 1790 to Blumenbach, and
in x81 of the Critique of Judgment, Kant singles out a specific
formulation among the broad field of theories associated with the
label “epigenesis.” In doing so, he draws explicit attention to the
difference between Blumenbach’s concept of Bildungstrieb and a
mere formative force, Bildungskraft. What is the nature of this
distinction, which was drawn in the 1789 revised edition of Über
den Bildungstrieb und das Zeugungsgeschäft, but can be traced back
to Blumenbach’s earliest writings on the same topic in 1781?
From the very first treatises on the Bildungstrieb in 1780 and
1781, Blumenbach had emphasized the difference between his new
concept of a “formative drive” and “all other forces of nature,”
stating as his result
that there lies within all living creatures from human beings
down to the maggot, from the cedar to mold, a special, innate
drive that remains active through their lifetime, initially to make
them take their shape, then to retain it, and, if possible, to
restore this shape when destroyed. A drive (or tendency or
striving, whichever one wishes to call it) that is entirely different
both from the general properties of [material] bodies, and from
the other forces specifically peculiar to organized bodies37; and
that seems to be one of the primary causes of all generation,
nutrition, and reproduction; and which, in order to prevent any
misinterpretation, and in order to distinguish it from all other
natural forces, I shall here call the formative drive (nisus
formativus).38
In particular, he warned, the Bildungstrieb should not be
confused with Wolff’s “essential force.” Wolff ’s epigenetic account
of generation (Theoria generationis, 1759) relies on the notion of a
vis essentialis, a non-teleological force which primarily serves
nutritive purposes. Its organizing effect is construed as a byproduct of its chemical and mechanical interactions with the
environment.39 This intentional alignment of the process of organic
with inorganic organization is precisely the opposite of Blumenbach’s move, which locates the source of the generation of
organic structure in organic matter alone. Thus, his epigenetic
theory is built upon the notion of a formative drive, rather than
force, that is unique to and inherent in “all living creatures”dand
those alone. Blumenbach realizes that the formative drive might
easily be confused with Wolff’s vis essentialis, given that they both
are responsible for the “effects because of which we ascribe life to
[plants and animals] [weswegen wir [Pflanzen und Tieren] ein Leben
zuschreiben].”40 However, in contrast to Wolff’s, Blumenbach’s
vitalistic epigenetic theory locates the difference between the
living and the non-living in the formative drive.
If this point remains implicit in the earlier edition, Blumenbach
emphasizes it all the more strongly in the 1782 edition of his Handbuch der Naturgeschichte, and in the revised 1789 edition of the treatise on the Bildungstrieb. Both the distinction between ‘drive’ and
mere force, and between the domain of the living and the non-living
become more pronounced. When Blumenbach states that “no one can
be more profoundly persuaded than I am of the massive gap which
nature has implemented between the animated, and the inanimate
creation, between the organized, and unorganized creatures,” he
takes the vitalist point as a premise rather than a problem: there is a
difference in kind between animate and inanimate matter.41 The
formative drive only acts in animate matter and cannot account for
the transition from inanimate to animate matter. But once active, it
will generate structure that had not been present before its action.
Such spontaneous generation is a characteristic of animate matter,
present to various degrees throughout its life but ceasing with it:
there is no such thing in nature as preformed germs: rather, a
special drive becomes active in the previously raw and unformed matter of generation, once it has matured and reached
its place of destination, and then remains active life-long.42
In the 1789 edition, Blumenbach also adds the clarification that
the spontaneous generation of structure does occur in inanimate
matter, such as crystals, as the result of a formative forceeebut a
force lacks the teleological connotation of the drive that sets
animate matter apart. The substantive distinction translates into a
normative and programmatic one for Blumenbach. As suggested by
the fruitful comparison between the generation of structure in
inanimate and animate matter, one can indeed legitimately
“employ the phenomena of either of these two major parts of
creation for explaining phenomena of the other.”43 As an explanatory strategy, however, this move relies on a prior distinction
between the subject matter of biology and physics, as we would say
retrospectively, and anticipates a process of institutionalized
disciplinary division that had just begun when Blumenbach was
writing.44 The coincidental, multiple coinings of the term ‘biology’
around the turn of the century are taken to be suggestive of such a
trend of disciplinary division.45 It is in this broader institutional
context in which Blumenbach suggests, as a result of his own
research as a professor at the Faculty of Medicine in Göttingen, an
epistemically productive division of labor in the sciences. Seen from
this perspective, Blumenbach’s notion of the Bildungstrieb demarcates a limited domain of inquiry for the life sciences.
