Defining “Development”
Thomas Pradeu, Lucie Laplane, Karine Prévot, Thierry Hoquet, Valentine Reynaud,
Giuseppe Fusco, Alessandro Minelli, Virginie Orgogozo, Michel Vervoort
To appear in a special anniversary issue of Current Topics in Development Biology,
edited by Paul Wassarman
“one cannot present a science without at the same time defining its terms”
(Leibniz, New Essays on Human Understanding)
“Insistence on the postulate of complete logical clarification would make science impossible”
(Heisenberg, Physics and Philosophy)
Abstract
Is it possible, and in the first place is it even desirable, to define what “development” means,
and to determine the scope of the field called “developmental biology”? Though these
questions appeared crucial for the founders of “developmental biology” in the 1950s, there
seems to be no consensus today about the need to address them. Here, in a combined
biological, philosophical, and historical approach, we ask whether it is possible and useful to
define biological development, and, if such a definition is indeed possible and useful, which
definition(s) can be considered as the most satisfactory.
Keywords
Development; embryology; developmental biology; scientific discipline; definition.
Introduction
How can we define “development”? And, in the first place, why should anyone care about a
definition of development? Despite the existence of a well-established and dynamic scientific
field called “developmental biology”, those two questions are hardly ever raised today
(Minelli and Pradeu 2014). Etymologically, “development” means “unfolding”, that is, the
progressive unfolding of a preexistent form or preexistent capacities. But very few would
endorse today this form of preformationism, which neglects interactions with the environment
and stochastic effects (Lewontin 2000).
In recent years, only a handful of developmental biologists have ventured to define
“development” in research papers or books (exceptions include Coen 1999 and Davidson
2001), and definitions of development are found mainly in textbooks. A frequent textbook
definition is “the process through which a single cell – often a fertilized egg – gives rise to a
complex multicellular organism” (Wolpert and Tickle 2011; see also Slack 1991; MartinezArias and Stewart 2002). Yet this definition has sometimes been criticized for its
“adultocentrism” (Bonner 1965; Minelli 2003), and the exclusion of unicellular organisms,
many forms of asexual reproduction where development starts from a multicellular stage, as
well as the phenomena of regeneration and ageing. Others have suggested to define
development as all the changes that occur in a given organism from its beginning to its death
(e.g., Oyama 2000; West-Eberhard 2003; Gilbert 2013), a definition perhaps too broad, as it
would include virtually all physiological processes (Pradeu et al. 2011). It seems, therefore,
1
that many developmental biologists would agree with Guirao and Aréchaga (1989) that “the
term ‘development’ is difficult to define”, and few try to offer an explicit definition.
But should developmental biologists really care about defining development? The
current research field of developmental biology offers an interesting and contrasting situation
with regard to this question. In an attempt to better characterize this situation, we asked all the
contributors to the present special issue of CTDB the two following questions: i) Do you think
that it is important, for your scientific work in developmental biology, to define the word
“development”?; ii) How, according to you, should the notion of “development” be defined?
Among the 24 contributors who accepted to answer our mini-survey, 13 of them (54%)
consider that they do not need a definition of development, while 11 (46%) believe exactly
the opposite. Moreover, these 24 contributors propose diverse definitions that disclose several
points of dissension, such as whether development should include regeneration, ageing, or the
idea of increasing complexity when an organism matures. Of course, the sample of our survey
is far too small to draw any definitive conclusion. And yet both our survey and a careful study
of past and present literature in developmental biology suggest a lack of consensus about what
belongs to “development” or “developmental biology”, and what does not.
