philosophies
Article
Beyond Consent: On Setting and Sharing Sexual Ends
Jordan Pascoe
Department of Philosophy, Women and Gender Studies, and Critical Race and Ethnicity Studies,
Manhattan College, New York, NY 10471, USA;
[email protected]
Abstract: This paper formulates a response to standard accounts of Kantian sexual morality, by first
clarifying why sex should be understood as a case of using a person as a thing, rather than merely as
a means. The author argues that Kant’s remedy to this problem is not sexual consent, but a model
of setting and sharing sexual ends. Kant’s account of sexual morality, read in this way, is a critical
framework for contemporary moves to think beyond consent, and to grapple with concerns about
sexual violation and “bad sex” that have gained uptake in the wake of the MeToo movement. The
author defends an account of sex as a process of setting and sharing sexual ends in a Kantian key,
which provides us with resources for thinking about the robust ongoing project of making our sexual
selves in nonideal conditions, as well as for identifying the wrongs of both “bad” sex and sexual
harassment. In doing so, they offer a critical middle ground between contemporary accounts of
sexual morality that center questions of individual agency or autonomy, and those that foreground
the intersubjective nature of sex.
Keywords: sexual consent; Kant; feminist philosophy; philosophy of sex
1. Doing Philosophy In Bed
Citation: Pascoe, J. Beyond Consent:
On Setting and Sharing Sexual Ends.
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21.
https://doi.org/10.3390/
philosophies8020021
Academic Editor: Raja Halwani
Received: 19 January 2023
Revised: 26 February 2023
Accepted: 4 March 2023
Published: 7 March 2023
Copyright:
© 2023 by the author.
Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland.
This article is an open access article
distributed under the terms and
conditions of the Creative Commons
Attribution (CC BY) license (https://
creativecommons.org/licenses/by/
4.0/).
Philosophers sometimes suppose that if we want to understand what kinds of relationships make sex permissible, we can look to other sorts of activities we engage in together:
perhaps sex is like a game of tennis [1,2] or squash [3]; perhaps it is something like dancing
together [4,5] or building a roof [4]. If sex is like these other activities, then it can be subject
to the same scrutiny and the same remedies. My students and I sometimes joke that when
we are doing philosophy of sex, we are just doing philosophy but playing the old game
where you add “in bed” to the end of each sentence, to see how the argument applies.
At the same time, feminists have consistently made the case for understanding sex as
importantly different from other sorts of activities, in that sex involves forms of objectification that go beyond other kinds of interaction [6]. And, as Kantian feminists have long
pointed out, they are not alone in making this claim: Kant, too, thought that sex involved a
dehumanizing form of objectification: on his account, sex was “cannibalistic”, an appetite
that leads us to consume one another [7] (6:360) [8–10]. Kant’s account differs from the
feminist account in that he takes the problem of objectification to be symmetrical, though
his analysis remains attentive to how asymmetries can exacerbate the problem.
Given this careful feminist attention to Kant’s account of sexual objectification, it is
curious that most accounts of Kantian sexual morality take Kant’s primary concern to be
that sex is an instance of using another person merely as a means [11,12] (p. 274), and that
sex is, therefore, much like other kinds of activities—a tennis match, a roofing project [2,3].
If sex is a problem of treating another person merely as a means, then it follows that sex is
subject to the same remedies as other kinds of interactions: namely, that sex is permissible
only when partners consent to sex, free from deception or coercion. Call this the standard
Kantian account.
In this essay, I will argue that the standard account misses a crucial distinction in
Kant’s conception of sex, which can provide us with critical resources for contemporary
sexual dilemmas. Following Kantian feminists, I take Kant’s account of the problem
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8020021
https://www.mdpi.com/journal/philosophies
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
2 of 16
of objectification seriously and tease out the distinction between using someone merely
as a means, and using someone as a thing. Doing so, I will argue, should complicate
contemporary accounts of sexual consent. On the standard account, if sex is an instance
of treating someone merely as a means, then the remedy is consent—namely, genuine,
voluntary, informed consent [3,11–13]. But if the problem for Kant is not using a person as a
means only, but instead the use of a person as a thing, then consent is an insufficient remedy.
Kant’s solution to this problem, famously, is not sexual consent, but marriage. Following contemporary Kantians, I argue that we can distill the critical feature that makes sex
permissible from Kant’s account of marriage, rather than defending an outdated sex-onlywithin-marriage argument. Kant’s claim was that when we are in danger of using someone
as a thing, we can only solve the problem by putting ourselves into a relation with them,
where we treat one another as end-setting beings, by promising to share our ends with one
another. I will show how Kant’s conception of sharing ends, is importantly different from
standard ideas of consent, and argue that an account of setting and sharing sexual ends,
can address the sorts of sexual wrongs that, as Tom Dougherty has argued, consent can
ameliorate but not eliminate [14].
In making this argument, I build on a robust body of work by contemporary feminist
Kantians on Kant’s account of sex, from Herman’s and Nussbaum’s arguments in the
1990s, to Helga Varden’s recent masterful rethinking of Kantian sexuality [3,8,10]. I want
to put these arguments into conversation with another body of work in sexual ethics,
which has been increasingly challenging dominant conceptions of sexual consent. These
arguments are theorizing ways to expand sexual discourse beyond consent, conceiving
of sex as a joint activity, and mapping alternate communicative and negotiation practices
for permissible sex. They respond to a growing awareness—particularly in the wake of
the MeToo movement—of the ways that normative consent operates as a sexual script
within heterosex, in which men propose and women consent, and in which a substantive
portion of sexual communication and negotiation is thus ignored [6,15,16]. As heterosexual
practices of consent are enshrined in law and policy, and then treated as if they were
gender-neutral, these patterns of passivity come to shape sex beyond heterosex. Thus, even
as consent is increasingly framed in law and policy in gender-neutral terms, it is critical
to remember that, as Linda Alcoff puts it, “consent is particularly insufficient as a means
to protect women’s freedom” [17] (p. 138). So Alcoff, like many contemporary feminists, is
theorizing permissible sex beyond consent.
Many of these moves to think beyond consent highlight the intersubjective nature of
sex: they theorize sex as a joint activity, as teamwork [4], but it is equally important not to
leave behind the question of agency. As Alcoff puts it, “the kernel of truth behind the turn
to consent . . . is a concern with what the person wants to do, with her will” [17] (p. 138). I
will argue that this is where Kant can be particularly helpful: by providing a theory of sex
as an intersubjective joint activity, that is nevertheless centered around a robust conception
of our sexual will. Kant’s concern with the will is not merely, as Alcoff warns, “a given
momentary intention . . . what the immediate statements and acts, desires, and pleasure, or
even stated consent, can convey” [17] (pp. 140–141). Instead, we find in Kant an account of
what Alcoff calls “will-formation in a larger sense” [17] (p. 140), or the practices through
which we make our sexual selves. But to see this dimension of Kant’s argument, we will
first have to distinguish between the moral problem with sex, as the use of a person as a
mere means, and the use of a person as a thing.
2. Using Someone as Merely a Means, or Using Them as a Thing?
On the standard account, sex is like other sorts of activities, and the danger sex poses
is, like other activities, the risk of using a person as a means only. The problem of using
someone merely as a means is likely familiar to anyone with even a passing familiarity
with Kant. In our ordinary lives, we make use of one another, as a means, in all sorts of
ways: the person I buy my coffee from is a means to my coffee; the person who gives me
a massage is a means to my relaxation. All of this is unproblematic because I pay for my
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
3 of 16
coffee and my massage, and so I am also helping my barista and my masseuse to their
ends (or, what I assume their ends are), of making a living. I have not used them merely as
a means. But, if I walk out of the coffee shop without paying, or convince a friend to do
a massage exchange and then refuse to reciprocate, then I have used the barista and the
friend as merely a means to my own ends, in a morally problematic way.
