Andrew Field1
A review of Free Will and Consciousness by Gregg D. Caruso2
Introduction:
Free-Will and Consciousness is an ambitious book which attempts to promote the case for free will
scepticism by exploring the recent scientific findings in the behavioural, cognitive and neurosciences
(BCN). It argues that these findings are contrary to our common sense belief in free-will, according to
which we consciously decide to choose different courses of actions. Such findings threaten our common
sense belief that our conscious intentions cause our voluntary actions as mistaken because ‘much of what
we do takes place at an automatic and unaware level.’3 Caruso is another scholar to sign up to the
increasing membership of free-will scepticism that includes distinguished proponents such as Derk
Pereboom4and Neil Levy5.
Within the free-will debate, Caruso refers to his position as ‘hard-enough determinism’6 in which the
underlying neural and psychological processes that produce all our actions and choices are part of a
‘causally determinate system (or ‘near-determined system’)7. Unlike hard determinism though, this
position leaves open the possibility that there is some indeterminism in the universe, most likely at the
micro level, ‘but it maintains that any such indeterminism is screened out at levels sufficiently low not to
matter to human behaviour.’8
Organisation:
Caruso spends the first third of the book presenting the traditional philosophical debate over the freewill
problem discussing the positions of libertarianism and compatibilism.
In the initial chapter, ‘The Problem of Free Will: A Brief Introduction and Outline of Position’, Caruso
briefly discusses the tension between moral responsibility and determinism, provides a brief outline of the
different philosophical positions in the debate, as well as a short discussion of the debate on moral
responsibility.
In Chapter two, ‘Against Libertarianism’, Caruso focuses on the two most prominent libertarian theories
of Agent-Causation (AC) and Event Indeterminism, weighing up the plausibility of each theory. Agent1
Review by Andrew Field, PhD Candidate, University of Birmingham.
2
Gregg Caruso, Free Will and Consciousness. (Lexington Books 2012). All page number citations refer to this
monograph unless specified otherwise.
3
p.2
4
Derk Pereboom, Living Without Free Will. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2001)
5
Neil Levy, Hard Luck: How Luck Undermines Free Will and Moral Responsibility. (Oxford: Oxford University
Press 2011)
6
p.4
7
Ibid.
8
Ibid.
Causal theory states that the agent himself is the cause of the free action, ‘as he is a self-determining
being, casually undetermined by antecedent events.’9 Caruso argues, the problem with AC is its inability
to account for mental causation satisfactorily, which is a necessary condition for free-will as exemplified
in our common understanding of human behaviour, as it either falls into radical emergentism or substance
dualism.
Event-Indeterminism, on the other hand, is a naturalised version of libertarianism that attempts to escape
the sui generis kinds of causation invoked by AC and other types of libertarianism. Robert Kane10, the
main proponent of such theory, argues that a free action is caused by the effort of an agent’s will when in
moments of moral conflict an agent has two or more options of action available, - which creates chaotic
conditions of amplified quantum indeterminacy at the relevant neurological level -, are activated in the
neural network. Caruso argues, however, that event-indeterminism cannot answer the Intelligibility
Question: how is libertarianism intelligible in a scientific worldview that embraces the physical universe
as causally closed? Kane is unable to give a plausible answer to how, given such quantum indeterminacy
at the neural networks, that the agent is in control of choosing his actions, since he is unable to invoke a
sui generis causation to account for his choosing of one action over the other. Moreover, a satisfactory
answer cannot rest on the view that random quantum indeterminacy chooses the suitable course of action,
since the agent does not have the required control for moral responsibility as we are not in control of
quantum indeterminacy at the neural network level.
In Chapter three, ‘Against Compatibilism’, at the start of this chapter Caruso gives us a general survey
between the debate between compatibilism and incompatibilism by discussing how compatibilism’s
response to the consequence argument is generally unsatisfactory, at least from an incompatibilist point of
view. However, Caruso’s main argument – in this chapter - attempts to show that experimental evidence
from social psychology research shows that compatibilism does not accurately reflect our pre-theoretical
beliefs; rather they are libertarian and incompatibilist in nature. To paraphrase one experiment from
Nichols and Knobe11, the vast majority of subjects (over ninety percent) answered that our universe was
similar to the indeterminist universe presented in the experiment (rather than deterministic). Moreover, if
our universe were deterministic then the vast majority of students responded that we would not be fully
morally responsible for our actions. This means that proponents of compatibilism cannot assert that their
conception of free-will is a reflection of our ordinary conception of it, and neither can they appeal to pretheoretical intuitions as support to their position. This conclusion becomes relevant when Caruso
demonstrates an innovative internal argument against compatibilism in chapter four.
