DOCUMENT RESUME
SE 063 070
ED 439 007
AUTHOR
TITLE
PUB DATE
NOTE
AVAILABLE FROM
PUB TYPE
EDRS PRICE
DESCRIPTORS
Anderson, John R.; Reder, Lynne M.; Simon, Herbert A.
Applications and Misapplications of Cognitive Psychology to
Mathematics Education.
1999-00-00
43p.
For full text see Web site:
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personal/ja/misapplied.html.
Opinion Papers (120)
MF01/PCO2 Plus Postage.
*Cognitive Processes; *Constructivism (Learning);
Educational Psychology; Elementary Secondary Education;
Learning; *Mathematics Education
ABSTRACT
There is a frequent misperception that the move from
behaviorism to cognitivism implies an abandonment of the possibilities of
decomposing knowledge into its elements for the purposes of study and
decontextualizing these elements for instruction. Cognitivism does not imply
outright rejection of decomposition and decontextualization. Two movements
based in part on this rejection--situated learning and constructivism--were
analyzed. These two schools of thought are not identical: situated learning
emphasizes that knowledge is maintained in the external, social world;
constructivism argues that knowledge resides in an individual's internal
state, perhaps unknowable to anyone else. However, both schools share the
general philosophical positions that knowledge cannot be decomposed or
"decontextualized" for purposes of either research or instruction, and each
group often appeals to the writings of the other for support. Since rejection
of decomposition and decontextualization appears to be the core common ground
of this "new look" in mathematics education, this paper examines the degree
to which modern cognitive psychology lends support to that rejection.
(Contains 92 references.) (ASK)
Reproductions supplied by EDRS are the best that can be made
from the original document.
Page: 1
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
Applications and Misapplications of
o
Cognitive Psychology to
Mathematics Education 1
PERMISSION TO REPRODUCE AND
DISSEMINATE THIS MATERIAL HAS
BEEN GRANTED BY
TO THE EDUCATIONAL RESOURCES
INFORMATION CENTER (ERIC)
John R. Anderson
Lynne M. Reder
Herbert A. Simon
Department of Psychology
Carnegie Mellon University
Pittsburgh, PA 15213
EDUCATION
offc',c.dfirg12,,ERNLE9rh
C4'721
EDUCATIONAL RESOURCES INFORMATION
CENTER (ERIC)
This document has been reproduced as
eceived from the person or organization
or mating it.
Minor changes have been made to
improve reproduction quality.
Points of view or opinions stated in this
document do not necessarily represent
official OERI position or policy.
[email protected]
[email protected]
[email protected]
Abstract
There is a frequent misperception that the move from behaviorism to
cognitivism implied an abandonment of the possibilities of decomposing
knowledge into its elements for purposes of study and decontextualizing these
elements for purposes of instruction. We show that cognitivism does not imply
outright rejection of decomposition and decontextualization. We critically
analyze two movements which are based in part on this rejection--situated
learning and constructivism. Situated learning commonly advocates practices
that lead to overly specific learning outcomes while constructivism advocates
very inefficient learning and assessment procedures. The modern
information-processing approach in cognitive psychology would recommend
careful analysis of the goals of instruction and thorough empirical study of the
efficacy of instructional approaches.
Following on the so-called "cognitive revolution" in psychology that began in
the 1960s, education, and particularly mathematics and science education, has
been acquiring new insights from psychology, and new approaches and
instructional techniques based on these insights. At the same time, cognitive
psychologists have being paying increasing attention to education as an area of
application of psychological knowledge and as a source of important research
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonal/jaimisapplied.html
2
BEST COPY AVAILABLE
Page:
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
problems. There is every reason to believe that as research in cognitive
psychology progresses and increasingly addresses itself to educational issues,
even closer and more productive links can be formed between psychology and
mathematics education.
However, there is a tendency now to present all manner of educational opinion
as bearing a stamp of approval from cognitive psychology. For instance,
Lamon and Lesh (1992) write in the introduction to a recent book they edited:
"Behavioral psychology (based on factual and procedural rules) has given way
to cognitive psychology (based on models for making sense of real-life
experiences), and technology-based tools have radically expanded the kinds of
situations in which mathematics is useful, while simultaneously increasing the
kinds of mathematics that are useful and the kinds of people who use
mathematics on a daily basis. In response to these trends, professional and
governmental organizations have reached an unprecedented, theoretically
sound, and future-oriented new consensus about the foundations of
mathematics in an age of information." (p. 18-19)
In fact, as in many recent publications in mathematics education, much of
what is described in that book reflects two movements, "situated learning" and
"constructivism", which have been gaining influence on thinking about
education and educational research. In our view, some of the central
educational recommendations of these movements have questionable
psychological foundations. We wish to compare these recommendations with
current empirical knowledge about effective and ineffective ways to facilitate
learning in mathematics and to reach some conclusions about what are the
effective ways. A number of the claims that have been advanced as insights
from cognitive psychology are at best highly controversial and at worst
directly contradict known research findings. As a consequence, some of the
prescriptions for educational reform based on these claims are bound to lead to
inferior educational outcomes and to block alternative methods for
improvement that are superior.
These two schools, of situated learning and constructivism, are not identical:
situated learning emphasizes that knowledge is maintained in the external,
social world; constructivism argues that knowledge resides in an individual's
internal state, perhaps unknowable to anyone else. However, both schools
share the general philosophical positions that knowledge cannot be
decomposed or "decontextualized" for purposes of either research or
instruction, and each group often appeals to the writings of the other for
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonaUjaimisapplied.html
3
Page:
Tuesday. November 30. 1999
support. Since rejection of decomposition and decontextualization seems to be
the core common ground of this "new look" in mathematics education, we will
first examine the degree to which modern cognitive psychology lends support
to that rejection.
Decomposition and Decontextualization
In an influential educational paper, Resnick and Resnick (1992) provide a
succinct statement of a common theoretical understanding in cognitive
psychology called the information-processing approach:
"Information-processing theories of cognition (Anderson, 1983; Newell and
Simon 1972), for example, analyze cognitive performances into complexes of
rules, but performances critically depend on interactions among those rules.
Each rule can be thought of as a component of the total skill, but the rules are
not defined independently of one another. The 'competence' of a
problem-solving system thus depends on how the complex of rules acts
together." (p. 43)
A number of educational researchers (e.g., Shepard, 1991) have cited Resnick
and Resnick as reporting that cognitive psychology has shown that cognition
cannot be analyzed into components. On the contrary, what the above quote
states (and what the cognitive literature they allude to says) is quite the
opposite. This literature, incorporating extensive empirical evidence, deals
both with the "rules" (components or processes) to which Resnick and Resnick
refer, and also, emphatically, with the interactions among these processes: the
interaction between these processes and sensory stimuli (the organism's
awareness of its current environment), and the interaction of processes with
information (other components of knowledge) that has been assembled in
memory through previous engagement with the environment. The whole
purpose of modeling cognition with computer programs--a central tool in
information-processing approaches -is to develop a full picture of these
interactions among components of knowledge.
Unlike earlier behaviorist theories, information-processing theories do not
posit a simple one-to-one mapping between individual rules or knowledge
components and individual bits of behavior. They deny this precisely because
continual interaction can be observed among components of knowledge and
behavior. Information-processing psychology has advanced rapidly by
developing methods both for identifying the components and for studying
them in their interactions with their entire contexts. This is the meaning of the
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonaliarmisapplied.html
4
Page: d
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
"unified theories of cognition" (e.g., Newell, 1991) which has guided so much
of the recent research and theory-building.
Thus, componential analysis is very much alive and well in modern cognitive
psychology. The information-processing approach tries both to deepen our
understanding of the components and to understand the relations among them
and with their environments. Examples of these methods of componential
analysis are the use of think-aloud protocols as data (Ericsson and Simon,
1993) and the use of models that simulate the interactions of perceptual,
memory, learning and thinking processes over a wide range of cognitive tasks
(e.g., Anderson, 1993; Feigenbaum and Simon, 1984; Newell, 1991).
With respect to decomposition, the correct principle is:
Assessing learning and improving learning methods requires careful task
analysis at the level of component skills, intimately combined with study of
the interaction of these skills in the context of broader tasks and environments.
So much for decomposition; what about decontextualization? Because
components interact with one another, it might prove impossible to invoke and
study them outside certain contexts. To cite a simple example, processes for
carrying out multi-column addition will only be evoked in the context of a
problem large enough to require carrying; they cannot be studied by posing
problems of adding 3+4 or 5+2.
While some context will often be required to assess a component, there are
always bounds on how complex such a context need be. It is a
well-documented fact of human cognition that large tasks decompose into
nearly independent subtasks (Simon, 1981, Chapter 7; Card, Moran &
Newell, 1983), so that only the context of the appropriate subtask is needed to
study its components. For instance, there is no need to teach or assess the
ability to perform multi-column addition in the context of calculating income
taxes. The process of adding tax deduction items is the same as the process of
taking sums in other tasks. And whether one does the sum by hand or by
calculator is unlikely to affect the rest of the tax calculation procedures. Thus,
the larger procedure is independent of the summing procedure, just as the
summing procedure is independent of the larger procedure.
The addition procedures might become tied into the tax calculation
procedures--for example, ignoring cents in calculating the sums. Such
specialized subprocedures are especially frequent at high levels of expertise.
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonalia/mIsapplied.html
5
Page::
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
However, this just means that the expert's procedure involves a structure of
different subtasks than the novice's, not that it cannot be analyzed into
components nor that these components cannot still be assessed in subtasks of
the original task. Thus, with respect to decontextualization, while it may be
difficult to get behavioral measures of individual components; these
components organize themselves into subtasks to achieve subgoals, and these
subgoals can have independent, assessable, behavioral realizations. It does not
require recondite research to demonstrate the near-decomposability of human
tasks. Every page of a good cookbook contains examples of assumed
component procedures (e.g., sauté, parboil) as do the how-to books in
domains like carpentry, plumbing or car repair. Moreover, one can apply these
procedures in new contexts such as when a chemistry lab requires us to boil
water. Fortunately for us human beings, with our very limited short-term
memories, the workings of each component can be understood without
simultaneous awareness of the details of all the other components.
With respect to decontextualization, the correct principle is:
Assessing learning and improving learning methods requires research and
instruction in contexts that are consistent with the scopes of the skills currently
under investigation. Component skills can be viewed within narrower contexts
than broad skills. Relating context to task is essential in order to meet the
limits of human attention and short-term memory capacity.
This false rejection of decomposition and decontextualization runs deep in
modern mathematics education. So, for instance, in the 1993 draft of the
NCTM assessment standard for school mathematics, we find condemnation of
the "essentialist view of mathematical knowledge" which assumes
"mathematics consists of an accumulation of mathematical concepts and skills"
(p.12). We can only say we find frightening the prospect of mathematics
education based on such a misconceived rejection of componential analysis.