The way to avoid using someone merely as a means, therefore, is through their genuine
consent, which must be voluntary, as in not coerced, and informed, as in not deceived [11].
As Pauline Kleingeld has argued, this actual consent must be the condition for my action:
I avoid treating you merely as a means when the reason I go forward with the action is
that you have consented to it [12]. It is critical to have an account of how to avoid treating
people merely as a means because it allows us to use people to build houses for us, sell us
coffee, or play tennis—all of which are fine ways to use people, as long as your genuine,
informed, and voluntary consent is the reason we do this together.
This sounds like a solid account of sexual consent, too: the reason I have sex with you
is that you consent, knowingly and voluntarily, to have sex with me. Thus, on the standard
account, I use you for sex as merely a means, only if I violate the requirement that I get your
genuine, informed, and voluntary consent [11,13]. As long as you do consent, knowingly
and voluntarily, to have sex with me, then we have created what Kant would call a united
will, through which we have both agreed to the action that we are about to undertake [12]
(p. 404): when I want to have sex with someone, I desire to treat them as a means to my
end (say, pleasure); when I have their consent, we align my end (my pleasure) with their
end (their pleasure).
The trouble is that while this is, indeed, how Kant thinks most permissible interactions
must work, it is not how he thinks sex works. Kant described sex as “cannibalistic,” and
emphasized the ways that sex is an appetite through which we make ourselves into the
object of someone’s appetite—that is, a thing to be consumed, like ‘a roast pork’ [18] (27:387).
Kant’s description of sex as an instance of using someone as a thing date back to his earliest
notes on sex [19] (19:460), and metaphors of consumption appear consistently over decades
of thinking about sex, from the Lectures on Ethics, where he worries that after sex, we cast
our lovers aside ‘as one casts away a lemon which has been sucked dry’ [18] (27:384), to
the Appendix to the Rechtslehre, where he worries that men are exhausted ‘by women’s
frequent demands upon’ them [7] (6:360). There, he concludes that “in this sort of use by
each of the sexual organs of the other, each is a consumable thing with respect to the other,
so that if one was to make oneself such a thing by contract, the contract would be contrary
to law” [7] (6:360). Sex is, indeed, an instance of the use of a person, but it is an objectifying,
appetitive form of use: it is a form of use in which we are used directly as a thing, and thus,
to consent to sex is to consent to be used as a thing.
The first question we must ask is, (how) is using a person as a thing, different from
using them merely as a means? And then, the second question is, if using a person as
a thing, is indeed different from using them merely as a means, then what remedy is
necessary for this sort of use? Is genuine, voluntary, informed consent sufficient? And if
not, what is?
I have two answers to the first question. First, for Kant, the kind of use sex entails is
indeed importantly different from the kinds of use tennis, house-building, or a massage
entails. When I hire someone to build me a house, make me a coffee, or give me a massage
it is their skills that I make use of: Kant says that “a man can certainly enjoy the other as
an instrument for his service: he can utilize the others’ hands or feet to serve him, though
by the latter’s free choice” [18] (27:384). But the use we make of another through sex is
different: “we never find that a human being can be the object of another’s enjoyment, save
through the sexual impulse” [18] (27:384). Because sex is an appetite directly for the body of
another, Kant thinks, it is a relation through which one makes oneself into a thing, “which
conflicts with the right of humanity in his own person” [7] (6:278). The only other instance
where a person makes himself into a thing in this way is through enslavement, which is
a relation in which a person has no right against the slave for his labor, but a relationship
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
4 of 16
in which the slave becomes an object to be used, a body directly subject to the master’s
will [20].1 Sex and slavery are distinct from other kinds of use, on Kant’s account, because
they involve allowing someone else to make direct use of my body for their own ends,
rather than an agreement to grant another a right against me for the use of my skills or
my time. In the latter case, my body is still subject to my will. If I have consented, this
is fine; if I have not given genuine, informed, voluntary consent, then I am being used
merely as a means to someone’s end. But in the case of sex or slavery, my body is being
used by another to fulfill their ends: my body is being used according to someone else’s
will. Thus, I am being used as a thing. If I consent to this treatment, I consent to being used
as a thing—and this, Kant argues, is something that I cannot do.
But, secondly, I think we could reasonably disagree with this distinction. In practice,
many contemporary philosophers of sex do simply disagree with Kant’s take on sex, and
argue, more or less, that when we think about sex, we simply add “in bed” to the end of our
general propositions. And so maybe sex is like tennis or getting a massage, and maybe the
rules that govern those relations should govern sexual relations. Maybe Kant was simply
wrong about the moral dangers of sex, just as he was wrong about the impermissibility of
same-sex relations [3].
Before we dismiss the Kantian distinction, however, let us consider why so many
contemporary feminists have taken this distinction to tell us something important about sex.
Barbara Herman, Martha Nussbaum, and Rae Langton have famously located, in Kant’s
argument, important parallels to contemporary feminist arguments about objectification:
the worry that there is, indeed, something profoundly objectifying about sexual relations,
something akin to using a person as a thing, that does not arise in a tennis game or at the
coffee shop [8–10]. Herman, as we’ve seen, identifies strong similarities between Kant’s account of sexual objectification and the arguments advanced by radical feminists like Andrea
Dworkin and Catherine MacKinnon [8]. And while Herman argues that the central difference is that, for Kant, this problem of objectification is symmetrical, rather than gendered, I
think we have good reason to think that Kant’s analysis, like Dworkin’s and MacKinnon’s,
is attentive to how power relations shape the problem of sexual objectification: this is why
he argues against prostitution, concubinage, and morganatic marriage, since the only way
to make the inevitable objectification of sex permissible is to embed it within a relationship
of legal equality. When it is allowed to unfold in unequal relations—relations in which
men have power, and women do not—then it operates, he thinks, rather like slavery, in
which one person agrees to be a thing used by the other person, according to their will
(even if one has consented to this use). If Dworkin and MacKinnon are right that, under
conditions of patriarchy, most heterosexual relations take some version of this form, then
we have good Kantian reasons to be quite worried about what we consent to, when we
consent to sex. (Given that marriage is itself a patriarchal institution, we have little reason
to think, as Kant did, that marriage will solve this problem). If we dig deeper into Kant’s
account of our sexual selves, as Helga Varden has done, then we find resources in Kant for
understanding why being objectified, violated, or traumatized does so much damage to
our ways of being ourselves, and of being at home in the world [3].
So, one way to take Kant’s account of sex seriously is to say that Kant thought sex was
wildly objectifying and morally dangerous. We can say that he is wrong about this—that
much sex is not wildly objectifying and morally dangerous, that a lot of the time we
have sex for good and moral reasons, and in ways that are consistent with our duties, to
ourselves and each other. But it is worth noting that some sex is wildly objectifying and
morally dangerous, either because it is the kind of “bleak” sex we’ve become so aware
of in the wake of #MeToo [4,5], or because it is kinky sex, and so it is objectifying and
morally dangerous, on purpose [21]. It is also worth acknowledging, with MacKinnon and
Dworkin, that the moral dangers of sex and objectification are not equally distributed, so
that grappling with these dangers is a regular feature of, for example, womanhood under
patriarchy (#yesallwomen).2 If this is the case, then it is important to acknowledge the ways
that (1) sex is importantly different from tennis or getting a massage and (2) the kind of
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
5 of 16
using a person as a thing that sex allows can also impact our tennis games and massages—e.g.,
that one way to understand sexual harassment is as an instance where someone who is
meant to be using me as a means (for a tennis game or a massage or a coffee) instead begins
to try to use me as a thing. We will return to this point below.
3. What We Cannot Consent to
I turn now to the second question: if sex is an instance of using a person as a thing,
then what is the remedy? Kant claims that you can’t consent to being used as a thing [7]
(6:279, 360). This is why you can’t consent to enslavement, and it is why no agreement
to prostitution or concubinage can be binding [7] (6:279). So, consenting to sex doesn’t
solve the problem: it would simply be consenting to be used as a thing [7] (6:360), and this
consent would conflict “with the right of humanity in his own person” [7] (6:278). When I
consent to being used as a means, this saves me from being used merely as a means. But
when I consent to sex, I just consent to being used as a thing. Sex isn’t transformed by my
consent in the same way that other forms of use are.
