Beliefs, Lebensformen, and Conceptual History
Peter Harrison
Reply to John Heibron, Yiftach Fehige, and Stephen Gaukroger, Metascience, 25/3
2016, DOI 10.1007/s11016-016-0104-7
Symposium on Peter Harrison, The territories of science and religion. Chicago:
Chicago University Press, 2015. xiii + 300 pp. $30 Cloth
I am grateful to my interlocutors for their careful reading of the book and their
incisive remarks. Thanks also to the editors of Metascience for this opportunity to
offer a brief response.
Necessarily, I am unable to respond to everything the
commentators have raised and instead will address four major concerns which to
varying degrees appear in each of the three commentaries.
1. Christianity and Propositional Religion.
One of the key arguments of the book is that the modern understanding of the
relationship between science and religion requires a careful investigation of the
origins of the concepts themselves. In relation to ‘religion’, my argument was that
our modern idea of plural religions characterised by sets of beliefs and practices is an
idea that appears for the first time in the early modern period. All three of my
reviewers have expressed various levels of doubt about this claim, pointing variously
to the importance of creedal statements for the early church, to the vigour with which
heresy (false belief) was pursued in the middle ages, and to the fact that the premodern relations between Christianity and Judaism (and possibly Islam) already look
like the kinds of relationships between competing religions that on my account
emerged only in the modern period.
John Heilbron counters my suggestion about the non-propositional essence of
Christianity by alluding to the principle extra ecclesiam nulla salus (no salvation
outside the Church) and by pointing to examples of how in late antiquity and the
middle ages the Church seemed preoccupied with creeds and the exclusion of
heretics. But the maxim extra ecclesiam nulla salus actually serves to exemplify the
general thesis that I am proposing. Salvation was the business of Christianity, and it
was made available through membership of the Church and participation in its
sacraments. There is no reference in the formula to beliefs or to anything called the
Christian religion. In the middle ages, membership of the Church was made possible
through the sacrament of baptism, typically conferred upon infants unlikely to be
offering explicit assent to the doctrines of the Church. The relevant terms point to
this. Christianizare (to Christianize) referred to baptism, not profession of belief.
Similarly, for adults in this period, catechismus denoted not the learning of dogmas,
but a process of initiation into Christian rites and mysteries (Ristuccia 2013, 17-18,
41-44). This is why Jean Delumeau could suggest that Europe really only became
‘Christian’—in the sense of a widespread inculcation of explicit Christian beliefs
among the general populace—following the Protestant and Catholic Reformations
(Delumeau 1977: Harrison 2015, 94). For the vast majority of Christians in the middle
ages what was required was faith in a Godhead and implicit faith (or trust) that the
Councils of the Church had a correct theoretical grasp of the person and work of
Christ.
Stephen Gaukroger shares John Heilbron’s view that medieval Christianity
was understood primarily in doctrinal terms: “religion did come to be construed in
doctrinal terms by Christian theologians”. He goes on to say that Christian
theologians treated “all religious differences in terms of differences in doctrine”. For
Gaukroger this is exemplified by the fact that Islam and Judaism were regarded as
heresies. I do think that pre-modern relations among Christians, Jews and Muslims in
some ways look like subsequent relations among religions and there is more work to
be done here. But it should be stressed that Jews and Muslims were not regarded as
heretics, since heresy was “a corruption of Christian faith”: that is to say, the category
of heresy is internal to Christianity (Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, 2a2ae. 11.
2). Admittedly, on the face of it, heresy looks like a prime instance of privileging
propositions and heresy hunting would seem to indicate that a premium is placed
upon correct belief. Again, though, it is important to understand that the culpability
of heresy lay in the fact that it arose out of the vice of pride (and the subsidiary vices
of curiosity and obstinacy). The underlying problem was moral, rather than cognitive.
