Introduction
Reconceptualizing Subaltern Politics in
Contemporary India
ALF GUNVALD NILSEN AND SRILA ROY
What Is Subaltern Politics?
The term ‘subaltern politics’ refers in a broad sense to the political activity of social groups who are adversely incorporated into
determinate power relations (see Green 2011a). Subaltern politics
inds a number of manifestations, ranging from everyday forms of
resistance, via rights-based campaigns on the terrain of civil society and participation in electoral democracy, to armed struggles
for revolutionary transformation. However, cutting across these
manifestations is the articulation of oppositional agency—that
is, challenges to the extant structuring of power relations and the
multiple forms of marginalization that are produced by this structuring. In this book, we are concerned with the conceptualization
of the dynamics of these processes as they crystallize in the context of contemporary India.
In recent decades, India has emerged at the helm of the process
that the United Nations Development Programme has dubbed ‘the
rise of the South’—that is, the ‘dramatic rebalancing of global economic power’ that has been propelled by impressive growth rates
in the BRICS countries, namely, Brazil, Russia, India, China, and
South Africa (UNDP 2013: 13). Indeed, the combination of economic dynamism with the remarkable stability and continuity of
India’s parliamentary democracy has led some observers to hail
the country as one that holds valuable lessons for other developing countries in the global South (see, for example, Bhagwati and
Panagariya 2013; Desai 2011; D. Gupta 2010, 2013). However, the
story of India in the twenty-irst century is not simply one of economic progress and democratic inclusion (Corbridge et al. 2013;
Kohli 2012; Nayyar 2006; Sen and Drèze 2013). As Stuart Corbridge
and Alpa Shah (2013) have recently pointed out, the much-lauded
‘Indian boom’ is blighted by the persistence of entrenched poverty
and widening inequalities, a deepening agrarian crisis across large
swathes of the countryside, and rampant exploitation of casual
labour in the country’s vast informal sector (see also Breman 2003;
Walker 2008). Socio-economic marginalization in turn intersects
with structures of power based on caste, gender, and sexuality to
create the patterns of exclusion, vulnerability, stigma, and disenfranchisement that deine subalternity in contemporary India (see,
for example, Dave 2012; A. Sharma 2008; Waghmore 2013).
However, subalternity and the relations of power through
which it is produced are also vigorously contested from below. In
a process that Corbridge and Harriss (2000) refer to as ‘the reinvention of India’, dominant and subaltern groups engage in complex
processes of negotiation, contestation, and struggle over the future
form, direction, and meaning of democracy and development,
redistribution and recognition, and—ultimately—the very ediice
upon which the Indian state rests. And this scenario is arguably
best understood as a manifestation of the protracted unravelling
of the Nehruvian nation-building project from the late 1960s until
the present (Ray and Katzenstein 2005).
The making of India’s postcolonial state was predicated on
the demobilization of mass-based movements that had played a
key role in the struggle for independence (Ray and Katzenstein
2005). Simultaneously, the Congress Party constructed its hegemonic position in the electoral arena by incorporating the leading
2
New Subaltern Politics
representatives of large land-owning castes in a way that reinforced their power relative to lower castes and labouring classes
(Frankel 2005). The effect of these alignments was to reproduce
entrenched forms of power in Indian society at the same time as
the political agency of subaltern groups was contained and circumscribed by ‘the strong hand of the Nehruvian state’ (Ray and
Katzenstein 2005: 14).
During the second half of the 1960s, the worsening stagnation of
the Indian economy combined with the erosion of the ‘dominant
party system’ of the Congress to produce spaces for the articulation of new oppositional projects from below. The outbreak of
the Naxalite revolt in 1967 signalled the onset of two decades
that would witness the emergence of new social movements
moored in and mobilized around subaltern groups—for example,
women, Adivasis, informal-sector workers, Dalits—who had not
only been marginalized in relation to the postcolonial state, but
had also occupied a relatively peripheral position in left politics
since independence in 1947 (Omvedt 1993; Vanaik 1990). Adding
momentum to this upsurge was the process that Christophe
Jaffrelot (2003) has referred to as a ‘silent revolution’—that is, the
rise of political parties that represented and mobilized Dalits and
lower-caste groups in electoral politics (see also Michelutti 2008).
This process, Jaffrelot (2003: 494) argues, is one in which power is
transferred ‘on the whole peacefully, from the upper caste elites to
various subaltern groups’.
Whereas the onset of neoliberal reform in the early 1990s was
very much a manifestation of the political clout of India’s globalizing elites,1 the past two and a half decades have also witnessed
the further development of new forms of subaltern politics.
One prominent development is, of course, the re-emergence of
Maoism as a signiicant political force in India’s ‘Red Corridor’
(see Harriss 2011a; Mukherji 2012; A. Shah 2010; N. Sundar 2012)
and the intensiication of struggles against land acquisition and
displacement (Levien 2012). Moreover, the combined impact of
development strategies that are increasingly centred on neoliberal forms of empowerment and the introduction of rights-based
legislation to protect civil liberties and social entitlements has
arguably ‘reconigured not only the material interactions between
Introduction
3
the state and India’s marginalized, but also the imagined spaces
within which marginal groups renegotiate their relationships with
the state’ (Williams et al. 2011: 12; see also Corbridge et al. 2005;
Madhok 2013; A. Sharma 2008).
The current conjuncture, then, is one in which multiple forms
of subaltern politics are locked in a confrontation with what
Corbridge and Harriss (2000, chapter 6) refer to as ‘elite revolts’:
hegemonic projects that seek to mould India’s economy, polity,
and society in ways that consolidate the power of the country’s
dominant social groups. The signiicance of this confrontation and
its outcomes for India’s future development is considerable, and it
is ultimately this that compels us as researchers to think through
the conceptual optics that we deploy in our engagement with the
oppositional agency and political projects of subaltern groups.
Why Engage the Subaltern Studies Project?
This book and the project through which it has emerged undertake
this rethinking through a critical engagement with the Subaltern
Studies project. This might seem like an odd point of departure
for a venture that is concerned with understanding the contemporary forms and dynamics of subaltern politics. After all, when
the Subaltern Studies project was launched in the early 1980s, its
primary purpose was to unearth the history of what Ranajit Guha
(1982b: 4) called ‘the politics of the people’ in the wider context
of the Indian struggle for independence from colonial rule.2 And
in its further evolution, the project turned increasingly towards
an interrogation of metatheoretical questions related to the historiography of colonialism and modernity.3 Indeed, in a recent
article, Partha Chatterjee (2012: 49) has argued that the conceptual
and methodological approaches that were originally developed in
and through the Subaltern Studies project are not adequate to the
task of understanding politics from below in contemporary India:
‘Subaltern Studies was a project of its time; another time calls for
other projects’ (see also Chakrabarty 2013).