The major agenda of this paper is to focus on the claims of situated learning
and constructivism, discussing them separately and focusing in each case on a
small number of central claims that we believe are unwarranted. There are
other issues beyond those we discuss, but these are perhaps the most important
for choosing among research directions and pedagogical strategies.
Situated Learning
Two of us have been involved in past reviews relevant to situated
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personal/jaimisapplied.html
6
Page: f
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
learning--Simon in support of the mutual compatibility of modern information
processing theory and situated cognition (Vera & Simon, 1993) and Reder in
an assessment of the effectiveness for training of techniques located at various
points along the scale of "situatedness" (Reder & Klatzky in a report of the
National Research Council, 1994). We will focus on the four claims of
situated learning discussed in the NRC report.
Claim 1: Action is grounded in the concrete situation in which it
occurs
That action is situationally grounded is surely the central claim of situated
cognition. It means that the potentialities for action cannot be fully described
independently of the specific situation, a statement with which we fully
concur. But the claim is sometimes exaggerated to assert that all knowledge is
specific to the situation in which the task is performed, and that more general
knowledge cannot and will not transfer to real-world situations. Supposed
examples of this are Lave's (1988) description of Orange County homemakers
who did very well at making supermarket best-buy calculations but who did
much worse on arithmetically equivalent school-like paper-and-pencil
mathematics problems. Another frequently cited example is Carraher,
Carraher and Schliemann's (1985) account of Brazilian street children who
could perform mathematics when making sales in the street but were unable to
answer similar problems presented in a school context.
Even if these claims are valid and generalizable beyond the specific anecdotes
that have been cited, they demonstrate at most that particular skills practiced
in real-life situations do not generalize to school situations. They assuredly do
not demonstrate that arithmetic procedures taught in the classroom cannot be
applied to enable a shopper to make price comparisons or a street vendor to
make change. What such observations call for is closer analyses of the task
demands and the use of such analyses to devise teachable procedures that will
achieve a balance between the advantages of generality and the advantages of
incorporating enough situational context to make transfer likely. What they
also call for is research on the feasibility of increasing the application and
transfer of knowledge by including ability to transfer as a specific goal in
instruction--a skill that is given little attention in most current instruction.
At one level there is nothing new in this claim about the contextualization of
learning. There have been numerous demonstrations in experimental
psychology that learning can be contextualized (e.g., Godden & Baddeley,
1975; Smith, Glenberg, & Bjork, 1978). For instance, Godden and Baddeley
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonaliarmisapplied.html
7
Page:
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
found that divers had difficulty remembering under water what they learned on
land or vice versa. However, it is not the case that learning is totally tied to a
specific context. For instance, Godden and Baddeley's divers could remember
some of what they learned in the other context. In fact, there are many
demonstrations of learning that transfers across contexts and of failures to find
any context specificity in the learning (e.g., Fernandez & Glenberg, 1985;
Saufley, Olaka, & Baversco, 1985) a fact that has often frustrated
researchers who were looking for context sensitivity.
How tightly learning will be bound to context depends on the kind of
knowledge being acquired. Sometimes knowledge is necessarily bound to a
specific context by the nature of instruction. Thus, to return to an earlier
example, one would not be surprised (and only a little upset) to learn that
carrying is bound to the context of doing base-ten addition and would not
generalize to another base system. In other cases, how contextualized the
learning is depends on the way the material is studied. If the learner elaborates
the knowledge with material from a specific context, it becomes easier to
retrieve the knowledge in that same context (Eich, 1985), but perhaps harder
in other contexts. One general result is that knowledge is more context bound
when it is just taught in a single context (Bjork & Richardson-Klavhen, 1989).
Clearly, some .skills, like reading, transfer from one context to another. For
instance, the very fact that we can engage in a discussion of the
context-dependence of knowledge is itself evidence for the context
independence of reading and writing competence. Many of the demonstrations
of contextual-binding from the situated camp involve mathematics, but
clearly, mathematical competence is not always contextually bound either.
Although the issue has seldom been addressed directly, the psychological
research literature is full of cases where mathematical competence has
transferred from the classroom to all sorts of laboratory situations (sometimes
bizarre--the intention was never to show transfer of mathematical skills--e.g.,
Bassok & Holyoak, 1987; Elio, 1986; Reder & Ritter, 1992). It is not easy to
locate the many published demonstrations of mathematical competence
generalizing to novel contexts; these results are not indexed under
"context-independence of mathematical knowledge" because, until recently,
this did not seem to be an issue.
The literature on situation-specificity of learning often comes with a value
judgment about the merits of knowledge tied to a nonschool context relative to
school-taught knowledge, and an implied or expressed claim that school
knowledge is not legitimate. Lave (1986, 1988 p. 195) goes so far as to
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonaliarmisapplied.html
8
Page: E
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
suggest that school-taught mathematics serves only to justify an arbitrary and
unfair class structure. The implication is that school-taught competences do
not contribute to on-the-job performance. However, numerous studies show
modest to large correlations between school achievement and work
performance (e.g., Hunter & Hunter, 1984; Brossiere, Knight, & Sabol, 1985)
even after partialling out the effects of general ability measures (which are
sometimes larger).
We conclude that action is indeed grounded in the situation where it occurs.
We dissent strongly from some of the supposed implications that have been
attached to this claim by proponents of situated action, and we have shown
that our dissent has strong empirical support. Instead, the evidence shows that:
How contextualized learning is depends on the way the material is studied.
Knowledge is more context bound when it is just taught in a single context.
Knowledge does not have to be taught in the precise context in which it will
be used, and grave inefficiencies in transfer can result from tying knowledge
too tightly to specific, narrow contexts.
We need closer analyses of the task demands to devise teachable procedures
that will balance the advantages of generality with the advantages of
incorporating enough situational context to make transfer likely.
We also need to study how to increase the application and transfer of
knowledge by including ability to transfer as a specific goal in instruction.
In particular, knowledge does not have to be taught in the precise context in
which it will be used, and grave inefficiencies in transfer can result from tying
knowledge too tightly to specific, narrow contexts.
Claim 2: Knowledge does not transfer between tasks
This second claim, of the failure of knowledge to transfer, can be seen as a
corollary of the first. If knowledge is wholly tied to the context of its
acquisition, it is not going to transfer to other contexts. Even without strong
contextual dependence, one could still claim that there is relatively little
transfer, beyond nearly identical tasks, to different physical contexts. For
instance, while one might be able to do fractional math in any context, it
might not transfer to learning algebra. There is a long tradition of research on
transfer in psychology, going back at least to Weber in 1844 and Fechner in
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonaUjaimisapplied.html
9
Page: f
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
1858 (Woodworth, 1938, Chapter 8), demonstrating that, depending very
much upon the experimental situation and the relation of the material
originally learned to the transfer material, there can be either large amounts of
transfer, a modest amount of transfer, no transfer at all, or even negative
transfer.
The more recent psychological literature is also full of failures to achieve
transfer (e.g., Gick & Holyoak, 1980; Hayes & Simon, 1977; Reed, Ernst, &
Banerji, 1974; Weisberg, Di Camillo, & Phillips, 1985), but it is also full of
successful demonstrations of transfer (e.g., Brown, 1990; Brown &
Campione, 1993; Kotovsky & Fallside, 1989; Schoenfeld, 1985; Sing ley &
Anderson, 1989; Smith, 1986). Indeed, in the same domain (Tower of Hanoi
isomorphs) quite different amounts of transfer occur depending on the amount
of practice with the target task and on the representation of the transfer task
(Kotovsky & Fallside, 1989). In general, representation and degree of practice
are critical for determining the transfer from one task to another.
Sing ley and Anderson (1989) argued that transfer between tasks is a function
of the degree to which the tasks share cognitive elements. This hypothesis had
also been put forth very early in the development of research on transfer
(Thorndike & Woodworth, 1901; Woodworth, 1938), but was hard to test
experimentally until we acquired our modern capability for identifying task
components. Sing ley and Anderson taught subjects several text editors, one
after another and sought to predict transfer (savings in learning a new editor
when it was not taught first). They found that subjects learned subsequent text
editors more rapidly and that the number of procedural elements shared by two
text editors predicted the amount of this transfer. In fact, they obtained large
transfer across editors that were very different in surface structure but that had
common abstract structures. Sing ley and Anderson also found that similar
principles govern transfer of mathematical competence across multiple
domains, although here they had to consider transfer of declarative as well as
procedural knowledge. As a general statement of the research reported by
Sing ley and Anderson, transfer varied from one domain to another as a
function of the number of symbolic components that were shared. If anything,
Sing ley and Anderson found empirically slightly more transfer than was
predicted by their theory.
What about the situations where subjects have shown relatively little transfer?
In one famous series of studies (Gick & Holyoak, 1980, 1983), subjects were
presented with Duncker's (1945) classic radiation problem: "Suppose you are a
doctor faced with a patient who has an inoperable stomach tumor. You have at
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonalia/misapplied.html
10
Page: 1C
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
your disposal rays that can destroy human tissue when directed with sufficient
intensity. How can you use-these rays to destroy the tumor without destroying
the surrounding healthy tissue?" (adapted from Gick & Holyoak, 1983). Prior
to their exposure to the target problem, subjects read a story about an
analogous military problem and its solution. In the story, a general wishes to
capture an enemy fortress. Radiating outward from the fortress are many
roads, each mined in such a way that the passing of any large force will cause
an explosion. This precludes a full-scale direct attack. The general's plan is to
divide his army, send a small group down each road, and converge on the
fortress. The common strategy in both problems is to divide the force, attack
from different sides, and converge on the target. After reading this story,
however, only about 30 percent of the subjects could solve the radiation
problem, which is only a limited improvement (although an improvement by a
factor of three) over the 10 percent baseline solution rate (Gick & Holyoak,
1980).
One of the striking characteristics of such failures of transfer is how relatively
transient they are. Gick and Holyoak were able to increase transfer greatly just
by suggesting to subjects that they try to use the problem about the general.
Exposing subjects to two such analogs also greatly increased transfer. The
amount of transfer appeared to depend in large part on where the attention of
subjects was directed during the experiment, which suggests that instruction
and training on the cues that signal the relevance of an available skill might
well deserve more emphasis than they now typically receive--a promising
topic for cognitive research with very important educational implications.
As a methodological comment, we think that there is a tendency to look for
transfer in situations where one is least likely to find it. That is, research tends
to look for transfer from little practice in one domain to initial performance in
another domain. Superficial differences between the two domains will have
their largest negative effect when the domains are unfamiliar. We do not
require that students show the benefit of one day of calculus on the first day of
physics. Rather, we expect that they will be better physics students at year's
end for having had a year's study of calculus.
