Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
Selfish or selfless? The role of empathy in economics
Alan Kirman and Miriam Teschl
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 2010 365, 303-317
doi: 10.1098/rstb.2009.0192
References
This article cites 40 articles, 5 of which can be accessed free
Rapid response
Respond to this article
http://rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org/letters/submit/royptb;365/1538/303
Subject collections
Articles on similar topics can be found in the following collections
http://rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org/content/365/1538/303.full.html#ref-list-1
neuroscience (268 articles)
Email alerting service
Receive free email alerts when new articles cite this article - sign up in the box at the top
right-hand corner of the article or click here
To subscribe to Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B go to: http://rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org/subscriptions
This journal is © 2010 The Royal Society
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010) 365, 303–317
doi:10.1098/rstb.2009.0192
Review
Selfish or selfless? The role of empathy
in economics
Alan Kirman1 and Miriam Teschl2,3,*
1
GREQAM, Université Paul Cézanne, Ecole des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales,
et Institut Universitaire de France, Aix-Marseille III, France
2
Robinson College, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, UK
3
Department of Economics, University of Vienna, Austria
Empathy is a longstanding issue in economics, especially for welfare economics, but one which has
faded from the scene in recent years. However, with the rise of neuroeconomics, there is now a
renewed interest in this subject. Some economists have even gone so far as to suggest that neuroscientific experiments reveal heterogeneous empathy levels across individuals. If this were the case,
this would be in line with economists’ usual assumption of stable and given preferences and
would greatly facilitate the study of prosocial behaviour with which empathy is often associated.
After reviewing some neuroscientific psychological and neuroeconomic evidence on empathy, we
will, however, criticize the notion of a given empathy distribution in the population by referring
to recent experiments on a public goods game that suggest that, on the contrary, the degree of
empathy that individuals exhibit is very much dependent on context and social interaction.
Keywords: empathy; rationality; other-regarding preferences; identity; public goods game;
social interaction
1. SETTING THE BACKGROUND OF
EMPATHY IN ECONOMICS
Both sympathy and empathy are concepts that have
been used in economics at least since the eighteenth
century (Fontaine 1997, 2001). Sympathy is generally
taken as the concern for the welfare of others, whereas
empathy is conceived of as the capacity to put oneself
in someone else’s shoes and thus to share the sentiments or thoughts of that person. Despite the early
interest of Smith (1759 [1976]) and Hume (1740
[2000]), it would not be true to say that both concepts
have a particularly developed tradition in economics,
especially insofar as empathy is concerned. It is standard to characterize the historical interest in empathy
by referring to Smith’s view that we can place ourselves
in another person’s situation by imagination and thus
understand what it is like to be the other person in
particular circumstances, as explained in his Theory
of moral sentiments. However, as Fontaine (1997)
shows, empathy plays a much more general role in
Smith’s work and also figures in his Wealth of nations,
simply because it is conducive to a successful trade
between economic agents. Indeed, if one wanted to
make an offer, one must do so in a way that appeals
to the self-love of the trading partner. For this to
happen, the traders must put themselves in the shoes
of the other person and see how they would react in
those circumstances. Yet, there is little evidence that
subsequent economists took up this point about an
advantageous change in perspectives (Fontaine 1997).
One might well ask why considerations of empathy
disappeared for so long from the economics literature.
One answer is that as economic theory developed and
became formalized in the twentieth century, almost all
of the emphasis was put on the idea of anonymous
individuals satisfying specific axioms of rationality
and interacting only through the market. In such a
view, there was no place for the idea that individuals
might want, or need, to put themselves in the place
of others. However, with the development of game
theory, such an idea became central. Here, the idea
is that individuals interact directly and consciously
with each other. Indeed, the basis of game theory is
that this interaction is strategic. In that framework,
unlike the standard economic model, there is what is
usually referred to as the ‘common knowledge’
assumption (Aumann 1976; Binmore 1990), which
means that the individuals involved reflect on the
actions of the others with whom they interact and
know that the others do the same. It is clear, of
course, that this is a different idea from the more
standard idea of empathy as an affective understanding
of the emotions of another. Singer & Fehr (2005)
make a distinction between the two ideas and refer
to this conscious taking into account of the other as
‘mentalizing’. But, if, as authors such as Binmore
suggest, we are to build our model of society and its
functioning on the basis of the strategic interaction
between individuals, then we must keep this aspect
of empathy as a central consideration. As Binmore
(1994, p. 289) points out, empathy must not be
* Author for correspondence (
[email protected]).
One contribution of 12 to a Theme Issue ‘Rationality and emotions’.
303
This journal is q 2010 The Royal Society
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
304
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
Review. Empathy in economics
considered as ‘some auxiliary phenomenon to be mentioned only in passing’, but rather as something basic to
humanity which can enable us to understand the nature
of strategic interactions between individuals. Hence,
‘Homo economicus must be empathetic to some
degree’ (Binmore 1994, p. 28).1 This empathy, if it
is to condition the way in which individuals anticipate
each other’s actions and coordinate, must be based on
experiences with other people. It is these experiences
that allow the empathizing person to better understand
the position in which the other person may be. The
notion of empathy in this mentalizing sense provides
an important reason as to why economists have
recently become more interested in this capacity.
Yet, this idea has a long history and it was only as the
problem of the coordination of individual activities
became less central that it fell out of sight. In fact, this
problem goes back at least to Hobbes and was discussed
by Hume (1740 [2000]) who was perhaps the first to
make explicit reference to the role of mutual knowledge in coordination. In his account of convention in
A treatise of human nature, Hume argued that a necessary
condition for coordinated activity was that agents all
know what behaviour to expect from one another.
But he does not argue that by so doing they will reach a
good outcome. Note here, however, an important distinction with the usual idea of affective empathy.
What Binmore holds is that empathy can trigger an
identification with another person, without the person
in question ceasing to be able to clearly separate which preferences belong to which person. This ‘empathetic
identification’ (Binmore 1994, p. 288) is crucial for
human societies because without it people would be
unable to arrive at and sustain equilibria in the games
that are played with others throughout their lives and
which Binmore refers to as the ‘Game of Life’.
Yet, despite the resurgence of interest in empathy as
a tool to gather information about another’s preferences, beliefs and intentions, the only persistent use
of empathy in economics has been as an instrument
of interpersonal comparison of utility with the aim of
constructing social preference orderings. Here, it is
important to be clear about whose preferences are
involved. In an analysis of this social choice literature,
two different concepts of empathy have been proposed
(Fontaine 2001): partial empathetic identification,
which refers to an imagined change of circumstances
with another, and complete empathetic identification,
which is the imagined change of circumstances
together with subjective features. That means
that while in the first case, the individual keeps his
or her individual preferences2, in the second case
the individual actually adopts the other person’s
preferences. The latter approach, however, causes problems for the continuity of personal identity
(in economics often defined as being the preference ordering) of the empathizing person and renders the
construction of a social preference ordering on the basis
of individual preferences difficult. Sen (2006) makes this
point in relating the question to that of identity. As he says,
There are two quite different uses of identity, namely an
‘epistemic’ use, in trying to know what others feel and
what they see by placing oneself in the position of
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
others, and an ‘ethical’ use, in counting them as if they
were the same as oneself. The epistemic use is inescapably
important, since our knowledge of other people’s minds
has to be derivative, in one way or another, on our placing
ourselves in the position of others.
Partial empathetic identification has its own difficulties, however, and has been shown to lead to
Pareto inferior social states with respect to what individuals would really prefer. Moreover, partial
empathetic identification has been criticized precisely
because it omits the subjective features of individuals
in the imagined change of positions. What an empathetic person is interested in should be the feelings of
the other and not their own. To overcome these
problems, propositions have been made to consider
complete empathetic identification without the loss
of personal identity. This has been achieved, for
example, by assuming not simply the adoption of
another’s preferences, but some form of deductive
understanding of the causal variables that determine
these preferences. Thus, not only the desires of the
other are taken on board, but also the factors that produced them are taken into account. This is not without
its own problems since it implies a deeper identification with the other.
Another source of interest in empathy can be associated with recent developments in behavioural and
experimental economics, which have now started to
include empathy among a number of other emotions
attributed to the economic agent that are considered
to foster prosocial behaviour. Bowles & Gintis (2003,
pp. 432 – 433), for example, write:
Prosocial emotions are physiological and psychological
reactions that induce agents to engage in cooperative
behaviours [. . .]. Some prosocial emotions, including
shame, guilt, empathy, and sensitivity to social sanction, induce agents to undertake constructive social
interactions; others, such as the desire to punish
norm violators, reduce free riding when the prosocial
emotions fail to induce sufficiently cooperative behaviour in some fraction of members of the social group.