A second limiting move, this time not on domains of inquiry but
on the action of the formative drive itself, is Blumenbach’s argument for the constancy of species in his Beiträge zur Naturgeschichte
(1780 and later editions). It takes species to be representations of
possible forms of the organization of matter. In every single newly
generated individual, the Bildungstrieb acts on the specific physiological composition of matter passed down from the parent generation. Crucially, this composition limits the possible results of
formative action. As Peter McLaughlin argues, “For Blumenbach,
epigenesis of the individual implies generic preformation.”46 Just
like the distinction between Bildungskraft and Bildungstrieb, this
implication did not escape Kant’s attention; indeed, Kant proved
himself to be a perceptive commentator in characterizing epigenesis as a “system of generic preformation” in the Critique of Judgment.47 The specific form to be reached in epigenetically described
41
Blumenbach (1789), 71.
Blumenbach (1789), 24.
43
Blumenbach (1789), 72.
44
This disciplinary diversification is one of the characteristics of 18th-century
science. Approaching the question from the study of experimental practice rather
than from an institutional perspective, Klein and Lefèvre date the introduction of
“organic substances” as those created by the processes of life as occurring around
1790. Klein and Lefèvre (2007), ch. 13.
45
McLaughlin (2002).
46
McLaughlin (1982), 17e18.
47
Kant (1790), AA 5, 423.
42
37
In the 1789 edition, Blumenbach specifies those as “contractibility, irritability,
sensibility etc.,” i.e. as the mechanical forces described by Haller and others as being
at work in the physiological functioning of the animal bodies. Blumenbach (1789),
25.
38
Blumenbach (1781), 12 (our translation).
39
See Witt (2008) for a recent discussion.
40
Blumenbach (1781), 17 (our translation).
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107
ontogenesis is always prescribed, and in that sense limited, by
virtue of the individual’s being part of a species.
3. 1787
There is a noticeable difference between Kant’s views of
epigenesis qua scientific theory in the late 1780s and 1790, on the
one hand, and his notes from the 1770s and early 1780s, on the
other. In 1787 Kant made use of the phrase “the epigenesis of pure
reason,” and in 1789 he published the essay “On the use of teleological principles in philosophy” in which he first mentions Blumenbach’s Handbuch. “The idea of Bildungstrieb,” Kant writes in the
essay, “brought so much light into the doctrine of generations, not
to inorganic matter but only to the members of organized beings,”48 thus emphasizing Blumenbach’s distinction between
organic and inorganic matter. In the Critique of Judgment, Kant
identifies Blumenbach with epigenesis, and epigenesis with
immanent natural development. Epigenesis “considers nature . as
itself producing [als selbst hervorbringend] rather than merely as
developing [als entwickelnd] those things that can initially be represented as possible only in accordance with the causality of ends,
and thus with the least possible appeal to the supernatural, leaves
everything that follows from the first beginning to nature.”49 Thus
Kant singles out two different reasons for his endorsement of
Blumenbach’s theory of epigenesis as a scientific theorydand in so
doing, incisively highlights Blumenbach’s main programmatic
points. Firstly, and in line with his long-standing methodological
demands, Blumenbach’s version of epigenesis did not require any
appeal to divine or supernatural forces. As a scientific theory, his
account specifically emphasizes the immanent development, or in
Kant’s words, regards nature as self-producing (selbst hervorbringend). Secondly, in its limitation to organic matter, it had a
clearer demarcation of explanatory scope than Wolff’s theory.
While we do not know for certain when Kant first read Blumenbach, his first published mention of the term ‘epigenesis’
appeared in his 1785 review of Herder’s Ideen, which owed a great
deal to Blumenbach.50 It was also in this review that Kant first
formulates a viable conception of epigenesis, which remained at
the core of his later account of epigenesis in the Critique of Judgment. In the review, Kant provides numerous quotations from the
Ideen, some commentary on these quotations, and finally a brief,
albeit highly critical, response to Herder’s methodology and his
conception of reason. This highly critical attitude toward Herder’s
methodology strongly contrasts with Kant’s more tempered reaction to Herder’s views of epigenesis.