For this reason, Aquinas treats heresy in his discussion of the theological virtues and
their corresponding vices. Heresy caused harm to individuals by being injurious to the
virtue of faith and by separating the person from God. Heresy was also damaging to
the community because of its potential to promote schism. In relation to the
theological virtues, then, heresy was opposed to faith, and schism was opposed to
charity (Aquinas, Summa theologiae, 2a 2ae 10, 1; 39, 1). The point is here that
2
heresies might be defined in doctrinal terms but they are not understood ‘in purely
doctrinal terms’. Rather, false doctrinal beliefs are the visible symptoms of heresy
and the means through which it could be detected. None of this is to deny that
important conciliar statements were indeed expressed in creeds and propositions, or
that patristic Christianity was more propositional than competing systems of thought
and ways of life. But Christianity was not understood as a religion constituted by its
propositional components. That would only come in the modern period, when
internal divisions within Christianity are characterised in terms of beliefs and
practices.
In all of this, I am not denying that propositions are present in pre-modern
Christianity and that their truth matters in an important way. But explicit profession
of beliefs is not the key thing. An analogy may help here. Consider current practices
of immunization. These have been routine for some time in the first world, although
now contested by a small but vocal anti-vaccination movement. On the one hand, the
efficacy of immunization requires that certain propositions be true, and these
propositional truths have been established and are defended by medical and scientific
authorities. Yet the efficacy of a vaccination programme does not require that all
those immunized be cognizant of and assent to propositional truths about how
immunization works. What is required is a trust in medical authorities, a belief in the
public health system, and a willingness to participate in the relevant activity.
Moreover, the point of immunization is not to inculcate correct beliefs about the
operation of vaccines, but to protect against disease and confer ‘herd immunity’.
Membership of the immune ‘herd’ is not conferred through the profession of true
beliefs, but by being immunized. The threat posed by an anti-vaccination movement
might similarly be thought of in two ways. It could (quite correctly) be thought to lie
in the fact that its proponents hold beliefs that are false. But the primary worry is not
epistemic. It is to do with the health of the children of vaccination sceptics and the
risk posed to others owing to a loss of herd immunity. The medical heresy of antivaccinationists is contested not primarily because of a requirement that they hold true
beliefs per se, but because their false beliefs have practical consequences for
themselves and others.
My argument is that something similar is true for the history of Christianity. It
is common to view the history of Christianity, as Heilbron and Gaukroger seem to,
through a modern lens that privileges propositional content. Thus viewed, the history
becomes largely the history of councils and creedal formulations, of the policing of
boundaries between orthodoxy and heresy, and the persecuting or expulsion of those
who hold false beliefs. My suggestion is that while this contesting of belief is clearly
a prominent feature of ecclesiastical history, it is not ultimately explicit belief in the
propositions that is most important for Christian identity in the middle ages. To
regard Christianity as primarily constituted by propositional belief is akin to seeing
immunization practices as primarily propositional. In both cases the truth of
propositions is crucial, but it is not the main thing. The reason that in the case of
religion we have come to think of propositions as primary is twofold: we have
retrospectively applied the epistemic preoccupations of the present onto the distant
3
past; and we have constructed its history from the evidence that has been most easy to
come by—that which is found in texts and institutional narratives.
2. Playing with Words?
John Heilbron concludes his review with some pointed remarks about my reliance
upon data to do with word usage and my assumption that changes in word frequencies
can signal significant conceptual shifts—“Let us not distort the historical record by
playing with words”. The case in point would be arguments built around the
changing meanings of ‘religio’ and ‘scientia’, and the coining of expressions such as
‘scientist’, ‘biology’, and ‘scientific method’. Heilbron rightly points out that
phenomena can exist before the relevant words come into common use, although of
course there will be clear exceptions. ‘Laser’ is attested from 1960 and it is a fairly
safe bet that there were no lasers before then. But matters will not always be so
straightforward, as Heilbron’s own example—the word ‘genocide’—seems to
indicate. Heilbron notes that while the word ‘genocide’ is attested only from the midtwentieth century, the phenomenon has a much longer history. The Israelites’
slaughter of the Amorites is his chosen example.