Contrary to the claim that knowledge does not transfer between tasks, the
evidence we have reviewed supports the following principles for securing
transfer of learning:
Depending upon the experimental situation and the relation of the material
originally learned to the transfer material, there can be either large amounts of
http://acipsy.cmu.edu/personal/Ja/mIsapplied.html
11
Page: 11
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
transfer, a modest amount, no transfer at all, or even negative transfer.
Representation and degree of practice are critical for determining the transfer
from one task to another, and transfer varies from one domain to another as a
function of the number of symbolic components that are shared.
The amount of transfer depends on where attention is directed during learning.
Training on the cues that signal the relevance of an available skill may deserve
much more emphasis than they now typically receive in instruction.
Claim 3: Training by abstraction is of little use; real learning occurs
in
"authentic" situations.
Like Claim 2, the claim that training by abstraction is of little use is a
corollary of the earlier claims. Nonetheless, one might argue for it even if one
dismisses the others. Claim 3 has been extended into an advocacy for
apprenticeship training (Brown, Collins, & Duguid, 1989; Collins, Brown, &
Newman, 1989). It is argued that, because current performance will be
facilitated to the degree that the context closely matches prior experience, the
most effective training is an apprenticeship to others in the performance
situation. This claim is used more than any other to challenge the legitimacy
of school-based instruction.
Abstract instruction can be ineffective if what is taught in the classroom is not
what is required in the job situation. Often this is an indictment of the design
of the classroom instruction rather than of the idea of abstract instruction in
itself. However, sometimes it is an indictment of the job situation. For
instance, Los Angeles police after leaving the police academy are frequently
told by more experienced officers "now forget everything you learned"
(Independent Commission on the Los Angeles Police Department, 1991: 125).
The consequence is that police officers are produced who, ignoring their
classroom training in the face of contrary influences during apprenticeship,
may violate civil rights and make searches without warrants. Clearly, one
needs to create a better correspondence between job performance and abstract
classroom instruction and sometimes this means changing the nature of the job
performance (including the structure of motivations and rewards) and fighting
unwanted and deleterious effects of apprenticeship learning.
Abstract instruction can be quite effective. In unpublished research, Sing ley
found that abstract instruction leads to successful transfer while concrete
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonallarmIsapplied.html
12
Page: 1;
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
instruction can lead to failure of transfer. He taught subjects to solve algebra
word problems involving mixtures. Some subjects were trained with pictures
of the mixtures while other subjects were trained with abstract tabular
representations that highlighted the underlying mathematical relationships. It
was the abstract training group that was able to transfer better to other kinds of
problems that involved analogous mathematical relationships. Perhaps the
most striking demonstration of the benefit of abstract instruction comes from
Biederman and Shiffrar (1987). They looked at the very difficult task of
sexing day-old chicks--something that people spend years learning in an
apprentice-like role. They found that 20 minutes of abstract instruction
brought novices up to the levels of experts who had years of practice.
The issue of choosing between abstract and very specific instruction can be
viewed in the following way. If abstract training is given, learners must also
absorb the money and time costs of obtaining supplemental training for each
distinct application. But if very specific training is given, they must
completely retrain for each application. Which is to be preferred, and to what
extent, depends on the balance among (a) the cost of the more general abstract
training, (b) the cost of the specific training, (c) the cost of the supplemental
training for application of abstract training, and (d) the range of jobs over
which the learner is likely to have occasion to apply what was learned.
Someone who will spend years performing a single set of very specific tasks
might be well advised to focus on specific training. But if the cost of
supplemental training is not large (i.e., if there is substantial transfer over the
range of tasks), or if technological or other changes are likely to alter tasks
substantially over the years, or if the range of tasks the learner is likely to
address over time is substantial, then abstract training with supplemental
applications training is clearly preferable. It is easy to work out an exercise of
this kind by assigning numbers to the various costs and to the variability of the
tasks encountered, and thereby to show that there is no solution that is optimal
for all cases.
Most modern information-processing theories are "learning-by-doing" theories
which imply that learning would occur best with a combination of abstract
instruction and concrete illustrations of the lessons of this instruction.
Numerous experiments show combining abstract instruction with specific
concrete examples (e.g., Cheng, Holyoak, Nisbett, & Oliver, 1986; Fong,
Krantz, & Nisbett, 1986; Reed & Actor, 1991) is better than either one alone.
One of the most famous studies demonstrating this was performed by
Scholckow & Judd (described in Judd, 1908; a conceptual replication by
Hendrickson & Schroeder, 1941). They had children practice throwing darts at
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonal/ja/mIsapplied.html
13
Pape: 1::
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
a target underwater. One group of subjects received an explanation of
refraction of light which causes the apparent location of the target to be
deceptive. The other group only practiced, receiving no abstract instruction.
Both groups did equally well on the practice task which involved a target 12
inches under water, but the group with abstract instruction did much better
when asked to transfer to a situation where the target was now under only 4
inches of water.
A variation on the emphasis on apprenticeship training is the emphasis that has
been given to using only "authentic" problems (e.g., Lesh & Lamon, 1992).
What is authentic is typically ill-defined but there seems to be a strong
emphasis on having problems be like the problems students might encounter in
everyday life. A focus on underlying cognitive process would suggest that this
is a superficial requirement. Rather, we would argue as have others (e.g.,
Hiebert, Hearner, Carpenter, Fennema, Fuson, 1994) that the real goal should
be to get students motivated and engage in cognitive processes that will
transfer. What is important is what cognitive processes a problem evokes and
not what real-world trappings it might have.
Abstract instruction can be ineffective if what is taught in the classroom is not
what is required in the job situation, but under other conditions, it can be quite
effective.
Whether abstract or specific instruction is to be preferred, and to what extent,
depends on the balance among (a) the cost of the more general abstract
training, (b) the cost of the specific training, (c) the cost of the supplemental
training for application of abstract training, and (d) the range of jobs over
which the learner is likely to have occasion to apply what was learned.
Most modern information-processing "learning-by-doing" theories imply that
learning would occur best with a combination of abstract instruction and
concrete illustrations of the lessons of this instruction that get students
motivated and engaged in cognitive processes that will transfer. What is
important is what cognitive processes a problem evokes and not its real-world
trappings.
Claim 4: Instruction needs to be done in a highly social environment
The claim that instruction is only effective in a highly social environment is
based on the ideas that (a) virtually all jobs are highly social in nature and (b)
learning is closely associated with its context. As we have shown, the second
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonal/jarmisapplied.html
14
Page: 11
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
claim is overstated. We suspect that the first claim is also somewhat
overstated, although we are not acquainted with any analyses of existing job
surveys that show how much social interaction, and what kind, is involved in
various jobs. Clearly, there are jobs that are not social in character and for
which this claim does not hold. Likewise, it is clear that there are jobs where
performance is highly social. Obviously it is important that people with such
jobs learn (within or outside the specific job context) to deal effectively with
the social nature of their jobs.
While one must learn to deal with the social aspects of jobs, this is no reason
why all skills required for these jobs should be trained in a social context.
Consider the skills necessary to become a successful tax accountant. While the
accountant must learn how to deal with clients, it is not necessary to learn the
tax code or how to use a calculator while interacting with a client. It is better
to train independent parts of a task separately (see the earlier discussion of
nearly independent subtasks under decontextualization) because fewer
cognitive resources will then be required for performance, thereby reserving
adequate capacity for learning. Thus, it is better to learn the tax code without
having to simultaneously interact with the client and better to learn how to
deal with a client when the tax code is no longer a burden.
In fact, a large history of research in psychology shows that part training is
often more effective when the part component is independent, or nearly so, of
the larger task (e.g., Knerr, Morrison, Muman, Stein, Sticha, Hoffman,
Buede, & Holding, 1987; Patrick, 1992). Indeed in team training, it is
standard to do some part-task training of individuals outside of the team just
because it would be expensive and futile to get the whole team together when
a single member needs training on a new piece of equipment (S alas,
Dickinson, Converse, & Tannenbaum, 1993). In team sports, where a great
deal of attention is given to the efficiency of training, the time available is
always divided between individual skill training and team training. We will
have more to say about the issue of part versus whole training when we
discuss the constructivist advocacy of carrying on all instruction in complex
learning situations.
Another facet of the claim that instruction is best in a highly social
environment comes not from those advocating situated learning, per se , but
from those advocating the advantages of co-operative learning (e.g., Johnson
& Johnson, 1989) as an instructional tool. Co-operative learning, also known
as "communities of practice" and "group learning", refers to learning
environments where people of equal status work together to enhance their
http://act.psy.cmu.eduipersonal/a/misapplled.html
15
Page: if
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
individual acquisition of knowledge and skills. This environment or structure
is to be contrasted with tutoring (where the tutor and tutee are of unequal
knowledge and status) and team training (where the desired outcome is
concerned with team or group performance). In a review by the Committee on
Techniques for the Enhancement of Human Performance (National Research
Council, 1994), it was noted that research on cooperative learning has
frequently not been well controlled (e.g., nonrandom assignments to
treatments, uncontrolled "teacher" and treatment effects), that relatively few
studies "have successfully demonstrated advantages for cooperative versus
individual learning," and that "a number of detrimental effects arising from
cooperative learning have been identified--the "free rider," the "sucker," the
"status differential," and "ganging up" effects (see e.g., Salomon and
Globerson, 1989, pp. 94-95).
As the NRC review of cooperative learning notes, there have been a
substantial number of reports of no-differences (e.g., Slavin, 1990), but
unfortunately, there have also been a huge number of practitioner-oriented
articles about cooperative learning that tend to gloss over difficulties with this
approach, and treat it as an academic panacea. Indeed, the approach is applied
too liberally without the requisite structuring or scripting to make it effective.
Cooperative learning needs to be structured with incentives (for children at
least) that motivate cooperation and a sharing of the goal structure. Because of
this uncritical application it seems likely that the costs of this type of
instruction may outweigh the intended benefits. In colleges we find group
projects increasingly popular among instructors but some of the difficulties
encountered show that group learning can become counterproductive. Students
sometimes complain that the difficulty of finding times to meet to work on
assignments together make the practice frustrating and that same students
exploit the system and assume that other partners in the group will do all the
work (and hence acquire all the knowledge and skills). A reported practice
among some students is to divide the labor across classes so that one member
of a group does all of the work for a project in one programming class, while
another carries the burden for a different class. Clearly these situations are not
the intended outcomes of cooperative learning, but are the sorts of things that
will occur if there is not thoughtful implementation and scripting of the
learning situation.