In the rest of the book, Caruso begins exploring the relationship between free-will and consciousness.
Throughout Free-Will and Consciousness Caruso simultaneously takes on libertarianism and
compatibilism on closely related but separate fronts. Against libertarianism, Caruso wants to dispose its
main virtue of the supposed phenomenology of conscious agency and free-will by offering us a
deterministic account of the illusion of free-will by appealing to David Rosenthal’s version of Higher
Order Thought (HOT) theory of consciousness12. Against compatibilism, Caruso argues that this
9
P.19
10
Robert Kane, A Contemporary Introduction to Free Will. (New York: Oxford University Press 1995)
11
Joshua Knobe and Shaun Nichols, Experimental philosophy. (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2008)
12
David Rosenthal. Consciousness and Mind. (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2005)
deterministic feeling of free-will is largely not under conscious executive control, but is run by the
adaptive unconscious and behaviour is automatically triggered nonconsciously by environmental
determinants. Any folk-psychological account of free-will that compatibilism should endorse without
appearing ad hoc should, as a necessary condition, have consciousness playing a leading role in initiating
and causing behaviour. The recent findings from the BCN show this is not the case.
Chapter four, ‘Free-Will and Consciousness (I) Automaticity and the Adaptive Unconscious’, explores
the compelling empirical research on the adaptive unconscious and the automaticity of higher processes.
Caruso sketches the adaptive unconscious as an evolutionary adaption which, as recent experiments in the
last twenty years have shown, regulates higher-level processes to the unconscious, just as the unconscious
is widely known to regulate sub-mental processes.
In regards to automaticity, Caruso demonstrates countless examples where the environment
unconsciously and automatically triggers a stereotype, which in turn causes us to act in unintended ways
without conscious control, deliberation, guidance or will. However, this review will only concentrate on
the question of whether the environment can trigger goal-directed behaviour nonconsciously without
conscious control. Following Bargh’s auto-motive goal-directed model13 that was developed in response
to this very question, it was found that “goal structures can be activated directly by relevant
environmental stimuli … goals, once activated, produce the same outcomes whether they are put in
motion by consciously made choice or through external stimuli.” The upshot of this model means that
subjects will behave in a goal-directed manner that was selected without conscious control or guidance in
that particular moment, although this goal-directed behaviour would have once been consciously chosen
before it was nonconsciously implemented. This was demonstrated in an experiment where subjects were
primed to behave in a co-operative manner in a fishing game where they could choose between behaving
in a competitive manner by maximising profits by keeping all the fishes they took from the lake or by
behaving in a co-operative manner by replenishing the lake by letting the fish go back into the lake.
Importantly, in these experiments the participants were both unaware that these goals had been activated
and also that they were behaving in a manner to achieve this co-operative goal. These experiments show
us ‘we fail to realize just how wide open our unconscious minds are, and how easily our decision making
is influenced by unnoticed environmental determinants.’14
Caruso says that ‘such results are disturbing precisely because they undermine our intuitive sense of
conscious control’15 and compatibilism is threatened by this because the picture of the adaptive
unconscious controlling the bulk of our day-to-day lives ‘is more threatening than normal determinist
arguments because it suggests we do not possess the kind of conscious executive control we typically
assume’16
Caruso is right to think that such experimental data pose a threat to the compatibilist sense of free-will by
undermining the folk-psychological notion of executive conscious control being the commander of our
moment to moment actions, but in no sense is this disastrous to their outlook. The compatibilist most
John Bargh, “Auto-motives: Preconscious determinants of social interaction” in Tory Higgins and Richard M.
Sorrentino (eds) Handbook of motivation and cognition, (New York: Guildford Press 1990) 93-140.
