OPERATIONS RESEARCH
Vol. 61, No. 1, January–February 2013, pp. 1–16
ISSN 0030-364X (print) ISSN 1526-5463 (online)
http://dx.doi.org/10.1287/opre.1120.1068
© 2013 INFORMS
CROSSCUTTING AREAS
OR Forum—Quantum Mechanics and
Human Decision Making
Paras M. Agrawal, Ramesh Sharda
William S. Spears School of Business, Institute for Research in Information Systems, Oklahoma State University, Stillwater, Oklahoma 74078
{
[email protected],
[email protected]}
In physics, at the beginning of the twentieth century it was recognized that some experiments could not be explained by
the conventional classical mechanics, but the same could be explained by the newly discovered quantum theory. It resulted
in a new mechanics called quantum mechanics that revolutionized scientific and technological developments. Again, at the
beginning of the twenty-first century, it is being recognized that some experiments related to the human decision-making
processes could not be explained by the conventional classical decision theory but the same could be explained by the
models based on quantum mechanics. It is now recognized that we need quantum mechanics in psychology as well as
in economics and finance. In this paper we attempt to advance and explain the present understanding of applicability of
quantum mechanics to the human decision-making processes. Using the postulates analogous to the postulates of quantum
mechanics, we show the derivation of the quantum interference equation to illustrate the quantum approach. The explanation
of disjunction effect experiments of Tversky and Shafir (Tversky A, Shafir E (1992) The disjunction effect in choice
under uncertainty. Psych. Sci. 3(5):305–309) has been chosen to demonstrate the necessity of a quantum model. Further,
to suggest the possibility of application of the quantum theory to the business-related decisions, some terms such as price
operator, state of mind of the acquiring firm, etc., are introduced and discussed in context of the merger/acquisition of
business firms. The possibility of the development in areas such as quantum finance, quantum management, application of
quantum mechanics to the human dynamics related to healthcare management, etc., is also indicated.
Subject classifications: decision analysis: theory; quantum decision model; quantum information processing; human
decision making; quantum interference.
Area of review: OR Forum.
History: Received July 2010; revisions received April 2011, November 2011; accepted February 2012. Published online
in Articles in Advance December 13, 2012.
1. Introduction
nanotechnology, femto-chemistry, molecular biology, cosmology, high-energy physics, quantum mechanics is valuable and indispensible.
In recent years, one notes a growing interest in the application of quantum mechanics to areas such as quantum cryptography (e.g., Bennett and Brassard 1984, Bennett et al.
1992, Chung et al. 2008) as well as quantum computation
(e.g., Shor 1997, Lo et al. 2000, Hand 2009). As regards
the application of quantum mechanics beyond physical
sciences, Bohr (1929) attempted to show the similarity
between the mental processes and the quantum mechanical
phenomena. In his writings, he also discussed the similarities between quantum mechanics and the functions of the
brain (e.g., Bohr 1933). In recent decades, there have been
various notable attempts to ascribe the quantum mechanical
properties to brain, mind, and consciousness (e.g., Chalmers
1996, Lockwood 1989, Penrose 1989, Penrose et al. 2000,
Pessa and Vitiello 2003, Satinover 2001).
Recently there has been some new work to explore applicability of quantum models in better understanding nuances
of human decision making. The purpose of this paper is to
introduce and explain the quantum concepts through simple
terms and notations, to apply these concepts in better understanding the recent applications of quantum mechanics to
It is well known that quantum mechanics leads to many
peculiar results such as quantum interference, uncertainty
principle, quantum nature of light, quantum theory of measurement, tunneling, etc., which are in contradiction with
our common sense and classical mechanics. Physicist Niels
Bohr, who won the 1922 Nobel Prize in Physics chiefly
for his work on atomic structure, once remarked, “If quantum mechanics hasn’t profoundly shocked you, you haven’t
understood it yet” (Bohr n.d.).
Despite its strange behavior, the quantum mechanics is
considered as the most successful theory of physics. Stenholm and Suominen (2005, p. 1), in their book on quantum approach to informatics, write: “Quantum theory has
turned out to be the most universally successful theory of
physics. 0 0 0 Without the understanding offered by quantum
theory, our ability to build integrated circuits and communication devices would not have emerged.” A large number of scientists (e.g., Planck, Einstein, Bohr, de Broglie,
Heisenberg, Schrödinger, Born, Dirac, Pauli, Pauling) have
been awarded Nobel Prizes for their contributions related
to quantum mechanics. In various walks of modern science
and technology, including electronics, nuclear technology,
1
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
2
human decision making, and to suggest applicability of
models based on quantum mechanics to some new areas of
research.
1.1. Quantum Mechanics and Human
Decision Making
Regarding the human mind, economics Nobel Laureate
Herbert Simon wrote in collaboration with Newell (Simon
and Newell 1958, p. 9): “The revolution in heuristic problem solving will force man to consider his role in a world
in which his intellectual power and speed are outstripped
by the intelligence of machines. Fortunately, the new revolution will at the same time give him a deeper understanding of the structure and working of his own mind.”
It is interesting to note the significance attached by these
authors to quantum mechanics in the same paper in these
words: “In dealing with the ill-structured problems of management we have not had the mathematical tools we have
needed—we have not had ‘judgment mechanics’ to match
quantum mechanics” (p. 6). The expectations of Simon and
Newell, expressed half a century ago, regarding the necessity of understanding of our own mind and a mechanics
of the decision-making process are not yet fulfilled. However, we are now gaining momentum in the direction of
understanding the human decision processes even through
quantum mechanics. Thus, the objective of this paper is
to introduce these concepts and review the recent progress
to stimulate more exploratory research on applications of
quantum mechanics concepts in decision making.
Kahneman, Tversky, and Shafir have made notable contributions in the area of judgment under uncertainty and the
influence of heuristics and biases on the cognitive system
(Tversky and Kahneman 1974, Tversky and Shafir 1992,
Shafir and Tversky 1992). The significance of the work
is attested to by the fact that Kahneman was awarded the
Nobel Prize in 2002. Results of several experiments related
to the judgment under uncertainty, as noted by Tversky and
Shafir (Tversky and Shafir 1992, Shafir and Tversky 1992),
in the area of human psychology could not be explained by
the classical statistics. The disjunction effect experimentally
observed by Tversky and Shafir (1992) is a typical example of the intricacies of the human mind that could not be
understood by the classical decision theory. For example, in
an experiment of Tversky and Shafir (1992), a participant
is offered to play a gamble (by tossing a coin) with a 50%
chance of winning $200 and a 50% chance of losing $100.
After the first play, the participant is offered to play the
second identical game with or without the knowledge of
the outcome of the first gamble. It has been observed that
a majority of participants are ready to accept the second
gamble after knowing that they have won the first one, and
a majority of participants are also ready to accept the second gamble after knowing that they have lost the first one,
but only a small fraction of participants are ready to accept
the second gamble if they do not know the outcome of the
first gamble. The question arises: if they prefer to accept
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
the second gamble in case they win or lose the first gamble, then according to the sure-thing principle of Savage
(1954), they should prefer to accept the second gamble even
when they do not know the outcome of the first gamble.
However, the experiment contradicts such logical expectations. Why? We could not yet get the answer of this “why”
from the conventional (classical) theories. Such a violation
of the sure-thing principle of Savage (1954) has also been
observed by Tversky and Shafir (1992) in another experiment related to buying an attractive vacation package.
The successful studies to explain some of these paradoxes by incorporating mathematical equations related
with quantum mechanics into the psychology (Aerts 2009,
Busemeyer et al. 2006, Pothos and Busemeyer 2009,
Khrennikov 2009, Yukalov and Sornette 2009a) clearly
reveal that some aspects of the human behavior, which
could not yet be explained by the classical decision theory,
can be explained by quantum mechanical equations. The
investigations of Bordley (1998) and Bordley and Kadane
(1999) also suggest the importance of quantum mechanical notions and equations in explaining some aspects of
human decision making. It may be noted that classical
mechanics and quantum mechanics differ ideologically as
well as mathematically; and for macrosystems the approximate form of mathematical equations of quantum mechanics agrees with the equations of classical mechanics.
If the decision-making processes of the human mind follow the probabilistic behavior of quantum mechanics, then
one can expect the applicability of the same in other areas,
which are directly affected by human decision making.
Thus, it is not surprising that researchers in economics and
finance have explored application of quantum mechanics
(Baaquie 2004, Bordley 2005, Kondratenko 2005, Baaquie
2009a). The application of quantum mechanics to economics and finance can be seen in various areas, such
as a price dynamics model (Choustova 2007), stock price
(Schaden 2003, Bagarello 2009), interest rate (Baaquie
2009b), incorporation of private information (Ishio and
Haven 2009, Haven 2008), etc. As an example of the value
of quantum mechanics in the field of economics, one can
refer to the study conducted by Segal and Segal (1998).
