HUMAN AFFAIRS 25, 110–120, 2015
DOI: 10.1515/humaff-2015-0009
RULE-FOLLOWING, MEANING CONSTITUTION,
AND ENACTION
PATRIZIO LO PRESTI
Abstract: The paper submits a criticism of the standard formulation of Wittgenstein’s rule-following
paradox. According to the standard formulation, influenced by Kripke, the paradox invites us to consider what
mental or behavioral items could constitute meaning. The author proposes instead an enactivist understanding
of the paradox. On this account there is no essential gap between mental items and behavioral patterns
such that the paradox enforces a choice between meaning being constituted either internally ‘in mind,’ or
externally ‘in behavior.’ The paper begins with an introduction to the paradox and then presents arguments
against standard solutions. It ends with the enactivist proposal, admitting that although much more needs to
be said before it can be established as a full-fledged alternative, it nonetheless holds some promise both for
revising our understanding of the paradox and for the formulation of a novel solution.
Keywords: Wittgenstein; rule-following; meaning; enaction; interaction.
The rule-following paradox (Wittgenstein, 1953) is arguably the most “radical” problem for
modern philosophy (Kripke, 1982, p. 1), its “iconoclastic” consequences unmatched (Pettit,
2002, p. 31). Allegedly at stake are the foundations of mathematics (Wittgenstein, 1956),
rules of logic, and meaningful language. The paradox has even been called an “antinomy of
pure reason” (Boghossian, 2012, p. 47), and a modern “scandal of philosophy” (Peacocke,
2012, p. 66).
Here is the passage in which Wittgenstein formulates the paradox:
This was our paradox: no course of action could be determined by a rule, because every course
of action can be made out to accord with the rule. The answer was: if everything can be made
out to accord with the rule, then it can also be made out to conflict with it. And so there would
be neither accord nor conflict here (Wittgenstein, 1953, § 201).
The reasoning preceding the quoted section concerns language meaning. The question is:
how can symbols have definite meanings such that in using one now I can (fail to) use it in
accord with that meaning? Wittgenstein notices that token symbol uses initiate many paths
for future use, which can be made out to accord or conflict with past uses. So, there is in
principle an indefinite number of interpretations of symbols or words that are all within the
set that can be made out to accord and conflict with past use. Hence, no interpretation of past
110
© Institute for Research in Social Communication, Slovak Academy of Sciences
use can constitute a rule that singles out one definite meaning. Hence the paradox: while we
use words in definite ways and do so quite successfully to communicate in everyday practice,
there seems to be no rule we may rely on as a determiner of correct use.
Wittgenstein responds to these considerations in the second half of the quoted section:
It can be seen that there is a misunderstanding here from the mere fact that in the course of
our argument we give one interpretation after another; as if each one contended us at least for
a moment, until we thought of yet another standing behind it. What this shows is that there is
a way of grasping a rule which is not an interpretation, but which is exhibited in what we call
“obeying the rule” and “going against it” in actual cases (Wittgenstein, 1953, § 201).
Perhaps, then, we might better understand what constitutes meaning by abandoning
the idea that it is constituted by interpretation. We then avoid the problematic property
of interpretations that they are themselves correct or incorrect with respect to what they
interpret (Wittgenstein, 1953, § 198), according to a rule—a property that threatens to gear
our investigations towards a regress of interpretations. The question then is: with what do
we replace interpretations as constitutive of meaning? How are what we call ‘obeying’ and
‘going against’ the rule exhibited in actual cases? In the closing three lines of the quoted
passage Wittgenstein makes an inference that might hold the clue:
Hence there is an inclination to say: every action according to the rule is an interpretation. But
we ought to restrict the term “interpretation” to the substitution of one expression of the rule
for another (Wittgenstein, 1953, § 201).