The term “developmental biology” came to encompass and replace, in intellectual
societies and journals, the older labels of “embryology” and “growth” (or “growth and
differentiation”) at the end of the 1950s (Gilbert 1991: ix; Burian and Thieffry 2000; Crowe et
al. 2015). In fact, the questions of what development means and how extensive developmental
biology should be were crucial for the biologists who, immediately after the Second World
War, participated in the construction of the emerging discipline that came to be called
“developmental biology”. In the Foreword of the very first issue of the Journal of Embryology
and Experimental Morphology (renamed Development in 1986), Albert M. Dalcq (1953)
announces that, with the advent of “the science of development”, embryologists witness “an
extraordinary extension of their field”, in depth (the reach of the “macromolecular level”),
space (the progressive establishment of a “common denominator” of morphogenesis,
regeneration, asexual reproduction, and embryonic development), and time (the gradual
effacement of “the conventional boundaries between the biological phases of life”, with a
shift of attention from early embryonic phases only to a much broader focus on
cytodifferentiation, growth, and even continuous re-construction throughout life and ageing).
In a similar vein, in his Introduction to the first issue of the US journal Developmental
Biology, Paul Weiss (1959) suggests that many seemingly isolated phenomena studied
hitherto by embryologists, plant physiologists, nutritionists, or oncologists, constitute in fact
“one continuous spectrum”, unified by the “same basic principles” of growth, differentiation,
morphogenesis, maturation, ageing, regulation, and regeneration, which all together constitute
“development”.
Because of the remarkable successes of developmental biology from the 1950s to the
present day, its current practitioners do not focus as ardently as their predecessors on the
question of how to define the term “development” and how to delineate its scope. Importantly,
though, this question has not entirely disappeared. For example, the British Society of
Developmental Biology recently considered whether its name should change to the “British
Society of Developmental Biology and Stem Cells”, illustrating “heated discussion in the
developmental biology community about what its relationship should be to the stem cell field”
(St Johnston 2015).
Thus, it appears that there was not, and there still is not, any strong consensus among
developmental biologists about both the definition of development and the delineation of the
domain of developmental biology. In this essay, our aim is to determine whether today’s
developmental biologists should, as their predecessors of the 1950s did, seek a definition and
a delineation of development. More precisely, we address, in a combined biological,
2
philosophical, and historical approach, the vexing problem of whether it is possible and useful
to define biological development, and, if such a definition is possible and useful, which
definition(s) should be used.
1. Should we try to define development? No, we should not
1.1. It is useless
As illustrated by several sharp answers to our survey, many biologists feel that attempting to
define development is simply useless. Biologists are generally interested in specific empirical
studies, that is, studies of precise mechanisms in a given model organism (e.g., gene
expression during embryogenesis in the sea urchin, or Wnt signaling in the formation of the
chick’s neural crest, or auxin signaling in the formation of a plant embryo root). Therefore, it
may seem that general definitions are not useful for the work that really matters, namely
experimentation. If, in practice, developmental biologists can perfectly do their research
without ever wondering about what development means, then why should they care?
A precise definition can even be considered as a hindrance for doing practical research
in developmental biology. Most scientific concepts remain undefined, implicit, and this is not
an obstacle for everyday science (Kuhn 1962). According to many historians of science,
conceptual fuzziness is widespread in science, and even fruitful (Rheinberger 2000; Keller
2002). Some degree of imprecision can contribute to foster communication between scientists,
both within a scientific domain and between domains. For example, Keller (2002: 181) claims
that it is largely because of its malleability that the concept of positional information (Wolpert
1968) became popular and fruitful, that is, extensively used and discussed until today.
1.2. It is impossible
A different attitude consists in saying that defining development, as useful as it might be, is in
fact impossible. In nature, developmental phenomena are so diverse that it would make no
sense to pretend that one single definition could bring together all these processes. First, the
word “development” can be applied to many organisms across species. Would it not be
hazardous to assert that this same word might be applied to plants, microbes, and animals all
alike? It seems likely that every general definition of development will inevitably meet with
some exceptions (Minelli 2014). Second, it covers phenomena situated at many different
levels (molecular, cellular, and so on). Third, it encompasses a series of generally successive
and heterogeneous processes, such as, in animals, fertilization, cleavage, gastrulation,
organogenesis and, sometimes, metamorphosis and regeneration. Faced with such a
multifaceted diversity, how could developmental biologists offer one single, unifying,
definition of development?