In this study they consider quantum effects to explain
extreme irregularities in the evolution of prices in financial markets. In the concluding paragraph of this study,
Segal and Segal (1998, p. 4075) write: “The quantum
extension of Black-Scholes-Merton theory provides a rational, scientifically economical, and testable model toward
the explanation of market phenomena that show greater
extreme deviations than would be expected in classical
theory 0 0 0 0”
An electronic companion to this paper is available as
part of the online version at http://dx.doi.org/10.1287/opre
.1120.1068. In Appendix-A in the e-companion, we have
described some facts related to the historical development
of quantum mechanics. At the beginning of the twentieth century, it was recognized that some experimental
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
3
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
results could not be explained by the conventional classical
mechanics, but the same could be explained by the newly
discovered quantum physics. It resulted in a new mechanics
called quantum mechanics that revolutionized scientific and
technological development. The uncertainty principle, the
quantum theory of measurement, the statistical significance
of the wave functions of quantum mechanics, the mathematics involving operators and the abstract vector space,
quantum statistics, etc., are some of the various features of
quantum mechanics that are not available in the conventional classical mechanics. Therefore, in case of difficulty
in explaining some aspects of psychology, or economics,
or any other branch of knowledge through the classical
mechanics, one may expect that some special features of
quantum mechanics may be helpful. As mentioned earlier,
we have already noted some success in this direction in the
area of human decision making. In view of such aspects, it
becomes valuable to be familiar with some basics of quantum mechanics.
By the phrase “understanding human decision process
through quantum mechanics,” we mean the application of
some aspects, such as mathematical framework, of quantum
mechanics. For example, we may consider some states of
mind in an abstract space that mathematically behave as the
quantum states in the Hilbert space (von Neumann 1983,
Messiah 1970), and the decision-making process as a process statistically governed by the formulation based on the
postulates of quantum mechanics. This, however, does not
mean that the human mind becomes a quantum mechanical object. Just as a quantum description of electrons, light
quanta, etc., require the necessity of a constant known as
Planck’s constant (h = 60626 × 10−34 Joule-Second), we
do not need Planck’s constant for explaining the abovementioned disjunction effect or other paradoxes of psychology. Likewise, in quantum mechanics, Schrödinger’s
time-independent and time-dependent wave equations contain Planck’s constant, but in the corresponding equations of quantum dynamics of human decision making
(Busemeyer et al. 2006, Pothos and Busemeyer 2009), this
constant occurring in the equations of quantum mechanics
is replaced by another parameter.
1.2. Application of Quantum Models to
Disjunction Effect and Other Decisions
While explaining the disjunction effect and other paradoxes of psychology with the help of quantum models,
Khrennikov (2009) considers the effect of quantum interference in the form of an equation that has an adjustable
parameter called the coefficient of interference. Yukalov
and Sornette (2008, 2009a, b, c) provide a detailed theory
called quantum decision theory (QDT). Using the postulates analogous to the postulates of quantum mechanics,
they derive the quantum interference equations that relate
various experimental probabilities.
To explain the same disjunction effect, Pothos and
Busemeyer (2009) consider the evolution of the state
of mind using an equation analogous to Schrödinger’s
time-dependent wave equation of quantum mechanics. The
duration of time and the interaction parameters have been
considered as adjustable parameters. For comparison, they
also study the evolution of the state of mind using the
equivalent Markov (classical) model, and found that their
Markov (classical) model could not explain the experimentally observed violations of the sure-thing principle of Savage (1954), whereas the quantum model could
explain them.
In a quantum decision model discussed in detail in §2,
we employ various aspects of the quantum decision theory
of Yukalov and Sornette (2009a) but consider more general
and simpler kinds of operators to derive the same quantum
interference equation as derived by Yukalov and Sornette
(2009a), so that the range of applicability may widen and it
becomes easier to apply to other related problems. Further,
to demonstrate the possibility of application of the quantum approach to other decision problems, we consider an
example of the problem of a merger of two business firms.
It may be a long way to arrive at a successful and valuable outcome of the application of a quantum model to the
problem of merger of two business firms. However, here
we shall simply introduce the problem to familiarize the
reader with the notations and application of the quantum
models in this area.
Thus, the purpose of this paper is to serve as a tutorial by illustrating current and future potential applications
of quantum concepts to human decision making. In §2,
the mathematical details of a sample quantum model are
described. Application of the quantum approach in explaining the disjunction experiments, and the possibility of its
application to the business-related problems, together with
the discussion of the related studies in this area, are presented in §3. The final section provides the summary and
concluding remarks.
2. Mathematical Details of a Sample
Decision Model
To simplify, we describe the model with reference to a
practical example. We consider the two-stage gambling
experiment of Tversky and Shafir (1992). In this experiment, subjects are first offered to play a gamble (by tossing
a coin) with a 50% chance of winning $200 and a 50%
chance of losing $100. After the first play, the subjects
are offered to play the identical game with or without the
knowledge of winning or losing the first gamble. We introduce several probabilities and the related notations associated with this experiment in Table 1. In this section, we
shall describe the quantum decision model to explain the
results of this experiment, which could not be explained by
the conventional (classical) methods.
For an understanding of the basic postulates of quantum mechanics, we consider an analogy: Suppose we ask
our banker to provide us with information regarding the
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
4
Table 1.
p4X1 5
p4X2 5
p4A X1 5
p4AX1 5
p4A X2 5
p4AX2 5
p4A5
p4B X1 5
p4BX1 5
p4B X2 5
p4BX2 5
p4B5
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
Notations regarding various probabilities.
Probability of winning the first gamble
= No. of participants winning the first
gamble/No. of participants.
Probability of not winning the first gamble (losing)
= No. of participants not winning the first
gamble/No. of participants.
Probability of accepting the second gamble after
knowing that he/she has won the first gamble.
Joint probability of winning the first gamble and
accepting the second gamble. It is equal to the
product of p4X1 5 and p4A X1 5.
p4AX1 5 = p4X1 5p4A X1 5.
(1)
Probability of accepting the second gamble after
knowing that he/she has not won the first gamble.
Joint probability of not winning the first gamble
and accepting the second gamble. It is equal to
the product of p4X2 5 and p4A X2 5.
p4AX2 5 = p4X2 5p4A X2 5.
(2)
Probability of accepting the second gamble
in absence of any knowledge of winning or
losing the first gamble.
Probability of not accepting the second gamble after
knowing that he/she has won the first gamble.
See the corresponding terms with A in this table.
The difference between A and B symbols is in
“accepting” and “not accepting.” In this regard,
parallel to Equations (1) and (2), we shall have
p4BX1 5 = p4X1 5p4B X1 5, and
(3)
p4BX2 5 = p4X2 5p4B X2 5.
(4)
It can be easily understood that the sum of
probability of accepting and not accepting is 1,
i.e.,
p4A5 + p4B5 = 10
(5)
Notes. The events and activities are denoted as follows:
X1 : Win first gamble. X2 : Not win the first gamble.
A: Accept second gamble. B: Not accept the second gamble.
amount of interest we have earned. To answer this question,
the bank teller would first open our account, which would
contain all information regarding our deposits, check withdrawals, etc. The details regarding our account in the register or on the computer screen would give the present status
of our account. To answer our query regarding the amount
of interest, the teller would perform some operations/
Table 2.
calculations related to the amount of interest. Similarly,
in quantum mechanics, analogous to the details of our
account, there exists a state function or a state ket or a
state vector or simply a state of the system for the system
under consideration; and corresponding to “the amount of
interest” in our analogy, in quantum mechanics we have
an operator. For example, in physics there are operators
corresponding to energy, momentum, position, etc., and in
the quantum decision model we will see that there can be
operators like price operator, buy operator, pass operator,
win operator, accept operator, etc. Finally, from some operations of the operators on the state of the system we would
get the desired result just as a bank teller arrives at the
amount of interest earned.
The example above describes the method of getting
the desired information in the framework of quantum
mechanics. We present such a framework in Table 2. We
describe the postulates of quantum mechanics (Messiah
1970, White 1966, Agrawal 1989) and also introduce those
for the quantum decision model. One would note that
there is one-to-one correspondence between these two sets
of postulates. Just like the existence of “our account” in
the above-mentioned example, postulate #1 described in
Table 2 asserts that there exists a state ket that represents/describes the system. Next, corresponding to the
“amount of interest” in the above analogy, here in Table 2
we have postulate #2 that says that there exists an operator
Ô associated with a measurable O. Further, just like the
method of determination of the amount of interest, postulate #3 described in the table provides the recipe to compute
the average value of O from the knowledge of the state
of the system and the operator Ô. According to this
postulate, the average value of O is
O = Ô0
For the meaning of the matrix element Ô, Equation (EC-1) and Table 5 in the e-companion would be
helpful. To provide confidence and clarity, its application
at many places has been illustrated in this section. While
going through applications, the reader would note that the
mathematical treatment discussed in this work does not
need any complicated calculus or algebra or trigonometry.
Postulates of quantum mechanics and quantum decision model.
Regarding
(1) State corresponding to a
system
(2) Operator corresponding
to a measurable
(3) Result of measurement
Quantum mechanics
Quantum decision model
The dynamical state of a system can be fully
represented by a state ket .
With every physical quantity (dynamical variable)
O, an operator Ô can be associated.
The average result of measurement, O, of O
in state is given by
The state of a system can be represented by a
state ket .
With every prospect or a variable O an operator
Ô can be associated.
