<p>This chapter seeks to show how the most consequential contemporary critiques of mediatio... more <p>This chapter seeks to show how the most consequential contemporary critiques of mediation—found in the work of Quentin Meillassoux and Alain Badiou—reinstall a form of species-humanism under cover of a procedure of mathematical abstraction that Marx (and Melville) have already put in question. Here—and returning to the distinctive imbrication of things with the matter of poetic expression and with the expression of what comes to be called subjectivity that so captivates Marx about Lucretius's poem—it is John Donne, Pablo Neruda, and again Freud who provide us with a contemporary account of de-theologized fetishism on which to build a critico-political project in the wake of Marx's writing.</p>
Alain Badiou’s Seminar: The One – Descartes, Plato, Kant (1983-1984) inaugurates "The Semina... more Alain Badiou’s Seminar: The One – Descartes, Plato, Kant (1983-1984) inaugurates "The Seminar," the collection of transcribed and edited seminars that Badiou chose for publication from the sessions he held over his career. To its place opening "The Seminar" other, perhaps more important functions should be added, however. The Seminar: The One serves, with the companion seminar on the Infinite (1984-1985), as a bridge between Badiou’s Theory of the Subject (1982) and the work for which he is best known, Being and Event (L'Être et l'Événement, 1988; English translation, 2005).1 (His play Incident at Antioch, whose first drafts are written during the years that Badiou holds the seminars on The One and The Infinite, builds another, rather different, bridge.) At once quite technical and rather chatty, The One – Descartes, Plato, Kant offers a genealogy for two decisive steps in Badiou’s thought: his description and his axiomatization of the operation “count...
Regress threatens throughout Lyotard’s Differend, especially where the argument appears to make n... more Regress threatens throughout Lyotard’s Differend, especially where the argument appears to make normative ethical or political claims. How a term, a case or an example “links onto” a phrase serves as a way of examining how instituting can be non-regressively grounded, and with what consequences for abstract political subjectivity. The essay offers an alternative to liberal philosophical (Arendt, Nussbaum) and jurisprudential (Marbury v. Madison) schemata of political institution.
Le séminaire "La vie la mort" de Derrida opère, comme d'avance motivé par ses suites et comme con... more Le séminaire "La vie la mort" de Derrida opère, comme d'avance motivé par ses suites et comme contresigné par ce nom qui n'apparaît pas-le nom d'Épicure-un virage vers un matérialisme non productif, non représentationnel, dépourvu en quelque sort de statut ontologique, voir non ontologisable, triomphant, normatif, voué à une économie de la cause. Nietzsche, lecteur antagonique d'Épicure (Lettre à Ménécée: "Accoutume-toi à considérer que la mort n'est rien pour nous")-constitue son écran-substitut. Nietzsche, dont la lecture sert à fermer-ouvrir les grandes boucles du séminaire de Derrida. Il s'agit donc de fouiller "La vie la mort" à la recherche des traces de la rencontre Nietzsche-Épicure-une rencontre définitive, elle, bien qu'invisible et silencieuse, bien que presqu'illisible dans le texte de Derrida, au sujet du rapport "la vie la mort."
Cet étrange anneau ne dit oui à la vie que dans l'équivoque surdéterminante du triomphe de la vie... more Cet étrange anneau ne dit oui à la vie que dans l'équivoque surdéterminante du triomphe de la vie, du triomphe sur la vie, du triomphe marqué dans le sur d'un survivre. Derrida, "Survivre" 1 En tout cas la traduction étrange de Sache par cause est portée par la suite, lorsque Heidegger enchaîne, "die Sache, der Streitfall", la chose, le cas litigieux est en soi-même "ist in sich selbst Aus-einander-setzung." Derrida, "La vie la mort" 2 Mais non, il n'est pas là, rien à voir, on n'y touche pas, Épicure, dans le séminaire que nous lirons ensemble, le séminaire de Jacques Derrida "La vie la mort," conduit durant les années 1975-1976. "Mes chances," le grand essai de Derrida sur l'Épicurisme et sur la chute, le cas, cadere et fallentel le cas-chute, si peu dévié, qui hante la Sache quand elle devient der Streitfall (litige, différend)n'arrivera que sept ans plus tard, en 1982. Lucrèce, lui, "disciple sombre, mais venu à la clarté," comme 3 l'appelle Nietzsche; Lucrèce, qui est toujours en retard, ou qui arrive trop tôt comme le dit toujours Nietzsche, Lucrèce n'apparaîtra chez Derrida qu'en 1989, dans le cadre du séminaire "Manger l'autre." C'est là que Derrida commentera des vers du De rerum natura, seulement certains, se gardant dans ces pages toujours inédites de faire paraître le poème complet-et, même là, dans ce séminaire, ce ne sera qu'au travers de la traduction-adaptation que fait Michel Deguy du poème Latin. 