However, the Subaltern Studies project cannot simply be
brushed aside as irrelevant to the study of subaltern politics in
4
New Subaltern Politics
contemporary India. Despite being rooted in historiographical
concerns, the project has been of singular importance in orienting scholarly attention towards the signiicance of popular politics
and mobilization from below in postcolonial India (see Arnold,
this volume). And as we as scholars focus our inquiries on the
oppositional agency of subaltern groups, we tend to ind ourselves drawing on and engaging in debates with the analytical
templates that were central to the Subaltern Studies project—in
particular, perhaps, the foundational argument that the politics
of subaltern social groups should be conceived of as constituting
an ‘autonomous domain’ that is different and distanced from the
realm of ‘elite politics’ (see Ranajit Guha 1982b: 4). Interestingly,
in Chatterjee’s (2012: 45–7) engagement with the challenges facing
the study of contemporary subaltern politics in India, it is precisely this conception that is singled out for critical discussion. A
conceptual lens centred on the notion of subaltern communities
that exist beyond the reach of hegemonic projects and apparatuses
of governmentality, he argues, has become increasingly untenable
due to signiicant changes in the Indian political landscape: ‘The
deepening and widening of the apparatuses of governmentality
has, I believe, transformed the quality of mass politics in India in
the last two decades’ (ibid.). And for Chatterjee, this throws up the
crucial imperative of redeining subalternity in order to be able to
grasp the dynamics of subaltern politics in India today (ibid.: 46).4
This volume can be read as an attempt to address this imperative. Crucially, our attempt does not revolve around devising a
new singular template for understanding subalternity and subaltern politics in contemporary India. Rather, we seek to initiate a
critical but constructive dialogue with the conceptual legacies of
the Subaltern Studies project by bringing together a set of essays
that draw on research into ields as diverse as the lifeworlds of
urban subalterns in globalizing Gujarat, the activism of sexual
subalterns in eastern India, discourses of merit in higher education
institutions in Tamil Nadu, and struggles over land acquisition in
rural West Bengal—to name but a few—to suggest possible ways
in which to move towards new understandings of the agency that
subaltern groups develop to negotiate and resist the workings of
power from above in contemporary India. To highlight this guiding
Introduction
5
thread that runs throughout the volume, we turn in the remainder
of this introduction to a more detailed discussion of the theorization of subalternity and hegemony.
Trajectories towards a Deinition of the Subaltern
To put it simply, Gidwani (2009) says, subalternity is the state of
being subaltern. What it means to be subaltern is, however, scarcely
so simple, especially given the analytic extension and even overuse of the term since its popularity under the Subaltern Studies
project. Gidwani (ibid.: 66) provides a descriptor of the term which
is, as he puts it, working albeit elastic; that is, subalternity refers
to ‘persons and groups hierarchically positioned as subordinate
or inferiors within nation states, capitalist production relations,
or relations of patriarchy, race, caste, and so forth’. His usage of
the term in this instance remains conined to an empirical grouping as it was for the early subaltern historians. For others within
the group, the term ‘subaltern’, drawn from Antonio Gramsci,
signalled relations of dominance and subordination—‘in terms of
class, caste, gender, race, language and culture’ (G. Prakash 1994:
1477)—in Indian society as opposed to subordinate groups alone.
Indeed, the meaning of the term subaltern is characterized by this
tension between empirical designations of identity positions, on
the one hand, and a critical understanding of how power, subordination, and agency are constituted within a speciic set of social
relations, on the other. As we show in what follows, the trajectory
of the term within the Subaltern Studies project, especially the
move from subaltern to subalternity, exhibits a shift of perspective
from identity to power.
Ranajit Guha (1982a, 1982b) deined the subaltern rather loosely
as that part of the population—the working classes, peasantry, and
subordinate classes—who were not part of the elite. Subalternity
was furthermore associated with subordination, subaltern being
used ‘as a name for the general attribute of subordination in South
Asian society whether this is expressed in terms of class, caste,
age, gender and office or in any other way’ (Ranajit Guha 1982a:
vii). It was also placed in a dichotomous relationship with the
6
New Subaltern Politics
elite given that subordination is ‘one of the constitutive terms in a
binary relationship of which the other is dominance’ (ibid.).
The category of the elite was divided, in a Weberian-like taxonomy, into a dominant (colonial) elite, an indigenous elite, and
dominant indigenous groups at the local and regional levels. The
last category of the indigenous elite at regional and local levels was
not only a heterogeneous one, but one that differed from area to
area owing to regional disparities with respect to socio-economic
development. Consequently, ‘the same class or element which was
dominant in one area … could be among the dominated in another’
(Ranajit Guha 1982b: 8). While Guha here seems to recognize that
the boundaries of his taxonomy might be blurred in some cases,
its foundational assumption remains a ‘structuralist populism’
(Roosa 2006) that pits elites against people. It forms, moreover, the
basis of Guha’s (1982b: 4) argument that subaltern politics constitutes ‘an autonomous domain’. As David Arnold (1984: 170–3)
has pointed out, this autonomy was understood as resulting from
the conluence of the village collectivities that emerged from the
exigencies of agricultural production, the limited reach of precolonial polities and the relative insularity of agrarian economies,
and inally the failure of the nationalist movement to incorporate
the peasantry into the ambit of modern anticolonial nationalism.
In an attempt to ‘recover’ the agency of the subaltern that had
been denied by elite historiography, Guha (1982b: 4) argued that
subalterns acted independently of elites and that their politics constituted an autonomous sphere, ‘for it neither originated from elite
politics nor did its existence depend on the latter’. The historical
recovery of subaltern agency was in aid of constituting subalterns
as autonomous subject-agents in their own right.