The average result of measurement, O, of O
in state is given by
O = Ô/ .
When is normalized, i.e., for = 1, the
above relation becomes
O = Ô/ .
When is normalized, i.e., for = 1, the
above relation becomes
O = Ô.
O = Ô.
(6)
(6a)
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
5
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
One needs to be familiar with only a few notations such as
, , , and Ô. In this regard, the description of terms and notations of quantum mechanics given in
Appendix-B and C in the e-companion would be helpful.
A state may be denoted by different kinds of notations (see Appendix-B). We have adopted Dirac’s notations
(Dirac 1958) to denote the state ket. In Dirac’s notation,
a state is denoted by a label placed in the symbol (see
Table 3). As an example of the state of a system, we again
draw our attention to the problem of the two-stage gambling experiment. In Table 3, we have described various
states. The first entry in this table gives a state A corresponding to accepting the second gamble, i.e., in this
state (state of mind) the probability of accepting the second gamble is 100%. We denote this state by notation A.
Here, symbol is used to specify that it is a state ket
(see Appendix-B). Before proceeding further, it may be
appropriate for a reader to be familiar with all other states
described in Table 3.
In Table 4, we describe two operators, ÔW and ÔA .
ÔW operator corresponds to the probability of winning the
first gamble, and it may be named as “win operator.” ÔA
operator corresponds to the probability of accepting the
second gamble, and it may be named as “accept operator.”
2.1. Experimental Data to Be Explained
Before going further, it would be appropriate to be familiar
with, in our notations, the experimental data we need to
Table 3.
A
B
X1
X2
AX1
AX2
BX1
BX2
Notations regarding quantum states.
Represents a state corresponding to accepting the
second gamble. In this state the probability of
accepting the second gamble is 100%.
Represents a state corresponding to not accepting
the second gamble. In this state the probability of
not accepting the second gamble is 100%.
Represents a state in which the probability of
winning the first gamble is 100%.
Represents a state in which the probability of
winning the first gamble is 0%.
Represents a state in which the probability of
winning the first gamble is 100% and the
probability of accepting the second gamble is
100%. It is the tensor product (see Appendix-C
in the e-companion) of A and X1 , i.e.,
AX1 = AX1 .
Represents a state in which the probability of losing
the first gamble is 100% and the probability of
accepting the second gamble is 100%. It is the
tensor product of A and X2 , i.e.,
AX2 = AX2 .
See the corresponding terms with A in this table.
The difference between A and B symbols is
in “accepting” and “not accepting.”
Note. For mathematical simplicity all states described in this table
are taken as normalized.
Table 4.
Notations regarding operators.
ÔW
(Win operator)
Operator corresponding to the probability
of winning the first gamble. It has
eigenvalues 1 and 0. Eigenvalue = 1
corresponds to the winning of the first
gamble and 0 corresponds to losing the
first gamble.
ÔA
Operator corresponding to the probability
of accepting the second gamble. It has
(Accept operator)
eigenvalues 1 and 0. Eigenvalue = 1
corresponds to accepting the second
gamble and 0 corresponds to not
accepting the second gamble.
explain. The experiments performed by Tversky and Shafir
(1992) reveal the following:
p4A X1 5 = 00691
p4B X1 5 = 1 − p4A X1 5 = 00311 (7)
p4A X2 5 = 00591
p4B X2 5 = 1 − p4A X2 5 = 00411 (8)
p4A5 = 00361
and
p4B5 = 1 − p4A5 = 00640
(9)
The interesting part of these data is as follows: 69% of
participants are ready to accept the second gamble if they
know that they have won the first gamble, and 59% of
participants are ready to accept the second gamble, even
if they know that they have lost the first gamble. However, when they do not know the result of the first gamble,
only 36% of the participants are ready to accept the second gamble. We note here that a majority of participants
prefer to accept the second gamble in either case of win or
lose, but when they are uncertain about winning or losing,
then only a small fraction of the participants are ready to
accept the second gamble. In literature (Tversky and Shafir
1992), this is known as the disjunction effect in choice
under uncertainty.
The above data contradicts the sure-thing principle
given by Savage (1954). According to this principle, if a
prospect x is preferred to y knowing that event R happens,
and if x is preferred to y with the knowledge that event R
did not happen, then x should be preferred to y even when
the result of happening of R is unknown. This principle
is considered as one of the basic axioms of the rational
classical theory of decision under uncertainty.
2.2. Eigenkets and Eigenvalues
Using the hermitian nature of the operators in quantum
mechanics, in general, it can be shown that if in state i
the result of measurement of O is ai with 100% certainty,
then the following relation holds well:
Ôi = ai i 0
Here Ô is an operator associated with O. In quantum
mechanics, we call i satisfying above relation as eigenket of operator Ô having eigenvalue ai (see Appendix-B
in the e-companion for more details). The reverse is also
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
6
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
true, i.e., if the state of the system is an eigenstate of an
operator Ô, then the result of measurement of O in that
eigenstate would be the corresponding eigenvalue and the
uncertainty or variance in that result of measurement would
be zero.
In the quantum decision model, we assume that kets
(), bras (), and operators belong to the Hilbert space
in the same way that we consider in quantum mechanics.
Therefore, we get the same concept of eigenkets and eigenvalues in the quantum decision model as well. The scalar
product and matrix elements Ô are also
defined in the same way as they are in quantum mechanics
(see Appendix-B in the e-companion).
In view of this description, we can say that state A
is an eigenstate of operator ÔA corresponding to eigenvalue 1, and state B is an eigenstate of the same operator corresponding to eigenvalue zero. Similarly, X1 is an
eigenstate of operator ÔW corresponding to eigenvalue 1
and X2 is an eigenstate of operator ÔW corresponding to
eigenvalue 0. In equation form we can write
ÔA A = A1
ÔA B = zeroB = 01
ÔW X1 = X1 1
(10)
ÔW X2 = zeroX2 = 00
(11)
Here 0 refers to a ket such that its scalar product with
any bra equals zero.
Before proceeding further, we need to be familiar with
the basics of the tensor product space as described in
Appendix-C. In the foregoing description, we consider two
types of spaces. (1) A two-dimensional win-lose space:
the operator ÔW , and states X1 and X2 belong to this
space. (2) A two-dimensional accept-reject space: the operator ÔA , and states A and B belong to this space. As
explained in Appendix-C, we can have a four-dimensional
tensor product space as a product of these two spaces.
The states AX1 , AX2 , BX1 , and BX2 (here AX1 ≡
AX1 , and so on) would belong to such tensor product
space. Further, as explained in Appendix-C, for an operator
corresponding to ÔA (or ÔW 5 of two-dimensional space we
can have another similar operator in this four-dimensional
space and, for the sake of convenience and without causing any confusion, such an operator in the four-dimensional
tensor product space can be denoted by the same notation
ÔA (or ÔW 5 (Messiah 1970). Thus, we can write
ÔA AX1 = AX1
Figure 1.
and
ÔW AX1 = AX1 0
(12)
For other similar equations, one may refer to Appendix-D
in the e-companion. Further, we know that eigenkets
belonging to different eigenvalues of a given operator are
orthogonal (for details one may refer to Appendix-B in the
e-companion). We use the same concept here. Thus, we
shall have
X1 X2 = X2 X1 = 01
A B = B A = 00
AX1 AX2 = AX2 AX1 = 0
(13)
and
BX1 BX2 = BX2 BX1 = 00
(14)
For more equations along these lines, please refer to
Appendix-D in the e-companion. Here X1 X2 is called
the scalar product of kets X1 and X2 ; for details, one
may refer to Appendix-B in the e-companion.
2.3. Determination of the State of the System
We have operators and eigenstates related to this experiment. All we need is to obtain the ket representing the state
of the system. Let gives the state of win/lose of the system. This state in win-lose space (Hilbert space) would
be a linear combination (for an illustration, see Figure 1) of
the related eigenket X1 corresponding to win and eigenket
X2 corresponding to lose. Thus, we can write
= 1 X1 + 2 X2 0
(15)
For the sake of mathematical convenience, we choose the
expansion coefficients 1 and 2 such that the ket is
normalized, i.e., = 1. This normalization condition
would lead to
1 2 + 2 2 = 10
(16)
As the ÔW operator corresponds to the probability of winning the first gamble, for computing the probability of winning the first gamble we shall employ Equation (6a) and
this operator ÔW . Using Equation (6a), for the probability
of winning the first gamble, we can write
p4X1 5 = ÔW 0
(17)
In view of Equations (15) and (11) we can get
ÔW = 1 X1 0
(18)
For the bra vector , Equation (15) leads to
= ∗1 X1 + ∗2 X2 0
(See Table 5 in the e-companion.)
(19)
Here superscript ∗ has been used to indicate the complex
conjugate, i.e., ∗1 is complex conjugate of the number 1 .
The win-lose state of the first game is a linear combination of win state (X1 ) (“smiling face”) with probability amplitude 1 , and the lose state (X2) (“sad face”) with probability amplitude 2 (see Equation (15)).