13
14
P.120
15
P.128
16
Ibid.
likely will have to make concessions in regards to this by admitting that free-will is not the director of all
decisions regarding our higher level mental processes, no matter how minor, since the experimental
evidence shows that the phenomenology of such a belief was misguided. This is not an ideal backward
step for them to make, but compatibilists might argue that real free-will consists in those moments when
consciousness control, self-control, deliberation and planning are causally efficacious in making real-life
decisions. Although Caruso argues there is not enough conscious control for us to be morally responsible
for our actions in the basic desert sense, Caruso himself does suggest that consciousness ‘plays an
important role in formulating long-term actions, plans and intentions’ although it does not initiate these
actions or cause these actions, consciousness also plays a role in ‘non-spontaneous decision making by
providing focal-attention to help prioritize and recruit subgoals and functions’17
It is a testament to Caruso’s internal argument against compatibilism that by invoking the threatening
implications of the adaptive unconscious and the automaticity of behaviour to the severely reduced
efficacy of conscious control to our numerous daily decisions that a fierce battleground between
compatibilism and incompatibilism will be fought in this arena: how much conscious control do we have
over our non-urgent moment to moment decisions? Does consciousness have a downstream effect on
these actions, behaviours and decisions? Is this enough conscious control for free-will and/ or moral
responsibility?
In chapter five, ‘Free Will and Consciousness (II) Transparency, Infallibility and Higher-Order Thought
(HOT) Theory’, Caruso argues that one of our defining features of consciousness, the apparent
transparency and infallibility of consciousness is a cognitive illusion that leads us wrongly to infer that we
are free and causally undetermined because we are unable to introspect the deterministic processes of our
decision making. To explain such a deterministic process and cognitive illusion, Caruso endorses
Rosenthal’s HOT version of the theory of consciousness. According to HOT theory, ‘a mental state is
conscious only if one is, in some suitable way, conscious of that state.’18 By the transparency of
consciousness, Caruso means that, we are conscious of everything in our minds. He argues convincingly
that there is ample evidence to suggest that consciousness is not transparent, and this was covered in the
bulk of chapter four, that many of our mental states, desires, intentions, judgements, beliefs and goals can
often occur unconsciously. By the infallibility of consciousness, Caruso means that we are certain about
the knowledge of our mental states and our judgments cannot be in error. He argues that the ability to
know our own mental states is limited, as consciousness, even via introspection, does not always
accurately represent our mental states to us. This leads us to confabulate reasons for acting, as our
conscious phenomenology for acting does not match up with our actual reasons for acting, as illustrated in
an example with hypnotized subjects, ‘[a]fter being hypnotized, subjects can enact a posthypnotic
suggestion –e.g., “when you awake you will be immediately crawl around on your hands and knees.”
When asked what they are doing, subjects almost immediately generate a rationale – “I think I lost an
earring down here192021. Moreover, it is intimated that confabulation of our reasons for acting happens on
17
P.201
18
P.156
19
Michael Gazzaniga, The Social Brain. (New York: Free Press 1985)
20
Ernest Hilgard, Hypnotic susceptibility. (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World 1965)
21
George Estabrooks, Hypnotism. (New York: E.P. Dutton 1943)
a daily basis) by arguing that we confabulate stories and create explanations as our conscious selves do
not fully know why we act in the way that we do22 23 24
Assuming that daily confabulation of reasons is true (although some philosophers doubt it) it poses some
deep and worrying problems for free-will when paired together with the situationist experiments. Reexamining the structure of confabulation, as the hypnotist example plainly illustrates, the supposed
phenomenology of the subject’s reasons for acting does not match up with the actual mechanism of the
reason for acting. Given the situationist experiments, the primary conclusion is that objects (banal
everyday objects like a Lucozade bottle, a briefcase etc.) in our environment can nonconsciously select
and influence our desires, motivations and goal-directed behaviour. The fundamental worry then is that
we can never be sure, despite our supposed infallible phenomenology, when we are actually acting for our
supposed reasons since nearly any object in the environment could be nonconsciously selecting our goaldirected behaviour without our awareness. The worry is not that we are always confabulating reasons, but
rather we are unsure when we are confabulating reasons and when we are not, as our phenomenology for
why we acted would still seem just as infallible, and we would be woefully ignorant that environmental
determinants have influenced our decision making processes.
In Chapter six, ‘Consciousness and Free Will (III): Intentional States’, Caruso focuses on two other
phenomenological features of consciousness. Firstly, our intentional states are causally undetermined and
arise spontaneously. Secondly, our feeling of conscious will: the feeling that we consciously initiate our
behaviour through our conscious intentions and desires.