If we take this literally, empathy is not clearly
defined and is rather taken to be some form of visceral
reaction, which makes it difficult to understand
whether empathy is really referring to the process of
changing perspective and looking at the world from
another person’s point of view, or is simply taken to
be an experience of communal feelings that promotes
concern for the other person’s welfare. In any case,
the inclusion of those emotional aspects of the economic agent has given a new stimulus to the
discussion as to whether ‘homo economicus’ really is
the selfish or self-regarding individual who is usually
depicted in economics, or whether the nature of
homo economicus is fundamentally different, e.g. by
having an in-wired other-regarding component,
which may have evolutionarily advantageous origins.
Neuroeconomists have now started to look at empathy in more detail (Singer & Fehr 2005; Singer et al.
2006). Roughly speaking, neuroeconomics tries to
analyse the nature of the activation of the human
brain while individuals are carrying out economic
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
Review. Empathy in economics
decisions, often in the context of typical economic
experiments such as the ultimatum game (Fehr &
Camerer 2007; Sanfey 2007; Oullier et al. 2008). Neuroeconomics is a recent but growing field; yet the
specific research on empathy is only in its infancy.
Nevertheless, neuroeconomists consider that the
study of empathy will help shed light on two different
issues. One is an epistemological question (similar to
Binmore’s suggestion): understanding the process of
how people put themselves in the shoes of others will
help to clarify what knowledge people can reasonably
have about other people’s beliefs, intentions and
motives. This refers back to the common knowledge
assumption mentioned above. This capacity is certainly important from a self-interested point of view:
if one can better predict what another person is
going to do based on an empathetic understanding,
it will help to make better decisions for oneself. On
the other hand, the study of empathy may also be
important for motivational reasons: if empathy leads
not only to a better understanding of the other person’s beliefs, intentions and motivations, but to a
feeling of shared experience with the other person’s
sensations and emotions, this may well undermine
purely self-interested choices and instead promote
other-regarding behaviour. That is, empathy may be
the basis for ‘social’3 preferences and lead to altruistic
and other-regarding behaviour. If this were the case, it
would again provide a good reason for reconsidering
the conception of the economic agent as a purely
self-interested or self-regarding individual.
Thus, broadly speaking, we can say that empathy
concerns three key areas: (i) game theory and the
common knowledge assumption, (ii) welfare economics and interpersonal utility comparisons, and
(iii) behavioural economics/neuroeconomics, testing
on the one hand how people can come to know
about the preferences of others and on the other investigating the idea that other-regarding preferences may
or may not lead to non-selfish behaviour.
The ‘third’ economic area of empathy, behavioural
and neuroeconomics, is of course a particularly interesting field of research since it combines economic
theory with results from neuroscientific research and,
in that sense, promises to make substantial contributions to the other two areas in which empathy
enters into economics, i.e. game theory and welfare
economics. In addition, some neuroeconomists are
eager to show the existence of other-regarding preferences as explained above. Before proceeding it is
worth making a cautionary remark. Some economists
(see Gul & Pesendorfer 2008) have argued that this
field has little or nothing to tell us about the nature
of economic decision-making. Furthermore, the existence, relevance and importance of other-regarding
preferences are currently quite a contentious domain
in economics (Binmore & Shaked in press a,b). If we
assume such preferences do exist, then the next important issue for an economist to clarify is the stability and
distribution of other-regarding preferences. The question is, are there any particular ‘other-regarding
preference types’ in the population? Some neuroscientific experiments have been claimed to show that there
exists a heterogeneous expression of empathy across
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
305
experimental subjects (Singer et al. 2006). The idea
is that each person is endowed with a certain degree
of empathy or other-regarding preference. This could
therefore be translated into a particular distribution
of other-regarding behaviour based on these intrinsic
other-regarding preferences, assuming that it is this
type of empathy that leads to such behaviour. This is
good news for standard economists as they generally
assume preferences to be given and stable, and it is
on the basis of these that they are then able to construct models that lead to specific behavioural
predictions over time. Behavioural and neuroeconomists who are trying to introduce new insights into
an existing formalized background of economic
theory have therefore started to develop models that
incorporate a given distribution of other-regarding
preferences (see Fehr & Schmidt 1999). While this is
clearly consistent with standard procedures in economics, we will show, using data from a specific
economic experiment (Hichri & Kirman 2007), that
people reveal anything but stable other-regarding preferences. The claim of some neuroeconomists to be
able to identify different personal capacities for mind
reading and empathy should therefore be accepted
with caution, precisely because there is so little experimental evidence to date. The conclusion that we can
draw from our discussion is that individuals are
indeed concerned about aspects of outcomes other
than their personal advantage, but they do not have
consistent attitudes in this respect over time. It is not
yet clear what the reasons for such inconsistency are.
This raises a number of important questions that need
to be clarified at this point, namely whether and how
empathetic experiences are translated into otherregarding preferences that are then acted upon and
whether empathy can be considered to be a particular
trait or simply as a transitory product of particular
circumstances and, in particular, of social interactions.
Hence, the broad question that we will try to
address in the rest of this article is to what extent cognitive and neurological empathy research will help us
to clarify certain conceptual issues in economics such
as processes of interpersonal utility comparison or
the common knowledge assumption. The more
specific question, however, that we will look at is just
how far empathy research undermines the standard
conception of the economic agent as a self-interested
individual if it can be shown that empathy does lead
to other-regarding behaviour. For this we shall explore
in more detail the still very young neuroeconomic
literature on empathy and mind reading, and will
analyse how it feeds back into standard economics.
To answer the sort of questions that we have posed
so far, we have to understand the social psychological
and neuroscientific findings and investigations on
empathy. We will not try to give a review of this
literature—there are some very comprehensive review
papers on this available already (e.g. Decety &
Lamm 2006; Singer 2006; de Waal 2008; Singer &
Lamm 2009). What we shall do is to read some of
this literature through the lenses of an economist keeping in mind, all the time, the conceptual issues raised
in the three ‘economic’ areas of empathy mentioned
above. In order to do so, we will try to give a short
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
306
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
Review. Empathy in economics
presentation as to what cognitive and neuroscientific
research has to say on (i) how we can access and
understand the minds of others, (ii) whether empathetic experience maintains the distinction between
self and other, and (iii) whether these experiences
lead to selfish or selfless acts.
In the following section we will look more specifically
into the empathy literature from neuroeconomics. In
§3, we present a critique of the specific neuroeconomic literature on empathy and mind reading, which
concerns the relation of empathy to other-regarding
preferences. We do so by briefly discussing the issues
raised in a debate between two pairs of economists
who have very conflicting views about the value of
experimental and behavioural economics. On the one
hand, there are two, Binmore & Shaked (in press
a,b), who are very reluctant to replace the standard
conception of the economic agent as a self-regarding
individual, and who claim that this conception is sufficient to predict much of observed behaviour, even that
in apparent contradiction with standard rationality
issues. On the other hand, there are two behavioural
and neuroeconomists, Fehr & Schmidt (1999, 2009),
who have presented a model of an economic agent
with particular other-regarding preferences, namely
those exhibiting ‘inequity aversion’. In this model,
the agent is supposed to care about the difference
between others’ monetary outcomes and his own to
the extent that any difference between the agent and
someone else affects the agent negatively. One of the
key issues of their debate is Fehr and Schmidt’s
proposed distribution of intrinsic other-regarding preferences that Binmore and Shaked basically criticize as
not being derived according to well-defined scientific
standards. Should such a distribution exist, then
according to Binmore and Shaked, it should be properly specified in order to make valid predictions. We
take this point up to show the importance that some
economists attribute to the stability of a given distribution of other-regarding preference types. Once
again this allows one to fall back on the standard
idea of fixed and immutable preferences. It is in
response to this that we present the results of Hichri
and Kirman’s experiment which basically shows that
while there is some stability in terms of the degree of
other-regarding behaviour at an average level, no
such stability is observed at the individual level. In
our last section, we present some ideas as to what
may trigger this observed inconsistency and conclude
by emphasizing the importance of continuing to look
more closely into the decision processes that may
involve mind-reading and empathetic components.
The time is surely ripe for economists to study
empathy, in all its different forms, from the understanding of another person’s perspective to the
sharing of emotional feelings with others.
2. AN INTERPRETATION FROM AN ECONOMICS
POINT OF VIEW OF NEUROSCIENTIFIC
AND SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGICAL FINDINGS
ON EMPATHY
In this section, we give an overview of some psychological and neuroscientific findings that are of direct
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
relevance to the three empathy areas in economics
outlined above.