It is the tendency to interpret ‘interpretation’ as a mental act that constitutes meaning
that spells trouble. Thus Wittgenstein urges us to limit ‘interpretation’ to substitutions of
one expression of rule. Rule-expressions include doing that which accords with or violates
customs and practices established over time (Wittgenstein, 1953, §§ 199, 217, 219). Again,
what is correct or incorrect with respect to custom behavior, linguistic or otherwise, ought
not to be thought of as behavior that accords or conflicts with a mental act of interpretation,
lest we fall back into the original dilemma. Rather we ought to think of ‘obeying’ and ‘going
against’ practice and customs as ‘exhibiting’ actual case-by-case agreement on meaning.
But if being in accord with or in violation of a rule does not consist in an interpretation
in the sense of mental acts that distinguish accord from conflict, then the question becomes:
what makes the everyday engagement and exhibiting of a rule different and insulated from
the worry that, really, there are no rules? Kripke (1982, pp. 86-87) holds that since no mental
act or behavioral disposition could constitute rule-following we have to abandon the idea of a
“straight” solution to the rule-following paradox. A straight solution would be one according
to which there are necessary and sufficient conditions for saying that a behavior is a case of
rule-following. Kripke presents the problem of rule-following as a choice between the Scylla
of rule-following consisting in mental acts or intentions, on the one hand, and the Charybdis
of rule-following consisting in behavioral dispositions on the other. He writes, concerning
the addition function:
if the sceptic is right, the concepts of meaning and of intending one function rather than
another will make no sense. For the sceptic holds that no fact about my past history—nothing
111
that was ever in my mind, or in my external behavior—establishes that I meant plus rather than
quus … But if this is correct, there can of course be no fact about which function I meant, and
if there can be no fact about which particular function I meant in the past, there can be none in
the present either (Kripke, 1982, p. 13).
Abstracting from this particular example, we clearly see the two horns of a dilemma.
The first is to suppose that something ‘internal to mind’ constitutes meaning. The other is to
suppose that something in ‘external behavior’ constitutes meaning—presumably, ‘external’
in the sense of what is left of what I do when I have abstracted from my doings the intentions
that premise the action. These two options are what Kripke calls “straight” solutions to the
paradox. He rejects both in favor of a “skeptical” solution; one in which no fact
constitutes rule-following (Kripke, 1982, pp. 86-87). In the following sections (1 and 2) I will
face up to the two horns in order to expose any promise or further threat they may present.
In the end I accept Kripke’s rejection of both. But I do not accept that the rejection supports
skepticism (sections 3 and 4).
My aim is to thread a third non-skeptical route. The third route is enactivist in
spirit. It holds that behavior does not merely express-exhibit meaning but, in a sense
to be specified, meaning is co-constituted by mental acts and embodied behavior of
interpretation and representation of regularities of one’s self and others, thereby giving rise
to an operationally closed dynamic and circular causal pattern encompassing bodily and
mental action that reciprocally affords future bodily and mental action, thus perpetuating a
domain of meaning.
A caveat: the enactivist proposal is not, as presented in this piece, able to answer all
the intricacies of meaning constitution. This piece submits a dilemma, presents why the
suggested solution has not been found persuasive and suggests an alternative, non-skeptical
understanding of the dilemma. As such it is concerned with theory development and not with
defending an established paradigm. The reader is also advised that purely exegetical points
are not made or intended. This is not a prescriptive account of how a text, in particular one
by Wittgenstein, ought to be read. Objections that pertain to exegesis alone should therefore,
unless relevant to the validity of the argument, be put aside for present purposes.
Dispositions—the first horn
A natural reaction to Wittgenstein’s idea that ‘just acting’ expresses-exhibits a rule
(Wittgenstein, 1953, §§ 217, 219) is to argue that behavioral dispositions constitute
meaning. The false impression that rules determine meaning may then be refined through
an identification of the patterns people are disposed to follow. These dispositions can be
stated in generalized form as if rules. What constitutes following a rule is then one’s being
in accord with dispositions that constitute meaning. So we would have a natural reduction of
rules to behavioral dispositions that in turn constitute meaning.
