Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
12 pages
1 file
Heidegger has powerful adherents in societies as disparate as Russia and Iran. If liberal democracies are to reckon with his followers, they must wrestle with his thought.
Political Research Quarterly, 2022
The revival of ideologically motivated right-wing political agitation across the Western world demands that its intellectual sources be discovered. Martin Heidegger has occupied a position among anti-liberal, anti-modernist, and anti-Western forces across the globe comparable to that of Karl Marx on the socialist Left. Yet scholars still lack the conceptual terminology for capturing the political import of his work. The recent publication of Heidegger's Black Notebooks provides an opportunity for rereading his central political works in order to recover their meaning for contemporary political movements. Such a rereading also illuminates the sources of Heidegger's remarkable and misunderstood influence on the political Right. It thus explains a matter of urgent and high importance for generalist political scientists.
2022
Juxtaposing the name of Martin Heidegger and the word “Politics” creates an explosive formula: even the mind of not specialized readers immediately goes to antisemitism, Nazism, and to the Third Reich. It’s almost impossible to dissociate Heidegger and his adhesion to National-Socialism, although this adhesion is highly debated. In our opinion, trying to minimize the philosophical responsibilities of the thinker and the political responsibilities of the man is a wrong move, as explicitly stated by the Italian philosopher Domenico Losurdo. In his book La comunità, la morte, l’Occidente: Heidegger e l’ideologia della Guerra, Losurdo speaks about a “purifying bath from Politics”, mentioning three possible strategies of depoliticization of Heidegger’s thought. The first strategy is linguistic and consists of a neutral translation of certain Heideggerian terms, for example, the word völkisch translated as “folk”, an acceptable translation only if it’s clearly mentioned the political importance that the German word had during the Third Reich. The second strategy is biographical and bibliographical, it consists of the removal of the relation with certain authors and thinkers deeply associated with National-Socialism and with the minimization of various problematic passages of Heideggerian texts. The third strategy is entirely political and it’s the most popular one: the adhesion to Nazism is trivialized, seen as a temporary mistake not so relevant to the understanding of the philosopher. Absolution at any cost is only one side of the issue since the opposite position is equally problematic. Canceling Heidegger prevents both a serious discussion about what makes a phenomenon like National-Socialism possible, what makes it compelling and irresistible even for those who have, or should have, all the cultural instruments to resist and oppose fascism in its wide meaning; and a deep exploration of the political possibilities of the many critical and emancipatory elements of Heidegger’s thought. As Donatella Di Cesare claims, closing accounts with Heidegger mean neither dealing with fascism nor confronting the challenges that he poses to capitalistic modernity and to our age. In this sense, the attack on Heidegger is even an attack on his disciples who attempted to politically mobilize from a critical perspective the heritage of the “master”. Names like Giorgio Agamben, Jacques Derrida, and Michel Foucault are only a part of the harsh critics of neoliberal politics and society that in Heidegger’s thought found crucial philosophical political weapons . At this point, reading Heidegger from the Left cannot mean neither absolve nor cancel, it’s instead an inherently dynamic way of reading his works, where we must strive to distinguish revolutionary, emancipatory, and deconstructive passages from their reactionary or fascist counterparts. As we will see later, if in certain cases texts entirely devoted to justifying National-Socialism are clearly separable from texts in which the content is much more revolutionary, in many other occasions this line is not so easily traceable, since in the same text different political elements can be at work at the same time, limiting or even sabotaging each other. There is a second order of problems linked to the weight that Politics has in Heidegger’s thought. Even if biographically is a highly debated theme, looking on the theoretical side it is absent: it might appear that Heidegger almost doesn’t write or speak about Politics. There is only one text from the philosophical political tradition that he takes into account, the Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts by Hegel. The analysis of this Hegelian book is developed during the semester 1934-35 in form of a seminar, which means that we have only some notes from Heidegger itself and two summaries of the lessons, written by students. If the summaries are coherent and clear texts, for what about the notes the reader faces a fragmentary series of words and short sentences, often very difficult to understand without a broader context that clarifies the author’s position . The scarcity of material is just one side of our problem because looking through other places in which Heidegger writes explicitly about Politics we can only find critical remarks about it: there’s a certain insistence against Politics in general and, for example, das Politische, in particular, that could suggest surrendering to the idea of an apolitical or at least unpolitical Heidegger. At first glance, it seems possible to speak about Heidegger and Politics only in terms of Heidegger against Politics. This way of thinking is, in the opinion of who is writing, misleading and precludes full access to many political questions that the Heideggerian Denkweg raises, as we will try to show further in this short essay. At the moment, we only want to suggest the possibility that this refusal of Politics is more an exploration of another Politics, not rooted in those dominant metaphysical concepts on which the Western philosophical and political tradition founded itself. The Heideggerian refusal of Politics could in this sense be read as a dismissal of Politics based on the management of human actions, finalized to the systematic control of nature, History, and humanity itself . In this sense, what is at stake here is the opportunity to activate or reactivate certain passages, intuitions, and themes that could open to another Politics, radically critical of past and present political schemes and with an eye always pointed toward the possibility of alternative futures. Proceeding in this direction implies an operation of acknowledgment