Social neuroscience generally makes the distinction
that we have mentioned between two types of
empathic processes: a cognitive version of empathy
and an affective version of empathy (Singer 2006).
The former is often called the ‘theory of mind’ or
mentalizing and refers to the capacity to represent
other people’s intentions and beliefs, which is the
idea that game theorists often have in mind. The affective aspect of empathy (what is then referred to as
‘empathy’ proper) refers to the capacity to share the
feelings of others. This distinction can hardly be
clear-cut because representing another person’s beliefs
and intentions may also lead to the affective sharing of
a particular emotion or sensation, and experiencing
the same feelings may lead to a better understanding
of that person’s perspective.
(a) How can we access and understand
the minds of others?
One of the reasons for the interest in the mentalizing
type of empathy has been the discovery of so-called
mirror neurons (di Pellegrino et al. 1992; Gallese
et al. 1996). Up to now mirror neurons have been
described in the premotor cortex and the inferior parietal lobe of monkeys (Rizzolatti 2005). The evidence
for some similar system, often referred to as the
mirror system, in the human brain is only indirect as
there is no single-neuron study for healthy brains,4
although functional imaging studies have revealed
similar neural activation during action observation
(Rizzolatti & Craighero 2004). To be more precise,
although some consider that it is not appropriate to
say that mirror neurons have a particular functional
role (Rizzolatti 2005), there is an argument for the
whole brain having a mirror modus operandi (see
Wicker et al. 2003) and this may play a role in action
understanding, intention understanding, imitation
and also the emotional aspect of empathy.
This means that with the help of mirror neurons,
motor acts executed by other people and, in particular,
other people’s facial expressions, can be understood
and corresponding emotional experiences felt (e.g. of
disgust; Wicker et al. 2003). For example, experiments
have been conducted in which monkeys were tested on
grasping behaviour in two conditions (Fogassi et al.
2005): one involved the monkey grasping for a piece
of food located in front of it and bringing it to its
mouth (grasping-to-eat condition); in the second condition, the monkey grasped for an object in front of it
and placed it in a container (grasping-to-place). It was
observed that the same neurons were fired in the
observer’s brain during the grasping act, but not
during the subsequent motor act, i.e. bringing the
food to the mouth and eating act or the placing act.
Indeed, what this experiment showed is that the
respective discharge intensity of the neurons depended
on the goal of the action. It is often found in this kind
of study that the motor act of one action is influenced
by the subsequent action, which also means that one
knows before one does something what is going to
happen. Even more, there is a potential in the brain
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
Review. Empathy in economics
that can be measured prior to an action which can be
translated as ‘the brain knows before the mind does’.
The interesting aspect of this experiment is that even
if these monkeys observed another monkey performing
the same kind of actions, again, neurons were activated
differently depending on the grasping-to-eat and the
grasping-to-place condition. This indicates that they
not only understand the goal of the observed motor
act, but also discriminate between identical motor
acts according to the action in which these acts are
embedded. It is as if they could ‘read’ the intention
of the monkey they were observing. This capacity to
understand intentionality has sometimes been claimed
to be unique to humans.
The explanation for this sort of anticipation in
humans is that the brain stores internal representations
of dynamic information, which can then be used in
order to anticipate future movements and thus to
infer intentions from other people by observing their
movements (Blakemore & Decety 2001; Iacoboni
2009). That is, a person may have stored the consequences of his or her own actions based on
particular intentions, and that may be used to understand the intentions of other people. It is therefore
argued that the brain is a ‘powerful simulating
machine, designed to detect biological motion in
order to extract intentions from the motion and to predict the future actions of other animate beings’
(Blakemore & Decety 2001, p. 566). It is interesting
to note, in this context, that a part of the mirror
system is the superior temporal sulcus which is not
premotor at all but fires when biological motion is
detected. This creates ‘shared representations’
(p. 566) of motions that may be used for subsequent
understanding of somebody else’s actions and
intentions.
The step to mimicry is not difficult, at least for
humans who are considered to be the ‘best’ imitators,
for as the philosopher Hoffer (1955, p. 21) said,
When people are free to do as they please they usually
imitate each other.
Indeed, it is widely recognized that humans seem to
have a strong tendency to imitate and align their
behaviour with other people during social interactions
(see Lieberman 2007). Indeed, imitation facilitates
social interaction and influences people’s liking of
others (for an overview, see Iacoboni 2009). It has
also been shown that imitative behaviour fosters empathy and that empathic persons are more inclined to
unconscious mimicry (Chartrand & Bargh 1999; see
also de Waal (2008) for an overview). There are even
functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) studies
that neurally connect motor mimicry, such as contagious yawning, with empathic modelling (Platek et al.
2005). This all suggests that personal experience and
social closeness, together with motor actions that lead
to motor cognition (see Jeannerod 2006; Oullier &
Basso 2010), are important factors that foster the
understanding of other people’s actions and intentions. Through imitation and mimicry people learn
to feel what other people feel. However, there are
still some critics of this research who call for caution.
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
307
‘The observation of similar neural activations during
the firsthand vs. the vicarious experience of various
sensations and emotions (e.g. disgust, taste, pain)
raises the question whether these activations can
indeed be interpreted as shared representations’
(Singer & Lamm 2009, p. 87). This is because none
of the current neuroimaging methods can measure
the activity of single neurons or neural networks
directly. Usually, one compares two fMRI activation
maps with overlapping clusters—but the activation
could potentially still result from differing neural
activity. Extensive research on these issues is currently
being undertaken.5
(b) The self – other distinction
The neuroscientific literature insists on a clear separation between self and other, and this is, of course,
crucial for an understanding of empathy. However, it
is not entirely clear that such a distinction can always
be made. For such a distinction to be made one
might argue that one needs a clear definition of what
constitutes self. This has been a subject of debate in
philosophy at least since the classical Greeks. Sorabji
(2006) gives a detailed account of the role of self in
Western classical and modern philosophy as well as
in the Hindu, Buddhist and Islamic traditions.
Indeed, the denial of self stemming from antiquity
was embraced by Hume and Nietzsche, and later by
many analytical philosophers such as Wittgenstein,
Anscombe, Kenny and Dennett. But, to avoid what
could become an endless detour here, it may be just
as well to adopt Sorabji’s (2006, p. 20) more pragmatic
approach when he says,
One reason why the notion of self comes in is that
humans and animals could not cope with the world
at all unless they saw things in terms of ‘I’.
Again, the subject of this article, empathy, has no
meaning if we cannot make a meaningful distinction
between self and other. In particular, the assumption
that such a distinction can be made lies at the heart
of the literature on neuroscientific experiments on
empathy.
Consider Singer et al.’s (2004) experiment. They
recruited couples and both partners were brought
into the same scanner environment. Brain activity
was then measured in the female partner while painful
stimulation was applied either to her own or to her
partner’s right hand. The results suggested that some
parts, but not all, of the pain-related brain activation
were activated when the female partner observed
pain being inflicted on her partner, in contrast to the
neural activity when she experienced pain herself. In
particular, knowing that the partner experienced pain
activated the same affective pain circuits, but not
the primary somatosensory cortex. In addition, the
higher the activation of the affective pain circuits, the
higher the individuals scored in social psychological
empathy questionnaires that were distributed to
assess the individual level of empathy. The result was
that people experienced different levels of empathy
and this led the authors to the conclusion that not
everybody is endowed with the same level of
empathetic experience. But most importantly, the
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
308
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
Review. Empathy in economics
level of self-reported empathy was strongly correlated
with increased brain activity.
Now, it has been argued that ‘close relationships’
(such as couples) not only lead to behavioural similarities, but also have cognitive consequences (Aron
et al. 1991). In a close relationship, it has been
observed that a person acts as if some or all aspects
of his or her partner are partially the person’s own.
This concerns, for example, the distribution of
resources, where it has been found in experiments
with couples that little difference is usually made
between personal and partner’s resources and both
are considered beneficial to the person. The vicarious sharing of particular characteristics of the other
person has also been observed. Hence, self and other
apparently overlap, they become one, and this
‘oneness’ can be measured in several different ways.