Win
1 | X1 〉
Lose
+
2 | X2 〉
|〉 = 1 | X1〉 + 2 | X2 〉
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
7
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
Because the sum of p4A X1 5 and p4B X1 5 equals 1, using
Equation (24) and (26) one can obtain
By combining Equations (17)–(19), we get
p4X1 5 = ÔW = 6∗1 X1 + ∗2 X2 761 X1 7
= 6∗1 1 X1 X1 + ∗2 1 X2 X1 70
(20)
p4BX1 = 1 − p4A X1 5 = b1 2 0
Because X1 is normalized, therefore, X1 X1 = 1. Equation (20) in combination with this normalization condition
and Equation (13) leads to
Similarly, for the state of mind 2 (for an illustration, see
Figure 3) associated with losing the first gamble, one can
write
p4X1 5 = ∗1 1 = 1 2 0
(21)
2 = a2 AX2 +b2 BX2 1
(22)
Again, using operator ÔA , Equations (6a), (27),
(EC-13), (EC-15), (EC-25), and the normalization property
6AX2 AX2 = 17, we can get
From this result, one can obtain
2
p4X2 5 = 1 − p4X1 5 = 2 0
It is obvious that the win/lose is not a matter of decision by
the players in this experiment. Further, we know that among
the participants who have won the first gamble, some would
accept the second gamble and some would not. As AX1
corresponds to winning the first gamble and accepting the
second gamble, and BX1 corresponds to winning the first
gamble and rejecting the second gamble, therefore, the state
of mind 1 associated with the winning of the first gamble
can be expressed (for an illustration, see Figure 2) as a
linear combination of AX1 and BX1 :
where a2 2 +b2 2 = 10
p4AX2 = 2 ÔA 2 = a2 2 0
(27)
(28)
Further, because the sum of p4A X2 5 and p4B X2 5
equals 1, therefore, using Equations (27) and (28), one can
have
p4BX2 = 1 − p4AX2 = b2 2 0
The normalization condition requires 1 1 = 1. This
would lead to
To arrive at the state of mind representing all subjects
(sum of those who are losing and those who are winning the
first play), we would have linear combination of states 1
and 2 . The expansion coefficients for this combination
must be the same as those occurring in Equation (15), i.e.,
a1 2 + b1 2 = 10
= 1 1 + 2 2 0
1 = a1 AX1 + b1 BX1 0
(23)
(24)
For computing the probability of accepting the second
gamble with the knowledge of winning the first gamble, we
can use Equation (6a), operator ÔA , and state 1 . Thus,
we have
(29)
The above equation with the help of Equations (23), (12),
(EC-11), (EC-22), and the normalization property 6AX1
AX1 = 17 leads to
This equation implies that the state X1 of Equation (15)
in the win-lose space becomes state 1 in the win-loseaccept-reject space; the state X2 of Equation (15) in the
win-lose space becomes state 2 in the win-lose-acceptreject space; and the state of the same equation in
win-lose space becomes state in win-lose-accept-reject
space. On substituting the value of 1 given by Equation (23) and of 2 given by Equation (27) into Equation (29), we obtain
p4A X1 5 = 1 ÔA 1 = a1 2 0
= c1 AX1 + c2 AX2 + c3 BX1 + c4 BX2 1
p4A X1 5 = 1 ÔA 1 0
Figure 2.
(25)
(26)
(30)
Win state leads to win and accept state (rectangle and “smiling face”) with probability amplitude a1 , and
reject-win state (triangle and “smiling face”) with probability amplitude b1 . The linear combination of these
two states has been expressed as 1 (see Equation (23)). The factor 1 in every block reminds the probability
amplitude of the win state (see Figure 1).
Accept
Win
1a1 | AX1〉
1a1 | AX1〉 +
1b1 | BX1〉 = 1 | ψ1〉
1 | X1〉
Reject
1b1 | BX1〉
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
8
Figure 3.
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
Lose state leads to accept and lose state (rectangle and “sad face”) with probability amplitude a2 , and rejectlose state (triangle and “sad face”) with probability amplitude b2 . The linear combination of these two states
has been expressed as 2 (see Equation (27)). The factor 2 in every block reminds the probability amplitude
of the lose state (see Figure 1).
Accept
2 a2 | AX2〉
Lose
2 a2 |AX2〉 +
2 b2 |BX2〉 = 2 | ψ2〉
2 | X2 〉
2 b2 | BX2〉
Reject
where
and, using Equations (34) and (31) we can get
c1 = 1 a1 1
c2 = 2 a2 1
c3 = 1 b1 1
and c4 = 2 b2 0
(31)
p4AX2 5 = c2 2 0
(35)
We can similarly have
It may be noted that AX1 represents a state corresponding to accepting the second gamble and winning the first
gamble, AX2 represents a state corresponding to accepting the second gamble and not winning the first gamble,
BX1 represents a state corresponding to not accepting the
second gamble but winning the first gamble, and BX2 represents a state corresponding to not accepting the second
gamble and not winning the first gamble (for an illustration see Figure 4). These are four orthonormal eigenkets in
four-dimensional win-lose-accept-reject space.
p4BX1 5 = 1 2 b1 2 = c3 2 1
2
2
and
2
p4BX2 5 = 2 b2 = c4 0
(36)
Using Equations (32)–(36), (31), (27), (24), and (16), it can
be seen that
p4AX1 5 + p4AX2 5 + p4BX1 5 + p4BX2 5
= c1 2 + c2 2 + c3 2 + c4 2 = 10
(37)
The above equation in combination with Equation (31)
leads to
An alternative way to arrive at these results may be to
employ Equation (30) together with projection operators
(Messiah 1970). given by Equation (30) is a linear combination of four orthonormal kets AX1 , AX2 , BX1 , and
BX2 . AX1 represents a state in which the probability of
winning the first gamble and accepting the second gamble
is 100%. Therefore, for computing the joint probability of
winning the first gamble and accepting the second gamble,
one needs to determine the relative weight of state AX1 in
the combination given by Equation (30). This can be done
by using Equation (6a) with Ô as the projection operator
AX1 AX1 (Messiah 1970). Thus, we get
p4AX1 5 = c1 2 0
p4AX1 5 = 4AX1 AX1 5
2.4. Analysis of Probabilities
For evaluating the joint probability of winning the first
gamble and accepting the second gamble, p4AX1 5, we can
employ Equations (1), (21), and (26) and obtain
p4AX1 5 = 1 2 a1 2 0
(32)
(33)
= 4 AX1 54AX1 5 = c1∗ c1 = c1 2 0
Again, using Equations (2), (22), and (28) we can have
2
2
p4AX2 5 = 2 a2 1
Figure 4.
(34)
(38)
Similarly, for p4AX2 5, p4BX1 5, and p4BX2 5 we can get the
results, in agreement with those given by Equations (35)
The state of the system given by Equation (30) is a linear combination of four states corresponding to
win-accept, win-reject, lose-accept, and lose-reject states.
Win-Accept
1 a1 | AX1〉
+
Win-Reject
1 b1 | BX1〉
+
Lose-Accept
2 a2 | AX2〉
+
Lose-Reject
2 b2 | BX2〉
= |ψ〉
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
9
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
and (36), by using Equation (6a) and the corresponding projection operators, AX2 AX2 , BX1 BX1 , and
BX2 BX2 , respectively.
2.5. Analysis of the Situation When Outcome of
the First Game Is Unknown
Equation (30) represents a state that contains the information regarding winning and losing. The experiments of
Tversky and Shafir (1992), performed with 98 subjects to
determine p4AX1 5 and p4AX2 5, can be described by this
state together with Equation (15). Next, for the determination of probability of accepting the second gamble without
any information regarding winning and losing the first gamble, p4A5, they performed the experiment after 10 days.
In the experiments, there is no magic wand to wash the
information of winning and losing from the mind of a participant. Therefore, Tversky and Shafir (1992) used time to
wash the memory. However, in mathematics, one can wash
the information regarding pass and fail contained in Equation (30) by deleting X1 and X2 labels. Thus, corresponding
to the state of mind of another batch of participants considered by Tversky and Shafir (1992), we would have a state
0 that can be obtained by ignoring X1 and X2 in
given by Equation (30), i.e.,
0 = c10 A + c20 A + c30 B + c40 B
= 4c10 + c20 5A + 4c30 + c40 5B0
(39)
Equation (39), we shall see that one gets p4A5 that equals
to a sum of p4AX1 5, p4AX2 5, and an interference term. The
existence of such an interference term is not possible in the
classical framework. It is a special feature of the quantum
framework.
The difference in the expectation values of operator ÔA
in the states given by Equations (30) and (39) can be compared by using an analogy of a double slit experiment of
physics that is performed to study interference of electrons
with and without a watch over electrons near the slits. We
know that (see Feynman et al. 1966a) the interference pattern is not observed when the electrons are watched to
know the slit through which they pass. However, when we
do not have such a watch, then we get the interference
pattern.
We may also look at Equations (30) and (39) from
the reverse perspective. In the double-slit experiment (see
Feynman et al. 1966a), if we want to watch the electrons,
then we need to put the detectors near slits. In the same
way, here, if we want to insert the knowledge of outcome
of the first gamble in Equation (39), then we need to put
X1 and X2 in Equation (39) such that we get the values of
p4AX1 5, p4AX2 5, p4BX1 5, and p4BX2 5 the same as given
by Equation (30) (see Equations (33), (35), and (36)). This
would be possible when the values of coefficients ci and
ci0 4i = 1–45 are such that their magnitudes are equal (see
Equation (40)).