Kant begins the review by noting Herder’s disagreement with
the word ‘epigenesis.’ The prefix ‘epi,’ Herder explains, misleadingly implies action from outside of newly generated material. For
this reason, Herder offers the alternative term Bildung to imply
formation that is internal to nature. Kant quotes Herder: “It is Bildung (genesis), an effect of inner forces for which nature had prepared a mass to which they give their form, in which they are to
make themselves visible.”51 Kant is not averse to this point. Rather,
he writes that “the reviewer fully concurs [ihm der Recensent völlig
beitritt]” with Herder’s notion of Bildung, which Kant describes as “a
principle of life, which appropriately modifies itself internally in
accordance with differences of the external circumstances [innerlich nach Verschiedenheit der äußeren Umstände].”52 The parallel
between Herder’s portrayal of epigenesis, as endorsed by Kant, and
Blumenbach’s formulation, is striking. Herder emphasizes Blumenbach’s point that the formative force is a “principle of life,” not
a force that might act in organic or inorganic matter. But the similarities of vocabulary go further.
In the first volume of the Ideen (1784), Herder contends that “no
eye has seen preformed germs,” and goes on to state that if a being
possesses “organic forces [wirkende organische Kräfte],” then it can
“generate itself [so erzeugt es selbst].”53 Blumenbach, in the 1781
version of his treatise, had pointed to the fact that the “perfection
[Vollkommenheit] of our magnification lenses” is no good news for
the yet unseen preformed germs, and continues to describe the
action of epigenesis instead: in the “raw matter of the future
creature,” after its due “period of preparation,” the “formative drive
is stirred and can begin the formation of the hitherto unformed
matter.”54 In his review of Herder, Kant reiterates the language of
matter as “prepared”: what accounts for generation is an action
inherent to, and limited to, this kind of matter, i.e. organic matter.
Kant does, however, have one reservation regarding Herder’s
take on epigenesis:
if the cause organizing itself from within were limited by its
nature only perhaps to a certain number and degree of differences in the formation of a creature (so that after the institution
of which it were not further free to form yet another type under
altered circumstances), then one could call this natural vocation
of the forming nature also “germs” or “original predispositions,”
without thereby regarding the former as primordially implanted
machines and buds that unfold themselves only when occasioned (as in the system of evolution), but merely as limitations,
not further explicable, of a self-forming faculty, which latter we
can just as little explain or make comprehensible.55
In this comment, Kant anticipates his later formulation of “generic
preformation” by suggesting that the main explanatory advantage of
preformation, which Kant had used in his 1775 race essay, can be
accommodated by an epigenetic theory, with one caveat: the limitation of form. Thus he stresses a point that (pace Kant) Herder had
failed to emphasize in his account of epigenesis, but which Blumenbach had clearly made in the Handbuch der Naturgeschichte: the
form to be reached in ontogenic development is limited phylogenetically. It is also clear that Kant does not consider the language of
“germs” to be inherently in contradiction with that of epigenesis: in
the terminology he uses here, “germs” correspond to Blumenbach’s
“prepared matter” rather than “primordially implanted machines.”
This looseness of terminology explains why Kant does not see a need
to remove the language of Keime and Anlagen in the 1787 edition of
the Transcendental Analytic.56
It is important that Kant’s first published use of the term
‘epigenesis‘eein a quotation from Herdereecoincides with the one
moment in his review of the Ideen where Kant’s tone is not entirely
critical, but surprisingly agreeable. Kant’s reworking of Herder’s
conception of epigenesis is, in turn, strikingly similar to Blumenbach’s formative drive. It thus seems that Kant’s interest in
epigenesis in the late 1780s was prompted by Herder, and
53
Herder (1784/1785 [1989]), 6, 171 (our translation).
Blumenbach (1781), 42.
Kant (1785), AA 8, 62e63 (emphasis added on “limited” and “limitation”).
56
For this reason, and in contrast to the majority of the scholarship, we do not
think that Kant was actually offering two competing or paradoxical formulations in
the 1787 edition of the first Critique. Given that he came to conceive of epigenesis
along Blumenbachian lines, he did not regard the language of Keim and Anlage as
inherently opposed to epigenesis. See n. 1 above.
54
55
48
49
50
51
52
Kant (1788), AA 8, 180.
Kant (1790), AA 5, 424.
Richards (2002), 225.
Kant (1785), AA, 8, 50.
Kant (1785), AA, 8, 62.
103
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107
104
specifically coincides with Blumenbach’s version of epigenesis.57
What appeals to Kant in this conception of epigenesis is its two
inbuilt limitations. Blumenbach’s formative drive is restricted to
the domain of the living, and he construes it as a genuinely
formative, yet inherently limited faculty acting within that domain.