Instead of searching for the meaning of development per se, one might try to define a
series of more specific terms, like “cell differentiation,” “morphogenesis”, and
“organogenesis”. For this strategy to be successful, these processes themselves need to be
defined. But, to define a word, one must use other words, which themselves might prove
difficult to define – a process that could lead to an infinite regress. Potential definitions of
“development” are often circumlocutions involving other terms like “morphogenesis,” “shape,”
“irreversibility,” “pattern,” “complexity,” but generally those terms are themselves
particularly difficult to define (see Table 1).
2. Should we try to define development? Yes, we should
2.1. To delineate developmental biology as a field of study
3
A definition of development allows to delineate the domain of developmental biology as a
scientific field, that is, to determine which living things and processes should be considered as
subjects of developmental studies. Now, many biologists might say that they do not care
about a definition of development, but, presumably, not so many would say that defining the
research field named “developmental biology” is useless. Interestingly, several people who
answered our survey remark that biologists often disagree on whether certain processes – e.g.,
fertilization, regeneration – and certain organisms – e.g., plants – are part of developmental
biology. This problem is all but marginal: clarifying what falls under the scope of
“developmental biology” is crucial to compare different experimental settings and models,
and to determine how each may shed light on the others. As mentioned previously, defining
the scope of their field was one of the most pressing issues for the scientists involved in the
advent of “developmental biology” in the 1950s. For Paul Weiss (1959), in a time of
“progressive splintering of older disciplines into ever smaller and narrower technical
specialties”, the then emerging field of “developmental biology” aimed at doing exactly the
opposite, that is, “to promote the confluence and integration of related, but formerly isolated,
lines.”
Two examples illustrate why this question is still very important today. The first
example concerns the place of plants in developmental biology. The question of whether
plants should be included in the domain of embryology was raised as early as the first half of
the 19th century (e.g., Schleiden 1848). Including or excluding plants from the study of
development changes our vision of development: it questions whether development continues
in adulthood (Steeves and Sussex 1989), whether regeneration is part of development
(Birnbaum and Sanchez Alvarado 2008), and whether development should be defined
molecularly (in which case “development” would mean two different things for plants and for
animals) or rather at the level of general principles (in which case there may exist a unified
meaning of development, adequate for both plants and animals) (Meyerowitz 2002; Vervoort
2014).
In a similar vein, an interesting debate today is whether unicellular organisms should
be included into the study of development (O’Malley and Dupré 2007; Love and Travisano
2013), and if the term “development” means the same thing when applied to multicellular
organisms only (a very common practice among developmental biologists), or to unicellular
organisms as well. Though textbooks and meetings in developmental biology do not, in
general, include unicellular organisms, there has existed for more than thirty years a dynamic
field self-identified as “developmental microbiology” (e.g., Peberdy 1980). Furthermore,
multiple observations argue for their inclusion. Several unicellular organisms, such as
Acetabularia (Dumais, Serikawa and Mandoli 2000), social amoebae (Bonner 2009), and
bacteria (Peberdy 1980; Kroos and Maddock 2003) can be said to “develop”, in the sense that
they undergo important and stereotyped morphogenetic changes during their life cycle,
including morphogenesis, cellular differentiation, and intercellular signaling (Shimkets 1999;
Straight and Kolter 2009). A precise definition of development should reach a verdict on
whether unicellular organisms are to be included in “developmental biology”, and, perhaps
most importantly, this would help to determine how studies done on microbes and those done
on non-microbial entities could inspire each other.
Another similar question, which we mention only briefly here, is whether the notion of
development can be applied to cognition and behavior (Gottlieb 1992; Oyama, Griffiths and
Gray 2001). Here again, the only way to address such a question is to offer a definition of
development.
In addition, an explicit description of what belongs to developmental biology and what
does not can be useful from a purely institutional point of view. To have a clear view of
which journals, scientific societies, scientific meetings, funding opportunities, or academic
4
positions belong to developmental biology, it is necessary to know, if only at a very general
level, what development means. In line with Weiss’s aim, defining development and
delineating the domain of developmental biology can be useful to foster intellectual
collaborations and to give rise to a feeling to belong to a shared “community”, by bringing
together biologists with the same type of questions or approaches, and using the same kind of
vocabulary.