Varieties of dispositionalism (e.g., Pettit, 2002; cf. Millikan, 1990) have had their
share of criticism in recent debate. On the face of it, dispositionalism might seem the most
natural response to our dilemma, which is perhaps why Kripke (1982, pp. 22-32) devoted
considerable space in an attempt to refute it. Today dispositionalism appears less attractive.
In this section I present some arguments against dispositionalism.
112
Kripke pointed out that dispositions that subjects embody encounter the ‘problem
of finiteness’ (ibid., p. 26). The problem is that past instances of practice coincide with
indefinite ways of proceeding and none of them enjoy the privilege of being exclusively
true to past practice. In multiplication, for example, the multiplicand may be too large for it
to be possible for it to be read off from subjective dispositions about which product one is
disposed to getting. In that sense, although one might actually be disposed to multiplying
one way rather than another, dispositions cannot constitute the meaning of ‘multiplication.’
Subjects might be disposed to behaving in one particular way rather than another, even where
there are in principle an infinite number of future instances. But that does not give us any
reason to assume that a subject’s dispositions will not change over time as he re-engages
that practice, or that, when he engages it at any instant, that the dispositions operative at that
instant determine the correctness of conditions for future engagement. Due to the finitude
of subjective dispositions we are in the dark about whether dispositions can stay true to, or
at any moment constitute, the meaning of a practice, not just at the present moment but over
time as well (Kripke, 1982, p. 27; cf. Millikan, 1990, p. 327).
Another influential objection to a dispositionalist account of meaning constitution is
that people are disposed to making mistakes (Kripke, 1982, pp. 28-32). If meaning is to
be read-off from people’s dispositions, then there is no reason in principle to deny, for
instance, that ‘multiplication’ means something different in conditions of fatigue when
people are disposed to getting 2 as the product from 7 and 9 or are disposed to clinching the
person they mean to ‘converse’ with rather than ‘wrestle’. It has been argued that meaning
constituting dispositions should be identified as those, which, in the ‘right’ circumstances,
pick out a definite meaning. The question then is: which circumstances are ‘right’? It has
been suggested that the ‘right’ conditions are those in which ‘biological competences’
operate without interference (Millikan, 1990), and as those that result in interpersonal and
intrapersonal-intertemporal congruence in understandings of the meaning of a practice
(Pettit, 1990).
I cannot, for lack of space, provide detailed criticism of proposals as to what the ‘right’
conditions are for dispositions to operate so as to constitute meaning—nor can I assess
the many dispositionalist counterarguments (Soames, 1998; Horwich, 1998). But we may
consider three reasons why disposition-firings, even in the ‘right’ circumstances, cannot be
the meaning constituting facts we are looking for.
One problem is that idealizing conditions, the ‘right’ conditions, tends to trivialize
matters. Suppose we could delimit the conditions that were right. We would be left with
a trivial claim to the effect, for example, that Jones means horse by ‘horse’ if and only if
Jones applies ‘horse’ to horses in the right conditions. For instance, if on dark nights Jones
is disposed to mistaking horse-like cows in the distance for horses, ‘horse’ still means horse
(rather than horse or horse-like cow) because Jones would apply ‘horse’ only to horses if
the conditions were right. But, surely, if we could eliminate deceptive counterfactuals it is
trivially true that Jones would apply ‘horse’ only to horses. This analysis does not avail us.
We want an answer to the question of what fact constitutes ‘horse’ meaning horse, not how
Jones applies the word ‘horse.’ The latter only answers the analytically secondary question:
given that ‘horse’ means horse, under what conditions will Jones refer successfully? Saying
that Jones is disposed to applying ‘horse’ only to horses, in the right conditions, tells us
113
nothing about what constitutes the meaning of ‘horse’ to begin with. Unless we know what
makes conditions ‘right’ for dispositions to operate in them, not what people are disposed to
doing when the conditions are ‘right,’ we cannot distinguish which of them are dispositions
to making mistakes, and which constitute meaning.