The idea of an autonomous subaltern is perhaps the aspect of the
Subaltern Studies template that has received the most critical attention (O’Hanlon 1988; Sarkar 1997: chapter 3; Sivaramakrishnan
2002). The most well-known critique is associated with Gayatri
Chakravorty Spivak, whose intervention into Subaltern Studies
marks the turn away from using ‘subaltern’ as an empirical designation of identity positions and towards postcolonial studies and
a critical perspective on power relations. In her most provocative
intervention, ‘Can the Subaltern Speak?’, Spivak (1988a: 284–5)
Introduction
7
describes Guha’s ideas of the elite and the people/subaltern, and
his project of measuring the deviation of these from ideal types, as
being ‘essentialist and taxonomic’. As with the European philosophers Foucault and Deleuze, on the one hand, and Marxists on the
other, Spivak (1988b: 5) inds a hidden essentialism in the attempt
by subaltern historians like Guha to retrieve and represent subaltern consciousness ‘in a positive and pure state’. Such an attempt
is essentialist insofar as it negates the heterogeneity of subaltern
groups and transforms them ‘into an undifferentiated, humanist,
and implicitly male subject agent’ (Gidwani 2009: 68). The project
of recovering subaltern agency is also positivist in as much as it
presumes a ‘irm ground’ (Spivak 1988b: 10) or even an ‘idealistic bedrock’ (Spivak 1988a: 286), namely, subaltern consciousness
that one can access unmediated by discourse, representation, or
experience. This positing of some pure subaltern consciousness or
essence bypasses entirely the problem and politics of representation, which, Spivak is at pains to show, is impossible to do.
In contrast, Spivak argues that the subaltern can only be retrieved
and represented—be spoken for—in the terms set by dominant
or elite ideology, discourse, and politics. There is no pure space
from which she can speak and, insofar as she can speak through
dominant discourse alone, the subaltern cannot speak. The ethics and politics of representation mean that even well-meaning
attempts—like those of the subaltern historian or progressive
Western intellectuals—to give voice to the subaltern or to restore
her agency end by othering or objectifying her and reinforcing her
subordinate status. This is in large measure because of the failure
of these scholars to recognize their own complicity in practices of
representation that render, in an act of further epistemic violence,
their own subject positions transparent.
Spivak uses as an example the debate around sati or widow-sacriice in colonial India to show the disappearance of the subaltern
precisely in the act of representing her and her interests: ‘Between
patriarchy and imperialism, subject-constitution and object-formation, the igure of the woman disappears… . There is no space
from which the sexed subaltern can speak’ (1988a: 306–7). In not
being given a subject position from which to speak (G. Prakash
1994), the colonized or Third World woman is, unlike the politi8
New Subaltern Politics
cally organized proletariat, paradigmatic of subalternity borne out
of silencing, epistemic violence, and erasure. Her silencing marks
the limits of what can be historically retrieved (subaltern voice)
and epistemologically known (experience). It is well known that
the early Subaltern Studies project absented women as subjects
and did not employ gender as a category of analysis. For Spivak, in
contrast, the subaltern is an inherently sexed and racialized subject. The Third World woman is doubly effaced—‘more deeply in
shadow’ (1988a: 287)—than her male counterpart by virtue of gender and race and the twin pillars of patriarchy and imperialism.
The upshot of Spivak’s critique is threefold: there is no escape
from the politics and ethics of representation (Gidwani 2009).
There is consequently no pure space from which intellectuals or
social movements can hope to speak on behalf of, or represent,
subaltern interests (Kapoor 2008). Relatedly, there is no outside
of power structures. The subjectivity of the subaltern does not
lie in some pure, autonomous space outside of power relations,
but is constituted through these. This poststructuralist shift from
conceptualizing the subject as autonomous of (elite) discourse
to seeing it as an ‘effect of discursive systems’ (G. Prakash 1994:
1480) was a major outcome of Spivak’s intervention. Finally,
an understanding of gendered subalternity goes to the heart of
Spivak’s understanding of subalternity as such, as being removed
from all lines of social mobility (Sharpe and Spivak 2002; Spivak
2005; Spivak et al. 1996). She says in a later interview of ‘Can the
Subaltern Speak?’:
In the essay I made it clear that I was talking about the space as
deined by Ranajit Guha, the space that is cut off from the lines of
mobility in a colonized country. You have the foreign elite and the
indigenous elite. Below that you will have the vectors of upward,
downward, sideward, backward mobility. But then there is a space
which is for all practical purposes outside those lines. (Spivak et al.
1996: 288–9)
The subaltern are not just the non-elite but those who are ‘so displaced they lack political organization and representation’ (Green
2002: 18). So they are not simply cut off from elite politics but
Introduction
9
from politics per se: ‘subalternity is where social lines of mobility,
being elsewhere, do not permit the formation of a recognisable
basis of action’ (Spivak 2005: 476). It is in this sense that Spivak
contends that the proletariat is not a subaltern group because it is
organized in most instances (Green 2002).
More recently, however, Spivak (2000a, 2000b) writes of Third
World women as ‘new subalterns’ who are not outside of circuits
of power but integrated into them in problematic ways, especially
by a feminist-inspired neoliberal developmentalism. Subaltern
consciousness is once again key, not for the purposes of resistance
(as it was in the analytics of early Subaltern Studies) but for the
sake of justifying global developmental projects premised on the
‘agency’ of Third World women. The complicity of international
feminism in such a project also makes evident Spivak’s non-identitarian use of the category of subaltern: that it does not refer to
women per se or to anyone in the formerly ‘Third World’ or to
ethnic minorities in the West who are all, by virtue of their class
position and culture, complicit in ‘a corporate globalization that
maintains subaltern women in a position of subalternity’ (Sharpe
and Spivak 2002: 610). In more recent work, she deines subalternity as a position without identity or, as Morris (2010) puts it, a
predicament that is shaped by being structurally obstructed from
accessing power and voice. At least since Spivak’s intervention and
Subaltern Studies III, the term ‘subaltern’ has been employed less
as an empirical or identity category than as ‘a position of critique’
(G. Prakash 1994: 1481) or a ‘perspective’ (Das 1989) on dominant
discourse or a set of hierarchical relations.
But does the unspeakability of the subaltern leave any room
for agency? Prominent critics of Spivak have noted that her position might constrain subaltern agency so as to effectively efface
any possibility of resistance. It is true that Spivak has been more
interested in exposing the structures and imbrications of powerknowledge than in ‘the possibility of resistance on the part of the
objects of the power-knowledge nexus’ (Varadharajan 1995: xii).