2.2. For considering development within more inclusive processes
In science, whenever you decide to study a process which involves the transformation of
something, either through time or space or otherwise, you have to define this something,
operationally at least, in order to trace its change. This is the case of development in the
context of evolution (e.g., evolution of development), or in the context of ecology (e.g.,
environmentally induced developmental responses). In other words, when development is
viewed from the perspective of a more inclusive process, you need to define it. Current,
sometimes pragmatic, available definitions are restricted to specific developmental processes
(e.g., gastrulation, or prefoliation, see section 1.2), which merely allow studying the
evolutionary history of these specific processes, but do not allow investigating more general
issues, as for instance the role of developmental plasticity in the wider theoretical context of
evolutionary models (Fusco and Minelli 2010).
2.3. For communication with the public and legal purposes
Even biologists who are skeptical about the need to define development in their own
specialized domain would probably agree that defining development could be important for
non-biologists. First, anyone who teaches developmental biology knows that students find
definitions extremely useful. Second, many political and legal debates (for example those
related to abortion, assisted reproductive technologies, or the legal status of the fetus)
presuppose to have clear notions of “embryo” and “development”, for which politicians and
judges require the help of biologists. In agreement with Maienschein (2014), we are not
suggesting here that our ethical conceptions should be based on biological data, but rather that
legal decisions should not be in direct conflict with established scientific knowledge, and that,
if developmental biologists could provide a clear definition of development and related
notions, this would facilitate scientifically informed law making.
2.4. To overcome implicit meanings
Even when left undefined, a concept like “development” often has an implicit meaning,
generally rooted in a common background (acquired through education and lab practices) or
in intuitions, rather than cautious scientific considerations. Developmental biologists who say
that they do not have, and do not need, a definition of development actually do have in mind
implicit conceptions of development, which can bias their views and have negative effects on
research and discoveries. For example, the idea that development is intrinsically a
construction, and not destruction, almost certainly slowed down research on the role of
apoptosis in development (Saunders 1966; Baehrecke 2002). Another telling example
concerns the influence of genes on development. That genes play a key role in development is
beyond doubt, and an impressive achievement of developmental biology from the 1950s to
the present day has been the detailed molecular description of how developmental genes work
(Wolpert 1994; Gilbert 1998). That being said, the long-prevailing view that development is
to a large extent “autonomous” with regard to the environment and genetically determined has
oriented research towards “internal” and deterministic components of development, and this
implicit assumption led to neglect other, potentially crucial, interactions with “external”
factors (Gilbert and Bolker 2003; Sultan 2015), such as temperature, predators, symbionts
5
(Gilbert and Epel 2009), or stochastic processes such as developmental noise (Lewontin 2000)
and somatic mutations during normal development (Campbell et al. 2015).
For example, it has been widely assumed that the way immune systems develop and
enable hosts to resist diseases was to a large extent dependent on genetic factors. Now, in a
striking recent study on human monozygotic and dizygotic twins, Mark Davis’ group at
Stanford showed that environmental effects are much more important than genetic factors in
determining how the adaptive immune system develops and makes the organism resistant to
diseases (Brodin et al. 2015). Because of an unquestioned conviction that genes played a
major role in the development of the immune system, these environmental factors (especially
previous microbial exposures, vaccinations, diet, and dental hygiene) had not been thoroughly
investigated.
Importantly, the neglect of environmental factors is to some extent related to the
choice of model organisms. Many “classic” model organisms in developmental biology were
chosen in part because they were relatively robust under environmental perturbation (Bolker
1995). In turn, results obtained in these models have tended to reinforce the view that all
development is regulated from inside the egg, and that “outdoor” experiments were
unnecessary (Gilbert and Bolker 2003).