It is tempting to avoid triviality by substantiating ‘right’ by employing a term δ, say,
‘interpersonal convergence on meaning’ (cf. Pettit, 1990). But in that case vacuity is traded
for either circularity or regress (Boghossian, 2005, pp. 192-93). If the new definition of
‘right’ conditions does not involve normative terms, then it tells us nothing about why some
conditions are ‘right’ and others are not, and so the initial challenge has not been tackled.
On the other hand, if δ is normatively loaded, then we may ask what makes the conditions
it denotes any more ‘right’ than other conditions. In principle it is an open question; if δ
denotes something non-normative, are the δ-conditions right? No answer to this question
can recast δ, without regress, in non-normative terms. But if δ denotes something normative,
then it is an open question as to why we should accept it. A skeptic might disagree that those
are the ‘right’ conditions. If, in response, one falls back on a non-normative notion of δ,
the regress reappears. But if, instead, one responds by pointing to some further normative
considerations by virtue of which δ-conditions are normatively ‘right’, then the skeptic will
press for an argument as to why the new property thus picked out makes the conditions more
‘right’ than others. And this dispute can continue ad infinitum.
Now, dispositionalist accounts of meaning constituting facts encounter some serious
problems. I am not suggesting that arguments against dispositionalism are conclusive. Only
that, at the moment, dispositionalism faces obstacles that are too serious for it to be fruitful.
Intentions—the second horn
Another natural response to the rule-following paradox is to point out that the interpretationsregress that Wittgenstein encounters (Wittgenstein, 1953, §§ 201, 217) does not exhaust
which mental acts could constitute meaning. This is the second horn of our dilemma.
An obvious candidate for meaning constituting mental acts is intentions. Intentions with
general content, for instance, ‘do A whenever conditions are C,’ provide directives that
quantify potentially infinite situations. In that sense an intention view may offer a steppingstone to overcoming the problem that prior practice presents only a finitude of instances
coinciding with in principle indefinite number of rules for future practice (Wright, 2001, pp.
125-26). We may say that meaning is constituted by the generalized content of intentions
from which people engage in a practice. This, then, is how rule-following is possible: W
means M in conditions C if and only if people in C intend to use W to mean M. Thus, if we
recognize that conditions are of type C, and if we have an intention with the general content
to W to mean M whenever C, then to W in C is to follow the rule for meaning M in C.
But a regress lurks here as well. The problem (cf. Boghossian, 2012) is that the subject
will have to track the conditions, C, picked out by the generalized content of her intentions
in order to identify what to do in a practice she is currently engaged in or about to engage
in. If she intends to follow a rule of the form ‘whenever C, do A!’ she must believe that
she is in C and infer ‘do A!’ The subject must infer that she is in a condition fitting the
generalized content of her intention in order for her to behave according to the rule. But
114
now, the inference involved in this reasoning itself requires that she follows a rule—the rule
of inference from ‘if I am in C, I ought to do A!’ and ‘I am in C’ to ‘I ought to do A!’ When
the subject moves from the content of her intention via the premise that she is in C to the
conclusion that she ought to do A, she is using a rule of inference in order to follow a rule!
As Boghossian puts it:
If on the Intention view, rule-following always requires inference; and if inference is itself
always a form of rule-following, then the Intention view would look to be hopeless: under
its terms, following a rule requires embarking upon a vicious regress in which we succeed in
following no rule (2012, p. 41).
In order to avoid the regress one could dismiss the premise that inference is a matter of
rule-following. We may leave this as an open possibility, but note that giving up the idea that
inferences are instances of rule-following is radical indeed. The very idea that, from ‘P’ and
‘if P then Q’, concluding ‘Q’ is permitted, relies on the Modus Ponens rule. If there were no
rule allowing this inference, many arguments, in philosophy or otherwise, would stand on
shaky ground. If invoking intentions with general content was supposed to bridge the finitude
problem, then it appears no more plausible than the idea that dispositions could bridge that gap.