We can now compute p4A5 by using Equations (6a) and
(39), and the operator ÔA :
We would see that ci0 , (i = 1–4) in this equation, are the
same as ci occurring in Equation (30) except that they may
differ in the phase factor, i.e.,
p4A5 = 0 ÔA 0 0
c10 = c1 1
c20 = c2 1
c30 = c3 1
and
Using the above equation together with Equations (39),
(10), and (13), and the normalization condition A A = 1,
we obtain
c40 = c4 0
(40)
Thus, we can express ci0 in terms of their absolute values
and the phase angles, say i , as follows:
c10 = c10 exp4ii 5 = ci exp4ii 50
(It may be noted that exp4i5 = cos45 + i sin45, and i2 =
−1 (see Feynman et al. 1966b).)
Regarding the phase angles i , the values depend on the
states of mind of the participants. For our purpose, here
it may be sufficient to make sure that the values must be
such that 0 described by Equation (39) is normalized
so that the sum of p4A5 and p4B5 given by 0 satisfies
Equation (5).
It can easily be seen that if we compute the expectation
value of operator ÔA to get the probability of accepting
the second gamble with the information regarding winning
and losing using Equation (30), we would have the absence
of interference between the probability amplitude terms c1
and c2 , i.e., we would simply get this probability as a sum
of p4AX1 5 and p4AX2 5. However, with the state given by
p4A5 = c10 + c20 2 = c10 2 + c20 2 + c10 ∗ c20 + c20 ∗ c10 0
(41)
In view of Equations (33), (35), and (40), the above equation leads to
p4A5 = p4AX1 5 + p4AX2 5 + qint 4A51
(42)
where
qint 4A5 = c10 ∗ c20 + c20 ∗ c10 0
(43)
Because c10 and c20 can be complex numbers, in view of
Equations (33), (35), and (40), we can express c10 and c20
in terms of their absolute values, and the respective phase
angles 1 and 2 as follows:
c10 = c10 exp4i1 5 = 6p4AX1 571/2 exp4i1 51
and
c20 = c20 exp4i2 5 = 6p4AX2 571/2 exp4i2 50
(44)
(45)
With these expressions, Equation (43) yields
qint 4A5 = 26p4AX1 5p4AX2 571/2 cos42 − 1 50
(46)
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
10
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
Because the minimum and maximum possible values of
the cosine are −1 and +1, respectively; therefore, using
Equation (46) one can find that the interference term qint 4A5
satisfies the following relation:
−26p4AX1 5p4AX2 571/2
¶ qint 4A5 ¶ 26p4AX1 5p4AX2 571/2 0
(47)
Similarly, using Equations (6a) and (39), and the operator
[Î − ÔA ] for the probability of not accepting the second
gamble, (here Î is a unit operator), one can get
p4B5 = p4BX1 5 + p4BX2 5 + qint 4B51
(48)
where1
qint 4B5 = c30
3.1. Explanation of the Two-Stage
Gambling Experiment
For the coin-tossing experiment performed by Tversky and
Shafir (1992), one can take p4X1 5 = 005 and p4X2 5 = 005.
Further, using Equations (1), and (2) and the data given in
Equations (7) and (8), we can obtain p4AX1 5 = 00345 and
p4AX2 5 = 00295.
Classically, one expects the value of p4A5 as sum
of p4AX1 5 and p4AX2 5 4= 00645. Against this expectation, we here get p4A5 = 0036 (see Equation (9)). Equation (42), however, shows that this anomalous behavior can
be explained by the value of qint 4A5 equal to −0028. This
value of qint 4A5 = −0028 is consistent with Equation (47),
which gives
−00638 ¶ qint 4A5 ¶ 006380
∗ c40
+ c40
∗ c30 0
(49)
By writing equations similar to (44) and (45) for c30 and c40 ,
we can get
qint 4B5 = 26p4BX1 5p4BX2 571/2 cos44 − 3 50
(50)
Further, as mentioned earlier, we need phase angles such
that the sum of p4A5 given by Equation (42) and p4B5
given by Equation (48) satisfies Equation (5). Combining
Equations (42) and (48), we obtain
p4A5 + p4B5 = p4AX1 5 + p4AX2 5 + p4BX1 5
+ p4BX2 5 + qint 4A5 + qint 4B50
(51)
Equation (51) in association with Equations (37) and (5)
gives
qint 4A5 + qint 4B5 = 00
(52)
Thus, the above equation, together with Equations (50) and
(46), provides the relationship between cos42 − 1 5 and
cos44 − 3 5, which must hold well to ensure the validity
of Equation (5).
It may be noted that the main results of this treatment,
Equations (42), (46), (48), and (50), have also been derived
by Yukalov and Sornette (2009a) using the postulates and
states very similar to those described here. The treatment
presented here mainly differs from their treatment in the
consideration of a different kind of operators.
3. Application to Decision-Making
Problems
In this section, we discuss the applicability of the equations presented in the previous section to the experiments
of Tversky and Shafir (1992). We also compare various
models and describe the possibility of application of the
quantum models to other decision-related problems.
(53)
This consistency suggests that this treatment based on the
interference occurring in the quantum decision model cannot predict in advance the results of the experiment but can
explain the results. It may be noted that these experimental
results violate the classical axiom known as Savage’s surething principle (1954). Further, if we consider cos42 − 1 5
of Equation (46) as an adjustable parameter, then we
can say that the experimental data can be explained by
assigning
cos42 − 1 5 = −004390
(54)
This value of cos42 − 1 5 with Equation (46) leads to
qint 4A5 = −0028, which can explain the experimental results
for accepting the gamble. Similarly, for the probability of
rejecting to play the second gamble, we can get following
results:
p4BX1 5 = 001551
qint 4B5 = 00281
p4BX2 5 = 002051
and
p4B5 = 00641 (55)
cos44 − 3 5 = 007850
(56)
Yukalov and Sornette (2009a) argue that under uncertainty
(the lack of knowledge of the outcome of the first game)
the decision in favor of an “action” (accepting to play the
second game) is more difficult than that in favor of an
“inaction” (not to play). Therefore, with this assumption,
out of two terms, qint 4A5 and qint 4B5, that add to 0 (see
Equation (52)), we can say so much in advance that qint 4A5
would be negative and qint 4B5 would be positive. Can we
think of any method of predicting the value of qint 4A5 or
phase angles 2 and 1 in advance? The visualization of
any experimental procedure to determine phase angles in
advance without any knowledge of p4A5 or qint 4A5 seems to
be beyond the scope of our present understanding. Probably
there may be some link between the phase angles and the
distribution of time taken by different subjects in making a
particular decision. The problem, however, is very complex
and may be a matter for future research. At present, we can
only say that using quantum theory we are able to explain
the results of the two-stage gambling experiment, which
could not be explained by any classical formulation such
as the sure-thing principle of Savage (1954) or classical
Markov model studied by Pothos and Busemeyer (2009).
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
11
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
3.2. Explanation of the Buy-or-Not-to-Buy
Experiment
In this experiment of Tversky and Shafir (1992), the subjects (undergraduate students at Stanford University) were
asked to imagine that they had just taken a tough examination, and at the end of the fall quarter an attractive
Christmas vacation package to Hawaii at a very low price
was being offered to them. One group of 67 subjects (say
group 1) was asked to imagine that they passed the examination, another group of 67 (say group 2) was asked to
imagine that they failed the examination, and the third
group of 66 (say group 3) was asked to imagine that the
outcome of their examination was not known to them.
In this experiment, 54% of subjects from group 1, 57%
of subjects from group 2, and 32% of subjects from group 3
were ready to buy the vacation package. The analysis of
these data has been presented and discussed in Appendix-E
in the e-companion. From the analysis presented there,
we note that these experimental results can be explained
by relations similar to the interference equations derived
and discussed in §2.5. Thus, again we see that by using a
quantum model we are able to explain the results of buy-ornot-to-buy experiment of Tversky and Shafir (1992), which
could not be explained by any classical formulation such
as the sure-thing principle of Savage (1954).
3.3. Classical vs. Quantum Model
In classical formulation, the interference term qint 4A5 given
in Equation (42) remains absent. According to the classical statistics, a simple addition of probabilities p4AX1 5
and p4AX2 5 equals p4A5. To explain the results of twostage gambling experiment and other experiments, Pothos
and Busemeyer (2009) have employed quantum as well
as Markov (classical) models. While comparing different
models in §2 of their work, Pothos and Busemeyer (2009,
p. 2174) write: “Although cognitive dissonance tendencies
can be implemented in both the Markov and quantum models, we shall see that it does not help the Markov model,
and only the quantum model explains the sure thing principle violations.”
The following essential differences between the classical
and quantum formulations are worth noting:
(a) In a quantum model, the probabilities are expressed
as the squares of the probability amplitudes c1 1 c2 1 0 0 0 (see
Equations (33), (35), and (36)). In classical formulation, we
do not have such terms as probability amplitudes.