To start with the former, Caruso believes that the feeling that our intentional states are casually
undetermined is crucial to our illusory belief that we have free-will, as we are not conscious that our
intentions and desires are themselves causally determined. This gives us a sense of freedom with our
actions that our actions are free. This can be explained by HOT theory. According to HOT, the HOT’s are
unable to represent the original causes of our desires and intentions so we are unable to remain aware of
the causes of our desires and intentions.
In regards to the latter, Caruso discusses the infamous Libet experiments that he believes successfully
undermine a major part of the folk psychology of free-will, that our conscious intentions and willing’s
cause our actions. For the sake of brevity, I will not explain the Libet experiment here, but the
conclusions of his and similar experiments is that for simple motor actions, such as tapping your fingers
on the desk, it appears that we have an unconscious intention to tap our fingers (called a readiness
potential RP) before we have the conscious intention to tap our fingers. The Libet experiment, Caruso
argues, suggest that conscious will is an illusion – it is not the case that we consciously initiate actions
through our conscious intentions or decisions, rather our intentions and actions are initiated
unconsciously.
In Chapter seven, ‘Consciousness and Free-Will (IV): Self-Consciousness and Our Sense of Agency’,
Caruso argues that the illusion of free-will is maintained by our sense of agency that includes the two
22
Timothy Wilson, Strangers to ourselves: Discovering the adaptive unconscious. (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press
of Harvard University Press 2000)
Richard Nisbett and Timothy Wilson, “Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes”
1977, 84 Psychological Review: 231
23
24
Michael Gazzaniga and Joseph LeDoux, The integrated mind. (New York: Plenum 1978)
subjective components of ownership (characterized as I am experiencing the movement or thought) and of
authorship (characterized as I initiate an action through my will). To account for this sense of agency,
philosophers, theologians and laypeople have postulated the existence of a unified Self to account for this
wilful behaviour, this is Caruso’s target in this chapter.
The subjective experience of ownership can be explained away by the way in which HOT’s represent
their target mental states by employing the indexical concept “I”, which not only makes one conscious of
the target state, but also a sense of self to which the target state is represented as having by the HOT.
However, in medical diseases like alien hand syndrome or schizophrenia (especially in the case of thought
insertion), Caruso argues, the sense of ownership over our actions breaks down due to a self-identification
error over our thoughts and actions which we do not ascribe to our unified self or sense of agency. To
account for a sense of unity of our conscious, as well as HOT’s employing the essential indexical in
representing its target state, in introspective consciousness (when I have a third-order thought of the HOT
– which makes the HOT itself conscious) we identify that all of one’s conscious states belong to a single
unified conscious subject, and we identify on a range of considerations from ‘personal history, bodily
features, and psychological characteristics to current location and situation ‘.25
Accounting for a sense of agency, Caruso moves on to answering the question: what accounts for the
experience of wilfully initiating action, being the author of my own actions, having the self-as-cause? He
argues that ‘the relevant intentions and thoughts that precede an action are tagged with a sense of self (i.e.
if they are experienced as owned by a seemingly unified self), and (a) the subsequent action is perceived
as consistent with those thoughts, and (b) there are no other competing causes available for the action …
on this account, one experiences a sense of self-generation or authorship when they draw causal
inferences relating prior self-ascribed thoughts with consistent and self-ascribed actions.’26
An extended argument based on Caruso’s adaptive unconscious
Let us return to chapter four, Caruso discusses an experiment that reveals the utility of the adaptive
unconscious. The IOWA Gambling Task is an experiment that is designed to test real-life decision
making performance27. The subject sits in front of four card decks labelled A, B, C and D, is given $2000
facsimile money and told to earn as much money as possible and to lose as little as possible. The turning
of the decks A and B will yield a larger reward than decks C and D (say $100 to $50 respectively), but the
losses in decks C and D are much smaller and less regular than A and B. Over a sustained period of time,
picking only the A and B decks will give you losses in the long run, but continually choosing decks C and
D will give slow and steady monetary gain. Typically, the experiment lasts for a hundred turnings of the
cards, but the subject will be unaware how long it will last for, and will be told to continue with the
experiment until it is time to stop.