Our point is not to say that cooperative learning can not be successful nor
sometimes better than individual learning. Rather, it is not a panacea that
always provides outcomes superior or even equivalent to those of individual
training.
hap://act.psy.cmu.edu/personaliaimisapplied.html
16
Page: 1E
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
Summary: Situated Learning
In general, situated learning focuses on some well-documented phenomena in
cognitive psychology and ignores many others: While cognition is partly
context-dependent, it is also partly context-independent; while there are
dramatic failures of transfer, there are also dramatic successes; while concrete
instruction helps, abstract instruction also helps; while some performances
benefit from training in a social context, others do not. The development from
behaviorism to cognitivism was an awakening to the complexity of human
cognition. The analysis offered by situated learning seems a regressive move.
What is needed to improve learning and teaching is to continue to deepen our
research into the circumstances that determine when narrower or broader
contexts are required and when attention to narrower or broader skills are
optimal for effective and efficient learning.
In our discussion, we have focused, as do the proponents of situated learning,
on cognitive issues. There are, of course, also very important questions about
the circumstances under which people are most strongly motivated to learn.
Motivational questions lie outside our present discussion, but are at least as
complex as the cognitive issues. In particular, there is no simple relation
between level of motivation, on the one hand, and the complexity or realism
of the context in which the learning takes place, on the other. To cite a simple
example, learning by doing in the real-life domain of application is sometimes
claimed to be the optimum procedure. Certainly, this is not true, when the
tasks are life-threatening for novices (e.g., firefighting), when relevant
learning opportunities are infrequent and unpredictable (e.g., learning to fly a
plane in bad weather), or when the novice suffers social embarrassment from
using inadequate skills in a real-life context (e.g., using a foreign language at
a low level of skill). The interaction of motivation with cognition has been
described in information-processing terms by Simon (1967, 1994). But an
adequate discussion of these issues would call for a separate paper as long as
this one.
Constructivism
Constructivism has a less unified position than situated learning. Indeed, under
some interpretations, we are constructivists and have been called so by
mathematics educators (e.g., Silver, 1987). However, there is a rising
interpretation of constructivism that rejects the information-processing
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonalia/mIsapplied.html
17
Page: 1;
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
approach (Cobb, 1990) which is the subject of discussion here. Such views are
often espoused by those claiming to practice "radical constructivism". Even
among radical constructivists, positions vary and some theorists seem to be
making philosophical claims about the nature of knowledge rather than
empirical claims. Indeed, in the extreme, constructivism denies the relevance
of empirical data to educational decisions. However, some of the claims also
have clear psychological implications that are not always supported.
Claim 1: Knowledge cannot be instructed (transmitted) by a teacher,
it can only be constructed by the learner
The constructivist vision of learning is nicely captured by the following quote:
"learning would be viewed as an active, constructive process in which students
attempt to resolve problems that arise as they participate in the mathematical
practices of the classroom. Such a view emphasizes that the learning-teaching
process is interactive in nature and involves the implicit and explicit
negotiation of mathematical meanings. In the course of these negotiations, the
teacher and students elaborate the taken-as-shared mathematical reality that
constitutes the basis for their ongoing communication" (Cobb, Yackel, &
Wood, 1992).
As an example of this, Cobb, Wood, Yackel, Nicholls, Wheatley, Trigatti, &
Pertwitz (1991) describe an effort to teach second graders to count by tens.
Rather than telling the students the principle directly, they assigned groups of
students the task of counting objects bundled in sets of ten. Invariably, the
groups discover that counting by tens is more efficient than counting by ones.
Building a whole second-grade curriculum around such techniques, they found
their students doing as well on traditional skills as students from traditional
classrooms, transferring more, and expressing better attitudes about
mathematics.
One can readily agree with one part of the constructivist claim: that learning
must be an active process. Learning requires a change in the learner, which
can only be brought about by what the learner does--what he or she attends to,
what activities he or she engages in. The activity of a teacher is relevant to the
extent that it causes students to engage in activities they would not otherwise
engage in--including, but not limited to, acquiring knowledge provided by the
teacher or by books. A teacher may also engage students in tasks, some of
which may involve acquisition of skills by working examples. Other tasks
include practicing skills to bring them to effective levels, interacting with their
hap://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonalialmisapplied.html
18
Page: 1E
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
fellow students and with the teacher, and so on.
The problem posed to psychology and education is to design a series of
experiences for students that will enable them to learn effectively and to
motivate them to engage in the corresponding activities. On all of these points,
it would be hard to find grounds for disagreement between contructivists and
other cognitive psychologists. The more difficult problem, and the one that
often leads to different prescriptions, is determining the desirable learning
goals and the experiences that, if incorporated in the instructional design, will
best enable students to achieve these goals. Of course, arriving at good
designs is not a matter for philosophical debate; it requires empirical evidence
about how people, and children in particular, actually learn, and what they
learn from different educational experiences.
One finds frequent reference to Jean Piaget as providing a scientific basis for
constructivism. Piaget has had enormous influence on our understanding of
cognitive development and indeed was one of the major figures responsible for
the emergence of cognitivism from the earlier behaviorist era in psychology.
While it is fair to say that many of his specific claims have been seriously
questioned, the general influence of his theoretical perspective remains. Key
to constructivism is Piaget's distinction between assimilation and
accommodation as mechanisms of learning and development. Assimilation is a
relatively passive incorporation of experience into a representation already
available to the child. However, when the discrepancies between task demands
and the child's cognitive structure become too great, the child will reorganize
his or her thoughts. This is called accommodation (and often nowadays,
"re-representation").
Piaget emphasized how the child internalizes by making changes in mental
structure. The constructivists make frequent reference to this analysis,
particularly the non-passive accommodation process. (In this respect,
constructivism is quite different from situated learning which emphasizes the
external bases of cognition.) A more careful understanding of Piaget would
have shown that assimilation of knowledge also plays a critical role in setting
the stage for accommodation -that the accommodation cannot proceed without
assimilation.
Some constructivists (e.g., Cobb, 1990) have mistakenly implied that modern
information-processing theories deal only with assimilation and do not
incorporate the more constructive accommodation. Far from this, the
learning-by-doing theories that are widely employed in cognitive science are in
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personalia/misapplied.html
19
Page: lf
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
fact analyses of how cognitive structure accommodates to experience. We will
briefly describe here two such analyses, both to correct the misrepresentation
of information-processing theory and to establish a more precise framework
for discussing the effects of instruction.
In Anderson's (1993) ACT-R, one principal learning mechanism is knowledge
compilation. When learners come upon problems they do not know how to
solve, they can look at an example of how a similar problem is solved
(retrieved either from memory or some external source) and try to solve the
problem by analogy to this example. Knowledge compilation is the
accommodation process by which new procedures (rules) are created to
produce more directly the computation that this retrieve-and-analogize process
requires.
In Feigenbaum and Simon's (1984) EPAM, learning involves gradually
building up a discrimination net for recognizing objects and taking appropriate
actions. A discrimination net is a sequence of tests that are applied to various
features of an object. New tests are added as experience indicates that previous
tests were inadequate. Gradually, the system develops a complex sensitivity to
the situations and stimuli in its environment in a continuing process of
re-representation, or accommodation.
These theories provide concrete realizations of what it means for a system to
construct knowledge. As such they provide a basis for examining the
constructivist's claim that knowledge cannot be instructed. If passive recording
is what one means by "instruct" these learning mechanisms cannot be
instructed. However, it is quite wrong to claim that what is learned is not
influenced by explicit instruction. For instance, in ACT-R's learning by
analogy, instruction serves to determine the representation of the examples
from which one "constructs" one's understanding, and Piro lli and Anderson
(1985) showed in the domain of recursive programming that what one learns
from an example is strongly influenced by the instruction that accompanied the
example. In EPAM, which has had extensive success in modeling human
learning in a variety of perceptual and verbal learning tasks (e.g., Simon &
Feigenbaum, 1964), learning is strongly influenced by the sequence of stimuli
and the feedback that tells the system when responses are correct, and when
they are wrong.
There is a great deal of research showing that, under some circumstances,
people are better at remembering information that they create for themselves
than information they receive passively (Bobrow & Bower, 1969; Slamecka &
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personalia/misapplied.html
20
Page: 2C
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
Graf, 1972). However, this does not imply that people do not remember what
they are told. Indeed, in other cases people remember as well or even better
information that is provided than information they create (Slamecka &
Katsaiti, 1987; Stern & Bransford, 1979).
When, for whatever reason, students cannot construct the knowledge for
themselves, they need some instruction. The argument that knowledge must be
constructed is very similar to the earlier arguments that discovery learning is
superior to direct instruction. In point of fact, there is very little positive
evidence for discovery learning and it is often inferior (e.g., Charney, Reder
& Kusbit, 1990). Discovery learning, even when successful in acquiring the
desired construct, may take a great deal of valuable time that could have been
spent practicing this construct if it had been instructed. Because most of the
learning in discovery learning only takes place after the construct has been
found, when the search is lengthy or unsuccessful, motivation commonly
flags. As Ausubel (1968) wrote, summarizing the findings from the research
on discovery learning twenty-five years ago:
"actual examination of the research literature allegedly supportive of learning
by discovery reveals that valid evidence of this nature is virtually nonexistent.
It appears that the various enthusiasts of the discovery method have been
supporting each other research-wise by taking in each other's laundry, so to
speak, that is, by citing each other's opinions and assertions as evidence and
by generalizing wildly from equivocal and even negative findings." (p.
497-498)
It is sometimes argued that direct instruction leads to "routinization" of
knowledge and drives out understanding:
"the more explicit I am about the behavior I wish my students to display, the
more likely it is that they will display the behavior without recourse to the
understanding which the behavior is meant to indicate; that is, the more likely
they will take the form for the substance." Brousseau (1984)
An extension of this argument is that excessive practice will also drive out
understanding. This criticism of practice (called "drill and kill," as if this
phrase constituted empirical evaluation) is prominent in constructivist
writings. Nothing flies more in the face of the last 20 years of research than
the assertion that practice is bad. All evidence, from the laboratory and from
extensive case studies of professionals, indicates that real competence only
comes with extensive practice (e.g., Hayes, 1985; Ericsson, Krampe,
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonalia/mIsapplied.html
21
Page: 21
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
Tesche-Romer, 1993). In denying the critical role of practice one is denying
children the very thing they need to achieve real competence. The instructional
task is not to "kill" motivation by demanding drill, but to find tasks that
provide practice while at the same time sustaining interest. Substantial
evidence shows that there are a number of ways to do this;
"learning-from-examples," a method we will discuss presently, is one such
procedure that has been extensively and successfully tested in school
situations.
The evidence, then, leads us to the following conclusions about the role of
student and teacher in learning:
Learning requires a change in the learner, which can only be brought about by
what the learner does. The activity of a teacher is relevant to the extent that it
causes students to engage in activities they would not otherwise engage in.
The task is to design a series of experiences for students that will enable them
to learn effectively and to motivate them to engage in the corresponding
activities.