Her critique has been involved, in other words, with ‘the unremitting exposure of complicity rather than the charting of opposition’
(ibid.). Some, like Benita Parry (1987), have gone so far as to charge
Spivak with never letting the subaltern speak, and of recentring
10
New Subaltern Politics
the master discourse (of imperialism) even in the act of opposing
it. Even if one must reject an ‘essentialist, utopian politics’ (Spivak
1988a: 276; Varadharajan 1995: 93), is the assertion that the subaltern cannot speak the only alternative? And is it the case that all
resistance ultimately feeds back into power?
In fact, for Spivak, one stops being subaltern as soon as one acts
politically to achieve representation within a hegemonic formation. She says in an interview:
I don’t think that I declare myself to be allied to the subaltern. The
subaltern is all that is not elite, but the trouble with those kinds of
names is that if you have any kind of political interest you name
it in the hope that the name will disappear. That’s what class consciousness is in the interest of: the class disappearing. What politically we want to see is that the name would not be possible. So what
I’m interested in is seeing ourselves as namers of the subaltern. If
the subaltern can speak then, thank God, the subaltern is not a subaltern any more. (Spivak 1990: 158)
In what has been called a problem of the ‘disappearing subaltern’
(Hershatter 1993), certain groups like the organized working class
cease to be ‘subaltern’ in Spivak’s formulation, even as it is clear, as
we argue later, that subalternity cannot be reduced to the politics
of representation alone. Not only does such a formulation posit
subalternity in dramatically opposite terms to agency, but also to
agency that is available and manifest, above all, in subaltern politics. Even as ‘new subalterns’ are theorized as not being victimized
in the same way as historical subalterns, they are positioned as
entirely subjected to hegemonic power in ways that negate, once
again, subaltern agency and the possibility of political resistance
(see S. Roy 2014).
Thus, as much as Spivak’s intervention advances our understanding of subalternity by unmooring the concept from its
structuralist focus on identity, her alternative conceptualization is nevertheless problematic in that it suggests a position of
absolute exteriority in relation to hegemonic formations—the
condition of being cut off from lines of social mobility—and in
that it deprives subaltern groups of agential capacities. Given what
Introduction
11
we know about the ability of subaltern groups to develop oppositional agency even in extremely repressive contexts—slave revolts
being a case in point in this respect (see, for example, Blackburn
1988; da Costa 1994; Shuler 2009; Sidbury 1997)—this proposition
is less than convincing.
Rethinking Subalternity
So how can we think about subalternity in an alternative way? We
suggest an understanding that is: (a) relational—that is, subalternity is above all a positionality of adverse incorporation in a certain
set of socio-historical power relations; (b) intersectional—that is,
subalternity is constituted along several axes of power, whose
speciic empirical form must be deciphered in concrete empirical
settings; and (c) dynamic—subalternity does not preclude agency,
but agency arises and develops within and in relation to dominant discourses and political forms. Taken together, the volume
presumes and purports an expansive, relational, and intersectional
account of subalternity that locates it in a wide social ield of
power relations to address a plurality of context-speciic manifestations of power. Such an approach underscores the limitations of
understanding marginalization in relation to class alone, or indeed
along any single axis. It is also able to account for subaltern agency
as not being entirely subsumed, as in Spivak, under the power of
dominant discourse, or being, as in Guha, entirely voluntarist.
One way to develop such a conceptualization of subalternity
is to go back to Gramsci, from whom the subaltern historians
originally took the term ‘subaltern’. Marcus Green’s (2002, 2011a)
reading of Gramsci’s work is highly instructive. Crucially, Green
(2011a: 388) argues that, by subscribing to the thesis that Gramsci
used the term ‘subaltern’ as code for ‘proletariat’ in his Prison
Notebooks, the Subaltern Studies scholars ‘limit Gramsci’s expansive conception of subalternity’. Consequently, they elide the
ways in which Gramsci located subordination in a dense social
ield in speciic historical contexts, and as constituted by ‘exclusion, domination, and marginality in their various forms’ (ibid.).
As we will detail later in this Introduction, Green also proposes,
12
New Subaltern Politics
contra Spivak, an understanding of subalternity in which political
agency is recognized.
Against the equation of the subaltern with the proletariat
and subalternity with class domination alone, Green shows that
Gramsci’s original conception of subalternity was not limited to
understanding marginalization in relation to class or class domination, even as class was a major element in his understanding
of power and subordination: ‘subalternity [in Gramsci] was not
merely deined by class relations but rather an intersection of class,
race, culture, and religion that functioned in different modalities
in speciic historical contexts’ (Green 2011a: 395). Thus, Gramsci
treated the question of the subordination of women separately
(albeit briely) without subsuming it under class domination. To
the extent that gender subordination functions differently from
that of class, he recognized the suppression of women as a phenomenon that occurs across classes (see Moe 2010).
Subalternity was thus conceptualized in relation to multiple
social groups and the power relations between them. It was not
reducible to any singular social axis—class or gender—as it was in
the early subaltern historians’ privileging of economic relations
over other social relations, especially as these manifested themselves in conlicts between peasant communities and the political
economy of colonial capitalism. The pure subaltern subject was
invariably measured in class terms, given the original conceptualization of the category in terms of the non-elite. Earlier in this
discussion, we noted the blurring of the categories of elite and
subaltern even in Guha’s rigid taxonomy in which he allows—as
deviations from ideal types—the possibility of one social group
being hegemonic in one context and subordinate or subaltern in
another. What the (inadvertent) inclusion of such ambiguity in his
classiication allows is the recognition of the production of exclusion, oppression, and otherness in distinctive and interlocking
terms, whether based on class, caste, gender, sexuality, or religion,
as has become typical of intersectional understandings of (primarily gender-based) forms of social inequality and exclusion. One
can thus read an intersectional deployment of subalternity even in
early works (Chatterjee 1993; Spivak 1988a). This is especially evident in the manner in which the concept was employed to address
Introduction
13
the ‘shadowy igure’ of the female subaltern in Spivak, including
middle-class women whose political exclusion constituted the
realm of democratic citizenship. Such a focus complicates any
quest for a ‘pure’ subaltern, circumventing problems of empirical classiication of the ‘real’ subaltern besides opening up a wider
discursive ield to rethink subalternity from the perspective of
the intersectionality of race, class, gender, sexuality, and religion
(Green 2011a).