(b) In a quantum model, for getting p4A5 instead
of adding the respective probabilities, the respective
probability amplitudes get added, and then p4A5 is obtained
by squaring the probability amplitudes. Thus, the probability amplitude for p4A5 equals (c10 + c20 ), and p4A5 equals
4c10 + c20 52 (see Equation (41)). The interference term
qint 4A5 automatically appears when we compute the value
of 4c10 + c20 52 . However, in classical formulation, instead
of addition of probability amplitudes the probabilities are
added. Thus, classically, p4A5 equals to the sum of p4AX1 5
and p4AX2 5.
(c) The probability amplitudes, in general, may be complex numbers (see Equations (44)–(45)). The phase factors affect the magnitude of the interference term, qint 4A5.
In classical framework, we do not have such phase factors
or complex numbers in connection with the probabilities.
It may be added that the value of the interference term
given by a quantum model may be 0 also. In such a case,
the quantum results merge to the classical results. This happens when the value of cosine term of Equations (46) or
(50) equals 0.
Without an explanation of the disjunction effect with the
help of a quantum interference term, one may only say that
the disjunction effect, as observed in the two-stage gambling experiment, may be due to lack of sound thinking
of the subjects under uncertainty. In this regard, Tversky
and Shafir (1992, p. 305) write: “We suggest that, in the
presence of uncertainty, people are often reluctant to think
through the implications of each outcome and, as a result,
may violate STP.”
3.4. Quantum Decision Theory of
Yukalov and Sornette
Various features presented here are the same as given by the
quantum decision theory (QDT) of Yukalov and Sornette
(2009a). The main difference is in the selection of operators
Ô associated with Equation (6a). In §2, we have considered the operators characterized by their explicit operations (such as “win,” “accept”) through their eigenkets and
eigenvalues. In QDT, the operators are expressed in terms
of prospect states. For example, they consider an operator (11 2 AX1 AX1 ) corresponding to the prospect state
(11 AX1 ). By prospect state they mean the state in which
one is interested in reaching from the given state of mind.
It may be noted that in physics both kinds of operators
(the operators associated with observables similar to what
we have described here, and operators of kind ss (a ket
multiplied by a bra on right) similar to what Yukalov and
Sornette (2009a) have employed) are used.
It is interesting to note that the final results given by
Equations (42), (46), (48), (50), (53), (54), (EC-33), and
(EC-34) are in total agreement with those given by Yukalov
and Sornette (2009a). Regarding Equations (33), (35), (36),
and (41), these results would also be in agreement with the
QDT results, provided their parameters have the following
values:
ij = 11
for 4i = 11 21 and j = 11 250
(57)
Here parameters ij correspond to the expansion coefficients occurring in Equations (27) and (28) of Yukalov and
Sornette (2009a) (for a 2 × 2 dimensional case; i = 1 and 2
correspond to our A and B, and j = 1 and 2 correspond to
our X1 and X2 , respectively).
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
12
In absence of the knowledge of the explicit four equations required for the determination of 11 , 12 , 21 , and
22 , it is not possible to know the various possible values
of these parameters of Yukalov and Sornette (2009a). However, it can be verified that the values of these parameters
given by Equation (57) do not disagree with the requirements described by Yukalov and Sornette (2009a).
In view of the fact that Equation (57), which has been
obtained by comparing the present results and those of
QDT, does not disagree with the requirements described by
Yukalov and Sornette (2009a), and because there are not a
sufficient number of equations to determine these parameters ij , the present work also becomes valuable to the
formulation of Yukalov and Sornette (2009a) in the sense
that it provides a way (if not “the way”) to determine 11 ,
12 , 21 , and 22 .
In the present work, for determining the probability of
accepting the second gamble when the result of the first
gamble is not known, for the state of mind of the participants we employ Equation (39), not Equation (30). In addition, we use Equation (6a) and the accept operator ÔA to
compute the probability of accepting the second gamble.
Thus, we do not involve variables X1 and X2 related to win
and lose in such a determination. However, Yukalov and
Sornette (2009a) employ the state of mind given by Equation (30) and an operator that includes variables X1 and X2 .
It is interesting to note that their final results are exactly
the same as obtained here [Equations (42) and (46)]. Such
an agreement creates scope for further advancement in this
area. A search for the cause of arriving at the same result
by two different paths may be helpful in gaining a finer
understanding of the paths.
3.5. Khrennikov’s Coefficient of Interference
In an attempt to explain some experiments related to
the cognitive decision making and information processing,
Khrennikov (2009) describes the necessity of quantum or
quantum-like models. He explains that if classical mechanics holds well, then qint 4A5 of Equation (42) would be
equal to zero, and in case of nonclassical behavior, =
qint 4A5/826p4AX1 5p4AX2 571/2 9 can be called the coefficient
of interference. In view of Equation (46), this definition of
coefficient of interference shows that = cos42 − 1 5. For
the data related to the experiment performed by Tversky and
Shafir (1992), Khrennikov reports = −0044, in agreement
with Equation (54). Khrennikov further adds that when the
experimental data satisfy Equation (46) or (47), i.e., when
¶ 1, then we can say that the results are covered by the
conventional quantum model, but when > 1, then we are
outside the conventional quantum model. Khrennikov also
discusses an example for which > 1 holds well. He calls
such interference that is not covered by the quantum formalism as the hyperbolic (or cosh-type) interference. However,
in his words (Khrennikov 2009, p. 186), “the conventional
quantum formalism can be used as the simplest nonclassical
model for mental and social modeling.”
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
3.6. Quantum Model of Pothos and Busemeyer
The disjunction effect related to the two-state gambling
experiment of Tversky and Shafir (1992) has also been
explained by Pothos and Busemeyer (2009), using an alternative quantum model and a few adjustable parameters.
Their quantum probability model is based on an equation parallel to the time-dependent Schrödinger equation of
quantum mechanics (e.g., see Messiah 1970). They employ
this equation to study the effect of external information on
the evolution of the state of the mind with time.
Besides the explanation of the results related to the psychology experiments, the concluding remarks of Pothos and
Busemeyer (2009, p. 2177) regarding the quantum nature
of human cognition are worth noting. They write, “Finally,
recent results in computer science have shown quantum
computation to be fundamentally faster compared with
classical computation, for certain problems (Nielsen and
Chung 2000). Perhaps the success of human cognition can
be partly explained by its use of quantum principles.”
3.7. Application to Other Decision Problems
The above description reveals that in many situations the
decisions taken by a human mind cannot be understood by
a classical model but can be explained by a quantum model.
The usefulness of the equations related to quantum mechanics in psychology suggests that quantum models may also
be useful to other disciplines where the human psychology
plays an important role. One can argue that a successful
and valuable application of quantum models to the mainstream of business-related decisions is not a matter of “if”
but of “when,” “where,” and “how.” In this connection, the
following remarks of Overman (1996, p. 88) presented a
while back are also worth noting: “The experimentation
and adoption of the metaphors and methods of chaos and
quantum theory hold new promise for the management sciences in the next century. It is not so much that traditional
social scientific methods have become obsolete; it is that
we have a continuing need to expand the scope and power
of our methods just to keep pace with our organizational
realities.”
Group decision making in virtually any setting
(e.g., DeSanctis and Gallupe 1987), collaborative or
extended supply chain management (e.g., Guide and Van
Wassenhove 2009), merger and acquisition of business
firms (e.g., DePamphilis 2010), are some examples of
the decision-related problems of interest. Can quantum
mechanics provide a new and valuable insight in such
areas? The challenging task in tackling such problems is to
find the operators and eigenkets corresponding to the key
variables associated with the problem. It may be a long way
from realizing the potential of a quantum model and arriving at a successful and valuable application of the quantum
mechanical framework to the mainstream of business. However, at this stage, it may be worthwhile to see how some
issues related to a business problem can be expressed in
the notations of the quantum decision model.
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
13
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
With this objective, we consider an example of merger/
acquisition of a firm (say, firm B) by another firm A. First,
in addition to the financial interests, the psychology of managers and board members of firm A and B plays a major
role in arriving at the merger deal. Next, immediately after
the announcement of the merger deal, the role of the public perception influenced by the comments and analysis by
experts regarding the synergy, ego, and other aspects related
with the merger influences the share price of firms A and
B. However, here our interest is just to introduce the concept; therefore, we shall limit our discussion to the state of
mind of the acquiring firm.
This example would serve an additional purpose.
It would illustrate that a quantum decision model has a
wider applicability. One can use it even when interference
effect, similar to that described by Equations (42) and (46),
does not take place.
OA denotes a component of the state of the mind of
firm A that may contain fear (fear of competitors acquiring B, in case this proposed merger of B with A does not
take place), ego (ego of becoming a big firm), greed, and
other factors, such as future synergy perceived by A but not
currently perceived by the public, that do not contribute to
the market price within a short duration after the announcement of the deal. The firm A may realize that the public
would not be able to visualize some synergy factors in the
near future. According to A, such synergy factors would
not contribute to the market value of A immediately after
the announcement of the merger deal. The effect of such
synergy factors are also absorbed in the coefficient a2 .