Again: perhaps it is not that simple, and we have no reason to think that consent to
sex is much different from consent to a tennis match. But I think that, particularly in the
wake of the MeToo movement, in an era in which pornography shapes so much of sexual
desire and expectations [22–25] it is hard not to acknowledge that, for women, sex does
seem to sometimes involve consenting to being used as a thing. Often, one does not know,
when one consents to sex, that one has agreed to be a prop in someone else’s pornographic
fantasies. Sometimes, as Nancy Bauer argues, one does know, and one does it anyway [25].
In either case, the harms of sex are not always addressed by consent [26]. Therefore, as Tom
Dougherty has argued, we need resources for addressing those cases where these harms
are not eliminated, but only ameliorated, by consent [14].
Most accounts of consent insist that consent must be genuine, voluntary, and informed.
But in most of these accounts, “informed” operates as the opposite of “deceived.”3 As long
as I’m not being deceived by my partner, then apparently I know all I need to consent to sex.
Often, these accounts leave “sex” intact, failing to interrogate what actions and activities
are “on the table” when one consents to sex [5]. The default, in our culture and our legal
framework, is that “sex” refers to penetrative intercourse, ending in male orgasm: sex that
ends in some other way (say, when I say “stop”) has been prematurely ended. So, is that
what I consent to when I consent to sex? To penetration ending in male orgasm? Have I
consented to an act or an end? When I consent to have sex with someone, do I know what
sex is, for them? Do I know what they want it for? Do I know what they want me for?
While philosophers and activists have persistently pushed for more rigorous definitions of what genuine, informed, voluntary consent might look like [6,11,13,14,27], a
pernicious problem persists, wherein a more rigorous definition of consent laid out in, for
example, a campus consent policy or a philosophical essay is not the operative definition
deployed in the courtroom or the Title IX office.4 The problem also arises when those engaging one another in sexual contexts have different operative understandings of consent,
so I may think consent means that I know and understand your motives, while you may
think it means only that I have consented to a particular set of actions. Consent is, as Tom
Dougherty has argued, often understood as a binary—either I have consented, or I have
not [14] (p. 335)—and so it can be difficult to negotiate radically different understandings
of what consent entails within the terms. of one binary framework.5
This problem is exacerbated by the ways that, as feminist philosophers have argued,
consent frameworks tend to focus on “consent talk” to the exclusion of other forms. of
sexual communication and negotiation. Thus, Quill Kukla6 points to the ways that our
emphasis on the “script” of sexual consent directs our attention to a particular, ritualistic
kind of linguistic exchange—articulations of refusal or acceptance—rather than to a broader
range of sexual negotiations, including invitations, gift-giving, and the articulation of
boundaries [15]. In heterosex, as feminists have long argued, this script tends to encourage
men to attend to women’s articulations of acceptance or refusal to the exclusion of other
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
6 of 16
kinds of sexual communication; as a result, as Lois Pineau has put it, consent is often put
rather like “an offer from the mafia” [16] (p. 235)—an offer I can take (or leave, maybe),
about which I have little information or context. As Pineau notes, our conception of
consent—even voluntary, informed consent—rarely has a robust account of the epistemic
duties that consent requires [16,28].
This is not surprising if we consider that, on a Kantian account, consent’s structure is
most akin to a contract. When I enter into a contract to build a house or give a massage, I
grant the other person a right against me: I will an agreement that I will provide them with
my skills, my labor, and my time. The contract is designed to align our respective ends so
that we can make use of one another in permissible ways: my employer uses my labor to
fulfill his end of building his house or having his massage, while I use him to my end of
making money. For this to work, we need only a limited understanding of one another’s
ends: I need to know what parts of his house I’m building, when, and with what materials;
he needs to know my wage; we may need to agree on a completion date. The contract is
designed to ensure that we each get to keep and pursue the ends we already have and, that
we agree to will together a set of actions that will get each of us to where we want to be.7 If
consent is like a contract, then consent is the mechanism through which we can pursue the
ends we have set for ourselves in those cases where that pursuit involves others; beyond
what’s required by the contract, we leave our respective ends up to one another. Consent
allows us to interact with others in ways that ensure we are not treated as a means only.
But when we do this in bed, as it were, then Kant thinks we run into difficulty, since
we are not making an agreement for you to use my skills, my labor, or my time, but to use
my body, which is myself. And so you do not have a right against me, but a right to me.
You’re using me to fulfill your ends, and I’m using you to fulfill my ends. We may agree to
a set of actions to achieve these ends, but the fact remains: you are using me as a thing in
fulfillment of your ends, which are distinct from my ends. And so, you are making use of
my body (and thus, my person) in ways that have nothing to do with my capacities as an
end-setting being, with the right to humanity in my own person. And so, I consent to allow
you to make use of my body in the pursuit of your own ends, without necessarily knowing
what those ends are. If I do not know those ends, I cannot will those ends. And so even if
I have consented to the activity, there is a sense in which you are using my body against
my will.
There is a double danger here. The first, which Kant explores, is that I agree to let you
use me as a thing precisely because I am just using myself as a thing: we’re both just here
for pleasure, and we’re throwing ourselves away as things to get it. But the second, which
contemporary Kantians have taken up, is that in 21st century heterosex, it is rarely that
symmetrical. Often, women are consenting to being used as things in ways that entrench
and discipline patterns of gendered oppression. Sometimes, this takes the form of sexual
violation. Other times, it is simply another bar on what Marilyn Frye called the birdcage of
oppression: another night being treated as a prop in someone’s pornographic fantasy [29].
If what we emphasize about these experiences is that women consented to them, then we treat
sexual objectification as a normative form of gender discipline: we assume that because
you consented, the way you are treated must be okay. This, in turn, enforces patterns of
adaptive preference, in which women come to believe that they prefer to be treated in
these ways [30,31], that being objectified is in fact what they want: that what one really
wants, when one wants sex, is being wanted [32], even if how one is wanted is as a thing.
As Carol Hay has argued, this has an impact on women’s ability to set and pursue ends for
themselves, and thus, to respect themselves as rational beings [31]. We will return to this
point later.
4. Beyond Consent: Sharing Ends
Having argued that consent alone cannot solve the problem that sex poses, that of
using persons as things, Kant famously offers a solution: marriage. Namely, monogamous,
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
7 of 16
lifelong legal marriage defined by an equality of possessions, so that each person can be
said to “gain the other” person as they lose themselves. Romantic, right?
As contemporary Kantians, from Herman to Varden, have argued: it is kind of romantic [3,8]. At the heart of Kant’s very conservative account of marriage as essential to
permissible sex, is a radical idea: the reason marriage transforms sex is that it creates a
context in which partners share their ends, creating a community of ends. Marriage right is different from contract right: instead of aligning ends, married partners share their ends, which
is to say, they each transform their end-setting projects to have a shared community of
ends. So, because partners share ends, they cannot use one another’s body against their will:
because we share ends, sex becomes a shared activity in pursuing those ends, a condition
in which we each use one another to pursue our joint ends. In marriage, partners do not
merely consent to one another’s ends, or will actions in pursuit of one another’s ends: they
take on one another’s ends as their own, thereby transforming their own ends accordingly.