Finally, Green (2002) rereads Gramsci in a manner that offers a
way out of the impasse of the ‘disappearing subaltern’ in at least
two ways. Against Spivak’s aporetic position that the subaltern
ceases to be so the moment she is politically intelligible, Gramsci
does not equate such political agency with the end/termination
of subalternity. This is because Gramsci recognizes, according to
Green (2002: 18), that a subaltern group can exercise political organization and agency ‘without any level of hegemony and therefore
still be subject to the activity of dominant groups’. Political mobilization does not mean the transformation of subaltern groups
into dominant groups, and neither does it necessarily transform
the root causes of subalternity. Subaltern groups can only cease to
be subaltern once their subalternity is addressed, ‘once they have
transformed the relations of subordination that cause their marginalization’ (ibid.: 20).
Second, and contra Spivak’s polarization of political agency and
subalternity, Gramsci sees political organizing as being an integral
aspect of the condition of being subaltern: ‘Subaltern groups have
to become conscious of their social position, organize, and struggle
to transform their social positions, since organization and representation alone will not transform the relations of subordination’
(Green 2002: 19). Green points out that Gramsci thought of subalternity as existing ‘in degrees or levels of development’ (ibid.: 16),
and that ‘subaltern groups develop in various degrees or phases that
correspond to levels of political organization’ (ibid.: 15). Some are
more organized and exhibit higher levels of political consciousness
than others. Subalternity is thus not pitted against politics; political struggle is understood, instead, as intrinsic to subalternity.
The political struggles and mobilizations of subaltern groups do
not, however, take place in some autonomous domain, but in and
14
New Subaltern Politics
through the institutions and relations through which hegemony
is constituted. ‘Subaltern groups’, Gramsci (1971: 182) argued,
‘are always subject to the activity of ruling groups, even when
they rebel and rise up’. What he meant by this is that subaltern
agency—ranging from everyday negotiations of the workings of
power from above to collective action challenging adverse incorporation into a social formation—will tend to proceed by engaging
institutional ensembles, framing claims through discourses,
and mobilizing through political forms that are commensurable
with and geared towards the reproduction of unequal structures
of power. This is, in turn, a result of the fact that the compromises that have been struck in and through hegemonic processes
remain ones ‘in which the interests of the dominant social groups
prevail’ (ibid.): subaltern groups are positioned in relation to socioeconomic relations, political institutions, and cultural forms that,
despite concessions and compromises, buttress the reproduction
of hegemony. Consequently, subaltern resistance is conditioned
by and mediated through ‘the social condensations of hegemony’
(Morton 2007: 92).
Taken together, Gramsci enables an understanding of subalternity that embraces a notion of political agency as: (a) always
being mediated; and (b) as not necessarily guaranteed to be successful or transformative of the conditions of subalternity. This
takes us somewhat beyond the impasse identiied earlier, between
positing a subaltern subject that is entirely autonomous and one
that is entirely subject to structures of dominance and silenced. In
challenging this idea of ‘subaltern consciousness [as] either a completely independent product or … a mere relection of a totalising
hegemony from above’, Haynes and Prakash (1992: 19) emphasize
the entanglement of power and resistance in everyday life in South
Asia.
While such a formulation has become fairly commonsensical
since these debates took place in the wake of Subaltern Studies
(and its critique by Spivak), the expectation of autonomy and purity
has not abated in current ruminations on subaltern resistance and
politics. Contemporary movements of subalterns are invariably
located—by those reading them—in domains outside of the state
and market and as uninformed by understandings of state, law, and
Introduction
15
citizenship or as unmediated by trans/national actors including
scholars, activists, NGOs, and representatives of the state. The
expectation of purity has also inevitably led to proclamations of
such movements as being inadequately representative of subaltern interests or voices when mediated by discourses of rights and
practices of solidarity (see Sinha 2012). One hears, for instance,
repeated condemnations of the Indian women’s movement as
having become ‘NGO-ized’, not without a touch of nostalgia
amongst ‘older’ feminists committed to the ideals if not practices
of autonomy (see S. Roy 2011). Such anachronistic ways of reading
current subaltern movements—amongst academics and activists
alike—are partly a legacy of Subaltern Studies that, in associating subalterns with autonomy on the one hand, or alterity on the
other, mitigated its own analytical purchase in addressing a more
messy, impure ield of subaltern mobilization that traverses elite
and subaltern domains, civil and political society, and the bounds
of the ‘global’ and ‘local’. And as an extension of conceiving of
subalternity in this way, it also becomes necessary to rethink our
conceptualization of hegemony.
Rethinking Hegemony
Compared to the rich debates on subalternity, relatively little
attention has been devoted to the conceptualization of hegemony
in relation to the Subaltern Studies project. Indeed, writing in
1984, David Arnold commented that the project’s participants had
‘not, as yet, given sufficient attention to the forms that domination and hegemony took in colonial India’ (Arnold 1984: 175). This
would remain the case until Ranajit Guha penned two long essays,
‘Dominance without Hegemony and Its Historiography’ and
‘Discipline and Mobilize’, for the sixth and seventh volumes of the
series, respectively, which subsequently came to form the core of
the important book Dominance without Hegemony: History and
Power in Colonial India (Ranajit Guha 1998).
Essentially a development of the proposition that he had formulated in the introductory statement that launched the Subaltern
Studies project in 1982, Guha’s essay on dominance without
16
New Subaltern Politics
hegemony put forward an analysis of the organization of political
power under British colonial rule. This analysis was anchored in
a theoretical model in which power is understood as being constituted by the interaction between domination and subordination.
According to Guha, domination and subordination are animated
by the intersecting dynamics of coercion/persuasion and collaboration/resistance. And on this reading, hegemony is to be understood
as ‘a condition of dominance (D), such that in the organic composition of D, Persuasion (P) outweighs Coercion (C)’ (Guha 1998: 23).
Hegemony, for Guha, is the hallmark of the political in Western
capitalist democracies. In this context, he argues, the bourgeoisie
had gained the consent of subaltern groups as it emerged at the
helm of the struggle against feudalism. Following the paradigmatic
bourgeois revolutions in England and France, a hegemonic liberal
political culture was crafted that incorporated subaltern groups
within the ambit of democratic nation-states. In contrast, the colonial state established by the British in India rested fundamentally
on coercion: ‘As an absolute externality, the colonial state was
structured like a despotism, with no mediating depths, no space
provided for transactions between the will of the rulers and that of
the ruled’ (Guha 1998: 65). Furthermore, the political culture that
the colonial overlords sought to craft was one in which the central
idioms of rule—order, improvement, obedience, and rightful dissent—were mediated through ‘the precolonial political traditions
of the colonized’ (ibid.: 24). Consequently, colonial rule failed to
generate a hegemonic ruling culture: ‘One of the consequences of
that failure has been to inhibit the homogenization of the domain
of politics. For, under conditions of dominance without hegemony,
the life of civil society can never be fully absorbed into the activity
of the state’ (ibid.: 72).