Bechara et al. found that participants began to choose advantageously before they consciously realized
which strategy worked best. He found that after about ten cards participants began to generate
anticipatory skin conductance responses (e.g., their palms began to sweat) whenever they pondered a
25
P.229
26
P.243
Antoine Bechara et al, “Deciding advantageously before knowing the advantageous strategy”. (1997) 275 Science,
1293
27
choice that turned out to be risky, before they knew explicitly it was a risky choice. At about the same
time (around ten cards) they began to avoid decks with large losses. It wasn’t until much later, at about
eighty cards, that they were able to explain why decks C and D were better in the long run. And it wasn’t
until about fifty cards – forty cards after the gamblers started generating stress responses to the risky
decks – that they were able to say they had a “hunch” that something was wrong with those decks.
Bechara et al. concluded: ‘The results suggest that, in normal individuals, nonconscious biases guide
behaviour before conscious knowledge does’
Caruso uses this example from cognitive neuroscience to demonstrate that our adaptive unconscious
undermines the following assumption: ‘Most of us assume that our decisions and actions are guided by
conscious executive control. We assume that we are consciously and systematically processing incoming
information in order to construe and interpret our world and to plan and engage in courses of action.’ 28
Caruso demonstrates an admirable point about how our adaptive unconscious undermines the executive
conscious control we have regarding day-to-day events. However, the notion of adaptive unconscious can
be pushed further to demonstrate how important it is as a potentially crucial factor in an agent’s decision
making process that may affect his life in significant ways.
Before continuing, I will briefly describe the patients suffering from ventromedial prefrontal lobe
damage, to whom the healthy controls were compared to as a paradigm for abnormal decision making
processes. Bechara et al29 noticed that individuals who suffered specifically from ventromedial prefrontal
lobe damage as compared to general brain damage had abnormal decision making tendencies. It was often
the case that patient E.V.R, a prototypical example of this condition, ‘often decides against his best
interest, and is unable to learn from his mistakes. His decisions repeatedly lead to negative consequences.’
In the IOWA gambling task, similar to the controls, patients with ventromedial prefrontal lobe damage
began by sampling both the good (C-D) and bad (A-B) decks, but instead of remaining the majority of the
time like the controls with the advantageous decks, these patients returned frequently to the
disadvantageous decks.
Now, I will explore whether there is a link between abnormal decision making tendencies and what we
would typically describe as a paradigm example of a life that is the outcome of bad decision making
consequences, such as being in jail.
Recent research has tested the differences between healthy controls and criminals (who are physically and
psychologically healthy) on the IOWA gambling task. A paper from Yechiam30 that tested this hypothesis
states that our results ‘provide support for the similarity hypothesis31 in that criminals, in general, made
poor decisions characterized by failure to learn from repeated mistakes … Although both prisoners and
healthy controls preferred the disadvantageous decks initially, only the control group eventually learned
28
P.113
Antoine Bechara et al, “Insensitivity to future consequences following damage to human prefrontal cortex,”
(1994) 50 Cognition, 7
29
Eldad Yechiam et al. “Neurocognitive deficits related to poor decision-making in people behind bars.” (2008)
15(1) Psychonomic Bulletin & Review: 44
30
31
Michael Gottfredson and Travis Hirschi, General Theory of Crime. (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press
1990)
to strongly prefer the advantageous decks. None of the prisoner groups learned to prefer the advantageous
decks by the end of the task.’32
This conclusion sounds remarkably similar to the patients that suffered from ventromedial prefrontal
cortex (vmPFC) damage. Could it be the case that criminals suffer from a decision making abnormality
analogous to those with vmPFC damage without the physical damage? Potentially so when we consider
that long-term cocaine abuse also damages decision making in the vmPFC33. The results from Yechiam et
al34 continue ‘drug and sex offenders, and to some extent, OWI [dangerous driving] and theft criminals as
well, behaved similarly to chronic cocaine abusers [on the IOWA gambling test]. Compared to controls,
these groups weighted gains more than losses … Cocaine abuse has been linked to a reduction in the level
of the neurotransmitter dopamine, which has a central role in reward learning. Using cocaine results in an
increase in exhilaration to immediate gains35 It is therefore not surprising that forms of crimes
characterized by addiction (e.g. drug and sex crimes) are associated with a similar tendency to prefer
alternatives that produce high gains and discount their potential losses36.’