The learning-by-doing theories that are widely employed in cognitive science
are analyses of how cognitive structure accommodates to experience.
When students cannot construct the knowledge for themselves, they need
some instruction. There is very little positive evidence for discovery learning
and it is often inferior. In particularly, it may be costly in time, and when the
search is lengthy or unsuccessful, motivation commonly flags.
People are sometimes better at remembering information that they create for
themselves than information they receive passively, but in other cases they
remember as well or better information that is provided than information they
create.
Real competence only comes with extensive practice. The instructional task is
not to "kill" motivation by demanding drill, but to find tasks that provide
practice while at the same time sustaining interest. There are a number of
ways to do this, for instance, by "learning-from-examples."
Claim 2: Knowledge cannot be represented symbolically
The claim of the situated school that knowledge cannot be represented
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonalia/mIsapplied.html
22
Page: 2;
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
symbolically is more an epistemological claim in the constructivist's hands
than a psychological claim. The claim is that there are subtleties in human
understanding that defy representation in terms of a set of rules or other
symbol structures (e.g., Cobb, 1990). The argument is not really about
whether the knowledge is actually so represented in the human head, but
whether knowledge, by its very nature, can be represented symbolically.
Searle's well-known attempt to show that, in principle, a symbolic system
cannot understand language (the "Chinese Room" metaphor, Searle, 1980) is
an extension of this claim.
Among the misconceptions underlying the claim that knowledge is
non-symbolic is the faulty notion that "symbolic" means "expressed in words
and sentences, or in equivalent formal structures." Symbols are much more
than formal expressions. Any kind of pattern that can be stored and can refer
to some other pattern, say, one in the external world, is a symbol, capable of
being processed by an information-processing system. Thus, an EPAM-like
system can learn, when a stimulus satisfies certain tests (has certain features),
to create an internal symbol that designates the kind of object we know as a
cat. EPAM can then also learn and store in memory the name spelled "c-a-t"
(also a symbol), and associate it with the symbol (pattern) that allows it to
recognize a cat. But of course the English name and the object (the cat) are
denoted by quite different symbols--a cat is not a verbal structure but a furry
creature that can sometimes be seen in the environment.
A substantial number of symbolic systems have been built that can store
symbol structures representing mental images of external events and can
reason about the events pictorially with the help of these structures (Larkin,
1981). Careful comparison with the behavior of human subjects reasoning
about pictures or diagrams shows that these systems capture many of the basic
properties and processes of human imagery. Searle's Chinese Room story fails
because the inhabitants of his postulated room, unlike humans and other
symbolic systems, do not have a sensory window on the world: cannot
associate a pattern in memory with the external object that can be seen and
denoted by that pattern.
Cobb, Yackel, and Wood (1992) present constructivism as a rejection of the
"representational view of mind." We and other cognitive psychologists, who
do subscribe to a representational view, find little that we can recognize in
their characterization of that view. Cobb et al. quote Rorty's
mischaracterization of it:
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonaUja/misapplied.html
23
Page: 2:
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
"To know is to represent accurately what is outside the mind; so to understand
the possibility and nature of knowledge is to understand the way in which the
mind is able to construct such representations" (Cobb, Yackel, and Wood,
1992, p. 3 from Rorty, 1979).
The representational view of mind, as practiced in cognitive psychology,
certainly makes no claims that the mind represents the world accurately or
completelyal, and no strong claims about the nature of knowledge as a
philosophical issue. The true representational position is compatible with a
broad range of notions about the relation of the mind to the world, and about
the accuracy or inaccuracy and completeness or incompleteness of our internal
representations of the world's features. Its claim simply:
Cognitive competence (in this case mathematical competence) depends on the
availability of symbolic structures (e.g., mental patterns or mental images)
that are created in response to experience.
In constructivist writings, criticisms of the straw-man position typified by the
quotation from Rorty are used to discredit the actual representational view of
the mind employed in cognitive psychology. As we have already pointed out
in discussing the constructivist's first claim, modern cognitive theories
emphatically do not assume that learning is a passive recording of experience.
The misinterpretation of the representational view leads to much confusion
about external mathematical representations (e.g., equations, graphs, rules,
Dienes blocks, etc.) versus internal representations (e.g., production rules,
discrimination nets, mental images). Believing that the representational
version of learning records these external representations passively and
without transformation into distinct internal representations, constructivists
take inadequacies of the external representations as inadequacies of the notion
of internal representation. For instance, if a set of rules in a textbook is
inadequate this is taken as an inability of production rules to capture the
concepts. However, cognitive theories postulate (and provide evidence for)
complex processes for transforming (assimilating and accommodating) these
external representations to produce internal structures that are not at all
isomorphic to the external representations.
While it is true that education has proceeded for centuries without a theory of
internal representation, this is no reason to ignore the theories that are now
coming from cognitive psychology. Consider the analogy of medicine. For
thousands of years before there was any real knowledge of human physiology,
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personal/jarmisapplied.html
24
Page: 22
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
remedies for some pathological conditions were known and used, sometimes
effectively, by both doctors and others. But the far more powerful methods of
modern medicine were developed concurrently with the development of
modern physiology and biochemistry, and are squarely based on the latter
developments. To acquire powerful interventions in disease, we had to deepen
our understanding of the mechanisms of disease--of what was going on in the
diseased body.
In the same way, human beings have been learning, and have been teaching
their offspring, since the dawn of our species. We have a reasonably powerful
"folk medicine," based on lecturing and reading and apprenticeship and
tutoring, aided by such technology as paper and the blackboard--a folk
medicine that does not demand much knowledge about what goes on in the
human head during learning and that has not changed radically since schools
first emerged. To go beyond these traditional techniques, we must follow the
example of medicine and build (as we have been doing for the past thirty or
forty years) a theory of the information processes that underlie skilled
performance and skill acquisition: that is to say, we must have a theory of the
ways in which knowledge is represented internally, and the ways in which
such internal representations are acquired. In fact, cognitive psychology has
now progressed a long way toward such a theory, and, as we have seen, a
great deal is already known that can be applied, and is beginning to be
applied, to improve learning processes.
In summary, contrary to the claim that knowledge cannot be represented
symbolically, the evidence indicates the following actual state of affairs:
Symbols are much more than formal expressions.
Any kind of pattern that can be stored and can refer to some other pattern, say,
one in the external world, is a symbol, capable of being processed by an
information-processing system.
Cognitive competence (in this case mathematical competence) depends on the
availability of symbolic structures (e.g., mental patterns or mental images)
that are created in response to experience.
Cognitive theories postulate (and provide evidence for) complex processes for
transforming (assimilating and accommodating) these external representations
to produce internal structures that are quite different from the external
representations.
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personalia/mIsapplied.html
25
Page: 2:
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
Today instruction is based in large part on "folk psychology." To go beyond
these traditional techniques, we must continue to build a theory of the ways in
which knowledge is represented internally, and the ways in which such
internal representations are acquired.
Claim 3: Knowledge can only be communicated in complex learning
situations
Part of the "magical" property of knowledge asserted in the second claim, that
there is something in the nature of knowledge that cannot be represented
symbolically, is that no simple instructional situation suffices to convey the
knowledge, whatever it may be. This assertion is the final consequence of
rejecting decontextualization. Thus, constructivists recommend, for example,
that children learn all or nearly all of their mathematics in the context of
complex problems (e.g., Lesh & Zawojeski, 1992). This recommendation is
put forward without any evidence as to its educational effectiveness.
There are two serious problems with this approach, both related to the fact that
a complex task will call upon a large number of competences. First, as we
noted earlier with respect to part training, a learner who is having difficulty
with many of the components can easily be overwhelmed by the processing
demands of the complex task. Second, to the extent that many components are
well mastered, the student will waste a great deal of time repeating these
mastered components to get an opportunity to practice the few components
that need additional effort.
There are, of course, reasons sometimes to practice skills in their complex
setting. Some of the reasons are motivational and some reflect the special
skills that are unique to the complex situation. The student who wishes to play
violin in an orchestra would have a hard time making progress if all practice
were attempted in the orchestra context. On the other hand, if the student
never practiced as a member of an orchestra, critical skills unique to the
orchestra would not be acquired. The same arguments can be made in the
sports context, and motivational arguments can also be made for complex
practice in both contexts. A child may not see the point of isolated exercises,
but will when they are embedded in the real-world task. Children are
motivated to practice sports skills because of the prospect of playing in
full-scale games. However, they often spend much more time practicing
component skills than full-scale games. It seems important both to motivation
and to learning to practice one's skills from time to time in full context, but
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personal/ja/mIsapplied.html
Page: 2E
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
this is not a reason to make this the principal mechanism of learning.
While there may be motivational merit to embedding mathematical practice in
complex situations, Geary (1995) notes that there is a lot of reason to doubt
how intrinsically motivating complex mathematics is to most students in any
context. The kind of sustained practice required to develop excellence in an
advanced domain is not inherently motivating to most individuals and requires
substantial family and cultural support (Ericsson, Krampe, & Tesch-Romer,
1993). Geary argues, as have others (e.g., Bahrick & Hall, 1991; Stevenson &
Stigler, 1992), that it is this difference in cultural support that accounts for the
large difference in mathematics achievement between Asian and American
children.
Contrary to the contention that knowledge can always be communicated best
in complex learning situations, the evidence shows that:
A learner who is having difficulty with components can easily be
overwhelmed by the processing demands of a complex task. Further, to the
extent that many components are well mastered, the student wastes much time
repeating these mastered components to get an opportunity to practice the few
components that need additional effort.
There are reasons sometimes to practice skills in their complex setting. Some
of the reasons are motivational and some reflect the skills that are unique to
the complex situation. While it seems important both to motivation and to
learning to practice skills from time to time in full context, this is not a reason
to make this the principal mechanism of learning.
Claim 4: It is not possible to apply standard evaluations to assess
learning
The denial of the possibility of objective evaluation could be the most radical
and far-reaching of the constructivist claims. We put it last because it is not
clear how radically this principle is interpreted by all constructivists.
Certainly, some constructivists have engaged in rather standard evaluations of
constructivist learning interventions (e.g., Cobb, Wood, Yackel, Nicholls,
Wheatley, Trigaitti, & Perlwitz, 1992). However, others are very
uncomfortable with the idea of evaluation. As Jonassen (1992) writes:
"If you believe, as radical constructivists do, that no objective reality is
uniformly interpretable by all learners, then assessing the acquisition of such a
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonal/ja/misapplied.html
27
Page: 2;
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
reality is not possible. A less radical view suggests that learners will interpret
perspectives differently, so evaluation processes should accommodate a wider
variety of response options." (p. 144).