In x81 of the Critique of Judgment, Kant explicitly calls this implication of Blumenbach’s epigenetic theory “generic preformation.” It
is this conception of epigenesis as Bildung with limits that Kant
invokes metaphorically in the second edition of the first Critique.
4. Reason and Herder’s Ideen
Herder’s Ideen played a key role in Kant’s formation on at least
two counts. As we have shown, it was in the review that Kant first
formulated a viable conception of epigenesis as a scientific theory.
It was also in the context of the review that he recognized the
epistemic significance of epigenesis as a metaphor for his theory of
reasoneeleading him to employ the metaphor in 1787.
A key claim of Herder’s Ideen is that “reason is nothing but
something received, a learned proportion and direction of ideas
and forces to which the human being is formed through its organization and way of life .” This means, he continues, that “reason
is not innate. . . ”58 Rather, it develops over time and is thus
necessarily historical. It is, furthermore, effected by its natural (and
historical) environment, such that a proper understanding of
reason involves understanding its natural history.
The study of reason that Herder enumerates in the Ideen radically differs from the picture Kant had offered in the first Critique.
According to Herder’s account, to grasp reason, one must trace its
development and emergence in history, andeein deep contrast to
Kant’s transcendental conditions of possibilityeedistinguish the
natural conditions of its possibility. One such condition, Herder
argues, is uprightness. Importantly Herder’s explication of the
development of reason does not amount to an explanation of the
generation of reason through the coming together of isolated parts
whose emergence (and individual existence) is entirely contingent
(i.e., dependent on a variety of environmental circumstances).
Rather, his view is that the development of reason goes hand in
hand with the development of the whole organism, such that it is
impossible to speak of reason as independent of the other parts of
the human organism.
Thus Herder writes that “every creature is suitably organized to
live and move in its element . every creature . has its own, a new
world.”59 He offers several examples to clarify what he means,
illustrating how in each case, the animal or plant is structured according to its needs, and its complexity is commensurate with its
particular situation and environment. In the case of the human
being, Herder begins by noting that uprightness is specifically human, adding that this is not an accident but accords with the
structure and shape of the human body:
the foot of man is more firm and broad: he has a great long toe,
while the ape has only a thumb; his heel too is on a level with
the sole of his foot. All the muscles acting in this position are
adapted to it. The calf of the leg is enlarged; the pelvis is drawn
backwards; the hips are spread outwards from each other; the
57
This is in contrast to both Sloan and Zöller, who do not specifically identify
Herder (and Kant’s reworking of Herder in the review) with Blumenbach. Rather,
Sloan (2002) sees Herder as promoting a Wolffian version of epigenesis, while
Zöller (1989) sees Kant’s comments in the review as evidence of Kant’s “familiarity
with Wolff’s and Blumenbach’s concept of epigenesis” (81). On Herder’s familiarity
with Blumenbach’s work, see Richards (2002), 225e6 and Nisbet (1970), 196.
58
Herder (1989), p. 144; see also p. 93.
59
Herder (1989), p. 89.
spine is less curved; the breast is widened; the shoulders have
clavicles; the hands have fingers endowed with the sense of
feeling; to crown the structure, the receding head is exalted on
the muscles of the neck . 60
It is on account of the whole organismeeits structure, the relations between its parts, and its relation with its environmentee
that, Herder goes on to explain, uprightness becomes possible.
Importantly, he notes that uprightness is not essential to being
human, as is evident in children or humans who live among animals. Nonetheless, the very structure of the human body makes
uprightness possible. This means that uprightness is something
acquired in the right conditions. The same, Herder contends, holds
for reason. Thus, as one of the chapter titles so clearly puts it, “the
human being is organized for reason [Der Mensch ist zur Vernunftfähigkeit organisiert].”61 In other words, reason is possible given the
structure and environment of the human being. As such, it is not
something with which we are simply born. Rather, reason must be
developed in the right circumstances. Thus, even if rationality in
the human being is not entirely contingent (the structure of the
human body makes rational thought possible, in contrast to other
animals who lack this structure), it is also not entirely independent
of these circumstances. It is, in other words, not self-grounding;
rather, it is inextricably linked both to the total structure of the
human being and the environment.