Based on the previous discussion, what does it mean that all the criminals that participated in this
experiment did not choose the advantageous decks over the disadvantageous decks? And, in this context,
what is the relationship between the adaptive unconscious and the criminal in the sample represented? 37
Before investigating these questions, it is worth noting some preliminary caveats about the IOWA
gambling task. Firstly, as mentioned earlier in the text, each participant understands that the objective of
the game is to maximise as much profit as possible. Thus, we shall assume, that barring any psychological
illnesses, participants would know that by choosing the advantageous decks over the disadvantageous
decks they were acting in their own best interests. Secondly, the rules of the game are fully explained to
each participant, and their understanding of the rules and objectives of the game are tested for satisfactory
32
Emphasis mine
33
A Verdejo-Garcia et al, Emotion, decision-making and substance dependence: a somatic-marker model of
addiction. (2006) 4 Current Neuropharmacology: 17
Eldad Yechiam et al. “Neurocognitive deficits related to poor decision-making in people behind bars.” (2008)
15(1) Psychonomic Bulletin & Review: 44
34
35
A McGregor and D Roberts, Dopaminergic antagonism within the nucleus accumbens or the amygdala produces
differential effects on intravenous cocaine self-administration under fixed and progressive ratio schedules of
reinforcement. (1993) 624 Brain Research: 245
36
Though it needs further investigation as to whether one of the potential determining factors for the behaviour of
criminals is due to reduction in dopamine, these conclusions show that when it comes to decision making
supposedly mentally healthy individuals criminals display similar cognitive decision making errors of chronic
cocaine addicts. This disturbing implication raises some serious questions, such as the following, which will not be
followed up here, if we class individuals suffering from long-term cocaine addiction with diminished responsibility
(in the non-hard determinist metaphysics utilised by the court of law) should particular sub-set of supposedly
healthy criminals with decision making abnormalities have diminished responsibility for their actions as well?
37
It should be stressed that this discussion is focused on the criminals that participated in the IOWA gambling task
within this paper. This article does not assume the following statements: (a) that all individuals who lack the
adaptive unconscious are motivated to become criminals; (b) that you cannot commit criminal behaviour without
lacking the adaptive unconscious mechanism; (c) that a criminal cannot successfully pass the IOWA gambling task;
(d) committing a crime is directly due to not understanding your best interests
comprehension before the task can begin. This ensures that failing at the task cannot be due to a lack of
information.
So, what is the best explanation that all the criminals who participated in the experiment preferred the
disadvantaged decks?
Two brief reasonable explanations can be considered. Firstly, the criminals did have the nonconscious
mechanisms similar to the healthy controls to stay away from the “bad decks” but they preferred these
decks over the “good decks” anyways due to the high immediate gains of this deck. However, this
explanation appears unsatisfying if we assume that individuals typically act what appears to them to be in
their own self-interests, as repeatedly choosing the “bad decks” would contradict this notion (since it is
against the objective of the task).
This leads us to the second explanation which is much stronger: the criminals did not receive the
nonconscious mechanism that the disadvantageous “bad decks” were A and B like the healthy controls
did; (b) these criminals, for unknown decision making reasons, do not know which decks are in their best
interests, so they systemically prefer the decks which give them immediate gains and highs, like longterm cocaine abusers. Similar to long-term cocaine abusers that suffer from reduced dopamine levels,
these criminals do not learn from their repeated mistakes of choosing this “bad deck” and since they are
more focused on the immediate gains they do not worry about the long-term losses. So, unlike healthy
controls who eventually realise the advantageous decks compared to criminals, this appears to highlight
that it is not in the conscious executive control for the criminal to realise that he should be preferring the
“good decks” C and D rather than the “bad decks” A and B.
To briefly recap the argument so far, the IOWA gambling task is a decision making tool that simulates
real life decision making. In a recent experiment that utilised the task, all the criminals that participated in
the task failed to prefer the advantageous decks, whilst the majority of the healthy controls learned to do
so. Cognitive neuroscience experiments have demonstrated that these healthy controls have a
nonconscious mechanism (the adaptive unconscious) which produces physiological symptoms in the
healthy control at the start of the experiment when they are initially preferring the bad decks which
consists of cards which have immediate gains and large losses. These physiological symptoms, such as
sweaty palms, were unconscious indications that influenced the healthy controls to realise that preferring
these bad decks were a risky choice which should eventually be avoided. The best explanation which
accounts to why all the criminals failed the task was due to their lack of having the non-conscious
mechanism. It appears not to be in the conscious executive control of the criminal that he should prefer
the “good decks.”
