Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2013
…
11 pages
1 file
AI-generated Abstract
The paper discusses the evolving landscape of political thought, emphasizing the shift towards a more contextualized understanding of political theory. It critiques traditional approaches that focus narrowly on influential thinkers and suggests a broader exploration of various social documents and modalities of political expression. Additionally, the author outlines six key features of political thinking that encapsulate the complexities of decision-making, resource distribution, public support, social organization, policy-making, and expressive communication.
History: The Journal of the Historical Association, 2020
This article surveys the state of the field of the history of political thought. The premise of the discipline is that political arguments and ideas have developed historically and thus have theoretical histories that can be located and traced. But, as our survey of the field shows, what counts as ‘context’ is up for debate, and contextual methods have become more sensitive to present‐day concerns. The border between the history of political thought and political theory is increasingly porous. We begin with some of the main claims and criticisms of the ‘Cambridge’ method of political thought, chiefly associated with Quentin Skinner, John Dunn and J. G. A. Pocock. We then consider newer developments, such as the ‘global turn’, which have steered the discipline beyond its traditionally European or male subject matter. While this shift in direction is welcome, we caution against a history that abstracts away from local sites of political contestation. Finally, we stress that (Western) historians moving beyond the West have even more reason to stay conscious of their own linguistic and cultural limitations.
CR: The New Centennial Review, 2010
History of European Ideas, 2011
The University of Cambridge has long been a centre for the teaching of the history of political thought. 1 In 1873, to meet concerns that the study of history alone might ''exercise too exclusively the memory and receptive imagination of the student'' (at the expense of the higher faculties of abstraction and generalisation), the new Historical Tripos included a number of ''theoretical'' courses taken over from the longer-established degree in Moral Sciences. 2 Among these was a paper in ''Principles of Political Philosophy and General Jurisprudence'', for which undergraduates read a fairly miscellaneous selection of ten books, from Aristotle's Politics to Maine's Ancient Law via François Guizot, John Stuart Mill, and John Austin. 3 True to the purpose of the paper, these books were read for direct political and philosophical illumination rather than as episodes in intellectual history. 4 It was indeed the view of a series of Cambridge historians in the later nineteenth century-most notably Sir John Seeley and Oscar Browning-that the study of history was properly understood as a foundation for a political science, and that (in Browning's words) ''the Tripos ought to some extent.. .be regarded as a Political Tripos.'' 5 In this conception, Browning was fighting a losing battle even at the end of the nineteenth century, and today the question of how to supplement the learning of history so as to borrow a degree of intellectual rigour from elsewhere has long lost its point. 6 (Nobody now doubts that history is a proper university subject, and accusations of objectionable novelty and intellectual flimsiness have found new targets.) It was a sign of the times when in 1929 ''Political Science A''-essentially a course in the comparative study of political institutions-was replaced by a paper on ''The History of Political Thought''. 7 Political philosophy, originally included in the Tripos as an intellectually bracing addition to mere historical erudition, was now to be treated as itself part of the history to be studied. 8 This approach informed pioneering work by J.G.A. Pocock and Peter Laslett in the 1950s, and theoretical manifestos by Pocock, John Dunn, and Quentin Skinner in the following decade. 9 Since then, Cambridge has been associated with a distinctive way of studying the history of political thought, in which surviving texts are assigned to past contexts of political circumstance and intellectual practice in order to make possible the recovery of those texts' character as specific ''speech acts'' performed by historical agents. 10 It is an irony that this ''genuinely historical'' view of the history of political thought (to use Quentin Skinner's expression) has its origins in the inclusion of consciously nonhistorical subjects in the Cambridge Historical Tripos. 11 Between undergraduate education and the production of original historical research lies the training of graduate students, and at the graduate level the ''Cambridge School'' has had a pedagogical as well as a scholarly dimension from the outset. 12 It is a sign of the continuing vitality of graduate work in the history of political thought in Cambridge that since 2008 graduate students History of European Ideas 37 (2011) 396-402
Scienza & Politica, 2023
After the recent publication of a couple of succinct and overarching essays covering the state of the field in the history of political thought (in the English language), Prof. Davide Cadeddu from the University of Milan expressed polem-ical remarks on some of their content. At the same time, he asked for comments on his own article, inviting the response several of English-speaking scholars (or scholars educated in anglophone cultural context). In response to this challenge, ten colleagues John Dunn (King’s College, University of Cambridge) Humeira Iqtidar (King’s College London) Iain Hampsher-Monk (University of Exeter) Richard Bourke (King’s College, University of Cambridge) Adrian Blau (King’s College London) Alexandra Chadwick (University of Jyväskylä) Duncan Kelly (Jesus College, University of Cambridge) David Leopold (Mansfield College, University of Oxford) Peter Burke (Emmanuel College, University of Cambridge) Richard Whatmore (University of St Andrews) answered with texts of different length and complexity. Depending on each case individually, each scholar was either in agreement or disagreement with the statements previously formulated by him, henceforth eliciting, more or less implicitly, new reflections on the matter at hand.