Perhaps, though intentions could be interpreted as substituting rules, rather than constituting
rules, as per Wittgenstein’s suggestion above. Rather than intentions constituting something in
addition, i.e., rules, which then constitute meaning, people intend to behave in definite ways
and those intentions simply are what we call ‘rules.’ In that case, the intention view is not
that people intend to follow rules but that intentions constitute meaning directly. Thus I may
confidently say that ‘×’ means multiplication because that is how I intend to use ‘×’.
However, if intentions constitute meaning, then whatever a subject intends the meaning
of a practice to be will be its meaning. We take this route at the peril of collapsing the
distinction between behaving in accord with the meaning of a practice, on the one hand,
and intending to behave in accord with its meaning, on the other. Jones may intend to mean
something by ‘×’ that he didn’t mean earlier. Insofar as intentions constitute meaning,
though, there is no principled distinction to be made between Jones failing to mean a definite
function by ‘×’ and his deciding upon a new meaning that he now intends for it. Whatever
he intends its meaning to be is its meaning (Wittgenstein, 1953, § 202). If he is wrong in
the light of his earlier intentions, he may modify his intentions to get back on track—or,
which amounts to the same thing, modify the meaning by modifying his intentions. But then,
playing chess, for instance, and intending that what one is doing is playing chess amounts to
the same thing—which is absurd. Determining what Jones is doing would be equivalent to
determining what he intends to do. Jones may be throwing pebbles in a well intending this to
mean ‘checkmate’ or ‘touch down,’ and on to the present proposal that would then be what
his pebble throwing means.
There are, then, important obstacles at the second horn of the dilemma and, aside from
details we cannot do justice to here, this is where the discussion stands. Some opt for the first
horn, arguing that behavioral dispositions constitute meaning. Others opt for the second horn,
arguing that intentional or other representational states constitute meaning. What remains to
be said in defense of a non-skeptical approach to meaning constitution? I devote the final two
sections to that question.
115
Inadequate constraints
Our question was: which facts constitute meaning (Cf. Boghossian, 1989, p. 515)? The
rejection of both ‘internalist’ and ‘externalist’ options force our answer towards skepticism. I
want to argue, on the contrary, that we are not bound to either horn or to skepticism. I will do
so via an introduction to enactivist philosophy.1
A central idea of enactivism is that subjects do not construct detailed internal
representation of an external world from which they infer or recover meaning that then
informs action (Varela, Thompson, & Rosch, 1991, p. 149). Nor do subjects interpret past
practices, in the narrow sense of taking such practices as input, which they process in order
to derive meaning and to output behavior (ibid., pp. 156-7). Meaning is neither external and
recovered nor internal and projected.
The rejection of meaning as recovered from the external world does not, however, place
enactivism on the second horn, on which meaning is constituted internally and then projected
onto behavioral patterns. Meaning is understood rather as enacted (ibid., pp. 149, 173). The
verb ‘to enact’ signifies a temporally extended process of embodied and social interaction in
which what subjects do, and the way the world is, co-specify a relational domain of viability
(Thompson, 2007, p. 74). It isn’t from the content of intentional or other representational
states, on one side, or from mechanistically described behavior or environmental structures,
on the other, that meaning is somehow projected or recovered. Instead, social and physical
interactive processes are understood as driven by the dual force of internal and external
dynamics that molds a relational domain “in between” the internal and external (De Jaegher
& Froese, 2009, p. 447). Meaning consists in saliencies to think and act one way rather
than another. These saliences are enacted as people interact with each other and their
environments, and are ultimately grounded both in internal and external, biological and
(social and physical) interactive processes. What we think of, interpret, or judge as meaning
(what may appear as a rule) is the present state of such unfolding processes. Importantly,
enaction of meaning involves the co-constitution of the unfolding of practice, involving both
internal and external processes, neither of which is analytically primary but on a par.