One measure is, for example, the Inclusion of Other
in Self (IOS) scale, which asks subjects to select
from among seven different diagrams of overlapping
circles, representing total overlap to no overlap, to
describe their relationship with a particular person. It
is clear that if there is such an experience of oneness,
then empathetic experiences may trigger responses,
many of which are neuromotor in nature, that are
not strictly speaking directed towards the other, but
towards oneself, which makes them fundamentally
self-interested.6
Cialdini et al. (1997) conducted a number of experiments to show that any helping behaviour which
follows empathetic experiences can be attributed to
the experience of perceived oneness. Subjects were
asked to imagine the situation that a stranger, an
acquaintance, a good friend or a family member
(the four experimental conditions indicating different
degrees of closeness) was evicted from their
apartment. They were then asked to indicate how
much help they would be willing to provide (from
nothing, to giving an apartment guide, driving the
person through town to visit apartments, inviting the
person to stay for few nights in one’s own apartment,
etc.). They had also to indicate the level of empathetic
concern and oneness (measured with the IOS scale
among others) the respective situation caused. By
empathetic concern, the study meant the emotional
reaction characterized by feelings such as compassion,
tenderness, soft-heartedness and sympathy, brought
about by the act of perspective taking, that is the subject taking the point of view of the evicted person.
This concept followed Batson (1991) and colleagues,
who proposed the alternative theory to the oneness
hypothesis (the ‘empathy-altruism’ hypothesis),
which presupposes a clear distinction between self
and other, and stipulates that (altruistic) helping behaviour is caused by the prior experience of
empathic concern for the other. Cialdini et al.’s
(1997) results are that helping increases with both
empathetic concern and experience of oneness, but
empathetic concern was no longer predictive of helping behaviour once the influence of oneness had been
extracted. Hence for Cialdini et al., empathic concern
is only a signal of unity with another and any helping
is thus not an act of promoting anybody else’s welfare,
but one’s own.
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
Obviously, Batson et al. (1997) contested this and
ran their own experiments in which they induced in
people a low-empathic state and a high-empathic
state with respect to the story of Katie, a young student
in her final year who had recently lost her parents in an
accident and who now had to look after her two
younger siblings. In the low-empathic state, subjects
were told to be as objective as possible in the assessment of Katie’s situation and not to get caught trying
to imagine what the person had been through. In the
high-empathic state on the other hand, subjects were
encouraged to try to imagine how Katie may have
felt. As part of the experiment, subjects were also
given the possibility of helping Katie cope with her difficult situation (helping here meant participating in
sending letters to raise money for Katie and her siblings). Subjects also had to fill in a number of
questionnaires, among them the IOS scale to measure
any self – other merging. It turned out that the subjects
in the high-empathic condition did help more than
those in the low-empathic condition. Hence, perspective-taking manipulation led to increased helping.
Moreover, Batson et al.’s hypothesis was that even if
the effect of self – other merging was taken into
account, a direct effect of empathy on helping would
remain. And indeed, while there was a slightly higher
IOS score in the high-empathy condition, the self –
other merging could not account for the empathyhelping relationship. What Batson et al. seemed to
show with this experiment is that IOS may be a valuable measure of self – other merging in close
relationships, but that in the case in question, subjects
did not necessarily need to ‘merge’ with Katie in order
to feel some degree of care for her. Again, the thrust of
their argument is that perspective manipulation can
lead to higher empathy and this is associated with
increased helping behaviour.
Decety & Lamm (2006) give evidence for the self –
other distinction at a neurological level which came
from experiments that tested the effect of perspective
taking: either the subject had to imagine how it is for
another person to be in everyday-life situations that
elicit, for example, painful experiences, or how it is
for themselves to be in such a person’s shoes. The
results show that the right inferior parietal cortex, at
the junction with the posterior temporal cortex (temporoparietal junction), is specifically involved when
participants imagine how another person would feel,
but not when they imagine these situations for themselves (Decety & Lamm 2006, p. 1155). With respect
to Singer et al.’s (2004) experiment described above,
they comment that, while there are similarities in the
neural networks when one person observes another
person involved in receiving pain, it is also the case
that not exactly the same neural networks are activated
in the observation case and in the real experience case,
which excludes a complete overlap of self and other.
(c) Selfish or selfless?
This distinction between the ‘imagine-self ’ and ‘imagine-other’ perspective is important since it leads to
different behavioural consequences. If a person
observes another person in difficulties and experiences
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
Review. Empathy in economics
personal distress, they may try to escape helping this
person in order to alleviate their own negative
emotional state. If this person experiences empathetic
concern, he or she would engage in actions that try to
soothe the distress of the other person. Given that we
often observe that people do help, this would seem to
confirm the idea that people are aware of the difference
between self and other.
Decety & Lamm (2006) hold, rather ‘romantically’,
that for the experience of empathy, individuals need to
be able to disentangle their own feelings form those of
others. Empathy’s ‘goal’ is not to diminish personal
distress but to soothe the distress of another person
through helping acts (p. 1154). Maintaining a self –
other distinction is also a requisite for self-awareness
and the sense of being an agent. While self-awareness
is important in order to be able to make inferences
about another’s mental states, the sense of having a
personal identity, as an agent (see Jeannerod 2006),
is crucial to the idea that one is able to have a selfless
regard for the other.
Also related to the agent view is the fact that
cognitive and neuroscientific models of empathy
suggest that observing or imaging another person in
a particular emotional state automatically triggers a
representation of that state in the observer (e.g.
Preston & de Waal 2002). This is referred to as a
bottom-up process. Some researchers, however, point
out that ‘automatic’ means that this process does not
require conscious or effortful processing, but this
does not mean that it cannot be inhibited and controlled. This is reflected by the fact that deficient
empathy is possible—people can selectively disengage
from empathy. This empathy regulation is referred to
as top-down processes. One can, for example, selectively focus on specific sensory cues (such as facial
expressions) that convey the emotional state of some
person and that would trigger unpleasant or distressing
emotional reactions in the observer. This evokes the
early work of Darwin (1872) based on that of Clive
Bell, on the expression of emotions and the selective
interpretation of that expression by others. Distraction
is another mechanism for controlling empathetic reactions (see Decety & Lamm 2006 for an overview).
Indeed, empathy regulation may become an important
factor if empathy becomes too costly in everyday life.
There is therefore a limit as to how much empathy a
person can ‘bear’. This, however, suggests that
people are capable of reducing or even augmenting
empathetic experiences, which may trigger particular
behavioural responses—such as other-regarding or
prosocial behaviour. And yet, while the close link
between empathy and prosocial behaviour is repeatedly stressed, the exact mechanism governing the
passage from empathy to prosocial behaviour is not
clear at all. In fact, Singer & Lamm (2009, p. 84)
admit that ‘a clearcut empirical demonstration of a
link between empathy and prosocial behaviour is still
missing’.
Nevertheless, it should be clear from this discussion
that social and cognitive psychology as well as
neuroscience analyse many issues that seem to be
particularly relevant to economic decision-making
and economic concepts in general. Here, we will not
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
309
try to make any direct connections between, for
example, mind-reading capacities and the game
theoretic assumption of common knowledge. This
would be too rudimentary and needs to be the focus
of more intensive investigation. What we shall do,
however, in the next sections is to concentrate on certain neuroeconomic experiments and the conclusions
that have been drawn from them, and analyse the
extent to which they have already, rightly or wrongly,
influenced the conception and representation of the
economic agent.
3. THE NEUROECONOMICS OF MIND
READING AND EMPATHY
The title of this section is taken from that of an article
by Singer & Fehr (2005). This is one of the rather few
articles to date on mind reading and empathy in economics, but it describes enthusiastically what one may
expect from such research. First, we will summarize
some of the limited number of experiments on
empathy.
Singer et al. (2006) conducted an experiment to test
empathy-related responses to observing pain induced
in people with whom subjects previously interacted.
More specifically, subjects played a sequential prisoners’ dilemma game in which they could decide how
much money to give to another player. The other
player could then respond, either fairly or unfairly,
by returning a low or high amount of money.7 The
purpose of this game was to make subjects like the
fair players and dislike the unfair players. In a second
part of the experiment, they used fMRI to investigate
whether the liking or disliking acquired during the preceding game modulated empathic responses for pain.
All subjects of both sexes exhibited empathy-related
activation in pain-related brain areas (fronto-insular
and anterior cingulate cortices) towards fair players.
However, only women had real empathy for unfair
players. Men on, the other hand, had significantly
reduced empathy-related activation, but experienced
increased activation in reward-related areas, correlated
with an expressed desire for revenge. These results (at
least for men) are consistent with other results that
show that people derive satisfaction from norm violations. For example, de Quervain et al. (2004) showed
that if subjects had the possibility to effectively
punish when they heard about a defector’s abuse in
trust, the dorsal striatum was activated. This part of
the brain has been shown to be involved in the processing of rewards that accrue as a result of goal-directed
actions. Additionally, subjects with stronger activations
in the dorsal striatum were willing to incur greater
costs in order to punish. Singer et al. (2006) take
their results as providing the neural basis for theories
of what they refer to as ‘social preferences’ but which
we have called ‘other-regarding’ preferences,8 which
suggest that people value others’ gains positively
if they were perceived as being fair, but negatively if
they are considered to be unfair. People thus value ‘fairness’ in addition to their own personal advantage.