Contemporary Political Theory, 2004
One day, someone will write a history of introductory texts to the field of political thought. Such a history will reveal much about the changing preoccupations, both of the field of political theory in its relationship to the world of politics, and of its practitioners as members of a profession. It will tell the story of the construction, both of a more-or-less unified discipline and of a series of problematics, and it will no doubt have something to say about the wider social, cultural, and political dynamics to which those practitioners were subject and to which they saw themselves as responding. Inevitably, it would be work-in-progress, a footprint in time bearing traces of its own concerns, but reflexively so, aware that it would one day itself be the object of such a study. Although Finlayson offers no such history in his admirable introduction to this collection, he does offer an account of the concerns of political theory and of its potential role in actual political life, that is both accessible to those new to the field and seeking orientation in a complex, fragmented subject, and reflexively aware of its role in the making and remaking of that subject. It is explicitly not therefore merely a survey of the current state of the discipline, but is a collection, as Finlayson himself puts it, that 'has a 'mission.'' (p. 1) That 'mission' is to convince us that political theory matters; that it is not some abstract and aloof pursuit, detached from the politics that it claims to inform. On the contrary, Finlayson suggests, the more detached we feel from everyday politics and the more politics becomes a matter for 'experts' and professionals, the more important political theory F in all its manifestations: normative, explanatory, and critical F becomes. The collection then has the feel not only of 'A Reader and Guide' F doing exactly what it says on the tin, so to speak F but also of an intervention in, and engagement with, the field it seeks to delineate. And it is all the more interesting and exciting for that. Moreover, as the editor points out, many of the theorists whose work is represented and discussed here are not simply academics, but also activists, advisors to governments, journalists, and broadcasters too. Finlayson therefore makes out a good case for political theory as a concrete activity, and one that informs practice. Any tutor charged with the task of convincing a group of sceptical students as to why they need to be studying political theory could do a
The last few decades of the twentieth Century have been co-terminus with the reemergence and growth of political theory. It is a well known fact that prior to this political theory has been overshadowed by the so called scientific methods that sought to understand society and politics by using empirical and statistical methods. It took a while before the failure of behaviouralism and other methods of study inspired by it failed, and political theory was rightfully restored its place in the study of politics. However, this should not be construed as an argument that says that political theory had ceased to exist at this time when empiricism reigned supreme. It is just that not many people took notice of it (1). On of the eminent theorists responsible for the rekindling of interest in political theory has been John Rawls. Here it may be courageously asserted that in the twentieth century, there have been very few philosophers and none with the stature of Rawls. His magnum opus 'A Theory of Justice' has done for more for the revival of interest in political theory than any other work. It is only after the recognition that has been given to Rawlsian writings that we see other writers attempting original theoretical and philosophical tracts one of the names that comes up immediately for consideration here is Charles Taylor. It is in the era of Rawls that we also find the emergence of new forms of thinking emerging within theory, namely multiculturalism. From what has been presented so far it may appear that political theory and its revival have something do only with liberalism. It would not be entirely untrue if we were to argue that the revival of political theory happened within the gamut of a liberal framework of thinking. This has happened mainly because of the fact that in Marxism, which is the alternative to liberal thinking, there has been too much orthodoxy and an unwillingness to consider some of its theoretical foundations in the light of the failure of what it promised, and the lack of the desired results. It must be acknowledged that there have been introspective traditions within Marxism as represented by Lukacs and the critical theory tradition, but these have been caught in a vocabulary that has been the preserve of only those who knew the intricacies of Marxist thinking and theorizing. (2) On the other hand we can see that liberalism has shown a tendency to evolve much more as a result of a greater desire for introspection. This has been the most important reason for the survival of liberalism and its sustaining interest in a wide spread audience. However, let this not be construed as a lionizing of liberalism and the traditions that it has spawned. The fact that there have been so many traditions within liberalism, and that there are fundamental disagreements among them suggest very clearly that liberalism is nowhere near perfection.
This is the syllabus for the second iteration of the second-year undergraduate History of Political Thought course I taught at Bristol in 2013-14.
Political Studies, 1983
Over the last few years a number of books have appeared professing to have been inspired in their methodological considerations by the writings of Quentin Skinner.1 The purpose of this essay is to offer some deliberations upon two important and connected questions. First, in what way are the new histories related to the history of histories of political thought? And, secondly, how far are we on the road to achieving a consensus on the appropriate methods for studying the history of political thought?2 Before these questions can be considered I am obliged to offer a characterization, which in the form given here is little more than a caricature, of the whole of the history of histories of political thought without entering into the detail. What I offer is an attempt to capture its unity without ignoring its diversity.
Nature Scientific Reports, 2019
IN NOVITATE Anno XXXVIII, Numero 63, dicembre 2023, 2023
Turai István (szerk.): Mesél a múlt. Régészeti feltárások Törökbálinton. Törökbálint 2021, 2021
Revista Notas Históricas y Geográficas, 2024
Science Research, 2017
O Ideário Patrimonial, 2018
Millennium 42(1), 239-246, 2013
Studia Slavica Academiae Scientiarum Hungaricae (Print), 2018
International Journal of Academic Research in Accounting, Finance and Management Sciences, 2023
O Islão na Europa face ao Islão Global: dinâmicas e desafios, 2012
2015 International Conference on Information Processing (ICIP), 2015
Pirilâmpsias: Composições e arranjos de José Eduardo Gramani Música popular brasileira para violino, rabeca e outros instrumentos de arco, 2024
2008 Second IEEE International Conference on Self-Adaptive and Self-Organizing Systems Workshops, 2008
ETS Research Report Series, 2018
CommIT (Communication and Information Technology) Journal, 2012
Annals of Nuclear Medicine, 2003