On Kant’s account, this must happen in a lifelong marriage, so that we only ever do
this once, and we do it permanently, and with all of our respective ends.8 Kantian scholars
have argued that we can take a lot of what’s useful here without assuming that it needs to be
forever [33,34]; others go further and argue that it need not even occur within a long-term,
committed relationship: it can happen within a given sexual encounter [10]. I argue that
we can generate a Kantian account of sex as a relation of shared ends without tethering
it to marriage, or even to a robust relationship.9 Whereas consent constructs a relation
in which persons propose (or assume) an end, and another assents to that end, a shared
community of ends requires people to each bring their ends to the table, and engage in a
process of transforming their own ends in light of the ends of their partner(s). This means
that partners carry what Lois Pineau has called an epistemological duty to in fact know
one another’s ends, and it means that partners have a duty to treat one another’s ends as
reasons to act accordingly [16,28]. My claim is that these duties can stand independently from
marriage, and indeed, from broader romantic relationships.10 If we can develop an account
of what it means to have sexual ends, or the ends relevant to a given sexual encounter, then
we can begin to think about what it might mean to treat sharing sexual ends as a model for
rightful sex in a contemporary context [28].11
Kant thinks that sharing ends in this way solves the problem of using persons as things
because when I share your ends, I have to know what they are, even if they change. This
requires us to treat others as ends in themselves in what Christine Korsgaard has called the
“positive sense,” in which we are required to respect the ends that another person has set for
themselves—which means, of course, knowing the ends another has set for themselves [35]
(pp. 192–193) [36] (p. 120).12 This is importantly different from how we align our ends
through contract. When I consent to an activity with you, we may agree on any terms and
limits needed to ensure that we do not end up treating one another as a means only. But
there is a limit to what we need to know of each other’s ends. I may agree to the activity, or
even to your ends, but this is not the same thing as taking your ends as my own.
In a shared community of ends, I not only understand that my partner is a person
with ends, but I agree to take their ends as my own, i.e., to transform my own ends in light
of my partner’s ends, on the condition that they will do so reciprocally. I can’t use you
only for my ends because my ends have been transformed: we are working towards our
ends. If your ends change, our ends change: sharing ends is an open, ongoing process. I
cannot treat you as a thing in a way that violates your humanity, because I no longer have
competing duties to myself and you: the idea is, my duties are dictated by our ends; they
are duties of solidarity. Korsgaard argues that “the kind of reciprocity I am discussing here
is not mere exchange from which one can walk away. What is exchanged is a part of one’s
practical identity, and what results is a transformation of that identity” [35] (p. 215 f 14).13
The “shared community of ends” model modifies autonomy in a way that the consent
model does not: it holds that what intimacy requires is not just that I respect my partner’s
relevant ends, but that I change what I want, that I rethink my own ends, to ensure that my
ends are my partner’s ends.
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
8 of 16
This is a robust ideal. And for Kant, it must be, because sex is a serious moral problem.
There are many ways we might fall short of this ideal: we might fail to communicate our
ends, to transform our ends in response to our partner’s, to take our partner’s ends as a
reason to act accordingly, to will our shared ends, to generate duties of solidarity [28]. But
we do, I think, have models of this kind of end-sharing outside of robust relationships to
fall back on. We have, for example, the kinds of negotiation many of us engaged in during
the pandemic, when the risk was so high that it was insufficient to ask for consent (“can I
take my mask off?”) or to issue an invitation (“will you come for Christmas?”). Instead, we
talked about what we were willing to risk in order to see one another; we asked each other
what we wanted and what we prioritized; we transformed our own ends accordingly to
see one another safely. These negotiations were not unlike those that happen in kink spaces
regularly, where participants share their ends, preferences, and limits to arrive at a shared
vision of a joint scene or scenario. Both of these are high-risk situations. And sure, maybe
vanilla hookup sex isn’t so high-risk. Then again, maybe it is.
5. Sexual Ends
One problem with consent consistently identified by feminist scholars is that because
consent orients attention to women’s assent or refusal, it often orients attention away from
other articulations of sexual desires, preferences, and limits [6,15,16]. In other words, it
often orients attention away from women’s articulations of their own sexual ends—and this
patterned communication can shape a paradigm in which women do not learn to share—or
set—sexual ends. Communicative frameworks, on the other hand, have emphasized the
importance of communicating and sharing sexual desires, preferences, and limits, but have
little to say about the conditions under which these desires, preferences, and limits are
shaped [16]. A benefit of a Kantian account is that in its attention to sharing sexual ends, it
also offers a starting point for an account of setting sexual ends.
At the heart of this is the difference between a requirement to have sex with someone
else such that I do not use them merely as a means, and to have sex with someone else such
that I respect them. What it is to respect me is to respect the ends I have chosen for myself.
And while the requirement not to treat me merely as a means is a requirement to respect
me as an end-setting being, e.g., not to get in the way of any ends I might hypothetically
choose for myself, the requirement to share my ends is a requirement to respect and take
on the actual ends I have chosen for myself. When you do that, you can’t use me as only
a thing, because you are respecting and sharing my ends, and thus, respecting me as an
end-setting being. But you can only do that if you know my ends—my actual ends, not
the ends you think I ought to set. These ends might be kind of kinky: we might both want
you to tie me up and whip me, or for you to indeed treat me as if I was a thing. But that is
different from me consenting to your proposal to tie me up and whip me, from me agreeing
to be a prop in your pornographic fantasy.
So, what are sexual ends? Let us begin by saying that sexual ends are those ends that
are relevant to a sexual situation. Some of these may be directly about sex: having an
orgasm might be an end, or pleasure, or connection, or being touched in ways that make
one feel seen—or, being touched in ways that make one feel like a thing. And some of these
might not be about sex, but be relevant to a given encounter: I may have ends of remaining
unpregnant, for example, or of protecting myself emotionally in some way—or, of not
being raped. Sexual end-setting is a subset of our general end-setting projects, and part
of engaging in sexual activity is determining what one wants from one’s sexual life—or,
setting and choosing ends relevant to one’s sexual self.
End-setting is part of the project of being a creature with wants and desires; it is
the intentional process of critically filtering our desires and inclinations, and determining
which will inform our life projects. Sexual desire and sexual ends are not the same things:
sexual ends are those desires that have been chosen by a person as the desires they can
will themselves to fulfill through action.14 Not all of my desires will survive this process
—either because I decide that some desires are not things I value, or are not consistent with
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
9 of 16
my broader projects, or cannot be fulfilled through the sorts of actions I feel I can will, or,
because I do not believe that my desires can be fulfilled, or that I am entitled to have them
fulfilled. This means, both, that we can be held responsible, to some degree, for the sorts of
things we select as sexual ends, and that any damage to our capacity for rational choice that
results from conditions of privilege, oppression, or trauma, may undermine our capacity to
choose sexual ends for ourselves.
I do not mean to suggest by this that our sexual ends are fully subject to rational
choice in the way that we might hope ends, more generally, might be. As Helga Varden has
persuasively argued, any account of sexual end-setting must make space for how sexual
desire, sexual identity, and gender identity are part of how we feel at home in the world
and ourselves, and so are not entirely reflective [3] (p. 129). There is therefore a certain
kind of “givenness” to our sexual desires, which shapes and limits the kinds of ends that
are possible for us [3] (p. 125).15 And because our desires are in many ways unreflective,
they are also shaped by the cultural and social context in which we find ourselves [17]
(p. 134) and the imaginary domain available to us [22], in ways we may not consciously
understand. These contexts may mark out what will seem “possible” or “plausible” to us;
they may generate and discipline our desires and limits in ways that we cannot perceive.
This is not to say that sexual desires cannot, and should not, be subject to some rational
scrutiny when they are chosen as reasons for action. Varden argues that our faculty of
desire is reflective, allowing us to step back and consider what we want and how it fits into
our broader life projects: our faculty of desire is the process through which we “develop,
transform, and integrate all the aspects of our being, grounding us in the particular beings
that we are” [3] (p. 44). Thus, while we generally accept the “givenness” of sexual desires at
the root of sexual orientation, we also understand that one’s sexual identity is the process
of accepting, choosing, and acting in light of those desires. Sexual end-setting is not
the process of choosing our desires, but of choosing which desires we will act on, and
how. Though our sexual desires might be alienated from our sense of self (I may have
desires I would rather not have, that are inconsistent with my broader projects), sexual
end-setting involves making my sexuality an integral part of my chosen identity and life
projects [3] (pp. 54–55). This means, too, that having our sexual ends ignored or violated
is a particularly pernicious form of violence, even when they are violated or ignored in
overtly nonviolent ways [3].