Moreover, fair behaviour of another person increases
empathic experiences of the other person who observes
this behaviour, while selfish behaviour reduces it.
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
310
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
Review. Empathy in economics
Knoch & Fehr (2007) let subjects play an
ultimatum game. In the ultimatum game, a proposer
has to make an offer of an assigned amount of
money to a responder, who has the possibility either
to accept the proposed offer or to reject it, in which
case both get nothing. A Nash equilibrium of such a
game is a choice of strategies by both players such
that given the strategy of the other neither has an
incentive to deviate. If the total amount in play is
E10, for example, one such equilibrium would be for
the proposer to propose E10 for himself and for the
responder to refuse any offer that gave a positive
amount to the proposer. This equilibrium does not
satisfy a more reasonable condition that of ‘sub-game
perfection’. Here, the idea is that the proposer works
backwards from the last step, and at each step sees
what is the best strategy for the other. In the last
step, the responder should accept any positive
amount that is proposed since something is better
than nothing. Since he understands this, the proposer
should propose the minimum positive amount for the
responder and keep the rest. It is worth explaining this
because it captures the essence of the mentalizing
approach, the proposer anticipating what the responder will do when faced with each possible
proposition. Now, the question is, do people actually
play like this?
In stark contrast to the theory, what has been shown
in many different experimental settings of the ultimatum game (see Oosterbeek et al. 2004) is that a
majority of proposers offer between 30 and 50 per cent
of their assigned money and that a vast majority of
responders reject offers that are below 20 per cent of
the assigned money. These results have also been
interpreted as being a sign for a concern of fairness
or equity. In Knoch & Fehr’s (2007) experiment, one
of the hypotheses that they examined was that reduced
self-control has an effect on accepting unfair offers.
Accepting such offers is considered here to be consistent with more immediate satisfaction of self-interest. It
has been observed that patients with lesions, particularly in the right prefrontal cortex, are less resistant
to the satisfaction of self-interest. To test this hypothesis, Knoch and Fehr relied on individuals who were,
in fact, healthy, but they induced a ‘virtual lesion’,
which meant that they applied a low-frequency repetitive transcranial magnetic stimulation over the course
of several minutes, which allowed a transient disruption of cortical functions.
Results showed that subjects who received right prefrontal transcranial magnetic stimulation were less able
to resist the economic temptation to accept unfair
offers, despite the fact that in an evaluation after the
experiment, they considered low offers as being
unfair. Knoch & Fehr (2007, p. 129) add that their
‘[. . .] findings are also congruent with the observation
of empathy deficits in patients with predominantly
right frontal lesions, as an inhibitory component is
required to regulate and tone down the prepotent
self-perspective to allow the perception and evaluation
of others’ perspectives’. Hence, this shows that
reduced self-control has similar implications to those
of empathy impairment. This again might seem to
suggest that empathy leads to more other-regarding
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
behaviour. However, a less ambitious, alternative
explanation is that the dichotomy between emotions
and rationality no longer holds and that the complex
neural activation during these decisions is interfered
with by the lesions.
These results would seem to lend support to Singer &
Fehr (2005) when they advocated the idea that neuroscientific research on mentalizing and empathizing may
help to explain how individuals assess other players’
preferences. Given the evidence from empathy research
so far (and again this was reinforced by Singer et al.’s
(2006) results explained above), they presented the
following ‘testable’ hypothesis—but have not tested it
yet (Singer & Fehr 2005, p. 343): first, people with
stronger capacities to empathize are better predictors
of other’s motives and actions. Second, people who exhibit more affective concern are more likely to display
altruistic behaviour. This clearly means that more
empathetic people should be more aware of what
others want and should also be more other-regarding.
Singer & Fehr (2005) also referred to the fact that
economists usually attribute a common prior
distribution of types in the population (e.g. of otherregarding preference types) in games with incomplete
information, but emphasized that this assumption
lacks empirical foundations. But ‘neuroeconomic
research (in mind reading and empathy) may help us
to understand what is going on in this black box’
(p. 344). And if empathy is related to other-regarding
preferences as suggested above, then we may also learn
something from observed behaviour about the
distribution of other-regarding preferences in a given
population. Given the heterogeneity of empathetic
reactions as shown by Singer et al. (2004), this may
well be taken to reveal the existence of a particular
distribution of other-regarding preferences. And, as
Fehr & Schmidt (in press) put it, it is of prime
importance for the empirical knowledge about otherregarding preferences ‘to have a parsimonious
empirical characterization of the distribution of social
preference types’.
4. STABILITY OF TYPES
This distribution of other-regarding preferences has
become an issue in the economics literature lately.
Fehr, together with Schmidt, has proposed a particular
type of other-regarding preference called inequity
aversion. Deviations from equality may be in two
directions, either the person receives less than somebody else (disadvantageous inequality), or the person
receives more than somebody else (advantageous
inequality).9 In both cases, the person is supposed,
according to this approach, to suffer a loss. The
inequalities are weighted, respectively, by, what
Binmore & Shaked (in press a,b) call in a critique of
Fehr and Schmidt’s paper, an ‘envy parameter’ a
and a ‘discomfort parameter’ b. These parameters
measure the extent to which inequity aversion weighs
on the preferences of each person. These two parameters summarize an individual’s attitude towards
inequality. Fehr & Schmidt (in press) assume that
individuals do not know exactly what other people’s
value of these parameters are, but that the joint
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
Review. Empathy in economics
distribution of ai and bi in the population is common
knowledge for all players. The polemic that has arisen
is about the distribution of these parameters that Fehr
and Schmidt claim to deduce from the experimental
evidence. Indeed, as Binmore & Shaked (in press a,b)
rightly assert, the proposed distribution (Table III of
Fehr and Schmidt’s paper) is far from their aim of a
‘parsimonious empirical characterization of social
preference types’. They propose a simple discrete
distribution of ai and bi, a distribution chosen because
it is consistent with the substantial experimental evidence they have on the ultimatum game. The same
distribution of the envy and discomfort parameters is
used by Fehr and Schmidt in order to explain other
experiments in their paper, among them the public
good game without and with punishment (see again
Fehr & Schmidt (1999) for references). But as Binmore and Shaked show, if Fehr and Schmidt had
used slightly different parameters, their theory of
inequity aversion would no longer be able to predict
observed behaviour in the various games they consider
in their original 1999 paper. The second critique
Binmore and Shaked make is that in later follow-up
papers, Fehr and co-authors (Fehr & Schmidt 2004;
Fehr et al. 2007, 2008) do not keep the same distribution, but use what they call a ‘simplified’
distribution of their 1999 paper because it makes calculation less tedious. Indeed, they anticipate that ‘a
complete characterization of the distribution of different social preference types in the population may
introduce so much complexity at the individual level
that models that attempt to capture this complexity
may become analytically intractable. For this reason,
a simple model such as the theory of inequity aversion
may still be useful, even though there is evidence that it
does not provide a full description of other-regarding
preferences’ (Fehr & Schmidt in press).
The question of whether there is a fixed distribution
of degrees of other-regarding behaviour in the population is important, and the exchange of opinion
between Fehr and Schmidt and Binmore and Shaked
is interesting for at least two reasons. Those who
claim that neuroeconomic research, and in particular
research on mentalizing and empathizing, will be
able to shed light into the ‘black box’ of assumed distributions of types are relatively unconcerned about
making quantitative estimates of the distribution of
the respective preferences appropriately, that is econometrically. Yet, as Binmore & Shaked (in press a,b)
argue, to find an appropriate and given distribution
of types is considered to be crucial for the economic
discipline. This view is also reflected in the fact that
economists usually assume given and stable preferences.
The
common
understanding
among
economists is that ‘for preferences to have explanatory
power they must be sufficiently persistent to explain
behaviours over time and across situations’ (Bowles
1998, p. 79). Hence, the ideal situation would, from
this perspective, be that research on empathy reveals
a given empathy distribution in a population, which
can then be correlated with stable other-regarding preferences that serve as the basis of economic accurate
predictions of behaviour. All of this, of course, rests
on the fundamental assumption in economics that
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
311
behaviour in general and choices in particular can
be assimilated to fixed and immutable preferences.
Choices and preferences are, in this view, synonymous, and this poses problems because the
consistency of choice, and particularly intertemporal
choice, that is imposed by the usual axioms is frequently violated in experiments. It would, of course,
be very convenient if individuals had a certain fixed
level of empathy which was independent of the context
in which they found themselves. Indeed, if this were
the case, one could design experiments that would
permit each individual to reveal their empathetic
predisposition.