If it were the case that consciously criminals may figure out which were the “good decks” and which were
the “bad decks” then you would expect to find a few criminals act in a similar manner to the healthy
controls on the test, even if it took them longer to come to this realisation. However, this is not the case,
as all the criminals that participated systematically and frequently preferred the “bad decks” in a similar
manner to patients suffering from vmPFC damage and long-term cocaine abuse. This suggests that these
criminals all had abnormal decision making processes, despite any physical manifestations of brain
damage, which meant that they would act against their best (not self) interest, repeatedly failing to learn
from their mistakes, and make decisions that would lead to negative consequences. This all stemmed from
factors which were out of their control beginning with the adaptive unconscious failing to reveal the best
interests (in this context, the “best decks”) to the criminal, as a consequence of this his consciousness
could never reveal to him his best interests, which entailed it was never in the conscious executive control
of the criminal to initiate action and behaviour in his best interests.
The criminals whom participated in the experiment had deficiencies in their adaptive unconsciousness
that led to abnormal decision making tendencies that were not prevalent in the majority of the healthy
controls. These decision making tendencies in some sense had to lead to circumstances that led to the
criminals being in jail.38
Conclusion
In conclusion, Free Will and Consciousness is highly recommended as it convincingly sets out to achieve
what it desires: provide a compelling determinist account of consciousness that accounts for the
libertarian phenomenology of free will, whilst at the same time its comprehensive account of
consciousness provides a threatening innovative internal challenge to compatibilism. Lastly, the vast
amount of neuroscience research conducted in this monograph is staggering, including insights ranging
from Jeannerod on motor control to Frith’s neurocognitive model in schizophrenia. No stone is left
untouched in the domain of scientific research.
38
Whether this deficiency in the adaptive unconscious directly motivated the criminal act is irrelevant. What
matters is that the criminal that participated in the experiment had an abnormal decision making process
(suggested by failing the IOWA gambling task), due to a deficiency in the adaptive unconscious. These decisions
eventually caused the individual to go to jail for committing a criminal act.
References
John Bargh, Auto-motives: Preconscious determinants of social interaction in Tory Higgins and Richard
M. Sorrentino (eds) Handbook of motivation and cognition, (New York: Guildford Press 1990) 93-140.
Antoine Bechara et al, Deciding advantageously before knowing the advantageous strategy . (1997)
275 Science, 1293
Antoine Bechara et al, I se siti it to futu e o se ue es follo i g da age to hu a p ef o tal
o te , (1994) 50 Cognition, 7
Gregg Caruso, Free Will and Consciousness. (Lexington Books 2012)
George Estabrooks, Hypnotism. (New York: E.P. Dutton 1943)
Michael Gazzaniga, The Social Brain. (New York: Free Press 1985)
Michael Gazzaniga and Joseph LeDoux, The integrated mind. (New York: Plenum 1978)
Ernest Hilgard, Hypnotic susceptibility. (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World 1965)
Robert Kane, A Contemporary Introduction to Free Will. (New York: Oxford University Press 1995)
Joshua Knobe and Shaun Nichols, Experimental philosophy. (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2008)
Neil Levy, Hard Luck: How Luck Undermines Free Will and Moral Responsibility. (Oxford: Oxford
University Press 2011)
Benjamin Li et, U o s ious Ce e al I itiati e a d the Role of Co s ious Will i Volu ta
(1985), 8(4) Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8(4): 529
A tio
Richard Nisbett and Timothy Wilson, Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental
processes 1977, 84 Psychological Review: 231
Derk Pereboom, Living Without Free Will. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2001)
Saul Smilansky, Free Will and Illusion. (New York: Oxford University Press 2000)
Timothy Wilson, Strangers to ourselves: Discovering the adaptive unconscious. (Cambridge, MA: Belknap
Press of Harvard University Press 2000)
Eldad Yechiam et al. Neurocognitive deficits related to poor decision-making in people behind bars.
(2008) 15(1) Psychonomic Bulletin & Review: 44
Michael Gottfredson and Travis Hirschi, General Theory of Crime. (Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press 1990)
A McGregor and D Roberts, Dopaminergic antagonism within the nucleus accumbens or the amygdala
produces differential effects on intravenous cocaine self-administration under fixed and progressive
ratio schedules of reinforcement. (1993) 624 Brain Research: 245
A Verdejo-Garcia et al, Emotion, decision-making and substance dependence: a somatic-marker model
of addiction. (2006) 4 Current Neuropharmacology: 17
David Rosenthal, Consciousness and Mind. (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2005)