Dominance without hegemony, Guha argues, was reproduced
under the postcolonial state. This was, above all, the result of the
ways in which the leadership of the Indian bourgeoisie shaped the
form and trajectory of the Indian freedom struggle: ‘Pliant and
prone to compromise from their inception, they lived in a state
of happy accommodation with imperialism for the greater part of
their career as a constituted political force from 1885 to 1947… .
Compromise and accommodation were equally characteristic of
Introduction
17
their attitude to the semi-feudal values and institutions entrenched
in Indian society’ (Guha 1998: 5). The willingness to compromise
and accommodate with landlordism and the colonial state, Guha
argues, combined with ‘the failure of nationalism to assimilate
the class interests of peasants and workers effectively into a bourgeois hegemony’ (ibid.: 133). Ultimately, the upshot of this failure
was the reproduction of ‘dominance without hegemony’ under the
postcolonial state (ibid.: xiii, 97).
Vivek Chibber (2013) has recently articulated a strong critique
of Guha’s perspective. At the heart of his argument is the contention that Guha’s contrast between hegemonic and non-hegemonic
forms of bourgeois rule is lawed. Revisiting the scholarship on the
English and French Revolutions, Chibber argues that their trajectory differs substantially from how they are portrayed by Guha.
In particular, he argues, the link between bourgeois revolutions
and political liberalism is very tenuous: ‘What they bequeathed
was an oligarchic state with an expanded scope for political participation—but only for members of the ruling order that had
hitherto been excluded’ (ibid.: 77). Crucially, Chibber notes that
whereas subaltern agency was imperative in energizing these
transformations in particular phases, this did not mean that the
political projects of dominant groups accommodated the claims
and demands articulated from below: ‘the leaders’ intention, far
from incorporating mass demands, was to marginalize them as
much as possible, and to keep the political agenda conined to the
preferences of the elite groupings… . The goal was to force through
an elite pact, not to transform the condition of the lower orders’
(ibid.: 85). Ultimately, the inclusion of subaltern groups in these
new political orders was an achievement of mobilization from
below, rather than an intrinsic feature of bourgeois hegemony:
‘For more than a century after the new states were installed, laboring classes had to wage unceasing struggle to gain any substantial
political rights—the very rights that Guha seems to associate with
a hegemonic order’ (ibid.: 87).
Chibber’s critique is instructive in the sense that it clears the
ground for a necessary rethinking of hegemony. In Guha’s work,
hegemony is arguably conceived of in a way that, on the one hand,
elides the signiicance of subaltern agency in the construction of
18
New Subaltern Politics
hegemonic formations, and, on the other hand, exaggerates the
element of consent over coercion. As Florencia Mallon (1995:
6) has argued, it is necessary to move beyond an understanding
of hegemony as ‘a belief in, or incorporation of, the dominant
ideology’ towards a conception of hegemony as ‘a set of nested,
continuous processes through which power and meaning are contested, legitimated, and redeined at all levels of society’ (ibid.).
Indeed, thinking of hegemony in processual terms brings us closer
to Gramsci’s original formulation of the concept, which focused
on how hegemony emerged through ‘a continuous process of formation and superseding of “unstable equilibria” … between the
interests of the fundamental group and those of the subordinate
groups’ (ibid.: 182). Hegemony, then, ‘does not just passively exist
as a form of dominance’, but is actively produced through contentious negotiations between dominant and subaltern groups (R.
Williams 1977: 112). To the extent that dominant groups are capable of gaining consent through such processes, the oppositional
projects of subaltern groups ‘will be reorganized and redeined,
obfuscated and partially buried’ (Mallon 1995: 7). Moreover,
Gramsci (1971: 263) was very clear that hegemony was always
‘protected by the armour of coercion’—in other words, whereas
dominant groups will accommodate the claims and demands of
some subaltern groups in their bid for hegemony, the oppositional
projects of other subaltern groups will be violently repressed by the
coercive apparatus of the state (Mallon 1995: 7). Ultimately, then,
the ‘compromise equilibrium’ (Gramsci 1971: 168) that results
from such processes—what Mallon (1995: 7) dubs a ‘hegemonic
outcome’—is a constellation that will always be vulnerable to new
rounds of assertion and contestation, which in turn means that
hegemony ‘has continually to be renewed, recreated, defended,
and modiied’ in active relation to the renewal and recreation of
subaltern politics (R. Williams 1977: 112).
Viewing hegemony in this way—as a contested process in
which consent and coercion are closely intertwined—is particularly apt for understanding the character of India’s neoliberal turn.
The character, impact, and outcomes of the neoliberal project
clearly relect the salience of elite interests. Witness, for example,
the coeval increase in economic growth and income disparities
Introduction
19
between 1991 and the present (see Jayadev et al. 2011), and the state
has certainly shown its willingness to mobilize coercive power in
the face of popular resistance, especially in relation to the ongoing
Maoist insurgency in the country’s Red Corridor (see, for example,
N. Sundar 2007: chapter 10, 2012).5 However, the trajectory of neoliberalization in India is simultaneously criss-crossed by political
processes that seek to garner consent from below. Chief among
these is arguably the emergence of what Sanjay Ruparelia (2013:
569) refers to as ‘the new rights agenda’—that is, the enactment of
several national laws that entrench both civil liberties and socioeconomic entitlements ‘through legally enforceable rights’ (see
also Chopra et al. 2011).6 Subaltern politics—in particular, the proliferation of socio-legal activism and the expansion of the popular
foundations of parliamentary democracy—has been a key driving
force in this process. Of course, it remains to be seen whether this
new agenda will serve as an effective resource for mobilization or
as a modality for co-optation and depoliticization, but, regardless
of this, the fact that liberties and entitlements have increasingly
been enshrined in law in recent years does testify to the negotiated
character of neoliberalism as a hegemonic project in contemporary
India.