However, the idea that any such stable distribution
exists is likely, as we will show, to be ‘wishful thinking’.
In what follows, we will use the evidence from a series
of public goods experiments run by Hichri & Kirman
(2007). The basic idea of public goods experiments is
that each individual is in a group and has an initial
allotment of money. Each person can split this
money into a private share and into the contribution
to a public good. Once individuals have made their
contributions, the total production of the public
good which is consumed by all the individuals and
the payoffs to each individual are determined. In
some experiments, this game is repeated for several
periods.10 The payoff to the participants of their
choices, depends on and varies with the experimental
design, but in most experiments it is taken to be
linear (Andreoni 1995). This linear case gives rise to
a corner solution. This means that, assuming that it
is common knowledge that players are rational payoff
maximizers, such a function gives a Nash equilibrium
in which every player contributes nothing for the one
shot as well as the finite repeated game. On the other
hand, at the social optimum everybody contributes
all of their wealth. Nevertheless, experimental studies
show that, at least in the early stages of such games,
there is a large fraction of people who over-contribute
in a public goods game with respect to the Nash
equilibrium.
Hichri & Kirman (2007) were particularly interested in finding a situation in which, even at the Nash
equilibrium, total contributions can be positive. For
this, they conceived a theoretical model with a concave
payoff from the contributions to the public good instead
of a linear payoff. In other words, the return from a contribution to the public good diminishes as the total
contributions rise. The result of this is that the Nash
equilibrium is any situation in which the total
contributions of the individuals adds up to a certain
positive amount. Thus, even at the non-cooperative
solution one can distinguish between the levels of
payment of different individuals. Indeed, since many
experiments focused on a linear payoff function which
implied that the Nash equilibrium is for all players to
contribute zero, little attention has been paid to individual differences in payments. With the model Hichri and
Kirman propose, the Nash equilibrium implies positive
contributions and one can see whether at the Nash
equilibrium it may be the case that some individuals
systematically contribute more than others. The idea
is that if individuals can be distinguished in this way,
one may be able to deduce that some are more ‘socially
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
312
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
Review. Empathy in economics
total contribution at the aggregate level
250
contribution
200
150
100
50
0
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25
periods
Figure 1. Total contributions in the public goods game. Adapted from Hichri & Kirman (2007). Grey circled line,
contribution; filled diamond, collective optimum and black circled line, Nash equilibrium.
conscious’ than others, they empathize more or, to use
Fehr & Schmidt’s (1999) term, they are more
‘inequality averse’.
The Nash equilibrium and the social optimum corresponding to this payoff structure are not trivial
solutions but are in the interior of the set of the possible choices. With a concave payoff function, the
respective Nash equilibrium can easily be calculated.
Hence, it can be said that in this game there is a
unique Nash equilibrium in the sense that for any
Nash equilibrium the contribution of the group, as a
whole, is the same. However, a contribution to that
equilibrium can be obtained by several combinations
of individual contributions. In that sense, we could
also say that many Nash equilibria are possible.
Since there are many Nash equilibria for the oneshot game, one might ask precisely what constitutes
an equilibrium for the repeated game. The answer is
that a Nash equilibrium for the game repeated
n times will be a sequence of n equilibria for the oneshot game. This means that, in such an equilibrium,
the same player may make very different contributions
at each step. The only requirement is that the total
contribution of the group should remain constant.
This means that the following sort of arrangement
could be an equilibrium. In the first period, one
player contributes a lot and the others very little, and
then in each subsequent period another takes over
the role of leader and makes the large contribution.
How, or why, a group would coordinate on such a solution is a different question. Much simpler, of course,
would be a situation in which the different players converge to constant contributions but which are different
from each other. In this case, we can characterize
people’s empathy by their ultimate generosity in the
Nash equilibrium. That solution would be consistent
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
with the debate between Binmore and Shaked and
Fehr and Schmidt outlined above, but it is not what
Hichri and Kirman have found.
In most public goods experiments, total contributions decline towards zero but do not reach that
level. In Hichri and Kirman’s experiments, total contributions do decline but towards the positive level
associated with the Nash equilibrium as is shown in
figure 1.
The question then remains, is it true that certain
individuals contribute more than others even when
they may have ‘learned to play Nash’?11 If this is so
then those that pay more can be characterized as
having more empathy than those who contribute less.
This would correspond to the idea that each individual
has a certain level of empathy that is essentially stable.
However, the experiments in question do not show
this. Looking at the payments of the different groups
who make up the total, emphasizing that in the experiments the groups have no interaction with the other
groups, one can observe that different groups organize
themselves so that different totals are obtained, as can
be seen in figure 2.
Hence, this does not suggest that certain groups
must contain more empathetic or other-regarding
members. This idea that this might be so is undermined by the fact that the contributions are far from
monotone and that as time progresses groups’ contributions fluctuate considerably. But the most striking
observation comes from the contributions of the
individuals themselves. The contributions of each of
the individuals in several groups do not converge to a
particular level, rather individuals modify their
payments as others do so, as can be seen in figure 3.
Yet, the remarkable aspect is that they seem somehow
to coordinate their contributions on a solution that is
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
Review. Empathy in economics
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
313
groups contribution over time
250
contribution
200
150
100
50
0
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25
periods
Figure 2. The contributions of six different groups in the same treatment. Adapted from Hichri & Kirman (2007). Lines with
dash, group 1; diagonals, group 2; triangles, group 3; solid line, group 4; crosses, group 5; and circles, group 6.
not far from a Nash equilibrium according to standard
rationality.
Here, it can clearly be seen that individuals offer
different amounts at different moments and, with
few exceptions, cannot be classified as low or high contributors reflecting their intrinsic empathy. This does
not mean that empathy does not play a role in determining the generosity of the individuals but, instead
of having a constant level of empathy, as is suggested
by Singer & Fehr (2005), the level of empathy
may be context dependent and influenced by the
interaction with others.
5. CONCLUSION
In this paper, we have argued that empathy is actually
‘pervasive’ in economic theory, and understanding
empathetic and mind-reading processes better is of
crucial importance both from an empirical and a
theoretical point of view in economics. Empathy is,
of course, a subject that has interested many disciplines, such as philosophy and psychology, and it has
recently attracted a great deal of attention in the
neurosciences. The research taken up is neuroeconomics, a rapidly growing area of research that uses
neuroscientific insights to elucidate the theory of economic decision-making. We have discussed this very
recent literature on empathy and mind reading in
some detail and have shown that one of the main conclusions claimed by some economists for these
studies is the existence of other-regarding preferences.
Such preferences are said to be responsible for the
altruistic or prosocial behaviour of the economic
agent. Positing the existence of these preferences has
been considered quite a radical departure from the
description of the economic agent in standard
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
economic theory. There they are taken to be, in the
‘worst’ case, a purely selfish or, in the best case, selfregarding individuals. In the latter case, agents
may care about the betterment of ‘others’ as well as
themselves but their consumption or state is simply
another argument of their own preferences. Otherregarding preferences are sometimes presented not
simply as being concerned with the welfare of specific
others, but may incorporate more general concerns,
such as inequity aversion (Fehr & Schmidt 1999).
However, it should be noted that, in a sense, this
idea is at odds with empathy as generally conceived.
For, in that view, one is not concerned with the situation of another individual but the state of the
population with respect to oneself. Can this really be
assimilated with the original idea of empathy?
Indeed, our argument is that even if there is such a
component governing people’s choices and, as Fehr
and Singer in a later contribution argue, the level of
such inequity aversion is intrinsic to each individual,
there is still a problem. For this would mean that
one would observe a stable distribution of inequity
aversion across players. Each person would behave systematically in the same way.
In some experiments we referred to earlier (Singer
et al. 2004, 2006), individual empathic character
traits have been assessed by empathy questionnaires
after having been scanned, and this revealed a positive
correlation between the self-reported empathy level
and actually measured brain activation. This seems
to suggest that there is indeed a particular disposition
or trait in individuals to experience empathy. However,
if people watch distressed people on the news, they
may not experience any empathy, while they would
do so if they saw people in their local community
suffering in the same way. This therefore suggests
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
314
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
Review. Empathy in economics
group 1
group 2
group 3
group 4
group 5
group 6
contribution
60
40
20
0
contribution
60
40
20
0
contribution
60
40
20
0
5
10
15
period
20
25
5
10
15
20
25
period
Figure 3. Individual contributions in six groups. Adapted from Hichri & Kirman (2007). Open circles, subject 1; filled circles,
subject 2; thick line, subject 3 and thin line, subject 4.
that empathy is not simply an automatic ‘bottom-up
process’, but that individuals may actually engage in
‘empathy regulation’ through ‘top-down processes’.