Our practice of setting ends for ourselves, therefore, is a critical component of what
Alcoff calls our self-making capacities [17] (p. 122). Our practices of setting sexual ends,
then, can be understood as our “making capacities concerning our sexual selves” [17]
(p. 122). This positions our sexual selves as an ongoing project or practice, rather than as
some “natural” sexual self. A key way that we make our sexual self is by encountering and
filtering our desires and limits, and by setting sexual ends for ourselves. Adopting new
ends, in the face of new desires, or new end-sharing projects may require us to gradually
shift or transform our existing projects [35] (p. 196) [37] (p. 180). Thus, end-setting is the
process by which we choose our lives and, by extension, constitute our identity.
Though end-setting is an individual project, it occurs in a social world, attentive to the
relationship of others to our ends. Relationships of all sorts are defined by how persons
interact with each other’s ends: contracts may bind parties to respect a limited set of one
another’s ends in particular ways; friendships and marriage turn on the reciprocity of
shared ends. Therefore, part of end-setting is selecting ends that could be aided or shared
by the specific others with whom we have, or hope to have relationships. We choose ends
that are consistent with the broader project of having the kinds of relationships we have, or
hope to have.16
Our end-setting projects, therefore, shape our relations with others. Having particular
ends, connected to particular life projects, is part of what makes us distinctive persons, and
so respecting me as a particular, embodied person means not just respecting my abstract
humanity, but respecting the particular, concrete ends I have chosen for myself. When
we set ends, we are also choosing what it will mean for others to respect us [28]. This is
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
10 of 16
particularly important in sexual contexts: we cannot extrapolate a person’s sexual ends
from our understanding of other features of their identity or life projects, or from our own
abstract sense of what others like or deserve. Sharing ends requires partners to share one
others’ actual ends, not the ends each supposes the other might have [36] (p. 115).
This is particularly important given that we set sexual ends in non-ideal conditions,
where the epistemic resources we rely on in our end-setting endeavors are hampered. We
set ends within history, in socially constructed contexts that may unknowingly inform both
our desires and preferences, and our end-setting projects [17]. Thus, as feminists have
long argued, women are actively dissuaded from setting sexual ends within rape and porn
culture; those ends they do set are often aimed at self-protection and resisting oppression:
for many women, “not being raped” is a central sexual end [17,38]. Many LGBTQIA+
people set sexual ends within social contexts shaped by compulsory cisheterosexuality and
persistent ignorance and pernicious prejudice against non-hetero sex. And, at the same
time, many heterosexual men set sexual ends in a context soaked in porn culture and toxic
masculinity, so that the ends that seem plausible may be violent and objectifying, shaped
by a pernicious sense of entitlement to sex, or a persistent fear of vulnerability.
As Carol Hay has pointed out, there is a range of ways that oppression can harm
a person’s ability to choose valuable ends for themselves, either because they do not
think they deserve valuable ends, or have been conditioned to prefer less valuable ends,
or because they cannot imagine that such valuable ends are real choices for them [31]
(p. 125). Our end-setting projects are doubly circumscribed by our epistemic resources
under conditions of oppression: first, by our sense of what kinds of desires we are entitled
to, and then by our sense of what kinds of actions are available to us.17 My sense of what
is plausible, or possible, for me will be shaped by my understanding of my place in the
world, which, under conditions of oppression and epistemic injustice, may be damaged
and dysfunctional in a variety of ways. And, because end-setting is relational, my choice
of ends may be further circumscribed by the kinds of ends I believe I can successfully
communicate in the contexts in which I find myself; if I have no reasonable belief that
a given end could gain “uptake” in a communicative exchange, then this may further
dissuade me from choosing such an end [39].
The epistemic terrain in which we set sexual ends thus shapes the kinds of sexual
ends that we set. While it is tempting to think of sexual ends as oriented by our desires,
or our chosen pleasures, it is equally important to acknowledge the ways that, in our
non-ideal sexual culture, our sexual end-setting projects may be (primarily) aimed at selfprotection. Recognizing self-protection as a valuable sort of sexual end is an important part
of recognizing non-ideal sexual agency [17,40] and affirming our duties to resist our own
oppression as part of our broader duty to ourselves to develop our own capacities [3,31].
There are dangers in self-protective and resistant [41] sexual end-setting projects.
As Hay points out, a woman’s duty to resist oppression will often manifest itself as a
duty to resist sexual harassment, objectification, and assault: it will manifest itself as an
ongoing epistemic orientation towards injustice, paying attention to and choosing the
appropriate resistant response to instances of harassment, objectification, discrimination,
and assault [31]. Hay illustrates this with the case of “Native Companion,” a woman
from one of David Foster Wallace’s essays who is harassed by a man while riding on an
amusement park ride, The Zipper. When he insists that she report the harassment, she tells
him that sometimes, she wants to relax, enjoy the ride, and ignore the assholes looking
up her skirt [31] (p. 90). Sometimes, Hay argues, riding the Zipper, seeking out fun and
pleasure even in the face of harassment, is what resisting one’s own oppression permits.
But more often, she suggests, the duty to resist oppression will take the form of recognizing
and perhaps choosing to respond to that harassment, out of respect for oneself. In other
words, the duty to resist oppression will often take the form of awareness of oppression,
rather than awareness of pleasure; it will often require enhanced knowledge of others,
awareness of and resistance to their ends. It will train us to be attentive to what others
want, rather than to an attunement to how our own desires inform our own end-setting
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
11 of 16
projects. Thus, while this self-protective form of end-setting, which is grounded in other
knowledge, is a practice required to resist immediate forms of oppression and abuse, it also
tends to retrench broader modes of gendered oppression, by further disciplining women
to think of sex in other-directed ways. As Varden and Alcoff agree, this allows us to see
the harms of sexual violation as a violation of our sexual self-making capacities; often, the
result of sexual violation is an abandonment of one’s sexual self-making in the name of
sexual self-protection; it is the adoption of a primarily self-protective sexual end-setting
project [3,17]. As Ann Cahill argues, the effects of this extend beyond those who have been
violated: when the threat of violation is a pervasive feature of one’s sexual awareness,
then even those who have not themselves been violated are disciplined into adopting
self-protective sexual end-setting projects [42].
The duty to resist our oppression is, as Hay puts it, a subset of the duty to develop our
capacities [31]. I think, then, that we could identify a duty to develop our sexual capacities,
or our sexual selves, through projects of sexual end-setting: we could say that, for those
of us who hope or plan to engage in sexual activity, we have duties both to resist our
own oppression in sexual contexts and to set sexual ends in ways that affirm the making
capacities of our sexual selves.18 I am not claiming that this duty is universal: there may be
those who have no intention to set or pursue sexual ends (and this may be, for example,
one way of understanding asexuality).19 But for those who do intend to engage in sexual
activity, for those engaged in the project of making a sexual self, the duty to set sexual
ends—and ends relevant to the sexual projects one hopes to have—is necessary to ensure
that one has ends to share. It is necessary, in other words, if one is to engage in sex without
being treated as an object.
6. The Case of Ms. Starlet
For those who think this requires too much, and that there was nothing wrong with
the standard account, and nothing wrong with simply taking sex to be a problem of treating
others merely as a means, consider a central example in Thomas Mappes’ essay on the
“standard” formulation of Kantian sexual consent [11]. Mappes describes the case of “Ms.
Starlet, a glamorous, wealthy, and highly successful model, [who] wants nothing more than
to become a movie superstar. Mr. Moviemogul, a famous producer, is very taken with Ms.
Starlet’s beauty. He invites her to come to his office for a screen test. After the screen test, Mr.