What Follows …
The essays in this volume eschew expectations of purity in
reading both subalternity and subaltern politics as being irmly
embedded in particular historical and social conjunctures and
as being potentially transformative of the same through the use
of available political technologies. Ajantha Subramanian (2011)
underscores the dual character of subalternity as both embedded
and transformative, as offering a ‘productive dialectic between the
historical embeddedness of subaltern life—its emergence from
within formations of state and capital—and how through art and
politics, subaltern actors attempt to reach beyond and transform
their conditions of existence’. Such an approach takes us away
from what she calls ‘deinitional exercises to assess whether particular groups are authentically subaltern’ (or not), to analyse not
20
New Subaltern Politics
merely contemporary forms of subalternity but also ‘processes of
subalternization and challenges to it from within spaces of power’
(ibid.).
The contributions to the volume provide hard-hitting critiques
of the underlying assumptions of Subaltern Studies–inspired
approaches to subaltern politics: the presumption of purity and
autonomy, the bifurcation of civil and political spaces and elite
and subaltern domains, the absence of (elite) mediation, and the
unrepresentability of the subaltern, to name but a few. Several call
for a reconsideration of Gramscian/Marxian analytical approaches
to subaltern politics, especially in the face of a more recent,
Foucauldian turn to governmentality, in proposing ways forward in
South Asian studies as well as postcolonial studies more broadly.
The three chapters that constitute the irst part of the book,
‘Engaging Gramsci’, take up this project explicitly and contribute to the bigger argument about hegemony that the collection
forwards within and against poststructuralist deployments of the
Gramscian concept (see especially Nilsen and Desai’s contributions, this volume). Alf Gunvald Nilsen’s contribution opens up
the discussion with a dense historical and theoretical discussion of
state–subaltern relations, which are presented in a bifurcated view
not just in Subaltern Studies but also in more recent Foucauldian
readings of the same. Both fail, he shows, to fully appreciate the
production of subaltern political agency and its containment in
and through the state, and how subalterns use the full resources
of ‘democracy’ and ‘modernity’ available to them, traversing
Chatterjee’s spatial divide of ‘civil’ and ‘political’ society. Nilsen
turns to Gramsci to provide a conceptual armoury capable, on the
one hand, ‘of grasping how subaltern politics is always-already
imbricated in state–society relations, and how, on the other hand,
state–society relations simultaneously enable and constrain subaltern politics’.
Manali Desai and Ajantha Subramanian equally address the
question of hegemony. Desai does so through a perceptive analysis of emergent political subjectivities of informal-sector workers
in Ahmedabad, Gujarat. Arguing for a conceptual approach that
recognizes the negotiated and fractured nature of hegemony, she
explores how the hegemonic project of the Bharatiya Janata Party
Introduction
21
(BJP), which has been centred on the fusion of majoritarian Hindu
communalism and neoliberal developmentalism, is appropriated
by Dalit and Other Backward Class workers in the informal economy. Desai’s analysis reveals ambivalence as the deining feature
of the political subjectivities of subaltern groups, which, in turn,
destabilizes the BJP’s hegemonic project and renders it potentially vulnerable to assertion from below. The ambivalent nature
of these subjectivities opens up ways of remobilizing the concept
of hegemony in critical dialogue with studies conducted through
conceptual optics centred on Foucault’s concept of governmentality, thereby opening up ways of rethinking the character and form
of subaltern resistance.
While several chapters of the book critique the presumption
of autonomy in early Subaltern Studies, Subramanian shows how
autonomy does exist as a belief and a fought-for privilege amongst
upper-caste elites. Lower-caste mobilization has had a considerable impact in terms of challenging upper-caste hegemony in
contemporary India. However, the study of caste in Indian politics,
she contends, remains incomplete if we do not take cognizance of
upper-caste responses to such assertion. In the context of her case
study of Indian technical education, this response has materialized
in the form of a discourse in which ‘merit’ and ‘meritocracy’ are
systematically related to being upper caste and to the reproduction of hegemony. Subramanian underscores the ways in which
the politics of the powerful is shaped by the politics of the powerless, emphasizing the need to think of hegemony in processual
and dynamic terms rather than as a monolithic ideological ediice.
The next part of the book, on ‘Imagination, Faith, Affect’,
enhances given deinitions of subalternity and subaltern politics
through foregrounding the imaginative, affective, secular, and religious dimensions of subaltern as well as elite identity, practices,
and life. Rashmi Varma’s chapter takes on Spivak’s conceptualization of the subaltern not just as a position of ‘social, economic,
and political subordination’, but as one of ‘radical, and indeed an
irretrievable alterity … that has profound implications for the
politics of representation’. The problem of representation, posed
in this manner in postcolonial theory, not only silences the subaltern subject but disallows political voice and subjectivity that can
22
New Subaltern Politics
partly be developed through projects of solidarity. Varma recovers
the igure of the Adivasi—‘the unrepresentable par excellence’—
as a political subject-agent in a number of literary texts, against
the preoccupation of postcolonial theory with the limits and (im)
possibilities of representation. She also incorporates, in this manner, a perspective on and critique of postcolonial theory that offers
‘ironic analogies’ with the materialist approaches to subalternity
offered elsewhere in the volume.
Aparna Sundar similarly challenges the presumption of subaltern religiosity as being autonomous not only of religious
institutions but also of ‘the secular democratic politics of the
elite’. Subaltern religiosity has, moreover, been pitted against elite
secularism in recent (albeit limited) attempts to understand the
role of religion in politics in ways that latten out the complex
imbrications of both religious and secular domains, especially
when it comes to religious minorities. Sundar’s case study of the
Catholic ishing communities of Kanyakumari district, Tamil
Nadu, ethnographically and analytically illustrates her contention that, ‘far from being an autonomous and self-enclosed sphere,
subaltern religiosity must be read within the context of changing
political economies, caste, national, subnational, and even geopolitical shifts’.
The conception of the political is further extended—beyond its
association with autonomy or elitism—in Srila Roy’s discussion
of the affective dimensions of sexual rights activism in contemporary India. Not only does sexuality provide new analytical and
empirical purchase on the concept of the subaltern, but the ethnographic instance of lesbian activism that Roy turns to displaces
some of the central presumptions of the original Subaltern Studies
project that had to do with the normative rational male subject.
Sexual subalternity also provides a stronger case for mobilizing a
more expansive, relational, and intersectional conceptualization
of the subaltern even as it implicitly underscores, as David Arnold
notes in his postscript to this volume, the potential of this concept to encompass a diverse range of marginalized subjects beyond
what was originally imagined. Indeed, the essays of this volume
incorporate under the sign of ‘subaltern’ a diverse range of subjects, including sexual minorities, Dalits, and Adivasis, whose
Introduction
23
subalternity is understood in terms of locally speciic conigurations of power and powerlessness and vis-à-vis dominant groups
such as local activists, privileged upper-caste educators, religious
majorities, and sexually normative identities and practices.