Indeed, there is quite a lot of evidence that empathy
can be modulated by a number of social-cognitive factors such as emotion regulation, selective attention,
but also by the kind of experiences individuals have
lived through and their closeness to certain people.
This would suggest that empathy is situation-specific
or at least context dependent. The question of whether
empathy can be seen as a disposition or trait, or
whether it is context dependent, is currently a matter
of debate (Decety & Lamm 2006; Singer & Lamm
2009).
In the public goods game we presented in some
detail above, Hichri & Kirman (2007), contrary to
what is done in other analyses of public goods
games, focused on individual donations to a public
good and found that these were not only rather dispersed but also volatile over time. This sort of
behaviour could not be explained simply in terms of
an empathy trait. Alternative explanations are
needed. One possibility is that ‘mind reading’ and
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
empathizing, together with the reaction to other
people’s contributions to the public good, enable
players in one particular group to coordinate on
something close to an equilibrium value of total
contributions. Another explanation could be the following: it has been shown that people seem to have a
particular self-concept of their moral self-worth
(Sachdeva et al. 2009). This implies that people do
not always have to behave in a particular way according
to their self-concept, but rather tend to use this as a
reference point around which they can move. If they
perceive themselves to have acted very morally, they
feel ‘licensed’ to act immorally (e.g. act in a noncooperative way), while if they perceive themselves as
not having been very moral, they need to ‘cleanse’
themselves by behaving morally (e.g. act cooperatively). Given that many individuals in each of these
groups, in many cases, alternate between giving a lot
and giving very little, this might be because they
engage in this kind of moral self-regulation. It remains
to be seen, of course, to what extent moral self-worth
is connected with people’s self-assessed empathetic
character traits. If it is, which might seem plausible
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
Review. Empathy in economics
given that empathy is often associated with prosocial
behaviour, then it could be that people consider
themselves to be high- or low-empathy people
(suggesting a particular disposition), but that they
smooth out selfish and altruistic actions around that
particular level of empathy ‘disposition’. In this case,
individuals would have to be observed over a very
long period in order to ascertain their natural level of
empathy, if it exists. Yet, even this would not put paid
to the idea that what is important is social interaction
and a constant evaluation and revaluation of the social
situation, as represented by the behaviour of others.
All of this suggests that we are still far from understanding the role and nature of empathy, and its
consequences for altruistic or general other-regarding
behaviour. Nevertheless, it also seems to be the case
that recent developments in the neurosciences in general and neuroeconomics in particular may contribute
to understanding the mechanisms involved. However,
existing work in that field has concentrated on rather
specific and simple examples from game theory such
as the ultimatum, public goods or prisoners’ dilemma
game. It is important to see whether the results available extend to more general cases of economic
decision-making and coordination. However, it is
equally important that neuroscientists become fully
aware of the nature and underlying assumptions of
the game they want subjects to play, including the
payoff structure, as these can crucially influence the
results that are obtained. This would mean that by
running, for example, public goods games with different levels of concavity of the payoff function, one may
change the particular empathy levels that individuals
apparently reveal. This of course distorts the results
of the experiments. One way to test this would be to
run the different experiments with the same pool of
subjects, grouped in the same way. However, as is
well known this can also produce distortions. But,
what is important is that the members of the teams
from different disciplines who run these experiments
should acquire a common pool of knowledge. Or to
put it more clearly, while it is certainly desirable that
economists have more cognitive and neuroscientific
knowledge, it is equally important that neuroscientists
know more about economics.
But it would be wrong to conclude by restricting our
attention purely to neuroscience and neuroeconomics.
Empathy and its role put the relations between individuals at the centre of the stage. Taking up the earlier
discussions in economics on this subject and linking
them with recent progress in other disciplines means
changing our basic economic thinking in a fundamental
way. If concern for others and anticipation of each others’
intentions are basic ingredients of individuals in a society,
then the standard view of homo economicus is not only
inadequate but also misleading.
ENDNOTES
1
Binmore’s idea of homo economicus is, of course, far from the traditional isolated maximizing individual since he interacts consciously
with others. This leads him to contemplate the reactions of others
and for this he has to be aware of what their utilities or payoffs are.
2
This is similar to Binmore’s concept of empathetic identification.
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
315
3
We will refer to other-regarding preferences instead of social preferences because social preferences are traditionally attributed to
preferences of a group of individuals or even of a whole society
and are assumed to rank different social states.
4
The sort of direct interference with the brain that is permitted for
experiments with monkeys is not allowed for human beings.
5
More criticism is soon to appear in a number of journals. See, e.g.
the ‘Talking brains’ blog by Greg Hickok, a professor of cognitive
neuroscience, and David Poepel, professor of linguistics and biology,
and their entry on ‘Eight problems for the mirror neuron theory of
action understanding’: http://talkingbrains.blogspot.com/2008/08/
eight-problems-for-mirror-neuron-theory.html.
6
It has been pointed out to us, by Gay Meeks, that if one pursued
this argument to the limit and imagined someone perfectly capable
of identifying with any member of the human race then this
person would become a selfless self, incapable of self-interest!
7
We are not quite sure why Singer et al. refer to this game as prisoners’ dilemma game, even though this type of game usually refers
to the investment game, trust game or centipede game if repeated
several times.
8
Singer, in her articles, usually refers to Rabin (1993), Fehr &
Schmidt (1999) and Camerer (2003) as being representatives of
theories of social preferences.
9
The theory of inequity aversion (Fehr & Schmidt 1999) assumes
that people are maximizing a utility function that takes account of
a person’s payoff, but also of unequal and hence inequitable
outcomes. Although the two terms inequity and inequality are
used interchangeably in the literature, it is important that one
carries a welfare judgement (inequity), whereas the other
(inequality), if it is measured by incomes or payoffs, can be measured
objectively.
10
Economists take it that the situation in repeated games is not the
same as that in ‘one-shot’ games. In a game played repeatedly with
the same players, each player can have a strategy that might
‘punish’ those who contribute little and therefore more cooperation
would be observed than in the one-shot game. However, experiments can only involve a finite number of rounds and the
previous argument only holds for games with infinite horizons.
Endowed with the concept of backward induction, it is easy to see
why. In the last round everyone should play Nash since there is no
possibility of subsequent punishment. But, if this is so, people
should do so in the penultimate round and so forth back to the
start. So, in such a repeated game, people who are good game theorists, or rather act as good game theorists expect them to, should
immediately settle to the equilibrium of the one-shot game. The
question is again, what if they do not do so? Perhaps, since people
play repeatedly they ‘learn how to play Nash’. So, they do not
start with a common knowledge and work everything out from the
beginning, but do move towards equilibrium. Thus, after a while
differences between behaviour will be ironed out and in the end
something close to equilibrium would be attained. Alternatively,
and this is of course Fehr and Schmidt’s (and others’) argument,
they may be motivated by something else such as inequity aversion
or other emotions and might empathize with those who receive
little and, as a result, contribute more than non-cooperative game
theory would suggest.
11
That players learn to play Nash does not mean that they are even
aware of this notion; it is simply based on the idea that agents
reinforce the probability of playing what seem to be successful
actions and diminish the probability of choosing others.
REFERENCES
Andreoni, J. 1995 Cooperation in public goods experiments:
kindness or confusion? Am. Econ. Rev. 85, 891 –904.
Aron, A., Aron, E. N., Tudor, M. & Nelson, G. 1991 Close
relationship as including other in the self. J. Pers. Soc.
Psychol. 60, 241–253. (doi:10.1037/0022-3514.60.2.241)
Aumann, R. 1976 Agreeing to disagree. Ann. Stat. 4,
1236–1239. (doi:10.1214/aos/1176343654)
Batson, C. D. 1991 The altruism question: toward a social
psychological answer. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
316
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
Review. Empathy in economics
Batson, C. D., Sager, K., Garst, E., Kang, M., Rubchinsky,
K. & Dawson, K. 1997 Is empathy-induced helping
due to self-other merging? J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 73,
495 –509. (doi:10.1037/0022-3514.73.3.495)
Binmore, K. 1990 Essays on the foundations of game theory.
Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Binmore, K. 1994 Playing fair. Vol. 1 of game theory and the
social contract. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Binmore, K. & Shaked, A. In press a. Experimental
economics: where next? J. Econ. Behav. Organ.
Binmore, K. & Shaked, A. In press b. Experimental
economics: where next? Rejoinder. J. Econ. Behav. Organ.
Blakemore, S. J. & Decety, J. 2001 From the perception
of action to the understanding of intention. Nat. Rev.
Neurosci. 2, 561–567.