In the hands of the most radical constructivists, Claim 4 implies that it is
impossible to evaluate any educational hypothesis empirically because any
such test necessarily requires a commitment to some arbitrary,
culturally-determined, set of values. In the hands of the more moderate
constructivists, the claim manifests itself in advocacy of focusing evaluation
on the process of learning more than the product, in what are considered
"authentic" tasks, and by involving multiple perspectives in the evaluation.
This milder perspective calls for emphasis on more subjective and less
precisely defined instruments of evaluation. While we share with most
educators their instinctive distaste of four-alternative forced-choice questions
and we agree that mathematics assessment should go beyond merely testing
computational skills, we question whether the very open-ended assessment
being advocated as the proper alternative will lead to either more accurate or
more culture-free assessment. The fundamental problem is a failure to specify
precisely the competence being tested for and a reliance on subjective
judgment instead. We examined a number of recent papers in Wirzup and
Streit (1992) addressing this issue. In one paper, Resnick, Briars, and Lesgold
(1992) present two examples of answers that are objectively equivalent (and
receive equal scores in their objective assessment scheme). However, they are
uncomfortable with this equal assessment and feel a subjective component
should be added so one answer would receive a higher score because it
displayed greater "communication proficiency." Although the "better" answer
had neater handwriting, one might well judge it as just more long-winded than
the "worse" answer. "Communication proficiency" is very much in the eyes of
the beholder. In another paper, Dossey (1992), in explaining the new NAEP
open-ended scoring, states that a student will be given 50% (2 points) for the
right answer if the justification for the answer is "not understandable" but will
be given 100% (4 points) for the wrong answer if it "does not reflect
misunderstanding of either the problem or how to implement the strategy, but
rather seems to be a copying error or computational error." While we are
sympathetic with the sentiments behind such ideas, such subjective judgments
will open the door to a great deal of cultural bias in assessment (Rist, 1970).
Anytime the word "seems" appears in an assessment, it should be a red flag
that the assessors do not know what they are looking for. The
information-processing approach would advocate precisely specifying what
one is looking for in terms of a cognitive model and then precisely testing for
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personaUja/mIsapplied.html
28
Page: 2E
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
that.
Another sign of the constructivist's discomfort with evaluation manifests itself
in the motto that the teacher is the novice and the student the expert (e.g., see
papers in von Glasersfeld, 1991). The idea is that every student gathers equal
value from every learning experience. The teacher's task is to come to
understand and value what the student has learned. As Confrey (1991) writes:
"seldom are students' responses careless or capricious. We must seek out their
systematic qualities which are typically grounded in the conceptions of the
student...frequently when students' responses deviate from our expectations,
they possess the seeds of alternative approaches which can be compelling,
historically supported and legitimate if we are willing to challenge our own
assumptions." (p. 122)
or as Cobb, Wood, and Yackel (1991) write:
"The approach respects that students are the best judges of what they find
problematical and encourages them to construct solutions that they find
acceptable given their current ways of knowing." (p. 158).
If the student is supposed to move, in the course of the learning experiences,
from a lower to a higher level of competence, we wonder why the student's
judgments of the acceptability of solutions are particularly valid. While we
value the teacher who can appreciate children's individuality, see their insights
and motivate them to do their best and to value learning, there must be definite
educational goals. More generally, if the "student as judge" attitude were to
dominate education, it would no longer be clear when instruction had failed
and when it had succeeded, when it was moving forward and when backward.
It is one thing to understand why the student, at a particular stage in
understanding, is doing what he or she is doing. It is quite another matter to
help the student understand how to move from processes that are "satisfactory"
in a limited range of tasks to processes that are more effective over a wider
range. As Resnick (1994) argues, many concepts which children naturally
come to (e.g., that motion implies force) are not what the culture expects of
education and that in these cases "education must follow a different path: still
constructivist in the sense that simple telling will not work, but much less
dependent on untutored discovery and exploration (p. 489)."
Again, we find important empirical reasons for proceeding in assessment in
somewhat different ways from those recommended by constructivitsts, and
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonalia/mIsapplied.html
29
Page: a
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
particularly, the more radical among them:
We all share an instinctive distaste for four-alternative forced-choice
questions, but these are not required to attain validity or reliability in
asssessment. Accurate and culture-free assessment does requires, however that
the competence being tested for to be specified precisely without undue
reliance on subjective judgment. Subjective judgments open the door to
cultural bias in assessment
It cannot be assumed that students' judgments of the acceptability of solutions
are particularly valid. If the "student as judge" view were adopted, it would no
longer be clear when instruction had failed and when it had succeeded
Summary: Contructivism
To argue for radical constructivism seems to us to engender deep
contradictions. Radical constructivists cannot argue for any particular agenda
if they deny a consensus as to values. The very act of arguing for a position is
to engage in a value-loaded instructional behavior. It would seem that radical
constructivists should present us with data about the consequences of various
educational alternatives and allow us to construct our own interpretations. (But
data beyond anecdotes are rare in such constructivist writings.)
It is not clear how many of those who describe themselves as constructivists
really subscribe to an outright rejection of evaluation and instruction. A less
radical contructivism may contain no contradictions and may bear some truth.
However, to repeat our conclusion with respect to situated learning, such a
moderate constructivism contains little that is new and ignores a lot that is
already known.
What is to be Done?
In the preceding pages of this paper, we have questioned a number of the basic
claims of situated learning and constructivism, but our own recommendations
for educational research and practice have mainly been left implicit. In this
final section we set forth briefly a program of research and action that is based
on the information-processing approach to of cognitive. We will address
research first, then instructional practice.
Recommendations for Research
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personal/ja/misapplied.html
30
Page: 3C
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
Educational research needs to understand both the component processes that
are involved in intellectual tasks and the ways in which these processes must
interact for good performance on complex tasks. Of course, as most complex
skills are hierarchical in structure, with component skills within component
skills, and so on, the inquiries must be carried out at several levels. At the
highest level, we should study the structure of real-world skills in both
laboratory and real-world settings. Such study requires clear statements of the
educational goals--the knowledge and skills aimed at--and careful design of
procedures for assessing the degree to which the goals have been achieved.
The research will need to study performance at various skill levels, from
novice to expert, and to employ a variety of observational methods, including
the analysis of verbal and video protocols and the computer modeling of
processes methods that have only recently been refined as a part of the
psychological research armatorium. These methods can yield a specification of
the cognitive structures which we want students to acquire. With this cognitive
specification in hand, we can use recent learning-by-doing theories in
psychology to guide instruction.
It is also important that we do careful empirical study of the instructional
programs developed under the information-processing approach and evaluate
them carefully in comparison with alternatives. Evaluation should include not
only (and perhaps not mainly) the immediate learning effects of instruction for
tasks like those used in training, but particularly (1) the retention of
knowledge and skills after a substantial time has elapsed from the completion
of training (months or even years), and (2) the transferability of the knowledge
and skills to a broader range of tasks than those used in the instruction. To
take an obvious example from mathematics, research on calculus instruction
should be evaluated in large measure (except, possibly, for mathematics
majors) by assessing the ability and propensity of students to use the calculus
successfully when it is relevant in their work in physics or economics.
There is unanimous agreement that what is desired is not rote learning but
learning with understanding. We need research that will tell us how to assess
better than we do now when a student is performing by rote, and when and to
what degree understanding has been achieved. For a long time there has been
evidence (Katona, 1940) that knowledge and skill acquired with understanding
is retained better and transferred better than that which is acquired by rote. If
this relation can be further validated, tests of retention and transfer can be used
to assess understanding and, conversely, achievement of understanding can be
used as a predictor of retention and transfer. It would be highly desirable,
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonalia/mIsapplled.html
31
Page: 31
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
also, to devise procedures that would help students to assess their own levels
of understanding.
Among the processes that have been shown by recent research to have
considerable power in speeding the learning process and encouraging the
learner to achieve deeper levels of understanding are learning from examples
and learning by doing. Computer tutors, using these and other methods, are
beginning to show impressive effectiveness, and methods of these sorts can
also be implemented with paper and pencil.
There is almost universal consensus that only the active learner is a successful
learner. Proponents of situated learning and constructivism have proposed a
number of modes of instruction that are aimed at encouraging initiative from
students and interaction among them. While we have criticized some of the
assumptions underlying current proposals for "child-centered" procedures as
both implausible and lacking empirical evidence, we fully agree that the social
structure of the environment in which education takes place is of utmost
importance from a cognitive, and especially from a motivational, standpoint.
Recommendations for Instruction
We need to be more tentative in our recommendations for instructional
methods than in our recommendations for research. Nevertheless, there is
already considerable empirical support for the superiority, relative to
mainstream classroom methods, of a number of procedures (like the
learning-from-examples and learning-by-doing methods already mentioned)
that are ready for classroom testing on a large scale.
The use with children of experimental methods, that is, methods that have not
been finally assessed and found effective, might seem difficult to justify. Yet
the traditional methods we use in the classroom every day have exactly this
characteristic--they are highly experimental in that we know very little about
their educational efficacy in comparison with alternative methods. There is
widespread cynicism among students and even among practiced teachers about
the effectiveness of lecturing or repetitive drill (which we would distinguish
from carefully designed practice), yet these methods are in widespread use.
Equally troublesome, new "theories" of education are introduced into schools
every day (without labeling them as experiments) on the basis of their
philosophical or common-sense plausibility but without genuine empirical
support. We should make a larger place for responsible experimentation that
draws on the available knowledge--it deserves at least as large a place as we
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personal/jarmisapplied.html
32
Page: 3;
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
now provide for faddish, unsystematic and unassessed informal "experiments"
or educational "reforms." We would advocate the creation of a "FEA" on
analogy to the FDA which would require well designed clinical trials for every
educational "drug" that is introduced into the market place.
Overall Conclusions
Given that so much educational reform is presented as a response to the
excesses of behaviorism, it is interesting to read the conception of good
education from one of the foremost proponents of behaviorism, B. F. Skinner.
In his classic Novel, Walden II, intended to innovate behaviorism, Skinner's
hero Frazier says:
Since our children remain happy, energetic, and curious, we don't need to
teach "subjects" at all. We teach only the techniques of learning and thinking.
As for geography, literature, the sciences--we give our children opportunity
and guidance, and they learn for themselves. In that we dispense with half the
teachers required under the old system, and the education is incomparably
better. Our children are not neglected, but they're seldom, if ever, taught
anything.
Education in Walden Two is part of the life of the community. We don't need
to resort to trumped-up life experiences. Our children begin to work at a very
early age. It's no hardship; its accepted as readily as sport or play. A good
share of our education goes on in workshops, laboratories, and fields. Its part
of the Walden Two code to encourage children in all the arts and crafts.
(Skinner, 1948, p. 119-120).