Moviemogul tells Ms. Starlet that he is prepared to make her a star, on the condition that
she agrees to sexual involvement with him. Ms. Starlet finds Mr. Moviemogul personally
repugnant; she is not at all sexually attracted to him. With great reluctance, she agrees to
his proposal” [11] (p. 285).
Read in the post-Weinstein era, the example is depressingly familiar, mapping almost
exactly the experience with Harvey Weinstein that Ambra Gutierrez caught on tape in an
NYPD sting, making visible the degradation and threat embedded in the “offer” [43]. The
question Mappes asks, however, is: is Mr. MovieMogul guilty of treating Ms. Starlet merely
as a means? He concludes: “has Mr. MovieMogul sexually used Ms. Starlet? No. He has
made her an offer that she has accepted, however reluctantly” [11] (p. 285). Ms. Starlet’s
consent, on Mappes’ account, solves the problem: if she accepts the offer, she is not being
used merely as a means. She gets something out of it, too.
These sorts of cases are prominent in the literature on consent, where determining the
difference between a “threat” and an “offer” is an important feature of defining “valid”
consent [11,14,44,45]. Like Mappes, Alan Wertheimer argues that consent is not valid when
it is in response to a threat that infringes on the consent-giver’s rights [45]. But if this is
the case, then determining whether Mr. Moviemogul’s “offer” operates as a threat hinges
on our understanding of what Ms. Starlet’s rights are. For Mappes, what matters is that
Mr. Moviegmogul’s offer is not coercive because, he says, “it is not plausible to believe that
she was, before acceptance of his proposal, entitled to his efforts to make her a star” [11]
(p. 285). But Mappes offers no account of what Ms. Starlet is entitled to, or what rights
might be infringed upon here: for example, is she entitled to be treated as someone with
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
12 of 16
value beyond her sexual value to him? Is she entitled to be treated as a professional, or
as someone with a career and audience that she brings to this new venture? Likewise, he
offers no account of what Mr. MovieMogul is not entitled to: he is not entitled to treat a
professional who has come, in good faith, to be evaluated on her acting abilities, as a sexual
object; he is not entitled to implicitly threaten her reputation, whether she takes him up on
his offer, or not.
This example is meant to illustrate, on Mappes’ account, how consent solves the
problem of treating someone merely as a means. But it illustrates, instead, how profoundly
consent is oriented through assumptions of male entitlement: men are entitled to sex, to
persuade, coax, and cajole women into sex. Men are entitled to set and pursue sexual
ends—even in contexts that are not, ostensibly, about sexual ends at all. And women are
entitled to accept or reject their proposals.
Tom Dougherty offers an alternate solution to this problem, arguing that in cases of
“minor duress,” consent often ameliorates the wrong embedded in the coercive offer, but it
does not eliminate it [14] (p. 342). Ms. Starlet would obviously be more gravely wronged if
Mr. Moviemogul simply ignored her refusal and forced her (as Weinstein did on numerous
occasions); that she is allowed to consent ameliorates how gravely she is wronged. On
Dougherty’s account, this complicates the “binary” of the consent paradigm, allowing
us to distinguish between the greater gravity of assault and the lesser gravity of coercive
offers [14] (p. 343).
Dougherty’s analysis, like Mappes’, hinges on the idea that the wrong of a “mildly”
coercive sexual offer is akin to the wrong of other kinds of minor duress. But if we take
seriously the Kantian distinction between using someone as a means, and using them as a
thing, we can better identify the wrong embedded in the offer. Ms. Starlet has entered a
negotiation in which there is, indeed, a risk that she will be treated as a means only; the
nature of the negotiation will determine if she can align her ends of becoming an actress
with Mr. Moviemogul’s ends. But when what he offers her is a sexual encounter to arrive
at those ends, he proposes to treat her as a thing. He has taken a meeting about using one
another as a means and turned it into a meeting about using one another as a thing. If we
assume that sexual use is continuous with other kinds of use, then we can’t identify this
wrong: we end up talking about the wrong of “coercive offers” and not about the wrong of
sexual harassment. The Kantian distinction allows us to more clearly delineate the wrong
of sexual harassment as what occurs not only when a person with more power makes a
coercive sexual offer, but also when they take a context in which one expects to be treated
as a person and a professional and turn it into a context in which one is objectified.
Dougherty may be right: Ms. Starlet’s consent may ameliorate the situation. But it is
difficult to read this example and not be troubled by the ways that, even if she consents,
Ms. Starlet is being used as a thing. She’s being given the “opportunity” to get something
out of it—to align her ends of stardom with Mr. MovieMogul’s end of treating her as a
prop in his performance of masculinity—but it is hard to say that this resolves the problem.
She’s being asked to consent to being used as a thing, to have her body used against her
will. And she’s being asked to do so in a context that, from her perspective, was not about
sex at all: a context in which she expected to be treated as a person, and finds herself asked,
instead, to agree to be reduced to the status of a thing.
This example illustrates how consent becomes a way to use someone, without using
them merely as a means. Mr. Moviemogul has enough power that he expects to get what he
wants, without compromise; Ms. Starlet’s willingness to accept his proposal is considered
only in light of the ends Mr. Moviemogul assumes that she has: she wants to be a movie
star. But as an end-setting being, Ms. Starlet likely has a broader range of ends that might
be relevant to this encounter, including an end of being taken seriously as an actress, an
end of not being used as a thing in someone else’s fantasy, and perhaps ends regarding
the kind of sex, and sexual relationships, she would prefer to have. On a Kantian account,
if she consents to this sexual relationship, she may be consenting because the encounter
aligns with one of her ends—her desire to be a movie star. She may not be used merely as
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
13 of 16
a means, but she may yet be used as a thing. And to consent to be used as a thing is indeed
to violate her duties to herself, including her duty to resist her own oppression. This is
dangerous because it may affect the kinds of ends she thinks are reasonable for her to have;
it may affect her capacity to set ends for herself. It may damage her will formation and the
making capacities of her sexual self [6].
Ms. Starlet’s predicament is a problem difficult to capture with an account of sexuality
that takes sex to be a case of using someone merely as a means, and that therefore likens
sexual offers to other kinds of “opportunities.” As Mappes’ analysis shows, it is a problem
to which consent offers an unsatisfying, if not downright harmful, solution. Taking Kant’s
account of sexual objectification seriously allows us to clearly articulate the violation
embedded in an “offer” to use a person as a thing in ways that make sense of Ms. Starlet’s
predicament, and provides us with a critical tool for thinking about the kinds of sexual
wrongs surfaced by the MeToo movement.
7. Conclusions
This paper has asked what follows if we take the problem of objectification seriously,
and assume that sex is unlike the sorts of activities in which we are in danger of treating
others merely as a means. Drawing on feminist critiques of heterosex, and the problems of
“bad” sex and sexual harassment laid bare during the MeToo movement, I suggest that
we may have reason to take seriously Kant’s claim that sex is morally dangerous in that
it creates contexts in which we are likely to use one another like a thing. If this is the case,
Kant argues, then sexual consent is insufficient for addressing the moral dangers of sex. To
address this problem, I develop an account of setting and sharing sexual ends in a Kantian
key. An emphasis on setting sexual ends, I argue, is important for addressing concerns
about sexual agency in a social and epistemic context in which women are discouraged
from setting sexual ends of their own; an emphasis on sharing sexual ends can broaden
the forms of sexual communication and negotiation relevant to shaping permissible sexual
encounters. This framework provides us with critical tools for addressing those contexts
where, as Dougherty has argued, consent can only ameliorate, rather than eliminate, sexual
wrongs [14]. It offers resources for addressing pervasive sexual injustices articulated by
the MeToo movement, including “bad” sex and the kinds of sexual “offers” that often
constitute sexual harassment. In doing so, it provides us with resources for contemporary
moves to think beyond consent, and to grapple with the ways that “consent is particularly
insufficient as a means to protect women’s freedom” [17]. Conceiving of sex as a process of
setting and sharing sexual ends in a Kantian key provides us with resources for thinking
about the robust, ongoing project of making our sexual selves in nonideal conditions, as
well as for grounding emergent accounts of what permissible sex might look like beyond
consent. In doing so, it offers a critical middle ground between contemporary accounts of
sexual morality that center questions of individual agency or autonomy, and those that
foreground the intersubjective nature of sex.