Bowles, S. 1998 Endogenous preferences: the cultural consequences of markets and other economic institutions.
J. Econ. Lit. 36, 75–111.
Bowles, S. & Gintis, H. 2003 The origin of human
cooperation. In The genetic and cultural origins of cooperation
(ed. P. Hammerstein). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Camerer, C. F. 2003 Behavioral game theory: experiments in
strategic interaction. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Chartrand, T. L. & Bargh, J. A. 1999 The chameleon effect:
the perception-behavior link and social interaction.
J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 76, 893 –910. (doi:10.1037/00223514.76.6.893)
Cialdini, R. B., Brown, S. L., Lewis, B. P., Luce, C. &
Neuberg, S. L. 1997 Reinterpreting the empathyaltruism relationship: when one into one equals oneness.
J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 73, 481 –494. (doi:10.1037/00223514.73.3.481)
Darwin, C. 1872 The expression of the emotions in man and
animals. London, UK: John Murray.
de Quervain, D. J. F., Fischbacher, U., Treyer, V.,
Schellhammer, M., Schnyder, U., Buck, A. & Fehr, E.
2004 The neural basis of altruistic punishment. Science
305, 1254–1258. (doi:10.1126/science.1100735)
de Waal, F. B. M. 2008 Putting the altruism back in to altruism:
the evolution of empathy. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 59, 279–300.
(doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093625)
Decety, J. & Lamm, C. 2006 Human empathy through the
lens of social neuroscience. Sci. World J. 6, 1146–1163.
(doi:10.1100/tsw.2006.221)
di Pellegrino, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V. &
Rizzolatti, G. 1992 Understanding motor events: a neurophysiological study. Exp. Brain Res. 91, 176–180.
Fehr, E. & Camerer, C. 2007 Social neuroeconomics: the
neural circuitry of social preferences. Trends Cogn. Sci.
11, 419 –427. (doi:10.1016/j.tics.2007.09.002)
Fehr, E. & Schmidt, K. 1999 A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. Q. J. Econ. 114, 817 –868.
(doi:10.1162/003355399556151)
Fehr, E. & Schmidt, K. 2004 Fairness and incentives in a
multi-task principal-agent model. Scand. J. Econ. 106,
453 –474. (doi:10.1111/j.0347-0520.2004.00372.x)
Fehr, E. & Schmidt, K. In press. On inequity aversion: a
reply to Binmore and Shaked. J. Econ. Behav. Organ.
Fehr, E., Klein, A. & Schmidt, K. 2007 Fairness and contract design. Econometrica 75, 121–154. (doi:10.1111/
j.1468-0262.2007.00734.x)
Fehr, E., Kremhelmer, S. & Schmidt, K. 2008 Fairness
and the optimal allocation of property rights. Econ.
J. 118, 1262–1284. (doi:10.1111/j.1468-0297.2008.
02169.x)
Fogassi, L., Ferrari, P. F., Gesierich, B., Rozzi, S., Chersi, F.
& Rizzolatti, G. 2005 Parietal lobe: from action organization to intention understanding. Science 308, 662 –667.
(doi:10.1126/science.1106138)
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
Fontaine, P. 1997 Identification and economic behavior: sympathy and empathy in historical perspective. Econ. Philos.
13, 261–280. (doi:10.1017/S026626710000451X)
Fontaine, P. 2001 The changing place of empathy in welfare
economics. Hist. Polit. Econ. 33, 387 –409. (doi:10.1215/
00182702-33-3-387)
Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L. & Rizzolatti, G. 1996
Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain 119,
593 –609. (doi:10.1093/brain/119.2.593)
Gul, F. & Pesendorfer, W. 2008 The case for mindless economics. In The foundations of positive and normative
economics (eds A. Caplin & A. Schotter), pp. 3 –42.
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Hichri, W. & Kirman, A. 2007 The emergence of coordination in public good games. Eur. Phys. J. B Condens.
Matter Complex Syst. 55, 149 –159. (doi:10.1140/epjb/
e2007-00032-8)
Hoffer, E. 1955 Passionate state of mind. New York, NY:
Harper Collins.
Hume, D. 1740 [2000] A treatise of human nature (eds D. F.
Norton & M. J. Norton). Oxford, UK: Oxford University
Press.
Iacoboni, M. 2009 Imitation, empathy and mirror neurons.
Annu. Rev. Psychol. 60, 653–670. (doi:10.1146/annurev.
psych.60.110707.163604)
Jeannerod, M. 2006 Motor cognition. Oxford, UK: Oxford
University Press.
Knoch, D. & Fehr, E. 2007 Resisting the power of temptations: the right prefrontal cortex and self-control. Ann.
NY Acad. Sci. 1104, 123 –134. (doi:10.1196/annals.
1390.004)
Lieberman, M. D. 2007 Social cognitive neuroscience: a
review of core processes. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 58,
259–289. (doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.58.110405.085654)
Oosterbeek, H., Sloof, R. & van de Kuilen, G. 2004 Differences in ultimatum game experiments: evidence from a
meta-analysis. Exp. Econ. 7, 171–188. (doi:10.1023/
B:EXEC.0000026978.14316.74)
Oullier, O. & Basso, F. 2010 Embodied economics: how
bodily information shapes the social coordination
dynamics of decision-making. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 365,
291 –301. (doi:10.1098/rstb.2009.0168)
Oullier, O., Kirman, A. & Kelso, J. 2008 The coordination
dynamics of economic decision making: a multilevel
approach to social neuroeconomics. IIEEE Trans.
Neural Syst. Rehabil. Eng. 16, 557 –571. (doi:10.1109/
TNSRE.2008.2009960)
Platek, S. M., Mohamed, F. B. & Gallup, G. G. 2005
Contagious yawning and the brain. Cogn. Brain Res. 23,
448 –452. (doi:10.1016/j.cogbrainres.2004.11.011)
Preston, S. D. & de Waal, F. B. M. 2002 Empathy: its
ultimate and proximate bases. Behav. Brain Sci. 25, 1 –72.
Rabin, M. 1993 Incorporating fairness into game theory and
economics. Am. Econ. Rev. 83, 1281–1302.
Rizzolatti, G. 2005 The mirror neuron system and its function in humans. Anat. Embryol. 210, 419– 421. (doi:10.
1007/s00429-005-0039-z)
Rizzolatti, G. & Craighero, L. 2004 The mirror-neuron
system. Ann. Rev. Neurosci. 27, 169 –192. (doi:10.1146/
annurev.neuro.27.070203.144230)
Sachdeva, S., Iliev, R. & Medin, D. 2009 Sinning saints and
saintly sinners. Psychol. Rev. 20, 523 –528.
Sanfey, A. G. 2007 Social decision-making: insights from
game theory and neuroscience. Science 318, 598–602.
(doi:10.1126/science.1142996)
Sen, A. 2006 Identity and violence. New York, NY: Norton.
Singer, T. 2006 The neuronal basis and ontogeny of empathy
and mind reading: review of literature and implications for
future research. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 30, 855–863.
(doi:10.1016/j.neubiorev.2006.06.011)
Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on January 4, 2010
Review. Empathy in economics
Singer, T. & Fehr, E. 2005 The neuroeconomics of mind
reading and empathy. Am. Econ. Rev. 95, 340–345.
(doi:10.1257/000282805774670103)
Singer, T. & Lamm, C. 2009 The social neuroscience of
empathy. Ann. NY Acad. Sci. 1156, 81– 96. (doi:10.
1111/j.1749-6632.2009.04418.x)
Singer, T., Seymour, B., O’Doherty, J. P., Kaube, H.,
Dolan, R. & Frith, C. 2004 Empathy for pain
involves the affective but not sensory components of
pain. Science 303, 1157–1162. (doi:10.1126/science.
1093535)
Singer, T., Seymour, B., O’Doherty, J. P., Stephan, K. E.,
Dolan, R. & Frith, C. 2006 Empathetic neural responses
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2010)
A. Kirman & M. Teschl
317
are modulated by perceived fairness of others. Nature 439,
466–469. (doi:10.1038/nature04271)
Smith, A. 1759 [1976] The theory of moral sentiments (eds
D. D. Raphael & A. L. Macfie). Oxford, UK: Oxford
University Press.
Sorabji, R. 2006 In Self: ancient and modern insights about
individuality, life, and deaths. Chicago, IL: University of
Chicago Press.
Wicker, B., Keysers, C., Plailly, J., Royet, J. P., Gallese, V. &
Rizzolatti, G. 2003 Both of us disgusted in my insula: the
common neural basis of seeing and feeling disgust.
Neuron 40, 655 –664. (doi:10.1016/S0896-6273(03)
00679-2)