Skip to main content
Pretheoretically, (B) 'all believers are immortal' is about all believers, but (1) B is not about any unbeliever. Similarly, (M) 'all mortals are unbelievers' is not about any immortal, but (2) M is about all mortals. But B and M are... more
    • by 
The Principal Principle (PP) says that, for any proposition A, given any admissible evidence and the proposition that the chance of A is x%, one's conditional credence in A should be x%. Humean Supervenience (HS) claims that, among... more
    • by 
I defend the epistemic thesis that evaluations of people in terms of their moral character as good, bad, or intermediate are almost always epistemically unjustified. (1) Because most people are fragmented (they would behave deplorably in... more
    • by 
    • by 
If (backward) time travel is possible, presumably so is my shooting my younger self (YS); then apparently I can kill him -I can commit retrosuicide. But if I were to kill him I would not exist to shoot him, so how can I kill him? The... more
    • by 
Besides pure declarative arguments, whose premises and conclusions are declaratives ("you sinned shamelessly; so you sinned"), and pure imperative arguments, whose premises and conclusions are imperatives ("repent quickly; so repent"),... more
    • by 
You may not know me well enough to evaluate me in terms of my moral character, but I take it you believe I can be evaluated: it sounds strange to say that I am indeterminate, neither good nor bad nor intermediate. Yet I argue that the... more
    • by 
Suppose that a sign at the entrance of a restaurant reads: "Do not enter these premises unless you have a reservation and you are properly attired. " You see someone who is properly attired and is about to enter, and you tell her: "Don't... more
    • by 
    • by 
    • by 
Surrender; therefore, surrender or fight" is apparently an argument corresponding to an inference from an imperative to an imperative.
    • by 
Imperatives cannot be true or false, so they are shunned by logicians. And yet imperatives can be combined by logical connectives: "kiss me and hug me" is the conjunction of "kiss me" with "hug me". This example may suggest that... more
    • by 
Kadri Vihvelin, in ''What time travelers cannot do'' (Philos Stud 81:315-330, 1996), argued that ''no time traveler can kill the baby who in fact is her younger self'', because (V1) ''if someone would fail to do something, no matter how... more
    • by 
According to Hempel's paradox, evidence (E) that an object is a nonblack nonraven confirms the hypothesis (H) that every raven is black. According to the standard Bayesian solution, E does confirm H but only to a minute degree. This... more
    • by 
    • by 
1980) proposed the Principal Principle (PP) and a "reformulation" which later on he called 'OP' (Old Principle). Reacting to his belief that these principles run into trouble, Lewis (1994) concluded that they should be replaced with the... more
    • by 
The first sentence of NE I.2 has roughly the form: "If A [there is a universal end] and B (because, if not-B, then C), then D [this end will be the best good]". According to some commentators, Aristotle uses B to infer A; but then the... more
    • by 
I defend the following version of the ought-implies-can principle: (OIC) by virtue of conceptual necessity, an agent at a given time has an (objective, pro tanto) obligation to do only what the agent at that time has the ability and... more
    • by 
    • by 
There exists a long and widespread tradition, with roots in classical Greek and eastern thought, which maintains that the life of desire, the life in which the pursuit of the satisfaction of desires occupies a central place, is doomed to... more
    • by 
    •   3  
      PhilosophyPolitical ScienceRatio