In his review of Herder, Kant sees this move as a kind of naturalization of reason. The review begins with an enumeration of
Herder’s key claims, including the claims that “alteration of the
animals and of the human being [is] in accordance with the climates” and that organization pervades all of nature, including dead
or inanimate nature, such as the ice crystal or snowflake.62 Kant
emphasizes Herder’s use of the terms organic and organic force,
noting that Herder “does not reckon with germs . but rather with
an organic force [Kraft], in plants as much as animals.”63 This force,
Kant goes on, underlies all of creation manifesting itself differently
in different beings. It is the transformation of this one force, Kant
maintains, that determines differences between beings. In the human being, Kant continues, this force is manifest at the erect gait.
While Kant’s characterization of Herder’s account emphasizes
uprightness in a way that overlooks Herder’s holistic understanding of development, the point that Kant wants to draw out and
which he finds most problematic holds: for Herder, reason is not
innate but acquired, and its acquisition depends on the natural
development of the human being in general. As such, it can be
studied in the same way that other aspects of the human organismeeand of nature in generaleecan be studied. It can be studied,
in other words, through the comparative method that Herder
employed in the Ideen and which he designated as anthropology.
It is Herder’s naturalization of reason and his corresponding
elimination of the task of metaphysics (and its replacement by
anthropology) that Kant found deeply problematic. In turn, it is in
light of these problematic views that Kant went on to develop and
put to use the notion of “the epigenesis of pure reason” as a metaphor in explicating the character of the categories. Kant’s programmatic aim in the adoption of that metaphor mirrors
Blumenbach’s in insisting on a separate domain of inquiry for the
life sciences: just as Blumenbach had argued that the generation of
structure in animate matter is the result of a capacity inherent to
60
61
62
63
Herder (1989), 112.
Herder (1989), 116.
Kant (1785), AA 8, 47.
Kant (1785), AA 8, 48.
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107
animate matter and animate matter alone, and thereby created a
distinctive domain of knowledge, so Kant sought to show that the
development of the categories employed by reason can only be
explained within an independent theory of reason, and not as the
product of natural-historical processes. Their development cannot
be explained through the action of natural forces, nor can it be
derived from nature, just as the generation of organization in
animate matter cannot be explained as the action of mere formative
forces (as in inorganic matter such as crystals) but only as that of a
formative drive. Where Blumenbach establishes a domain of the
study of life, Kant sought to reaffirm metaphysics as the singular
domain for the study of reason.
5. B166-168
The significant passages in the second edition of the Critique of
Pure Reason, in which Kant mentions the “epigenesis of pure
reason,” and uses the notion to describe the only possible way by
which to understand the relation between the categories and
experience, comes toward the end of the Transcendental Deduction
at B167. Kant introduces the notion of epigenesis here in a parenthetical remark, following a dismissal of an alternative way by
which to understand the relation between experience and concepts. He writes:
Now there are only two ways in which a necessary agreement of
experience with the concepts of its objects can be thought:
either the experience makes these concepts possible or these
concepts make the experience possible. The first is not the case
with the categories (nor with pure sensible intuition); for they
are a priori concepts, hence independent of experience (the
assertion of an empirical origin would be a sort of generatio
aequivoca). Consequently only the second way remains (as it
were a system of the epigenesis of pure reason): namely that the
categories contain the grounds of the possibility of all experience in general from the side of the understanding.64
It is important to begin by emphasizing the exact way in which
Kant is invoking epigenesis here; he is not stating that the mind is a
biological organism, which develops according to the laws of biological epigenesis. Rather, his claim is that epigenesis offers a model
by which to understand the workings of the mind, more specifically, the relationship between the categories and experience.
After he invokes this model, Kant goes on to reject a third model,
which he identifies with “a kind of preformation-system of pure
reason.”65 Such a picture of the mind, he explains, implies that “the
categories were neither self-thought [selbsgedachte] a priori first
principles of our cognition nor drawn from experience, but were
rather subjective predispositions for thinking.”66 From this, it is
evident that the epigenetic model means that the categories are
“self-thought.” This contrasts with the very first option he had
offered, in which the categories are merely empirical, “drawn from
experience.” In turn, the final (third) option that Kant offers (and
identifies with preformation) contrasts with the first two in that
the categories are neither self-thought, nor drawn from experience,
but rather “implanted [eingepflanzt]” in the mindeeas one would
imagine the germs are implanted in the natural organism. In other
words, the “preformation-system of pure reason” implies something like innate ideas.
64
65
66
Kant (1781/1787), B166-7.
Kant (1781/1787), B167.
Ibid.