In Appendix-F in the e-companion, using the concept of
a price operator P̂A and related eigenkets and eigenvalues,
we have shown that the expected market value of the stock
of A as perceived by A in the state of mind ëA is
3.8. Merger and Acquisition Problem: State of
Mind of the Acquiring Firm
P A = ëA P̂A ëA = 41 − a2 2 5pa KA 0
There is a large body of literature in finance and strategy
that has studied mergers and acquisitions (e.g., Malmendier
and Tate 2008, Morellec and Zhdanov 2005, Shleifer and
Vishny 2003, Tichy 2001, Andrade et al. 2001). The purpose of this illustration here is only to show the potential application of quantum mechanics to analysis of this
common phenomenon. Thus, we take a simplified view of
mergers and acquisition issues. Let us denote the state of
mind of the acquiring firm A by ëA . Using the expansion
postulate (see Appendix-B in the e-companion), it can be
expressed as a linear combination of related eigenkets of
the price operator:
This equation is very interesting. If a2 = 0, then ëA =
KA , and in this state of mind the firm A expects to see the
price of their stock after the announcement of the merger to
be pa KA . However, the presence of the nonzero value of a2
shows that firm A is ready to be satisfied if the market value
of their stock is 41 − a2 2 5 times pa KA . In other words,
in view of other possibilities, such as fear of competitors,
demand of ego to be a big firm, greed, and future synergy
perceived by them but not perceived by the public, they
are ready to sacrifice the price of one share (immediately
after announcement of the merger deal) by an amount equal
to a2 2 pa KA in favor of firm B. The value of a2 may
be unknown to them, but at the negotiation table a2 may
evolve to the right size to match the state of mind of firm
A with that of B, in case the merger deal is done. It may be
noted that in some situations, P A given by Equation (60)
may be less than pa . For KA = 1, it is certainly less than
pa when a2 2 is nonzero.
The presence of the a2 term in Equation (58) is not to be
considered as a weakness of A. Its existence facilitates the
merger. Due to this a2 term, gain to B becomes larger than
that to A, and the deal becomes possible. If the negotiating
team members are chosen such that in their mind the value
of a2 is very small, then the chances of concluding a deal
could be low. On the other hand, if it is very large, then
the premium payable to B would be very large.
In addition to the advantage of the synergy factor to B,
firm B would have an additional gain due to the sacrifice made by A due to the presence of the a2 term. If the
total number of shares of firm A is NA , then the sacrifice
a2 2 KA pa per share by A would mean an additional gain
equal to a2 2 KA pa 4NA /NB 5 to one share of B. Because
4NA /NB 5 is usually very large compared to 1, the gain per
share may be very large to B for even a small value of a2 .
It is interesting to note that the market value of stock of
the acquiring firm usually falls on the announcement of the
ëA = a1 KA + a2 OA 0
(58)
Here a1 and a2 are expansion coefficients. The normalization condition 6ëA ëA = 1] gives
a1 2 + a2 2 = 10
(59)
KA denotes a component of the state of the mind of
firm A related to the financial factors and public perception (as viewed by the firm A) responsible for the stock
price of A. Here, the symbol KA is chosen with an additional purpose. KA in KA is such that the market value
of stock A, as perceived by firm A, after the announcement of the merger is KA times the present market value
(pa ) of stock A. The value of KA is usually close to unity.
The firm A is of the view that the merger would be welcomed by the public such that the net value of all shares
of A and B would be S 4A5 times the current market value
of the same, where S 4A5 is a synergy dependent factor. The
synergy factor S 4A5 as perceived by A is absorbed in KA .
KA may be time dependent, but here we are confining our
attention to the value of KA within a short duration after
the announcement of the merger.
(60)
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
14
merger. A study conducted by Andrade et al. (2001) over
3,688 completed mergers during 1973–1998 reveals that an
acquiring firm on average loses 0.7% and the target firm
gains 16% on announcement. The interesting point of this
study is that these data are nearly the same for the three
decades of the study: 1973–1979, 1980–89, and 1990–98.
The simple model presented above illustrates the potential of applying a quantum mechanical framework to study
phenomena encountered in practice where the state of mind
of the players can be taken into account. Of course, measurement of parameters such as a2 remains a topic for further study.
4. Summary and Concluding Remarks
The most successful theory of physics, quantum mechanics, has a wide range of applicability in physics, chemistry,
biology, cosmology, etc. In recent years, its potential application to quantum cryptography and computation is also
being explored. In social sciences, its application to economics and psychology appears very promising. Recently
observed success of quantum models (e.g., Pothos and
Busemeyer 2009, Khrennikov 2009, Yukalov and Sornette
2009a) in explaining some experimental results of psychology, such as the disjunction effect observed by Tversky and
Shaffir (1992), that could not be explained by the conventional (classical) theories adds a quantum dimension to the
human decision-making process. In view of such success,
one may argue for the need to explore use of quantum
mechanics in other branches of knowledge such as business
where human decision making is involved.
With an objective of introducing various important and
basic concepts and mathematical equations associated with
any quantum treatment, here we have described a quantum
model with focus on the explanation of the disjunction
effect experimentally observed by Tversky and Shaffir
(1992). Due to basic differences between the physical
objects and the human decision-making processes, one
expects to see some differences between the quantum
mechanics as used in physical sciences and the quantum models applicable to the human decision-making processes. With a minimum number of changes in the basic
terms, postulates, and equations of quantum mechanics,
here we have described a quantum decision model suitable
for the decision-making processes. Essentially, the model
described here is based on the quantum decision theory
developed by Yukalov and Sornette (2009a). The application of postulates analogous to those of quantum mechanics and the selection of state of mind are similar to that
given by Yukalov and Sornette (2009a). However, here,
instead of prospect operators, we have considered more
general and simpler kinds of operators (such as win operator, accept operator) to derive the same final results as
derived by Yukalov and Sornette (2009a) so that the range
of applicability may widen and it becomes easier to apply
to the business-related problems.
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
The description of basic postulates of quantum mechanics and corresponding postulates of the quantum decision
model, in almost similar words, has been presented in
Table 2. While introducing terms of quantum mechanics
necessary for the quantum decision model, we have followed an approach of minimum necessary details in §2
with additional information in Appendices-B and C in the
e-companion. Further, with an objective of ease in comprehension, we have introduced operators, eigenkets, eigenvalues, state of mind, etc. with practical examples, and
avoided a formal rigor associated with a general case. It
is expected that with the understanding of the application
of these terms and equations as described here, it would
be easier to follow the related formal rigorous terminology of quantum mechanics as described in the textbooks of
physics for more advanced applications.
To illustrate the success and to explain the various terms
and equations of the quantum model, first it has been
applied to two experiments performed by Tversky and
Shafir (1992) related to the disjunction effect. As discussed earlier, the results of these experiments could not be
explained by the conventional (classical) theories, but have
been explained in recent years by various quantum models
(Pothos and Busemeyer 2009, Khrennikov 2009, Yukalov
and Sornette 2009a).
The study of merger/acquisition of two business firms
has been chosen to consider a business-related decision
problem. Various concepts of the model such as price operator (P̂A 5 and its eigen kets [KA 1 OA ] with the corresponding eigen values [pa KA , and zero], the normalization
and orthogonality conditions [Equations (EC-37) and
(EC-38)], expansion coefficients [a1 , a2 , and their relationship given in Equation (59)], etc. related with this problem
have been discussed. In this model, we also note the significance of the term a2 OA , which leads to a decrease in
the market value of the stock of the acquiring firm and an
increase in the market value of the stock of the acquired
firm immediately after the announcement of the merger
deal. More investigations are required to incorporate the
effect of the views of the board members, share holders,
and public perception in the quantum exploration of the
merger problem.
In addition to quantum interference to explain the disjunction effect, and quantum superposition of states to
explain the merger problem, quantum mechanics provides
many special features such as Heisenberg’s uncertainty
principle, quantum tunneling, quantum theory of measurement, etc. (e.g., Razavy 2003, Messiah 1970, Stenholm
and Suominen 2005, Bohm 1959), which can accommodate various kinds of diversities associated with human
decisions, in general, and business-related decisions, in
particular. Further investigations on the quantum models of information exchange and market psychology
(Choustova 2007, Haven 2008), quantum finance (Schaden
2003, Baaquie 2009a, Bagarello 2009), application of
quantum mechanics to human dynamics related with
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
healthcare management (Porter-O’Grady 2007), quantum
administration (Overman 1996), quantum probabilistic
behavior (Bordley 1997), etc., are needed to make a quantum difference in the world in this 21st century.
Electronic Companion
An electronic companion to this paper is available as part of the
online version at http://dx.doi.org/10.1287/opre.1120.1068.
Acknowledgments
The authors are thankful to Girish Agarwal, Department of
Physics, Oklahoma State University, for helpful discussions. They
also recognize the anonymous reviewers for their comments,
which helped improve the paper.
References
Aerts D (2009) Quantum structure in cognition. J. Math. Psych. 53(5):
314–348.
Agrawal PM (1989) Quantum mechanics. Joshi AW, ed. Horizons of
Physics, Vol. I (John Wiley, New Delhi, India), 25–54.