Funding: This research received no external funding.
Institutional Review Board Statement: Not applicable.
Informed Consent Statement: Not applicable.
Data Availability Statement: Not applicable.
Conflicts of Interest: The author declares no conflict of interest.
Notes
1
Kant’s use of sex and slavery as parallel cases is admittedly troubling for a philosopher writing at the peak of the global slave
trade, and, as Lina Papadaki has pointed out, there are important differences between the cases: to consent to slavery is to cease
to own one’s person in a very real way, while to consent to sex does not lead to someone else having rights over my body and
my person in the same kind of permanent, conclusive way [46]. However, Kant’s thinking about sex and slavery are closely
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
14 of 16
intertwined with his earliest lecture notes on these questions, and he developed his arguments against slavery and prostitution
together. For more on the relationship between these arguments, see Pascoe 2022 [20].
2
As well as a persistent problem for LGBTQ + folk, who are subject to comparably high rates of sexual violence and violation,
regardless of gender identity.
3
A notable exception is Alan Soble’s recent consideration of whether a “free & informed consent” principle should include being
informed about one’s own, and one’s partner’s motives for having sex; this means interrogating the why of sex as well as the
what [13]. Soble acknowledges that satisfying such a principle would be “not easy to accomplish”. I agree with him, that the
resources within consent frameworks give us few tools for interrogating our own motives, let alone those of our partners. But as I
argue here, I think developing a framework that takes setting sexual ends to be a critical step in the process of sharing sexual ends
can do much to develop the kinds of resources we need, and to cash out the sorts of “epistemic responsibilities” Pineau claims
that we have in a communicative model [16]. In other words, we may need resources beyond consent for satisfying a rigorous
“free & informed consent” model such as the one Soble proposes.
4
We might think of this by way of Haslanger’s distinction between the manifest concept—the conception of consent laid out
in campus consent policies—and the operative concept—the way consent is practiced. Much work to ameliorate consent has
transformed manifest, but not operative, consent practices [47]; for further discussion see Pascoe’s forthcoming [48].
5
Dougherty proposes that we acknowledge the existence of “partially valid consent” to identify those cases in which consent
ameliorates, but does not eliminate, sexual harms, such as cases in which consent is given under minor duress [14] (p. 342). Quill
Kukla has likewise identified the importance of developing an understanding of “non-ideal consent” to deal with those cases in
which fully valid consent is impossible—for example when one person is cognitively impaired [40]. The Kantian framework I
develop here is consistent with Kukla’s argument since the Kantian notion of end-sharing is an important feature of Kantian
relations of caregiving so that one’s right to care for another involves taking their ends, or, in the case of the cognitively impaired,
what you think their ends would be, as your own. But, as I discuss in Section 6, it is explicitly designed to identify the wrongs of
the cases of “minor duress” Dougherty examines, and to give an account for why consent is insufficient to identify and remedy
the wrongs of coercion and duress.
6
Writing as Rebecca Kukla.
7
Kleingeld’s key example of consent taking the form of “I will it” is that of a servant consenting to employment, but on Kant’s
account, the case of the servant is an instance of shared ends within the household, rather than one of consent [12] (p. 403). For an
analysis of this distinction as it applies to the servant, see [10].
8
I think we have resources in Kant’s argument for challenging both the monogamous and life-long nature of marriage: he argues,
after all, that we enter into a community of ends with both our marital partners and with servants, who agree to a community of
ends in which they will do “whatever is necessary for the good of the household” [7] (6:283). So we can do this with multiple
people, and we can do it in a relationship which can be terminated or temporary.
9
We can, for example, look to the kinky sex community to find examples of the kinds of carefully constructed shared communities
of sexual ends that can be constructed in limited sexual encounters. In kink communities, we find models of shared communities
of ends being created through careful communicative practices without partners needing to share the full details of their moral
commitments and end-setting projects. In a kink context, my partner may know little about me beyond my commitment to my
sexual ends, which align with theirs—thus setting us up for the shared community of ends. In other words, my partner needs to
have some understanding of my specific sexual end-setting project, which is something I can reveal to them through the process
of communicatively end-sharing, without necessarily sharing much about my broader ends or commitments. Instead, in the
construction of a shared community of ends, we may focus on the communicative practices that need to be respected: we may set
limits, determine safe words or nonverbal cues, and clearly communicate how certain speech acts and body language should be
interpreted. This process occurs against a background requirement that we have each entered this shared community of ends
with a clear sense of our own ends, desires, commitments, and limits, and that we co-construct a shared language through which
to communicate those throughout our encounter.
10
In this sense, I take my argument to be consistent with Raja Halwani’s account of the ways that the forms of objectification at play
in casual sex and promiscuity need not render these sexual encounters morally impermissible [49]. On my account, however, the
remedy is not merely consent, but a condition in which partners share a relevant set of sexual ends, which may include sexual
ends of treating one another in objectifying ways.
11
An account of sexual ends should be a key component of both communicative [16] and negotiation [50] models of permissible sex
since it attends to what one communicates or negotiates: what one brings to the table.
12
Korsgaard distinguishes this from the “negative sense”, in which we respect one another as the sort of being who can set ends for
themselves, which is to say that we respect autonomy, and we leave their choices up to them [35] (pp. 194–195). On my account,
treating another as an end in themselves in this “negative sense” is sufficient to ensure that one does not use them as a mere
means, but it may be insufficient in cases like sex where one is in danger of using another as a thing. In these cases, something
more akin to the “positive sense” in which I respect and share the ends another has set for themselves is required: one’s capacity
to successfully share and negotiate ends with another—is precisely what protects us from being treated like a thing in contexts in
which such “thingness” is on the table.
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
15 of 16
13
Such “relations of reciprocity” and shared ends include sex, friendship, and justice [35] (p. 195): contexts in which we engage in
particular projects of setting, sharing, and negotiating ends with one another, and in which we allow ourselves and our projects
to be transformed by these ends. In the context of negotiation a “kingdom of ends”, the goal is to arrive, through this process,
at a set of ends which could be universal, “subject to a possible vote” [35] (p. 193). I think we should distinguish practices
of sharing sexual ends from practices of arriving at a universalizable kingdom of ends in that the sexual negotiations aren’t
meant to be generalizable: we should take seriously the specificity of sexual desires and for non-vanilla desires, things that “not
everyone” might agree to. That’s why the specific relations through which we explore our sexuality are important: the goal of
a sexual community of ends is to set ends that will be transformed by one’s encounters with particular others: to set ends in an
intersubjective key.
14
While morality is the recognition of obligatory ends, my focus in this section is on normative but nonmoral ends, which are
optional and contingent, suggested by our wants and whims and desires. Because end-setting involves rationally filtering our
desires, we have choices about which desires we will adopt as the grounds for possible ends. We may ask ourselves, is this a
desire I want to fulfill? Can I will a set of actions to fulfill this desire? Do I value this desire? See [37].
For example, those who are truly committed, like Kant, to the proposition that homosexuality is unnatural and wrong will
nevertheless—like, evidently, Kant—find it impossible to cultivate heterosexual sexual ends in a landscape of homosexual
desire [3].
For example, lying, deception, and coercion are wrong both because they thwart the ends of others, and because they prevent
others from helping us to our ends by making our ends opaque to them.
15
16
17
Carol Hay argues “we cannot simply appeal to people’s subjective preferences—what people choose for themselves—when
internalized oppression has undermined their sense of what they are entitled to” [31] (p. 32).