Thus, it can be argued that most developmental biologists, even those who say they do
not need a definition of development, do in fact have implicit conceptions of development,
which can affect their practical research. Having a definition of development can help making
explicit these otherwise implicit assumptions, and perhaps overcoming them.
3. Analysis of a few possible definitions of “development”
For those who think that defining development is important, an open question is how exactly
should the notion of development be defined. Table 1 presents common definitions of
development, with their proponents (mostly scientists, though some of them are philosophers
or historians), and the potential difficulties they raise.
Definition
Process through which a single cell
gives
rise
to
a
complex
multicellular organism
Proponents
Barinaga (1994); Coen (1999);
Martinez-Arias
and
Stewart
(2002); Wolpert and Tickle (2011)
Elaboration of a new individual
form
Amundson (1994)
Love (2008)
Pradeu (2014: 15)
Slack (2013: 3)
Change of biological form through
time
Temporal change of organization
along the life cycle
Biological
readout
of
the
genomically
encoded
gene
networks that determine how the
organism is constructed
Waddington (1956: 3); Oyama
(2000); Oyama, Griffiths and Gray
(2001); Minelli (2003); WestEberhard (2003: 32); Gilbert
(2013)
Davidson (2001); Peter and
Davidson (2015)
6
Possible difficulties
- Excludes several important
developmental processes, e.g.,
regeneration
- Excludes many organisms (e.g.,
uncellulars), and several forms of
asexual reproduction
- “Adultocentrism”
(on these three aspects, see Minelli
2003)
- Difficult to define the notions of
“new”, “shape” or “form”
- Difficult to define “form”
Difficult
to
distinguish
development from metabolism
- Difficult to define “organization”
- Lacks specificity, as it includes
too many biological phenomena
- Ignores the role of other factors
that can control development, such
as hormones, mechanical forces
and environmental factors (Gilbert
Irreversible increase of complexity
over time
Arthur (1997: 277).
Restriction of possible outcomes Johnson (2001)
(specialization) and increase in
levels of organization.
Table 1. Some possible definitions of development
2002)
- Difficult to define “complexity”
- There are cases where
development
seems
to
be
associated with a decrease in
complexity, in particular during
metamorphosis of sessile or
parasitic animals (e.g., ascidians,
Sacculina)
Depends on the level considered
Obviously, this table is not exhaustive; our aim is simply to open the discussion about
possible definitions, on the basis of suggestions regularly found in the literature. Also, this
does not entail that anyone interested in defining the notion of “development” would have to
adopt a unique definition; quite the contrary, it is certainly possible to combine several
definitions, among those listed here, or others. Because of the relative malleability of the term
“development,” one interesting possibility could even be to articulate a “cluster” definition of
development, with at its core the processes that everyone considers as part of development
(e.g., gastrulation in metazoans, or seed germination in spermatophyta), and satellite
processes that at least some specialists consider as part of development (e.g., fertilization,
regeneration). Further investigations will have to determine whether elaborating such a
“cluster” definition is possible, and whether it is considered as useful by a number of
practicing developmental biologists.
Conclusion
So, should developmental biologists care about defining development? Overall, we believe
that arguments in favor of a definition of development prevail. First, it is crucial to determine
which subjects belong to “developmental biology” and to distinguish this domain from other
biological fields. Second, even when people claim to have no definition of development, they
have in mind an implicit conception that impacts their research, highlighting the need to make
explicit the implicit. Clarifying the meaning of scientific notions can be a remarkable way to
reflect on what we hitherto got right or wrong, and therefore decide on where to go in the
future.
Acknowledgments
We thank Paul Wassarman for his invitation to contribute to the present special issue of
CTDB. We also thank Wallace Arthur, Jean Gayon, Alain Ghysen, Scott Gilbert, Paul
Griffiths, Jane Maienschein, Michel Morange, Maureen O’Malley, Susan Oyama, and Karola
Stotz for their help.
References
Amundson, R. (1994). Two Concepts of Constraint: Adaptationism and the Challenge from
Developmental Biology. Philosophy of Science, 61(4), 556-578.