The inal three chapters, in Part 3 titled ‘Caste and Community
in Civil/Political Society’, engage with Partha Chatterjee’s new
conceptual framework for addressing contemporary as opposed to
historical forms of subaltern politics. They join a host of critical
voices that show how this framework fails to capture the actual,
on-the-ground dynamics of the politics of contemporary subaltern
groups in India (see, for example, Baviskar and Sundar 2008; M.
Shah 2008; Sundar and Sundar 2012; and also Nilsen, this volume).
In drawing on rich case studies to make their critiques, the contributions in this section provide a more fully leshed out version of
contemporary subaltern politics and how such politics is embedded in regional particularities and the on-the-ground dynamics of
class, caste, and gender.
Luisa Steur develops a critique of Chatterjee’s argument that
Marxian perspectives of agrarian transition have been rendered
irrelevant by the introduction of social policy regimes that ameliorate the ramiications of contemporary forms of primitive
accumulation. Drawing on the work of Eric Wolf, she argues that
Chatterjee’s contention that social policy has to be understood
as a purely political phenomenon, detached from the economic
dynamics of neoliberalization in India, fails to capture the dialectical interrelations between dispossession as a form of ‘structural
power’ that operates on the macro-level of global capitalism, and
social policy as a form of ‘tactical power’ that seeks to ensure the
popular legitimacy of neoliberal projects in determinate locales.
Through an analysis of Dalit activism around land acquisition in
Tamil Nadu, Steur investigates how corporate social responsibility works to delect the collective action of subaltern groups as it
obfuscates the workings of structural forms of power at play in
contemporary processes of primitive accumulation.
A critique of Chatterjee’s now infamous civil–political society
dichotomy and what it does for the conceptualization of ‘community’ in Subaltern Studies is what is at stake in Kenneth Bo
Nielsen’s contribution to this volume. While the early subalternists
24
New Subaltern Politics
presumed pre-existing community formations and solidarities,
later works by Partha Chatterjee argue that communities are strategically created in the course of political action. Notwithstanding
this theoretical advancement over the earlier conception of community, Chatterjee’s ‘community’ appears ‘curiously bereft’ of an
appreciation of internal power dynamics and social hierarchies,
thus reinforcing romanticized notions of uniied subaltern collectives and consciousness. Nielsen uses his case study of the
movement against land acquisition and industrialization in rural
West Bengal to show how hierarchies pertaining to caste and class
complicate straightforward assumptions of community formation
and solidarity.
The idea that state interventions in contemporary India reverse
the social consequences of primitive accumulation is also the subject of critique of the inal chapter by Subir Sinha. Discussing the
mobilization of transnational solidarity for the wrongfully jailed
Binayak Sen and the politics of a Delhi-based Residents’ Welfare
Association, Sinha problematizes Chatterjee’s trifurcated conceptualization of the political domain into civil society, political
society, and ‘an outside beyond the boundaries of political society’
(Chatterjee 2008: 61). It is a perspective, he claims, that fails to
capture the actual political fault lines generated by contemporary
processes of primitive accumulation. Particularly, Sinha argues
that the claim that welfare programmes constitute a signiicant
region of ‘political society’—separate from the domain of civil
society—is rendered problematic by the multi-level solidarity networks that mediate and translate between dispossessed subaltern
groups and the liberal democratic discourses of universal rights
and entitlements.
The discussions and arguments that are presented in this volume relate most immediately to the contemporary Indian context.
However, the processes that we are concerned with—namely, the
ways in which subaltern groups mobilize collectively to contest
and resist the dispossession, disenfranchisement, oppression,
and stigma that are wrought by hegemonic formations—should
resonate beyond this speciic empirical reference point. In his concluding essay in this volume, David Arnold notes that Subaltern
Studies was always meant to be relevant beyond ‘the massed
Introduction
25
ranks of the academy’. That ambition remains as important and as
valid as ever today, when, across the global South, the advent and
unfolding of the neoliberal project have redeined the fault lines
of political mobilization over the past three decades, thus giving
rise to what Prashad (2012: 9) refers to as ‘a world of protest; a
whirlwind of creative activity’. We hope, therefore, that this book
might serve as a constructive contribution to an informed and
engaged debate about the prospects for politics from below across
the regions of the global South.
Notes
1. See Corbridge and Harriss (2000, chapter 7), Kohli (2006a, 2006b),
and Vanaik (2001) for accounts of the elite-driven nature of economic
reform in India.
2. See Chakrabarty (2002, chapter 1), Chaturvedi (2000b), and Ludden
(2002a) for accounts of the evolution of the Subaltern Studies project.
The key contributions to the critical debates that were spawned by the
Subaltern Studies project are collected in Chaturvedi (2000a) and Ludden
(2002b).
3. The most signiicant contribution to this turn is arguably Dipesh
Chakrabarty’s (2000) Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought
and Historical Difference, which sets out to destabilize and transcend
Eurocentric narratives of transitions towards the modern. Other signiicant contributions include Gyan Prakash (1990, 1994) and Ranajit Guha
(2002). The debate between O’Hanlon and Washbrook (1992) and Gyan
Prakash (1992) is also important in this respect, as is Sumit Sarkar’s (1994)
critical intervention on Saidian frameworks in the writing of modern
Indian history.
4. Chatterjee (2004, 2008) has attempted to carry out such a redeinition by suggesting that subaltern politics in contemporary India operates
on the terrain that he refers to as ’political society’—that is, the terrain
constituted by the apparatuses of governmentality that attach to the state.
Political society is contrasted to civil society where the principles of liberal democracy prevail. In Chatterjee’s account, civil society remains a
domain of elite politics. Sinha, Nielsen, and Steur discuss the adequacy
of Chatterjee’s formulation in detail in this volume. See also Gudavarthy
(2012) for a collection of essays on Chatterjee’s recent work.
26
New Subaltern Politics
5. Violence and coercion are, of course, also central features of the
Indian state’s presence in Kashmir and the North-East states (see Baruah
1999; Duschinski 2009).
6. These include, for example, the Right to Information Act, the Right
to Food Act, the Right of Children to Free and Compulsory Education
Act, the National Rural Employment Guarantee Act, the Forest Rights
Act, and the recent Right to Fair Compensation and Transparency in Land
Acquisition, Rehabilitation and Resettlement Act.
Introduction
27