105
Kant rejects this third option because “in such a case the categories would lack the necessity that is essential to their concept.” He
elaborates via example: “the concept of cause, which asserts the
necessity of a consequent under a presupposed condition, would be
false if it rested only on subjective necessity, arbitrarily implanted in
us, of combining certain empirical representations according to
such a rule of relation.”67 Precisely because they are “arbitrarily
implanted in us,” Kant contends, innate ideas do not bear any necessity with regard to their concept. That is to say, the necessity is
not inherent to the concept, but external to it: they “lack the necessity that essentially belongs to their concept.”68 Thus, they
cannot produce objectively valid knowledge.
This might seem like an odd claim. Why, one might ask, would
innate ideas not deliver objective knowledge? Günter Zöller has
responded to this question by focusing on the distinction between
innate ideas and the a priori categories born out of the selfgenerating character of reason. The claim is that insofar as reason
is self-grounding and self-generating, the categories must be understood not as original or innate, but as “acquired” in and through
the activity of thinking.69 This contrasts with the innatist view,
which rests on “mere coincidence, due to some divine prearrangement.”70 The categories are not arbitrary, then, because they
are the “self-thought” products of the activity of thinking itself.
Although Zöller is right to emphasize the self-generating character of reason, and on that basis distinguish the categories from
innate ideas, the notions of self-generation and “self-thought”
alone do not fully explicate the character of the categories, account
for their objective validity, or distinguish the specificity (and
thereby the real significance) of Kant’s use of the metaphor of
epigenesis.71 For Zöller, Kant’s conception of epigenesis amounts to
the self-generation of reason, and can thus be modeled on either
Wolff’s or Blumenbach’s theories.72 As we have argued, however,
already in 1785, Kant had formulated a conception of epigenesis
that mirrors Blumenbach’seea conception that distinctively emphasizes limitation on two counts: the delimitation of living from
non-living beings, and phylogenetic limitation. The real import of
Kant’s metaphor, then, cannot simply be the notion of selfgeneration, but rather generation with limitation.
This becomes clear when we examine the context of the metaphor. It appears in the Deduction, where Kant aims to justify the
categories. As numerous commentators have argued, this means
that he must show not only that the application of the categories is
67
Kant (1781/1787), B168; emphasis added.
Kant (1781/1787), B168.
69
And not, as is the case in Herder, through the overall development of the
natural organism in its environment. Zöller quotes Kant: “The Critique admits
absolutely no divinely implanted (anerschaffene) or innate (angeborene) representations. It regards them all, whether they belong to intuition or to concepts of the
understanding, as acquired.” Zöller (1989), 227.
70
Zöller (1989), 231. Zöller explains that the innatist problem would not arise for a
theory of knowledge that is entirely based on innate ideas, without any input from
mind-external entities. It is only a theory of knowledge that regards knowledge as
the outcome of both something non-empirical and something empirical that requires a distinction between necessary (a priori) and non-necessary (empirical)
ideas.
71
We agree with Mensch (2013) who has shown that the significance of
epigenesis in the Transcendental Deduction goes beyond the claim that reason is
self-generating and the categories are self-thought; in addition, she argues,
epigenesis implies a “transcendental affinity within cognition itself,” an affinity
which grants unity to the “experience of nature’s coherence” (134). Our claim is
that this unity is achieved through limitation.
72
See n. 57. Precisely because Zöller does not recognize the way in which Kant
reinterprets epigenesis as a form of “generic preformation” in the Herder review, he
misses the fact that by 1787 Kant is specifically identifying epigenesis with generic
preformation (i.e., Blumenbach), such that its real import rests not simply in the
notion of self-generation, but also in the notion of limitation.
68
106
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107
possible, but also that the categories constrain or limit experience,
such that it is this limiting capacity that “ensure[s] that the logical
function of subject-predicate judgment is used in a certain way
.”73 In other words, to demonstrate the objective validity of the
categories, Kant needs to show that, as products of the activity of
thought, the categories are also limiting forces of and on this
activity.74
Precisely because the categories are the “self-thought” products of the operation of the understanding, they are not originally
present in the mind but formed through the activity of thinking.
This formation, in other words, takes place according to the rulebound activity of the understanding. The categories are thus the
products of the mind applying itself according to its own rules.
The categories are therefore both the outcome of a rule of
thoughteesuch that they can be described as “self-thought”ee
and the application of this rule onto experience. As the application
of this rule onto experience, the categories play a limiting functioneethe carve out experience into entities that must always be
subjects or entities that are predicated of these subjects. And it is
this limiting function of the categories that warrants their objective validity: they non-arbitrarily impose cognitive parameters on
experience.