From this point of view, the first two horns considered in the previous sections are
avoided. But importantly, enactivism does not square well with skepticism. Enactivism
suggests that we abandon the assumption that the two horns are mutually exclusive and
exhaustive of alternative solutions to the rule-following paradox by urging us to not accept
the either-or alternatives of internalism and externalism at the very beginning. If enactivism
has anything going for it, then the question about constitution cannot be formulated on the
assumption that we have already accepted that it raises two horns, represented by the ‘either
internal-mental or external-behavioral’-disjunction, or forces us towards skepticism. In order
to assess the force of this third non-skeptical solution, much more needs to be said about
enactivism.
1
Enactivism originated as a movement in the biology of cognition and the organisation of living
(Maturana & Varela, 1980). Since its inception it has developed into one of the staunchest adversaries
of the rules-and-representations model of mind and cognition (Varela, Thompson, & Rosch, 1991). It
is known for its animosity to the supposedly Cartesian separation of mind and body (Thompson, 2007,
pp. 226-30). I cannot give a full exposé of enactivism here and refer the reader to the works quoted.
116
Enacting meaning
Key concepts of enactivism are autonomy and sense-making. I introduce both here and then
elaborate in more detail the enactivist understanding of meaning constitution introduced in
the previous section.
Autonomy
Autonomy signifies the following property of agents: they are self-generating entities
that through their biochemical processes and interactions with other autonomous
agents and environments sustain an identity over time. Metabolism secures that living
organisms’ organization and structure is kept autonomous over time courtesy of being
thermodynamically permeable but operationally closed systems. This allows intake of
self-sustaining material that contributes energy to the organism, thus enabling it to act as
an autonomous being with its own organization and structure. The continuity of autonomy
achieved through this biological interactive process “establishes a perspective on the world
with its own normativity, which is the counterpart of the agent being a center of activity in
the world” (De Jaegher & Di Paolo, 2007, p. 488). This establishing of a perspective on the
world is simultaneously a realization of a domain of behavioral viability, or value, relative to
the organism’s biological autonomy and the structure of its environment. Behavioral patterns
become valuable as a function of their tendency to perpetuate autonomy in precarious
conditions. Consequences of interactive processes “have significance or value … in relation
to the processes of its [the agent’s] identity generation” (De Jaegher & Froese, 2009, p. 447).
That is, interaction becomes inherently having value and significance for autonomous agents
that occupy a center of activity in the world, both affectively through experience of tensions
between selfhood and alterity, as well as thermodynamically and biologically through the
unfolding interaction’s impingement on autonomy.
Sense-making
Sense-making is the process in which autonomous agents create and appreciate meaning as
consequence of the establishment of value through interaction with others and environments:
Exchanges with the environment are inherently significant for the cogniser and this is a
definitional property of a cognitive system: the creation and appreciation of meaning or
sense-making for short. … [S]ense-making is an inherently active concept. Organisms do not
passively receive information from their environments, which they then translate into internal
representations whose significant value is to be added later. Natural cognitive systems are
simply not in the business of accessing their world in order to build accurate pictures of it.
They actively participate in the generation of meaning in what matters to them; they enact a
world (De Jaegher & Di Paolo, 2007, p. 488).
Enactivists reject “the traditional dichotomy between internal and external determinants
of behaviour” (De Jaegher & Di Paolo, 2008, p. 2), replacing it with the idea that internal
and external dynamics, biological viability and (social and physical) interaction, co-specify
conditions in which meaning is enacted (ibid.).
117
Can we, from an enactivist perspective, avoid the ‘either-or’ dilemma about meaning
constituting facts? We can, but at present it is a long shot. We may concede that no
instruction or rule that I give myself, no generalized intentional content “engraved on my
mind as on a slate” (Kripke, 1982, p. 15), constitutes meaning. Nor is it plausible that
meaning is constituted by dispositions or something in the external world, for reasons
considered earlier. But this is not a concession that no fact (ibid., p. 13) constitutes meaning.