Cognitive psychology rose up in response to the simplistic conception of
human exemplified by the behaviorist views of Skinner, which he represented
in Frazier's views. We see that influential schools have arisen, claiming a basis
in cognitive psychology, that are advocating Frazier's program but which have
almost no grounding in cognitive theory and at least as little grounding in
empirical fact. This is particularly grievous because we think
information-processing psychology has a lot to offer to mathematics
education.
Information-processing psychology would propose that any effective
educational practice should begin with detailed, precise cognitive task
analysis. This requires first identifying what competences mathematics
education seeks to foster. Having these specified, one then has to engage in
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personal/ja/misapplled.html
33
Page: 3:
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
the labor-intensive process of developing cognitive models that embodied
these skills. With these in hand, one can bring to bear well-established
principles of learning to facilitate students' acquisition of the cognitive
components.
There are a number of ways to implement this agenda. One of the authors
(Anderson, Corbett, Koedinger & Pelletier, 1995) has been involved in an
effort to follow this program in designing computer tutors in America.
Another of the authors (Zhu & Simon, 1988) has been involved in an effort to
achieve this in China with paper-and-pencil technology. Both of these efforts
have resulted in significant achievement gains--students have learned more and
faster than they did by traditional methods. While there have been such local
successes, we must conclude that this kind of effort will fail to have any
meaningful impact on mathematical competence in America until there is
some consensus on the goals of mathematics education and a careful and
detailed cognitive analysis has been launched of how to achieve these goals.
Current situated and constructivist trends in mathematics education are
preventing this from happening because they refuse to focus on details and
precise specifications, believing that this would amount to accepting the
supposedly discredited tenets of decomposition and decontextualization.
The evidence for such information-processing approaches to education,
however incomplete, is enormously stronger than the evidence for the opposite
approaches, supposedly based in cognitive psychology, that are currently
dominating discussions of mathematics education. And this is our main
message: A program of educational reform is being adopted with weak
empirical and theoretical bases while a better, and better validated, program
stands ready for further development and application, and that is a situation
that should be and can be altered.
References
Anderson, J. R. (1983). The architecture of cognition. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Anderson, J. R. (1993). Rules of the Mind
.
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Anderson, J. R., Corbett, A. T., Koedinger, K., & Pelletier, R. (1995).
Cognitive tutors: Lessons learned. The Journal of Learning Sciences, 4,
167-207.
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personal/ja/misapplied.html
34
Page: 34
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
Ausubel, D. P. (1968). Educational psychology: A cognitive view. New
York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Bahrick, H. P. & Hall, L. K. (1991). Lifetime maintenance of high school
mathematics content. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 120,
22-33.
Bassok, M. & Holyoak, K. J. (1989). Transfer of domain-specific problem
solving procedures. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory,
and Cognition, 16, 522-533.
Biederman, I., & Shiffrar, M. (1987). Sexing day-old chicks: A case study
and expert systems analysis of a difficult perceptual learning task. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 13, 640-645.
Bjork, R. A. & Richardson-Klavehn, A. (1989). On the puzzling relationship
between environment context and human memory. In C. Izawa (Ed.) Current
issues in cognitive processes: The Tulane Flowerree Symposium on
Cognition. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Bobrow, D. G. & Bower, G. H. (1969). Comprehension and recall of
sentences. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 80, 455-461.
Brousseau, G. (1984). The crucial role of the didactical contract in the
analysis and construction of situations in teaching and learning mathematics.
In H.-G. Steiner (Ed.), Theory of mathematics education (pp. 110-119).
Occasional paper 54. Bielefeld, Germany: University of Bielefeld, Institut fiir
Didaktik de Mathematik.
Brown, A. L. (1994). The advancement of learning. Educational Researcher,
23, 4-12.
Brown, A. L. & Campione, J. C. (1994). Guided discovery in a community
of learners. In K. McGilly (ed.) Classroom lessons: Integrating cognitive
theory and classroom practice , Chapter 9, 229-270. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Brown, J. S., Collins, A. & Diguid, P. (1988). Situated cognition and the
culture of learning. Technical report form the Institute for Research on
Learning, No. IRL88-0008.
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personaUja/mIsapplied.html
35
Page: 3f
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
Carraher, T. N., Carraher, D. W. & Schliemann, A. D. (1985). Mathematics
in the streets and in the schools. British Journal of Developmental
Psychology, 3, 21-29.
Card, S. K., Moran, T. P. & Newell, A. (1983). The psychology of
human-computer interaction. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Charney, D.H., Reder, L. M., & Kusbit, G.W. (1990). Goal setting and
procedure selection in acquiring computer skills: A Comparison of tutorials,
problem-solving, and learner exploration. Cognition and Instruction, 7(4) ,
323-342.
Cheng, P. W., Holyoak, K. J., Nisbett, R. E., & Oliver, L. M. (1986).
Pragmatic versus syntactic approaches to training deductive reasoning.
Cognitive Psychol ogy, 18, 293 328.
Cobb, P. (1990). A constructivist perspective on information-processing
theories of mathematical activity. International Journal of Educational
Research, 14, 67-92.
Cobb, P., Wood, T., & Yackel, E. (1991). A constructivist approach to
second grade mathematics. In E. von Glasersfeld (Ed.) Radical
constructivism in mathematics education. D ordrecht, The Netherlands:
Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Cobb, P., Wood, T., Yackel, E., Nicholls, J., Wheatley, G., Trigatti, B., &
Perlwitz, M. (1991). Assessment of a problem-centered second grade
mathematics project. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 22,
3-29.
Cobb, P., Yackel, E. & Wood, T. (1992). A constructivist alternative to the
representational view of mind in mathematics education. Journal for
Research in Mathematics Education, 23, 2-33.
Collins, A., Brown, J. S., & Newman, S. (1989). Cognitive apprenticeship:
Teaching students the craft of reading, writing, and mathematics. In L. B.
Resnick (Ed.), Knowing, learning, and instruction: Essays in honor of Robert
Glaser. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Confrey, J. (1991). Learning to listen: A student's understanding of powers of
ten. In E. von Glasersfeld (Ed.), Radical constructivism in mathematics
http://aapsy.cmu.edurpersonal/jaimisapplied.html
36
Page: 3E
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
education., p. 111-138. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic
Publishers.
Dossey, J. A. (1992). Assessing mathematics: enhancing understanding. In I.
Wirszup & R. Streit (Eds.). Developments in school mathematics education
around the world, Volume 3., p. 208-222. Proceedings of the Third UCSMP
International Conference on Mathematics Education. Reston, VA: NCTM.
Duncker, K. (1945). On problem-solving (translated by L. S. Lees).
Psychological Monographs, 58, No. 270.
Eich, E. (1985). Context, memory, and integrated item/context imagery.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 11,
764-770.
Elio, R. (1986). Representation of similar well-learned cognitive procedures.
Cognitive Science, 10, 41-74.
Ericcson, K. A., Krampe, R. T. & Tesche-Romer, C. (1993). The role of
deliberate practice in the acquisition of expert performance. Psychological
Review, 100, 363-406.
Ericcson, K. A. & Simon, H. A. (1993). Protocol analysis: Verbal reports as
data, Revised edition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Feigenbaum, E. A. & Simon, H. A. (1984). EPAM-like models of
recognition and learning. Cognitive Science, 8, 305-336.
Fernandez, A. & Glenberg, A. M. (1985). Changing environmental context
does not reliably affect memory. Memory & Cognition, 13, 333-345.
Fong, G. T., Krantz, D. H., & Nisbett, R. E. (1986). The effects of statistical
training on thinking about everyday problems. Cognitive Psychology, 18,
253-292.
Geary, D. C. (1995). Reflections of evolution and culture in children's
cognition. American Psychologist, 50, 24-37.
Gick, M. L. & Holyoak, K. J. (1980). Analogical problem solving.
Cognitive Psychology, 12, 306-355.
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personalijaimisapplied.html
37
Page: 3i
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
Gick, M. L. & Holyoak, K. J. (1983). Schema induction and analogical
transfer. Cognitive Psychology, 15, 1-38.
Godden, D. R. & Baddeley, A. D. (1975). Context-dependent memory in two
natural environments: On land and under water. British Journal of
Psychology, 66, 325-331.
Hayes, J. R. (1985). The problems in teaching general skills. In J. Segal, S.
Chipman & R. Glaser (Eds.), Thinking and learning, Vol. 2. Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Hayes, J. R. & Simon, H. A. (1977). Psychological differences among
problem isomorphs. In J. Caste llan, D. B. Pisoni, and G. Potts (Eds.)
Cognitive theory, volume 2. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Hendrickson, G. & Schroeder, W. H. (1941). Transfer training in learning to
hit a submerged target. Journal of Educational Psychology, 32, 205-213.
Hiebert, J., Wearne, D., Carpenter, T. P., Fennema, E., Fuson, K., Human,
P., Olivier, A., & Murray, H. (1994). Authentic problem solving in
mathematics. Presented at the annual meeting of the American Educational
Research Association (AERA), New Orleans.
Hunter, J. E. & Hunter, R. F. (1984). Validity and utility of alternative
predictors of job performance. Psychological Bulletin, 96, 72-98.
Jonassen, D. H. (1992). Evaluating constructivist learning. In T. M. Duffy &
D. H. Jonassen (Eds.). Constructivism and the technology of instruction,
Chapter 12. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Johnson, D. W. & Johnson, R. T. (1989). Cooperation and competition:
Theory and research. Edina, MN: Interaction Book Company.
Judd, C. H. (1908). The relation of special training to general intelligence.
Educational Review, 36, 28-42.
Katona, G. Organizing and memorizing
University Press.
.
(1940) New York, NY: Columbia
Knerr, C. M., Morrison, J. E., Mumaw, R. J. Stein, D. J., Sticha, P. J.,
Hoffman, R. G., Buede, D. M. & Holding, D. M. (1987). Simulation-based
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personal/ja/misapplied.html
38
Page: a
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
research in part -task training. AF HRL-TR-86-12, AD-B107293. Brooks Air
Force Base, TX: Air Force Human Resources Laboratory.
Kotovsky, K. & Fallside, D. (1989). Representation and transfer in problem
solving. In D. Klahr, D. & K. Kotovsky (Eds.) Complex information
processing: The impact of Herbert A. Simon (pp. 69-108). Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Larkin, J. H. (1981). Enriching formal knowledge: A model for learning to
solve textbook physics problems. In J. R. Anderson (Ed.) Cognitive Skills
and their Acquisition . Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1981.
Lave, J. (1986). Experiments, tests, jobs and chores: How we learn to do what
we do. In K. Borman and J. Reisman (Eds.), Becoming a worker. Norwood,
NJ: Albex.
Lave, J. (1988). Cognition in practice: Mind, mathematics, and culture in
everyday life. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Lesh, R. & Lamon, S. J. (1992). Assessment of authentic performance in
school mathematics. Washington, DC: AAAS Press.