18
This argument is consistent with Helga Varden’s move to understand the duty to resist our own oppression as a perfect duty,
which must be realized alongside imperfect duties that hold us accountable to our own happiness and development, and to our
duties to assist others in theirs. Thus, we would have perfect duties to resist our own oppression as well as imperfect duties to
develop our sexual desires, limits, and preferences, to set sexual ends of our own that align with our distinctive conceptions of
happiness, and not merely with projects of self-defense [3].
19
This tracks accounts of asexuality that take asexuality to be a sexual orientation [51]; see also [3] (p. 95) for the ways that asexuality
combines the “givenness” of sexual orientation with the projects of end-setting that shape a sexual identity.
References
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
Goldman, A.H. Plain Sex. In The Philosophy of Sex: Contemporary Readings; Halwani, R., Soble, A., Hoffman, S., Held, J., Eds.;
Rowman & Littlefield: London, UK, 2017; pp. 53–72.
Soble, A. Sexual Use. In The Philosophy of Sex: Contemporary Readings; Halwani, R., Soblem, A., Hoffman, S., Held, J., Eds.; Rowman
& Littlefield: London, UK, 2017; pp. 293–320.
Varden, H. Sex, Love, and Gender: A Kantian Theory; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2020.
Gardner, J. The opposite of rape. Oxf. J. Leg. Stud. 2018, 38, 48–70. [CrossRef]
Mason, E. Problems of Consent. Talk at the Society for the Philosophy of Sex and Love Virtual Seminar, November 30; Society for the
Philosophy of Love and Sex: Philadelphia, PA, USA, 2022.
MacKinnon, C.A. Rape Redefined. Harv. Law Policy Rev. 2016, 10, 431.
Kant, I. Metaphysics of Morals; Gregor, M., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1996.
Herman, B. Could it be worth thinking about Kant on sex and marriage? In Immanuel Kant; Routledge: London, UK, 2017;
pp. 231–249.
Langton, R. Sexual Solipsism: Philosophical Essays on Pornography and Objectification; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2009.
Nussbaum, M.C. Objectification. Philos. Public Aff. 1995, 24, 249–291. [CrossRef]
Mappes, T. Sexual Morality and the Concept of Using Another Person. In The Philosophy of Sex: Contemporary Readings; Halwani,
R., Soble, A., Hoffman, S., Held, J., Eds.; Rowman & Littlefield: London, UK, 2017; pp. 273–292.
Kleingeld, p. How to use someone ‘merely as a means’. Kantian Rev. 2020, 25, 389–414. [CrossRef]
Soble, A. On the Sufficiency of Sexual Consent. In The Palgrave Handbook of Sexual Ethics; Springer International Publishing: Cham,
Switzerland, 2022; pp. 287–299.
Dougherty, T. Sexual misconduct on a scale: Gravity, coercion, and consent. Ethics 2021, 131, 319–344. [CrossRef]
Kukla, R. That’s what she said: The language of sexual negotiation. Ethics 2018, 129, 70–97. [CrossRef]
Pineau, L. Date rape: A feminist analysis. Law Philos. 1989, 8, 217–243. [CrossRef]
Alcoff, L.M. Rape and Resistance; John Wiley & Sons: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2018.
Kant, I. Lectures on Ethics. Heath, P., Schneewind, J.B., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1997.
Kant, I.; Frederick, R. Lectures and Drafts on Political Philosophy; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2016.
Pascoe, J. Kant’s Theory of Labour; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2022.
Pascoe, J. Hunger for You: Kant and Kinky Sex. What Philosophy Can Tell You About Your Lover; Open Court Press: Chicago, IL, USA,
2012; pp. 25–36.
Cornell, D. The Imaginary Domain: Abortion, Pornography and Sexual Harrassment; Routledge: London, UK, 2016.
Philosophies 2023, 8, 21
23.
24.
25.
26.
27.
28.
29.
30.
31.
32.
33.
34.
35.
36.
37.
38.
39.
40.
41.
42.
43.
44.
45.
46.
47.
48.
49.
50.
51.
16 of 16
Orenstein, p. Boys & Sex: Young Men on Hook-Ups, Love, Porn, Consent and Navigating the New Masculinity; Souvenir Press: London,
UK, 2020.
Srinivasan, A. The Right to Sex; Bloomsbury Publishing: London, UK, 2022.
Bauer, N. Pornutopia. N+1 2007, 5, 63–73.
West, R. The Harms of Consensual Sex. In The Philosophy of Sex: Contemporary Readings; Halwani, R., Soble, A., Hoffman, S., Held,
J., Eds.; Rowman & Littlefield: London, UK, 2017; pp. 371–380.
Chadha, K. Sexual consent and having sex together. Oxf. J. Leg. Stud. 2020, 40, 619–644. [CrossRef]
Pascoe, J. “Respect Women”: Thinking Beyond Consent After# MeToo. The Palgrave Handbook of Sexual Ethics; Palgrave Macmillan:
Cham, Switzerland, 2022; pp. 325–338.
Frye, M. The Politics of Reality; Crossing Press: Freedom, CA, USA, 1983; pp. 1–16.
Khader, S.J. Adaptive Preferences and Women’s Empowerment; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011.
Hay, C. Kantianism, Liberalism, and Feminism: Resisting Oppression; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2013.
Wade, L. American Hookup: The New Culture of Sex on Campus; WW Norton & Company: New York, NY, USA, 2017.
Denis, L. From friendship to marriage: Revising Kant. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2001, 63, 1–28. [CrossRef]
Papadaki, L. Kantian marriage and beyond: Why it is worth thinking about Kant on marriage. Hypatia 2010, 25, 276–294.
[CrossRef]
Korsgaard, C.M. Creating the Kingdom of Ends; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1996.
O’neill, O. Constructions of reason: Explorations of Kant’s Practical Philosophy; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1989.
Herman, B. The Practice of Moral Judgment; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1993.
Gavey, N. Just Sex?: The Cultural Scaffolding of Rape; Routledge: London, UK, 2018.
Dotson, K. Tracking epistemic violence, tracking practices of silencing. Hypatia 2011, 26, 236–257. [CrossRef]
Kukla, Q.R. A nonideal theory of sexual consent. Ethics 2021, 131, 270–292. [CrossRef]
Bryant, C. Erotic Defiance: Womanism, Freedom, and Resistance; Fortress Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 2023.
Cahill, A.J. Rethinking Rape; Cornell University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2001.
Farrow, R. From Aggressive Overtures to Sexual Assault: Harvey Weinstein’s Victims Tell Their Stories. The New Yorker October
10 2017. Available online: https://www.newyorker.com/news/news-desk/from-aggressive-overtures-to-sexual-assault-harveyweinsteins-accusers-tell-their-stories (accessed on 19 January 2023).
Kimberly, K.F. Consent and Coercion. Ariz. State Law J. 2018, 50, 951–1006.
Wertheimer, A. Consent to Sexual Relations; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2003.
Papadaki, L. Kant on Sexuality and Marriage. In The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism and Feminist Philosophy; Springer
International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2023; pp. 151–168.
Haslanger, S. Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2012.
Pascoe, J. The Whiteness of Consent. In Consent: Gender, Power and Subjectivity; Laurie, J.H., Róisín, R.F., Eds.; Routledge Press:
London, UK, forthcoming.
Halwani, R. Casual sex, promiscuity, and objectification. In The Philosophy of Sex: Contemporary Readings; Halwani, R., Soble, A.,
Hoffman, S., Held, J., Eds.; Rowman & Littlefield: London, UK, 2017; pp. 273–292.
Anderson, M.J. Negotiating sex. S. Cal. L. Rev. 2004, 78, 1401.
Dembroff, R.A. What is sexual orientation? Philosophers 2016, 16. Available online: https://philpapers.org/archive/DEMWIS.pdf
(accessed on 3 March 2023).
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual
author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to
people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.