Andrade G, Mitchell M, Stafford E (2001) New evidence and perspectives
on mergers. J. Econom. Perspect. 15(2):103–120.
Baaquie BE (2004) Quantum Finance (Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, UK).
Baaquie BE (2009a) Interest Rates and Coupon Bonds in Quantum
Finance (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK).
Baaquie BE (2009b) Interest rates in quantum finance: The Wilson expansion and Hamiltonian. Phys. Rev. E 80(4):046119-1–046119-23.
Bagarello F (2009) A quantum statistical approach to simplified stock
markets. Physica A 388(20):4397–4406.
Bennett CH, Brassard G (1984) Proc. IEEE Internat. Conf. Comput., Systems, and Signal Processing (IEEE, Piscataway, NJ), 175–179.
Bennett CH, Bessette F, Brassard G, Salvail L, Smolin J (1992) Experimental quantum cryptography. J. Cryptology 5(1):3–28.
Bohm D (1959) Quantum Theory (Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ).
Bohr N (1929) Wirkungsquantum und Naturbeschreibung. Naturwissenschaft 17(26):483–486.
Bohr N (1933) Light and life. Nature 131(3308):421–423, 457–459.
Bohr N (n.d.) http://www.brainyquote.com/quotes/quotes/n/nielsbohr164546
.html.
Bordley RF (1997) Quantum probability and its potential application to
decision analysis. Presentation, INFORMS, Hanover, MD.
Bordley RF (1998) Quantum mechanical and human violations of compound probability principles: Toward a generalized Heisenberg uncertainty principle. Oper. Res. 46(6):923–926.
Bordley RF (2005) Econophysics and individual choice. Physica A
354:479–495.
Bordley RF, Kadane JB (1999) Experiment-dependent priors in psychology and physics. Theory and Decision 47(3):213–227.
Busemeyer JR, Wang Z, Townsend JT (2006) Quantum dynamics of
human decision-making. J. Math. Psych. 50(3):220–241.
Chalmers D (1996) The Conscious Mind (Oxford University Press,
Oxford, UK).
Choustova O (2007) Quantum Bohmian model for financial markets. Physica A 374(1):304–314.
Chung YF, Wu ZY, Chen TS (2008) Unconditionally secure cryptosystems
based on quantum cryptography. Inform. Sci. 178(8):2044–2058.
DePamphilis DM (2010) Merger, Acquisitions, and Other Restructuring
Activities: An Integrated Approach to Process, Tools, Cases, and
Solutions (Academic Press, San Diego).
15
DeSanctis G, Gallupe RB (1987) A foundation for the study of group
decision support systems. Management Sci. 33(5):589–609.
Dirac PAM (1958) The Principles of Quantum Mechanics (Clarendon
Press, Oxford, UK).
Feynman RP, Leighton RB, Sands M (1966a) The Feynman Lectures on
Physics, Vol. III (Addison Wesley, Reading, MA).
Feynman RP, Leighton RB, Sands M (1966b) The Feynman Lectures on
Physics, Vol. I (Addison Wesley, Reading, MA).
Guide VDR Jr., Van Wassenhove LN (2009) The evolution of closed-loop
supply chain research. Oper. Res. 57(1):10–18.
Hand E (2009) Quantum potential. Nature 462(7271):376–377.
Haven E (2008) Private information and the “information function”: A survey of possible uses. Theory and Decision 64(2–3):193–228.
Ishio H, Haven E (2009) Information in asset pricing: A wave function
approach. Ann. Phys. 18(1):33–44.
Khrennikov A (2009) Quantum-like model of cognitive decision making
and information processing. BioSystems 95(3):179–187.
Kondratenko A (2005) Physical Modeling of Economic Systems. Classical
and Quantum Economies (Nauka, Novosibirsk, Russia).
Lo HK, Spiller T, Popescu S (2000) Introduction to Quantum Computation
and Information (World Scientific Publishing, Hackensack, NJ).
Lockwood M (1989) Mind, Brain, and the Quantum (Basil Blackwell,
Oxford, UK).
Malmendier U, Tate G (2008) Who makes acquisitions? CEO overconfidence and the market’s reaction. J. Financial Econom. 89(1):20–43.
Messiah A (1970) Quantum Mechanics, Vol. I (North Holland Publishing
Company, Amsterdam).
Morellec E, Zhdanov A (2005) The dynamics of mergers and acquisitions.
J. Financial Econom. 77(3):649–672.
Nielsen MA, Chuang LL (2000) Quantum Computation and Quantum
Information (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK).
Overman ES (1996) The new science of management: Chaos and quantum
theory and method. J. Public Admin. Res. Theory 6(1):75–89.
Penrose R (1989) The Emperor’s New Mind (Oxford University Press,
Oxford, UK).
Penrose R, Shimony A, Cartwright N, Hawking S (2000) The Large,
the Small, and the Human Mind (Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, UK).
Pessa E, Vitiello G (2003) Quantum noise, entanglement and chaos in
the quantum field theory of mind-brain states. Mind and Matter
1(1):59–79.
Porter-O’Grady T (2007) Quantum Leadership: A Resource for Health
Care Innovation (Jones and Bartlet Publishers, London).
Pothos EM, Busemeyer JR (2009) A quantum probability explanation for violations of ‘rational’ decision theory. Proc. Roy. Soc. B
276(1665):2171–2178.
Razavy M (2003) Quantum Theory of Tunneling (World Scientific Publishing, Hackensack, NJ).
Satinover J (2001) The Quantum Brain (Wiley, New York).
Savage LJ (1954) The Foundations of Statistics (Wiley, New York).
Schaden M (2003) A quantum approach to stock price fluctuations.
arXiv:physics/0205053.
Segal W, Segal IE (1998) The Black-Scholes pricing formula in the quantum context. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 95(7):4072–4075.
Shafir E, Tversky A (1992) Thinking through uncertainty: Nonconsequential reasoning and choice. Cognitive Psych. 24(4):449–474.
Shleifer A, Vishny RW (2003) Stock market driven acquisitions. J. Financial Econom. 70(3):295–311.
Shor P (1997) Polynomial-time algorithms for prime factorization and
discrete logarithms on a quantum computer. SIAM J. Sci. Statist.
Comput. 26(5):1484–1494.
Simon HA, Newell A (1958) Heuristic problem solving: The next advance
in operations research. Oper. Res. 6(1):1–10.
Stenholm S, Suominen K (2005) Quantum Approach to Informatics (John
Wiley & Sons, Hoboken, NJ).
Agrawal and Sharda: Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making
16
Operations Research 61(1), pp. 1–16, © 2013 INFORMS
Tichy G (2001) What do we know about success and failure of mergers?
J. Indust., Competition, Trade 1(4):347–394.
Tversky A, Kahneman D (1974) Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics
and biases. Science 185(4157):1124–1131.
Tversky A, Shafir E (1992) The disjunction effect in choice under uncertainty. Psych. Sci. 3(5):305–309.
von Neumann J (1983) Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics
(Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ).
White RE (1966) Basic Quantum Mechanics (McGraw Hill, New York).
Yukalov VI, Sornette D (2008) Quantum decision theory as quantum theory of measurement. Phys. Lett. A 372(46):6867–6871.
Yukalov VI, Sornette D (2009a) Processing information in quantum decision theory. Entropy 11(4):1073–1120.
Yukalov VI, Sornette D (2009b) Physics of risk and uncertainty in quantum decision making. Eur. Physics J. B 71(4):533–548.
Yukalov VI, Sornette D (2009c) Scheme of thinking quantum systems.
Laser Phys. Lett. 6(11):833–839.
Paras M. Agrawal is an emeritus research faculty in the
Department of Management Science and Information Systems
in the Spears School of Business at Oklahoma State University. He taught quantum mechanics to graduate students as a lecturer/professor of physics in India for more than a decade. His
publications include a book chapter on quantum mechanics, and
research articles on quantum wave packets, quantum scattering,
quantum chemistry, mechanical properties of carbon nanotubes,
molecular dynamics, and Monte Carlo simulations.
Ramesh Sharda is Director of the Institute for Research in
Information Systems (IRIS), ConocoPhillips Chair of Management of Technology, and a Regents Professor of Management
Science and Information Systems in the Spears School of Business at Oklahoma State University. His current research interests
are in exploring novel analytics applications in the entertainment
industry, manufacturing, and healthcare.
CORRECTION
The article “OR Forum—Quantum Mechanics and Human Decision Making” by Paras M. Agrawal and Ramesh
Sharda (first published in Articles in Advance, December 13, 2012, Operations Research, http://dx.doi.org/10.1287/
opre.1120.1068) was corrected as follows:
Page 4, Table 1, Eq. 3 was corrected to read as follows: p4BX1 5 = p4X1 5p4B X1 5,
Page 9, line 9 in the left column was corrected to read as follows: 0 0 0 determine p4AX1 5 and p4AX2 5, 0 0 0
Page 9, second line after Eq. 39 in the left column was corrected to read as follows: 0 0 0 same as ci occurring in
Equation (30)0 0 0
Page 13, Eq. 60 in the right column was corrected to read as follows: P A = ëA P̂A ëA = 41 − a2 2 5pa KA 0