Lesh, R. & Zawojeski, J. S. (1992). Problem solving. In T. R. Post (Ed),
Teaching mathematics in grades K-8: Research-based methods. p. 49-88.
Needham Heights, MA: Allyn and Bacon.
National Research Council (1994). Learning, remembering, believing:
Enhancing human performance. In D. Druckman & R. A. Bjork (Eds.).
Washington, DC: National Academy Press.
Newell, A. & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Patrick, J. (1992). Training: Research and practice. San Diego, CA:
Academic Press.
Pirolli, P. L., & Anderson, J. R. (1985). The role of practice in fact retrieval.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, & Cognition, 11 ,
136-153.
Reder, L. M. & Klatzky, R. (1994) Transfer: Training for Performance. In D.
http://act.psy.cmu.edu/personalia/misapplled.html
39
Page: 3f
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
Druckman & R. A. Bjork (Eds.) Learning, Remembering, Believing:
Enhancing team and individual performance (pp. 25-56). Washington, DC:
National Academy Press.
Reder, L.M. & Ritter, F. (1992) What determines initial feeling of knowing?
Familiarity with question terms, not with the answer. Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 18, 435-451.
Reed, S. K., & Actor, C.A. (1991) Use of examples and procedures in
problem solving. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, &
Cognition, 17 , 753-766.
Reed, S. K., Ernst, G. W., & Banjeri, R. (1974). The role of analogy in
transfer between similar problem states. Cognitive Psychology, 6, 436-450
Resnick, L. B. (1994). Situated rationalism: biological and social preparation
for learning. Mapping the mind: domain specificity in cognition and culture
(474-493). Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press.
Resnick, L. B., Briars, D. & Lesgold, S. (1992). Certifying accomplishments
in mathematics: The new standards examining system. In I. Wirszup & R.
Streit (Eds.). Developments in school mathematics education around the
world, Volume 3., p. 186-207. Proceedings of the Third UCSMP
International Conference on Mathematics Education. Reston, VA: NCTM.
Resnick, L. B. & Resnick, D. P. (1992). Assessing the thinking curriculum:
New tools for educational reform. In B. R. Gifford & M.C. O'Connor (Eds.)
Changing assessments: Alternative views of aptitude, achievement and
instruction. Boston, MA: Kluwer.
Rist, R.C. (1970). Student social class and teacher expectations: the
self-fulfilling prophecy in ghetto education. Harvard Educational Review,
40 , 411-451.
Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Salas, E., Dickinson, T. L., Converse, S. A. & Tannenbaum, S. I. (1993)
Toward an understanding of team performance and training. In R. W. Swezey
and E. Salas (Eds.), Teams: Their training and performance. Norwood, NJ:
Ablex.
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonal/jeJmisapplied.html
40
Page: 4C
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
Salomon, G., & Globerson, T. (1989). When teams do not function the way
they ought to. International Journal of Educational Research, 13, 89-98.
Saufley, W. H., Otaka, S. R., & Bavaresco, J. L. (1985). Context effects:
Classroom tests and context independence. Memory & Cognition, 13,
522-528.
Schoenfeld, A. H. (1985). Mathematical problem solving. New York:
Academic Press.
Searle, J. R. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 3 , 414-424.
Shepard, L. A. (1991). Psychometricians' beliefs about learning. Educational
Researcher, 20, 2-16.
Silver, E. A. (1987). Foundations of cognitive theory and research for
mathematics problem-solving. In A. H. Schoenfeld (Ed.) Cognitive science
and mathematics education. Hillsdale, NJ: LEA.
Simon, H. A. (1967). Motivational and emotional controls of cognition.
Psychological Review, 74, 29-39.
Simon, H. A. (1981). The sciences of the artificial Second edition.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Simon, H. A. (1994). The bottleneck of attention: Connecting thought with
motivation. In W. E. Spaulding (Ed.). Integrative views of motivation,
cognition, and emotion. Lincoln, NE: University of Nebraska Press.
Simon, H. A. & Feigenbaum, E. A. (1964). In information-processing theory
of some effects of similarity, familiarization, meaningfulness in verbal
learning. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 3, 385-396.
Singley, M. K. & Anderson, J. R. (1989). Transfer of Cognitive Skill
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
.
Skinner, B. F. (1948). Walden two. New York: Macmillan, Co.
Slamecka, N. J. & Graf, P. (1978). The generation effect: Delineation of a
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersoneliarmisepplied.html
41
Page: 41
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
phenomenon. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and
Cognition, 4, 592-604.
Slamecka, N. J. & Katsaiti, L. T. (1987). The generation effect as an artifact
of selective displaced rehearsal. Journal of Memory and Language, 26,
589-607.
Slavin, R. E. (1990). Cooperative learning: Theory, research and practice.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Smith, S. B. (1986). An analysis of transfer between Tower of Hanoi
isomorphs. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Carnegie-Mellon University,
Pittsburgh.
Smith, S. M., Glenberg, A., & Bjork, R. A. (1978). Environmental context
and human memory. Memory & Cognition, 6, 342-353.
Stein, B. S. & Bransford, J. D. (1979). Constraints on effective elaboration:
Effects of precision and subject generation. Journal of Verbal Learning and
Verbal Behavior, 18, 769-777.
Stevenson, H. W., & Stigler, J. W. (1992). The learning gap: Why our
schools are failing and what we can learn from Japanese and Chinese
education. New York: Summit Books.
Thorndike, E. L, & Woodworth, R. S. (1901). The influence of improvement
in one mental function upon the efficiency of other functions. Psychological
Review, 9, 374-382.
Vera, A. H. & Simon, H. A. (1993). Situated action: A symbolic
interpretation. Cognitive Science, 17, 7-48.
von Glasersfeld, E. (1991). Radical constructivism in mathematics
education. D ordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Weisberg, R. DiCamillo, M. & Phillips, D. (1985). Transferring old
associations to new situations: a non-automatic process. Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 17, 219-228.
Wirszup, I. & Streit, R. (1992). Developments in school mathematics
education around the world, Volume 3. Proceedings of the Third UCSMP
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonaUjarmisapplied.html
42
Page: 41
Tuesday, November 30, 1999
International Conference on Mathematics Education. Reston, VA: NCTM.
Woodworth, R. S. (1938). Experimental psychology
Holt & Company.
.
New York, NY: Henry
Zhu, X. & Simon, H. A. (1988). Learning mathematics from examples and by
doing. Cognition and Instruction, 4 , 137-166.
http://act.psy.cmu.edurpersonal/ja/misapplied.html
Y3
o/
b14 220263
1'2
p.02
412 268 2844
DR. J. R. ANDERSON »' CMU
APR-19-00 09:39 AM
ERi
03
PAGE
US. Department of Education
--
IC
,--
Office of Educational Researcr: and Improvement PERI;
National Library of Education (NEE)
Educational Resources Information Center (Er/C,)
REPRODUCTION RELEASE
(Specifc Document)
I. DOCUM NT IDENTIFICATION:
Title:
rrNG,) ,
,
rce.
1,411kc.e." I. a/ /Pilaff/led-(1/5'
A kl/td
II. REPRO UCTION RELEASE:
in 'row to d serneuite 45 Widely AI possible timely and signifltertlfratarists
of Ihtaree1 Lia the educatIotet cerimenity, aecymeeta eantivritme In tee
urmi of the ERIC system, Reeemmes kl education (RIM, are
whiny made evadable to.nere in microrelM, reproduCOO paper copy,
end electronic
le, Ind sold treouSh the ERIC Document Reproduction
Smut* +ELM). Credit it given to the !scum of each d000Mont, AIM, V
reproducton
Ill'aarikAted one of the following rOtlCii .6 aPfIntd to the docIpT110{
mentitiy Asti,
Ifoorrieslor
Of the Pace
Trre Welt
Amato
EERMISS ON
0135EMINAT
gran*/ to reprodus end tteternInate the identified 4:mument aloatie CHECK
ONE Of the following three eatIOns End On
'glom HAN wit! he
Tr. move sadly Mown tow vair bs
WOW 10 el Level PA lonvapenu
OFIEPROCUCe ANC
MATERIA. WAS
RAVE.") er
Th:E Z71)
kigt.:RMATI
nit sample Naha thaw below will be
IONA. RE3OuPtCE5
CEN7BR +ERIC:
at the bottont
Ifinerno rut ..einl0la It0.lCrrer to
Pe RIA1351C NI TO PtEPRODUa AND
DISErht NATE ''HIS MATERIAL IN
MICFOFICHI. AND .0
C7R011 IC MEDIA
;OR ERIc SCILLECtiON SUBEC.RISERS DNi-v
IAS 454N GRANTED Elf
,
PG RMI as tOrii TO REFERCOUCE AND
ItSEMINATE THIS AtATERIAL IN
;int. v WA NE.04 slel.AltTee aY
.10
NZ?,
el:4k
.,'NE 5 :,,t)C.A TICINAL RESCUFCSd
l'INAMATIC.14 CENSER ;01,7:)
TAE EDUCATIDNAl. RE3011RCES
NFoRVATION CENTER
12B
yer
Ssia SO, imiLl 1
IPSO 41110f6fisksm
midi i.e,
Lev el 24
Permatint reerorsvaa
4 Sr aim/ CRIC atchi.or
Nei end paper
.II 1125
tine& Are ter L !NM IA /4)14.4 pamitnfis reproduction
ClistarnIneuran in rolcIdeclia end
4140v:cue media
fet ENO arching cc Keaton eubteabars nary
tried, item for Levet at ream, arunvelni
144it.OUSIOn r4 1111.7netaitlan h relteertaba ory
Oceunien4 van bn en:4mm! Si Inficarea provided niprcduction vahly penmen
Pernlionior. 10 rWsIdisse a ereAred. tut Auk' In rasidted. etaariente will De preowned el.evei
iI.mfI41 IS
.....- .10.1-...-m..=.M.I...111111
tau b the Caucadoral h'esdoirces Infonnarion Canter (ERIC) ncmclushi p(07774diun fu
reproduce in disseminate INS dccumenl
end above. Reproduch6n !toff, the ERIC
mkrotthe or electronic media by peracns other
ERC empooyeed and-i4e ay3tem
MOMS venristion hum the aapyrigla WOK Ereagen is Teel, Icr lunlicel reprooVrAlanman
ty libraries and Other novice 40;ocas
ntonnstion needs of adircatwa iR resporhm to escapes inquirial
1.10Al
Sign
hers,-1
111...
0161166144Mairetkiiis.
LJ6114.12J2112j:aLjckOfe5SCY)
pleaSe
..
114611AX"IIIJA4-6'cutn.
Etpi.wa_.7
Hiat msb
1571
Wen