But again, this very example can be understood as supporting the line that I
take in the book. The term ‘genocide’ was coined in 1944 by Polish-Jewish lawyer
Raphael Lemkin, who invented it to describe the Holocaust (Sands 2016). The
coming into existence of this term, in my view, is more informative about the
contemporary context than the distant past, even if the word can be applied to past
phenomena that seem empirically comparable to more recent events. The relevant
1948 UN convention on genocide is relevant here, censuring acts committed with an
intent to destroy “national, ethical, racial or religious groups”. But problematically for
any historical application, these categories are taken as given, and this is precisely
what is at issue for the historian. One of the key arguments of my book is that the very
ideas ‘nation’, ‘race’, ‘ethnos’, ‘religion’ are not natural kinds but rather are ways of
categorising groups and activities that have slowly coalesced in modern Western
consciousness—they are cultural or historical constructions. Insofar as ‘genocide’ is
parasitic on these later notions its retrospective application to the past has the capacity
to be misleading.
The intention here is not to deny the existence of horrific acts in the past that
bear resemblance to modern instances of genocide. It is rather to point out that it
would have been impossible for individuals at the time to have conceived of
themselves as committing genocide. Moreover, uncritically applying the label
‘genocide’ to pre-modern events can blind us to otherwise interesting questions that
we might ask. Were the Amorites, Gibeonites, or Amalekites analogous to our
‘nation’, ‘race’ or ‘ethnos’, ‘tribe’, ‘religion’, ‘sect’, ‘urban subculture’, ‘criminal
gang’, ‘paramilitary group’, ‘racial minority’, or did they have connotations of a
number of these? In other words, it makes sense to ask how the ancient Hebrews
conceptualised various groupings, and the simplistic use of ‘genocide’ prevents us
from asking these kinds of questions. For example, in the unsavoury biblical account
4
of the slaughter of the Amalekites, what do we make of the fact that oxen, sheep,
camels and donkeys were included in the group targeted for annihilation? This set
does not map on to any of our familiar modern groupings very well, since it is so
much more than a “national, ethical, racial or religious group”. Moreover, what do we
make of the apparent insouciance of the reductors of the Hebrew Bible who chose to
include these disagreeable episodes in their canonical writings? This clearly indicates
a very different moral assessment of the events in question, in stark contrast to
contemporary holocaust deniers, or to official Turkish embarrassment about what
happened to the Armenians in the period 1915-20. All of these considerations are
important for a proper historical understanding of the past.
For reasons such as these (and there are more specifics in the book) it is not
mere word play to insist that terms such as ‘religion’, ‘science’, ‘scientist’, and so on,
can only be used in a loose sense to characterise phenomena in the distant past.
However much historical actors might have engaged in activities that seem to match
our modern descriptors, they themselves did not conceptualise their activities that
way, and indeed could hardly have done so. It may well be that no twenty-first
century mind is “agile enough”, to use Heilbron’s Swiftian turn of phrase, to imagine
precisely how they did think. And I do not deny the difficulty of escaping from the
straitjacket of our contemporary conceptions. But our present failures of imagination
should not prevent at least a theoretical concession that people in the past might have
conceptualised things in ways radically different from us. Paying careful attention to
language and linguistic changes, then, is not mere wordplay but is rather, to use
Wittgenstein’s expression, to equip ourselves for “a battle against the bewitchment of
our intelligence by means of language”.
3. Internal Realism and the Status of Beliefs
I want to turn now to the two key issues that Yitach Fehige highlights in his
comments. The first is what he regards as my ambivalence towards the well
established consensus amongst historians of science that the historical relations
between science and religion are best characterised as ‘complex’. The second
concerns what he sees as an implicit philosophical commitment to ‘internal realism’.
I will return to the complexity thesis below, but for now will address the question of
internal realism—an issue that to some extent takes us back to the question of
propositional truths and their changing status within Christianity.
The stance that I take in the book is that history provides one of the most
fruitful ways of gaining insight into contemporary science-religion relations. An
obvious alternative to this historical approach, and one not uncommon in sciencereligion discussions, is to adopt a philosophical analysis of the respective claims of
the two entities. As will be obvious to readers of the book, my worry about this latter
approach is its tendency to focus on those components of science and religion that are
susceptible to such analysis, which is to say, their propositional contents.
Philosophical analysis can thus become complicit in reinforcing unhelpful ways of
understanding science and religion. I do think, nonetheless, that philosophy has a lot
5
to offer to this discussion, and my historical analysis is informed by philosophical
commitments. I am grateful to Yiftach Fehige for attending to this dimension of the
question.