Skepticism follows only if an abstraction of mind from action is assumed as already accepted.
From an enactivist perspective, the abstraction is non-mandatory. The enactivist proposal
is to treat mind and autonomous action as co-constitutive of meaning, while engaging in
practice reciprocally specifies paths for future autonomous sense-making. What people
have in mind, and what they do (their linguistic, arithmetic, social and embodied action) are
not separate domains, but are co-dependent in the enaction of a meaningful world in which
agents emerge as minded beings; as beings having mental content. Internal biological and
metabolic processes together with (social and physical) interaction co-constitute practices
whose history and progression in turn establish value and concern for thinking and behaving
one way rather than another. Therefore neither internalism nor externalism will be satisfying
(Di Paolo, 2009). Neither internal nor external processes are, as such, sufficient for meaning
constitution in abstraction from their mutual co-specification of dynamical enactive
processes.
It will immediately be observed that there is an enormous gap to account for between
the enaction of biological viability, at one end, and mathematical sophistication, at the other.
I will return to this shortly.
But first, an important aspect of meaning enaction is that meaning is essentially dynamic.
The mental and behavioral aspects of meaning constituting processes are susceptible to the
dynamics of internal as well as external (social and physical) processes. Vice versa, the
domain of viability for thinking in the world, enacted through the interdependent dynamics
of internal and external processes, is in turn susceptible to modulation through the unfolding
of those internal and external, biological and interactive (social and physical) processes.
Thus the domain of meaning that autonomous sense-making organisms enact can itself be
understood as operationally closed at a higher level of description. The enacted world is
essentially an interactive domain in between agents and their environments (De Jaegher et
al., 2010) that is itself operationally closed. The interactive domain of value and concern
is higher-level in that it emerges from lower-level biological, embodied and affective
dynamics of agents and environments. It is operationally closed in the sense that it exerts a
“downward” causal force (Di Paolo et al., 2010; Lo Presti, 2013, pp. 11-12) on the unfolding
of lower-level biological, metabolic and (social and physical) interactive processes. However,
the sense-making that is thus being enacted is not biologically closed, since it encompasses
multi-agent systems and their environments in interaction as well as their histories of
interaction and sense-making. In this interactive process agents co-contribute to the enaction
of a domain of value and concern but are equally susceptible to the causal feedback from
that enacted domain. This two-level interdependence approach to meaning constitution
renders off-track the idea that generalized rules or directions (in mind or behavior) constitute
meaning. The meaning of future practice must be filtered through the dynamics of imminent
interaction. Imminent interaction, though its dynamics are somewhat restricted by histories of
118
interactions and the values and concern previously enacted, involves an embodied-affective
negotiation of here-and-now (physical and social) contingencies, and as such has a causal
force which thrusts interaction dynamics along slightly, or radically, different trajectories.
This causal process then molds the unfolding dynamics, again effectuating slight or more
radical changes, or preservation of, future interaction dynamics. Constituting meaning
becomes inherently activistic.
Wittgenstein’s rejection of the metaphor that meaning is determined by a rule whose
steps “have already been taken” and which “is to be followed through the whole of space”
(Wittgenstein, 1953, § 219) appears to be right. On an enactivist construal, we may say
that meaning is enacted in taking steps (in language use and calculation; in engagement).
The steps that have already been taken specify a way of thinking and acting in the future.
People do not engage practices as if they were novel, for each instance with an erased
mental, behavioral, and interactive history. We engage practices whose antecedently enacted
meaning affords ways of thinking, interpreting, perceiving, and interacting; practices are
enacted as making sense relative to our concerns. In this process, the co-contribution of
mental, behavioral, and (social and physical) interaction is the factual constitutive ground of
meaning.
The outcome of this suggestion is an alternative to the either-or story reviewed earlier.