of different moments in which Heidegger expresses political positions, in which his thought is political even without directly mentioning Politics and political philosophy. In doing so we cannot ignore the aforementioned ambiguity of Heidegger's political views: if the adhesion to National-Socialism and antisemitism are not only accidental mistakes that can be ignored, then there must be an internal trace of these elements, or at least of the conditions on which these elements have grown and developed, inside Heidegger’s thought. The coexistence of reactionary and revolutionary traits is therefore our main problem, especially when attempting to read Heidegger from a revolutionary perspective since we need to move in a contradictory situation that doesn’t lead straightforwardly to the political conclusions that we are trying to enhance. To move better onto this “minefield” we can borrow a couple of concepts from Deleuze and Guattari: deterritorialization and reterritorialization, besides expressing more effectively than “reactionary” and “revolutionary” the political tension that interests us here, are terms adequate to describe the double movement of this same tension. There is a famous passage from Anti-Oedipus that reads: «For capitalism constantly counteracts, constantly inhibits this inherent tendency while at the same time allowing it free rein; it continually seeks to avoid reaching its limit while simultaneously tending toward that limit. ». We are not saying that Heidegger is a capitalist, of course, instead, we are saying that the internal movement of Heidegger’s thought if we look at its political potentialities, can be brought back to a movement of contrary trend, a kind of self-inhibition very similar to the Deleuze-Guattarian one. This double movement of deterritorialization and reterritorialization works on two sides: on one side, when Heidegger approaches the extreme political limits of his same thought, he takes a step back, maybe the same step back that he blamed Kant for; on the other side and in the opposite direction, it is his same thought that “betrays” him, showing how much it is pushing some limits of western Politics, searching for an exit from the metaphysical thinking in which modernity is founded and in which History is trapped.
Heidegger is among the most controversial thinkers of the twentieth century. The depth of his thinking and his approach to the reading of philosophic texts has had a profound impact on multiple fields in Europe, America, and Japan since the late 1920s. His explicit support for National Socialism in the 1930s and his critique of liberal democracy and parliamentarianism both then and throughout the rest of his life, however, has called into question the moral and political significance even of his most abstruse philosophical remarks. His critics have repeatedly suggested that his thinking about ontology and logic played an essential role in shaping his attachment to the political policies of of National Socialism. Moreover, with the passage of time the shadow of his political affiliations have extended to darken the reputations of many of his students as well, including many of those who were forced to flee from the regime he supported, some to America where they were manifest opponents of the Nazi regime and deeply critical of their teacher for his support of the National Socialist movement. There are obviously many questions here. Perhaps the most important is whether and if so in what ways Heidegger's thinking leads or lends support to National Socialism or similar political movements. This is a question I have considered at length on several occasions and that I won't deal with it extensively here. Suffice it to say that I think this claim is true but limited in a variety of ways. A second question , is whether the work of his students, readers, and admirers is in some way perhaps even without their knowledge and against their intentions infected with the elements of Heidegger's thought that lead them in the direction of National Socialism. Should they in other words be suspect simply due to their having studied with Heidegger or having read and been influenced by his thought. In this talk I will try to answer these question by examining the relationship between teachers and students within the context of a general notion of the way in which thought is
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Cambridge University Press and University of Notre Dame du lac on behalf of Review of Politics are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Politics. More than fifteen years after Victor Farias's Heidegger and Nazism provoked the latest round in the Heidegger wars1, is there anything new worth saying about Heidegger's politics? Are there any new fronts to be opened in the debate about Heidegger and the political? The appearance of new works by Richard Wolin,2 Christopher Rickey3, and Gregory Fried4, provides us with the opportunity to reexamine the question of whether Heidegger's Denken contains a political philosophy, an ontological politics, and the ways in which such a political philosophy may be connected to Nazism. The appearance of previously unpublished lecture courses and texts in Heidegger's collected works, still unavailable when the current round in the Heidegger wars first began, has made available new sources for an examination of the place of the political in Heidegger's thinking. Thus, Wolin has explored the meaning of the meditation on "work" (Arbeit), which he believes is "the defining feature of his political worldview" (p. 189), in Heidegger's recently published 1934 lecture course on Logik. Rickey, meanwhile focuses on the just published early Freiburg lecture courses on the phenomenology of religious life, as central 1. The first round in the Heidegger wars began just after the end of World War II, in the pages of Les Temps modernes, where Heidegger's purported Nazism was first debated. A second round began in the 1960s, provoked by the publication of Heidegger's own speeches and lectures from the period of his Rektorat at Freiburg University (1933-34) in Guido Schneeberger's privately published Nachlese zu Heidegger (1962). The third or current round began with the publication of Farias's book in 1987. For an overview of the issues raised by the Heidegger wars, see Alan Milchman and Alan Rosenberg, "The Philosophical Stakes of the Heidegger Wars, Part I: Methodologies for the Reading
The workshop will bring together a range of scholars from International Relations, political and social theory, philosophy and human geography in order to develop a multidisciplinary engagement with Martin Heidegger’s work and to explore its relevance for contemporary International Studies.