Arthur, W. (1997). The Origin of Animal Body Plans. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Baehrecke, E.H. (2002). How death shapes life during development. Nature Reviews
Molecular Cell Biology, 3(10), 779-787.
Barinaga, M (1994). Looking to development’s future. Science 266: 561–564.
7
Birnbaum, K.D. & Sanchez Alvarado, A. (2008). Slicing across Kingdoms: Regeneration in
Plants and Animals. Cell, 132, 697-710.
Bolker, J. (1995). Model systems in developmental biology. Bioessays, 17, 451-455.
Bonner, J.T. (1965). Size and Cycle: An Essay on the Structure of Biology. Princeton
University Press, Princeton.
Bonner, J.T. (2009). The Social Amoebae: the Biology of Cellular Slime Molds. Princeton
University Press, Princeton.
Brodin, P. et al. (2015). Variation in the Human Immune System Is Largely Driven by NonHeritable Influences. Cell, 160, 37–47.
Burian, R. & Thieffry, D. (2000). Introduction to the Special Issue ‘From Embryology to
Developmental Biology’. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 3, 313-323.
Campbell, I.M., Shaw, C.A., Stankiewicz, P. & Lupski, J.R. (2015). Somatic mosaicism:
implications for disease and transmission genetics. Trends in Genetics, 31, 382–392.
Coen, E. (1999). The Art of Genes. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Crowe, N. et al. (2015). The diversification of developmental biology. Studies in History and
Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 53, 1-15.
Dalcq, A.M. (1953). Foreword. Journal of Embryology and Experimental Morphology 1(1),
1-4.
Davidson, E. H. (2001). Genomic Regulatory Systems: Development and Evolution.
Academic Press, San Diego.
Dumais, J., Serikawa, K. & Mandoli, D.F. (2000). Acetabularia: a unicellular model for
understanding subcellular localization and morphogenesis during development. Journal of
Plant Growth Regulation, 19(3), 253-264.
Fusco, G. & Minelli, A. (2010). Phenotypic plasticity in development and evolution: facts and
concepts. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 365, 547–
556.
Gilbert, S.F. (1991). Preface. In Gilbert, S.F. (Ed.), A Conceptual History of Modern
Embryology. The Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, p. vii-ix.
Gilbert, S.F. (1998). Conceptual breakthroughs in developmental biology. Journal of
Biosciences, 23, 169–76.
Gilbert, S.F. (2002). Book Review: Genomic Regulatory Systems: Development and
Evolution. American Journal of Medical Genetics, 108, 341-342.
Gilbert, S.F. (2013). Developmental Biology, Tenth Edition. Sinauer Associates, Sunderland,
MA.
Gilbert, S.F. & Bolker, J.A. (2003). Ecological developmental biology: preface to the
symposium. Evolution and Development, 5, 3–8.
Gilbert, S.F. & Epel, D. (2009). Ecological Developmental Biology. Sinauer Associates,
Sunderland, MA. 2nd ed. 2015.
Gottlieb, G. (1992). Individual Development and Evolution: The Genesis of Novel Behavior.
Oxford University Press, New York.
Guirao, M. & Aréchaga, J. (1989). Editorial Statement. A word of welcome – and a changing
of the guard. International Journal of Developmental Biology, 33, 1.
Johnson M.H. (2001). Functional Brain Development During Infancy. In Galvin Bremner and
Alan Fogel (eds.), Blackwell Handbook of Infant Development, Blackwell, Malden, MA, pp.
169-190.
Keller, E.F. (2002). Making Sense of Life. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
Kroos, L. & Maddock, J.R. (2003). Prokaryotic Development: Emerging Insights. Journal of
Bacteriology, 185, 1128–1146.
Kuhn, T. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolution. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Lewontin, R. (2000). The Triple Helix. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
8
Love, A.C. (2008). Explaining the ontogeny of form: philosophical issues. In Sarkar, S. and A.
Plutynski (Eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. Blackwell, Malden, MA, p. 223247.