The manner in which the categories actually determine and
constrain our experience in certain ways is beyond the scope of this
paper. Our purpose is not to explain how this application occurs,
but rather to show that it is this rule-bounded and limiting character of the categories, mirroring the account of limited natural
generation that Kant had formulated in his review of Herder, which
led Kant to adopt the metaphor of epigenesis to explicate his
conception of the mind.75 The categories, then, to quote Kant’s
statement from the review, are “limitations, not further explicable,
of a self-forming faculty [weiter nicht erklärliche Einschränkungen
eines sich selbst bildenden Vermögens].”76
The parallel between this conception of the pure concepts of the
understandingeeas the outcome of the rule-governed activity of
the understanding and the limiting application of this ruleeeand
Kant’s conception of epigenesis qua scientific theory is clear. As we
have argued, Kant’s understanding of epigenesis after 1785 involves
73
Guyer (1992), 131.
Zammito (2003) makes a similar point with regard to Zöller’s interpretation. As
he puts it, “Spontaneity of the categories was not sufficient for Kant’s transcendental deduction, he also needed their constitutive sovereignty over experience”
(92). Zammito takes this to be the ability of the mind to “produce new knowledge,”
which is to say that the mind “had to be a real cause (of knowledge) .” leading him
to conclude that “Kant’s epigenesis analogy . built intellectual causation (determination; constitution) into the fundamental structure of the transcendental
deduction of the possibility of experience.” As Zammito notes, such a conception
waseeon Kant’s transcendental principleseeunacceptable; but Kant had, according to Zammito, not fully understood the meaning of the analogy he was drawing,
because he “was especially ignorant of the revolution in thinking about this phenomenon inaugurated by Blumenbach in 1781” (93). We have tried to show that
this was indeed not the case, rather, that Kant did have a grasp of the revolution in
thinking brought about by Blumenbach, and that it was precisely on account of this
revolution that he came to adopt this metaphor. Thus, in contrast to Zammito’s
interpretation of where the “sovereignty” of the categories comes from on an
epigenetic model, we argue that it has nothing to do with the production of new
knowledge (i.e., content), but rather with the (formal) application of the rules
inherent to thought.
75
Sloan (2002) thinks that Kant’s preference for preformation and his insistence
on the use of the language of preformation to speak about the activity of cognition
has to do with the limitations that the preformative theory places on the selfstructuring capacity of living beings (244e245). As we have shown, however,
Kant’s conception of epigenesis following his Herder review involves limitation,
such that in the 1787 edition of the first Critique, he can invoke the metaphor of
epigenesis and imply limitation. Preformation, by contrast, is regarded as a deeply
problematic metaphor for the mechanism of cognition.
76
Kant (1785), AA 8, 63.
74
two key factors: the first, which many have emphasized, concerns
the self-generating character of living beings and reason. The second, much less noted aspect, involves limitation. It is precisely this
second aspect that attracted Kant to Blumenbach’s specific
conception of epigenesis and that Kant formulated in his Herder
review.
As we have shown, for Blumenbach the term ‘epigenesis’ involves limitation on two levels. First, it involves the limitation of the
formative drive by the composition of the reproductive matter of a
given species. On the cognitive level for Kant, this implied the
limitations of the categories, insofar as they are the outcomes of
rules of thought and the application of these rules.
Limitation for Blumenbach also meant the delimitation of
biological entities as opposed to physical oneseewith the corresponding differentiation between biology and physics. For
Kant, too, epigenesis involved limitation on this level, specifically, the delimitation and independence of the domain of
reason from the domain of nature. Metaphysics, as the study of
reason, is thus separated from natural history and anthropology.
As “self-forming” or “self-born,” reason is not born out of
something other than itself (i.e., natural forces) and thus cannot
be studied in the same way that other beings are studied. Contra
Herder, metaphysics for Kant is preserved as an independent
domain of study.
References
Blumenbach, J. F. (1780). Professor Blumenbach über den Bildungstrieb (nisus formativus) und seinen Einfluß auf Generation und Reproduction (pp. 247-266).
Göttingisches Magazin der Wissenschaften und Litteratur, 1. Jg., 5. Stück.
Blumenbach, J. F. (1781). D. Johann Friedrich Blumenbach über den Bildungstrieb und
das Zeugungsgeschäfte. Göttingen: Johann Christian Dieterich.