New Book Publication, 2022
In a review of the work of Karl Jaspers composed several years before the publication of his book Being and Time, Martin Heidegger suggested that the philosophical orientations of his period had made a wrong turn and skirted by the fundamental path of thought. He suggested that instead of taking up a heritage of original questions, his contemporaries had become preoccupied with secondary issues, accepting as fundamental what was in fact only incidental. In the years that followed, Heidegger’s promise to reorient philosophy in terms of the Seinsfrage, the question of Being, exercised a well-known influence on successive generations of thinkers on a global scale. The present book delves into the philosophical sources of this influence and raises the question whether Heidegger indeed made good on the promise to reveal for thought what is truly fundamental. In proposing this investigation, the author assumes that it is not sufficient to take Heidegger at his word, but that it is necessary to scrutinize what is posited as fundamental in light of its broader implications–above all for ethico-political judgment and for historical reflection. After addressing this question in the first part of the book, the second part examines the significance of Heidegger's reorientation of philosophy through the prism of its critical reception in the thought of Hannah Arendt, Ernst Cassirer, Emmanuel Levinas, and Paul Ricœur.
2023
An account of how Heidegger has been received in Iran and in Russia in the light of the emergence of a 'multipolar world' - a world that allows for the coexistence of radically different 'world views'.
(2015 onwards, with Antonio Cerella) Globalization is one of the most contested and (ab)used concepts of our time. Whether one interprets it as a ‘collective illusion’ or as the final stage of capitalism, as ‘uncontrollable multitude’ or as a radical opening of new spaces of freedom, the Global Age represents the conceptual and existential background of our being-in-the-world. But what lies behind the essence of this process? What mode of human existence is brought about by the age of technology and ‘global mobilization’? And is it possible to attempt a unitary interpretation of this age that presents itself as both total and pluralistic? This international collaborative project aims at rethinking these epochal questions in light of Martin Heidegger’s complex hermeneutics, and, in turn, question some of its most fundamental aspects: the metanarrative of Seinsgeschichte as withdrawal of Being; the structure of human being within the frame of technology; the relation between humanism and nihilism, as well as politics and technology; the changing character of subjectivity in the ‘age of the world picture’; the mythopoeic force of art and the uprooting of human beings. Interrogating Heidegger’s thought has, in fact, a significant potential for both International Political Theory and also the analysis of specific concepts and dynamics in contemporary international studies such as the changing character of spatiality, temporality, and subjectivity. The first activity of the project is an international workshop which brings together a range of scholars from International Relations, political and social theory, philosophy and human geography in order to develop a multidisciplinary engagement with Martin Heidegger’s work and to explore its relevance for contemporary International Studies. For details, see:https://heideggerandtheglobal.wordpress.com/
First parts of dossier (still in process) of materials now available and discussed in debates surrounding Heidegger and Nazism, which will soon include commentary on French-language texts unavailable to Anglophone readers. This dossier is intended as a guide for students and interested researchers, in order to enable people to become informed of what is now available, since so often meaningful debate on this incredibly important subject is derailed due to the suppression, disavowal, denial, or simple non-knowledge of relevant materials by one or more parties to said debates. This material is all pre-2015, and thus pre- the Black Books: it include materials on/from the GA, and correspondence, as this material has been published and unearthed over the last two decades. Interested parties are invited to use this dossier, which is however not intended to be cited, so much as a guide to materials that should be cited.
Arxiv preprint math/0608208, 2006
Journal of Asian Finance, Economics and Business, 2021
About the proposal to calculate the local solar day (Atena Editora), 2024
The Historic Environment Policy & Practice, 2023
International Journal of Advanced Trends in Computer Science and Engineering, 2020
Journal of Constructional Steel Research, 2014
The Russian Review, 2023
Tetrahedron Letters, 1989
REVISTA INVENTUM, 2009
Plant Cell, Tissue and Organ Culture, 2004
ISIJ International, 2002
Filozofia, 2020
Scientific reports, 2018
Chirurgia, 2021
Communications earth & environment, 2022