Internal (or pragmatic) realism is associated with the philosopher Hilary
Putnam (Putnam 1981; 1982). Briefly, in Reason, Truth and History (1981) Putnam
argued compellingly against metaphysical realism—the idea that there is a ‘readymade’ world out there waiting for us to discover. At the same time, and against pure
idealism, Putnam maintained that there exists a world that is causally independent of
our minds. The distinctive feature of his internal realism is the suggestion that objects
are mind-dependent, which is to say that they derive their existence from conceptual
schemes that are mental: “Objects are as much made as discovered” (Putnam 1981,
54). Thus, while the world is not a figment of our imagination, the objects with which
we furnish it are dependent on our own conceptual schemes. Putnam contends that
this remains a form of realism, to be contrasted with both idealism and a ‘facile
relativism that says “Anything goes”’ (the latter a reference to Paul Feyerabend’s
Against Method). Our conceptual schemes, then, are corrigible, but none, including
the sciences, offer us a God’s eye view of the world.
I am sympathetic to this general position, which lies between a naïve
metaphysical realism and a self-defeating relativism. I think it works better than the
vague and ambiguous ‘critical realism’ that seems have become the default
philosophical stance within science-religion dialogue (see Losch 2009). Insofar as our
conceptual schemes depend on culture (Putnam argues for culture and biology) this
stance is compatible with the arguments of the book, and I can see why Fehige has
characterised me as an internal realist. I am happy with the characterization, provided
that it is seen to be consistent with some other philosophical, but largely unstated
commitments. Putnam’s general approach, insofar as it seeks to occupy a middle
position between realism and relativism, stresses the culturally embedded nature of
our knowledge, and aligns meaning with use, has some similarities to Wittgenstein’s
later thought and, within the philosophy of science, the ideas of Kuhn and Lakatos.
My own assessment, as some other commentators have noted, is that my
philosophical orientation is closer to Wittgenstein than Putnam (Smith 2015;
Ristuccia 2016).
One Wittgensteinian theme of the book, as already hinted, is that some
philosophical problems are the result of our bewitchment by language. This is in
keeping with the argument that present tensions between science and religion arise
out of the concepts themselves. In this sense, the book does not seek to offer
solutions to present science-religion conflicts, proposing instead that the putative
problems would dissolve were we to abandon the categories that generate them. The
other theme, and this relates to Putnam’s point about objects being related to mental
concepts, is that forms of language arise out of forms of life (Lebensformen). Neither
religious beliefs nor scientific theories in this version of events can be fully explicated
independently of the forms of life out of which they arise. Again, this is incompatible
with metaphysical realism but does not rule out conversation or ‘conversion’, to use
Wittgenstein’s term. There is a parallel to my application of these Wittgensteinian
6
insights to history in the work of Pierre Hadot who applies the idea of forms of life to
the history of philosophy. Much more could be said about this (see Harrison 2016).
For now it is worth pointing out that this is also relevant to Stephen Gaukroger’s
suggestion of a distinction between propositional and non-propositional ways of
engaging with the world, which map respectively onto something like
religio/religiosity and science. This is not the distinction that I would want to make—
it sounds rather like some interpretations of the early Wittgenstein, or 1950s logical
positivism. My point would be rather that it is a mistake to construe either science or
religion in purely propositional or cognitive terms. What motivates this latter move is
often either a misplaced desire to put these two activities into dialogue, or an attempt
to demonstrate the rational superiority of science to religion.
4. The Complexity Thesis
Finally, I turn to the other major question that Fehige poses concerning my apparent
ambivalence to the thesis of John Hedley Brooke’s classic Science and Religion:
Some Historical Perspectives (1991), according to which ‘complexity’ is the best way
to characterise historical relations between science and religion. (Brooke is himself
cautious about wishing to be seen as the author of an alternative metanarrative, ‘the
complexity thesis’.) Like other historians of science-religion relations, I am deeply
indebted to Brooke’s work. He, along with David Lindberg and Ronald Numbers, has
done more than anyone to dispel the narrative of perennial conflict between science
and religion, while at the same time not wishing to argue for enduring harmony either.
Brooke’s work provides the foundation and many of the background assumptions
upon which my own work is based.