Blumenbach, J. F. (1782). Handbuch der Naturgeschichte. Zweyte durchgehends
verbesserte Ausgabe. Göttingen: Johann Christian Dieterich.
Blumenbach, J. F. (1789). Über den Bildungstrieb. Göttingen: Johann Christian Dieterich.
Guyer, P. (1992). The transcendental deduction of the categories. In P. Guyer (Ed.),
The cambridge companion to Kant (pp. 123-160). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Herder, J. G. (1989). Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit. In
J. Brummack, & M. Bollacher (Eds.), Johann Gottfried Herder: Werke in zehn
Bänden (Vol. 6) Frankfurt am Main: Deutsche Klassiker Verlag. First published
1784 and 1785.
Kant, I. (1763). Der einzig mögliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseins
Gottes. In AA vol. II, pp. 63e164.
Kant, I. (1766). Träume eines Geistersehers, erläutert durch Träume der Metaphysik. In
AA II, pp. 315e374.
Kant, I. (1772e1776). Reflexionen zur Metaphysik. In AA XVII, pp. 227e754 and
AA XVIII, pp. 3e725.
Kant, I. (1775). Von den verschiedenen Racen der Menschen. In AA II, pp. 427e444.
Kant, I. (1781/1787). Kritik der reinen Vernunft (A¼1781; B ¼ 1787) In AA vol. 3, and
AA vol. IV, pp. 1e252.
Kant, I. (1785). Recensionen von J. G. Herders Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der
Menschheit. Theil 1. 2. In AA vol. VIII, pp. 43e66.
Kant, I. (1788). Über den Gebrauch der teleogischen Principien in der Philosophie. In AA
vol. VIII, pp. 157e184.
Kant, I. (1790). Kritik der Urteilskraft. In AA vol. V, pp. 165e486.
Klein, U., & Lefèvre, W. (2007). Materials in eighteenth-century science: A historical
ontology. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Löw, R. (1980). Philosophie des Lebendigen. Der Begriff des Organischen bei Kant, sein
Grund und seine Aktualität. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.
Maupertuis, P. L. (1984). Essai de Cosmologie. Systeme de la nature. Response aux
objections de M. Diderot. Presentation de François Azouvi [1751]. Paris: Libraire
Philosophique J. Vrin
McLaughlin, P. (1982). Blumenbach und der Bildungstrieb. Zum Verhältnis von
epigenetischer Embryologie und typologischem Artbegriff. Medizinhistorisches
Journal, 17, 357-372.
McLaughlin, P. (2002). Naming biology. Journal of the History of Biology, 35, 1-4.
McLaughlin, P. (2007). Kant on heredity and adaptation. In S. Müller-Wille, & H.J. Rheinberger (Eds.), Heredity produced: At the crossroads of biology, politics and
culture (pp. 277-291). Cambridge: MIT Press.
Mensch, J. (2013). Kant’s Organicism: Epigenesis and the development of critical philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Piché, C. (2001). The precritical use of the metaphor of epigenesis. In T. Rockmore
(Ed.), New essays on the precritical Kant (pp.182-200). New York: Humanity Books.
Roe, S. (1981). Matter, life, and generation: 18th-century embryology and the HallerWolff-debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
D. Helbig, D. Nassar / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 58 (2016) 98e107
Sloan, P. (2002). Preforming the categories: eighteenth century generation theory
and the biological roots of Kant’s a priori. Journal of the History of Philosophy,
40(2), 229-253.
Witt, E. (2008). Form e a matter of generation. Science in Context, 21(4), 649-664.
Zammito, J. (2003). This inscrutable principle of an original organization’: epigenesis and ‘looseness of fit’ in Kant’s philosophy of science. Studies in the History
and Philosophy of Science Part A, 34(1), 73-109.
Zöller, G. (1988). Kant on the generation of metaphysical knowledge. In H. Oberer, &
G. Seel (Eds.), Kant: Analysen-Probleme-Kritik (pp. 71-90). Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.
Zöller, G. (1989). From innate to a priori. The Monist, 72(2), 222-235.
107
Further reading
Kant, I. (2000). In P. Guyer (Ed.), Critique of the power of judgment. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Kant, I. (2002). In H. Allison, P. Heath, G. Hatfield, & M. Friedman (Eds.), Theoretical
philosophy after 1781. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kant, I. (2007). In G. Zöller, & R. B. Louden (Eds.), Anthropology, history, and education. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.