What people do and think specifies a meaning that specifies a way for people to think
and behave in the future (e.g. in language use or in doing mathematics). We are not, then,
required to infer from prior instances what the meaning of a practice is to form a conclusion
about what to do or say now or in the future. We may do so, but it does not constitute
meaning. Neither is it necessary to have general instructions or rules ‘in mind’, or the
‘right’ dispositions. Meaning, and knowing how to proceed in accord with the meaning of a
practice (Wittgenstein, 1953, §§ 151-54), is a question of mental content and behavior being
fostered by, as well as fostering, engagement in day-to-day activities. Meaning constitution is
activism.
Enactivism, in conclusion, provides one venue for criticizing the very formulation of the
rule-following paradox. It suffices for my purposes if the criticism has initial plausibility. If
it does, then we can conclude that the two horns and skepticism, developed over the last three
decades or so, have, indeed, blinded us from a novel way of proceeding in our philosophical
investigating on meaning. If, in addition, enactivism is promising, then formulating a fourth
venue is within reach. One should expect that enactivism would have to withstand much
criticism to emerge as a feasible alternative. Either way, it is no less significant a conclusion
that at the moment we seem not to have properly understood our dilemma.2
References
Boghossian, P. (1989). The rule-following considerations. Mind, 98(392), 507-549.
Boghossian, P. (2005). Rules, meaning and intention: Discussion. Philosophical Studies, 124, 185-197.
2
This research was funded by the European Science Foundation’s EUROCORES program
EuroUnderstanding, and was carried out as part of the NormCon project. I would like to thank the
members of that project for helping me develop the argument here presented.
119
Boghossian, P. (2012). Blind rule-following. In A. Coliva (Ed.), Mind, meaning, and knowledge:
Themes from the philosophy of Crispin Wright. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. (2007). Participatory sense-making. Phenomenology and the Cognitive
Sciences, 6, 485-507.
De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. (2008). Making sense in participation: An enactive approach to social
cognition. In F. Morganti, A. Carassa, & G. Riva (Eds.), Enacting intersubjectivity: A cognitive and
social perspective to the study of interactions. IOS Press: Amsterdam.
De Jaegher, H., & Froese, T. (2009). On the role of social interaction in individual agency. Adaptive
Behavior, 17(5), 444-460.
De Jaegher, Di Paolo, E., & Gallagher, S. (2010). Can social interaction constitute social cognition?
Trends in Cognitive Science, 14, 441-447.
Di Paolo, E. (2009). Extended life. Topoi, 28, 9-21.
Di Paolo, E., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2010). Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social
interaction, and play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new
paradigm in cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Horwich, P. (1998). Meaning. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Lo Presti, P. (2013). Social ontology and social cognition. Abstracta, 7(1), 5-17.
Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Dodrecht:
Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Millikan, R. (1990). Truth rules, hoverflies, and the Kripke-Wittgenstein paradox. The Philosophical
Review, 99(3), 323-353.
Peacocke, C. (2012). Understanding and rule-following. In A. Coliva (Ed.), Mind, meaning, and
knowledge: Themes from the philosophy of Crispin. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pettit, P. (1990). The reality of rule-following. Mind, 99(393), 1-21.
Pettit, P. (2002). Rules, reasons, and norms. New York: Oxford University Press.
Soames, S. (1998). Skepticism about meaning: Indeterminacy, normativity and the rule following
paradox. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23, 211-250.
Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. Prentice Hall,
NJ: Basil Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L. (1956). Remarks on the foundations of mathematics. In G. H. von Wright, R. Rhees, &
G. E. M. Anscombe (Eds.). Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Wright, C. (2001). Rails to infinity: Essays on themes from Wittgenstein’s philosophical investigations.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Department of Philosophy and Cognitive Science,
Lund University, LUX,
Helgonavägen 3D,
223 62 Lund,
Sweden
Tel. +46 (0)705 95 25 93
E-mail:
[email protected]
120