Regarding the conflict thesis, there are two things to say. First, particularly in
elements of my previous work, I have strongly emphasised harmony, perhaps to the
point of seeming to posit an alternative metanarrative that was equal but opposite to
the conflict myth. Here I would simply say that the harmony I draw attention to is not
(indeed, cannot be) harmony between science and religion. Rather it is harmony
between particular religious ideas or motivations and natural philosophy or natural
history. Following on from this I do think that religion is a key factor in the
emergence and persistence of modern science, but that its role in those processes
remains complex. This is because, as Brooke himself has pointed out, religious
factors operate in many different ways—motivating key players, giving social
legitimation to scientific practice, providing a basis for theory choice, furnishing
presuppositions for the pursuit of science and, on occasion, contributing to the content
of scientific theories. Moreover, religious ideas and practices can have unintended
consequences and outcomes that ultimately turn out to be inhospitable to religious
ideas and sensibilities. So while I might seem on occasion to emphasise harmony in a
way that is inconsistent with an overall picture of complexity, I am not motivated by a
normative commitment to the idea of harmony, not least because harmonious
relations might turn out to be detrimental to one side or the other.
7
The other element of my ambivalence to complexity is indeed as Fehige has
proposed, a desire to move beyond what Ronald Numbers calls ‘the problem of
endless diversification’. I share with Brooke and Numbers the conviction that there is
no general historical narrative that can be told about science and religion, and that the
popular prevailing narrative of conflict is false. But if there is no metanarrative about
science and religion, I do think there is a possible narrative about the concepts
‘science’ and ‘religion’, and this was the topic of the book. That story, accordingly,
was not just about historical contingencies, as both Gaukroger and Fehige have
assumed. What connects and accounts for the development of these two concepts in
the modern West was a move away from a virtue-oriented understanding of persons
and the world they live in. This historical shift, associated with both the Protestant
Reformation and the Scientific Revolution (scare quotes if you will), promoted the
reification of both ‘religion’ and ‘science’, and it was that process that made possible
their present relations. To some degree, then, historical complexity is an artefact of
reading the categories of science and religion back into history. Beneath this
complexity lies a narrative that can be related, and it is a narrative about the common
factors leading to the generation of these two concepts. The prevalence of the conflict
myth called for a refutation on its own terms. This necessitated some degree of
retrospective reconstruction in terms of the modern categories. With that task
completed, it remained to give an account of the making of the myth, which in turn
called for an account of how the components of the myth were themselves
constructed. That new task made possible a new story, related in the book.
It may be, as many contemporary historians believe, that metanarratives (or
even just plain, old, modest narratives) are always wrong. But our discipline needs
narratives in order to prosper. Even the conflict myth has been fruitful in its own
way, for while it has been a source of considerable disinformation it has also
motivated much excellent research in the quest to refute it. My modest hope for The
Territories of Science and Religion is that it too will be fruitful in stimulating
conversation and discussion, and, more than this, that it might prove to be more
resistant to falsification than the conflict narrative. On the first point, this discussion
has been a good start.
References
Delumeau, Jean. 1977. Catholicism between Luther and Voltaire. London: Burns and
Oates.
Harrison, Peter. 2016. Forthcoming. “Physicotheology, Forms of Life, and the Future
of Science-Religion Dialogue”, Zygon 51.
Harrison, Peter. 2015. The Territories of Science and Religion. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Losch, Andreas. 2009. “On the Origins of Critical Realism”, Theology and Science 7:
85-106.
Putnam, Hilary. 1981. Reason, Truth, and History. Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press.
8
Putnam, Hilary. 1982. “Why There Isn’t a Ready-Made World”, Synthese 52: 141167.
Ristuccia, Nathan. 2016. Forthcoming. “Peter Harrison, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and the
Problem of Pre-Modern Religion” Zygon 51.
Ristuccia, Nathan. 2013. “The Transmission of Christendom”, PhD Dissertation,
University of Notre Dame.
Sands, Philippe. 2016. East West Street: On the Origins of Genocide and Crimes
against Humanity. London, Weidenfeld & Nicolson.
Smith, James K. A. July 19, 2015. “A Therapeutic Cartography”, LA Review of
Books.
9