Love, A.C. & Travisano, M. (2013). Microbes modeling ontogeny. Biology and Philosophy,
28, 161-188.
Maienschein, J. (2014). Embryos under the Microscope. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
Martinez-Arias, A., and Stewart, A. (2002). Molecular Principles of Animal Development.
Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Meyerowitz, E.M. (2002). Plants compared to animals: the broadest comparative study of
development. Science, 295, 1482-1485.
Minelli, A. (2003). The Development of Animal Form. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Minelli, A. (2014). Developmental disparity. In Minelli, A., and Pradeu, T. (Eds.), Towards a
Theory of Development. Oxford University Press, Oxford, p. 227-245.
Minelli, A. & Pradeu, T. (2014), Theories of development in biology: problems and
perspectives. In Minelli, A., and Pradeu, T. (Eds.), Towards a Theory of Development. Oxford
University Press, Oxford, p. 1-15.
O’Malley, M. & Dupré, J. (2007). Size doesn’t matter: towards a more inclusive philosophy
of biology. Biology and Philosophy, 22, 155–191.
Oyama, S. (2000 [1985]). The Ontogeny of Information. Duke University Press, Durham.
Oyama, S., Griffiths, P. & Gray, R., eds. (2001). Cycles of Contingency: Developmental
Systems and Evolution. MIT Press, Cambridge.
Peberdy, J.F. (1980). Developmental Microbiology. Wiley, New York.
Peter, I. & Davidson, E.H. (2015). Genomic Control Process: Development and Evolution.
Academic Press, London.
Pradeu, T. et al. (2011). The Boundaries of Development. Biological Theory, 6, 1–3.
Pradeu, T. (2014). Regenerating Theories in Developmental Biology. In Minelli, A., and
Pradeu, T. (Eds.), Towards a Theory of Development. Oxford University Press, Oxford, p. 1532.
Rheinberger, H-J. (2000). Gene Concepts: Fragments from the Perspective of Molecular
Biology. In Beurton, P., Falk, R., and Rheinberger, H-J. (Eds.), The Concept of the Gene in
Development and Evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 219-239.
Saunders, J.W. (1966). Death in embryonic systems. Science, 154, 604-612.
Schleiden, M.J. (1848). The Plant: A Biography. Hippolyte Bailliere, London.
Shimkets, L.J. (1999). Intercellular signalling during fruiting-body development of
Myxococcus xanthus. Annual Review of Microbiology, 53, 525–549.
Slack, J.M.W. (1991). From Egg to Embryo. 2nd ed. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Slack J.M.W. (2013), Essential Developmental Biology. Blackwell, Malden, MA.
St Johnston, D. (2015). The Renaissance of Developmental Biology. PLoS Biology,
13:e1002149.
Steeves ,T.A. & Sussex, I.M. (1989). Patterns in Plant Development. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Straight, P.D., & Kolter, R. (2009). Interspecies Chemical Communication in Bacterial
Development. Annual Review of Microbiology, 63, 99–118.
Sultan, S.E. (2015). Organism and Environment: Ecological Development, Niche
Construction, and Adaptation. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Vervoort, M. (2014). Comparison of animal and plant development: a right track to establish a
theory of development? In Minelli, A., and Pradeu, T. (Eds.), Towards a Theory of
Development. Oxford University Press, Oxford, p. 203-217.
Waddington, C. H. (1956). Principles of Embryology. Macmillan, New York.
9
Weiss, P. (1959). Introduction. Developmental Biology, 1(1), 1.
West-Eberhard, M.J. (2003). Developmental Plasticity and Evolution. Oxford University
Press, Oxford.
Wolpert, L. (1968). The French flag problem: a contribution to the discussion on pattern
development and regulation. In Waddington, C. H. (Ed.), Towards a Theoretical Biology, Vol.
1. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh, pp. 125–33.
Wolpert, L. (1994). Do we understand development? Science, 266, 571–572.
Wolpert, L. & Tickle, C. (2011). Principles of Development. 4th Edition. Oxford University
Press, Oxford.
10