4 Or, bien en avance de ces "rencontres" (je vois que vous devinez déjà le registre, l'institution même, que je "sup-pose" ici), bien en avance de ces rencontres explicitement épicuriennes, Derrida se meut déjà dans le jardin qu'enclosent, ou qu'ouvrent, les phrases célèbres que j'ai un peu mâchées pour en faire mon titre. Le lexique de la cause, celui qui noue les trois boucles du séminaire "La vie la mort," y joue constamment, à travers, ou de travers, comme obliquement : comme si, dans les matériaux que manie Derrida (le Nietzsche de Heidegger, les textes de Jacob, ceux de Nietzsche), quelque chose de cette "rencontre" qui reste encore à venir entre Derrida et Épicure était "portée par la suite" de certaines rencontres, comme enchaînée. Sans qu'on puisse pour autant dire qu'il y a, au sens classique, au sens
Regress threatens throughout Lyotard's Differend, especially where the argument appears to make n... more Regress threatens throughout Lyotard's Differend, especially where the argument appears to make normative ethical or political claims. How a term, a case or an example "links onto" a phrase serves as a way of examining how instituting can be non-regressively grounded, and with what consequences for abstract political subjectivity. The essay offers an alternative to liberal philosophical (Arendt, Nussbaum) and jurisprudential (Marbury v. Madison) schemata of political institution.
What do we need to know about “art” or “class struggle” before considering their relation to one ... more What do we need to know about “art” or “class struggle” before considering their relation to one another? Could you describe a specific work or text that might serve as an illustration of class struggle or as an exploration of the problem of representing it? Let us say that visual art, broadly speaking, does express the worldview of the dominant class. What kind of art then expresses the worldview of, say, hedge fund managers? Does the dialectic of the visible and invisible still hold for conceptual and post-conceptual art? What alternative critical apparatus would you propose, since neither Lenin nor John William Cooke seemed to care much for art. Why should we?
This essay describes and addresses the difficulty that Hispanism has in imagining its foundations... more This essay describes and addresses the difficulty that Hispanism has in imagining its foundations and origination. It reads Cervantes’s novela ejemplar “El licenciado Vidriera” as an allegory of disciplinarity and disciplinarization, which the novela treats as a matter inextricable from the sense of touch. This Cervantic, early-modern account of the primal relation between discipline and touch, the essay suggests, anticipates and allows us to see unexpected consequences to Derrida’s quite radical approach to disciplinarity.
“It goes without saying that but little use can be made of Lucretius” [Es versteht sich, dass Luc... more “It goes without saying that but little use can be made of Lucretius” [Es versteht sich, dass Lucretius nur wenig benutzt werden kann].1 So, by way of preface or prophylaxis, opens the fourth of Marx’s Notebooks on Epicurean Philosophy, composed around 1839 as Marx was preparing his doctoral dissertation. A long list of citations from De Rerum Natura (DRN) follows, and then Lucretius is put to use—as Plutarch’s antagonist, in the long battle over the Epicurean tradition. In these early, informal notes by a young dissertator the reception of Lucretius hangs in the balance; what Althusser refers to as an “underground current” of the materialism of the encounter surfaces and is soon, over the course of the next 15 years, rechanneled or resubmerged.2 An account of mediation at odds with the mechanics, the economics, of use presents itself here, to be translated, never entirely successfully, first into the great Hegelian lexicon that the young Marx and his preceptors were unfolding, then into the languages of political economy. What sorts of use can be made of a thing? In what respects is Lucretius something to be used?
Translatability in natural languages today supports, and can only be understood in the context of... more Translatability in natural languages today supports, and can only be understood in the context of, economic globalization, and the universalization of market logic. ‘Untranslatability’, as it is most often construed, does not provide a critical alternative to this logic: it bolsters it. A different account of untranslatability (and, by extension, of what it means for expressions in natural languages to be ‘translatable’) is required: this essay seeks to provide such. It finds in passages in Marx and in Derrida's Monolinguisme de l'autre, and in different translations of those texts, an untranslatability which is not one, irreducible to mathematical identity.
The battle is not yet joined, and the poet has listed for us the array of warriors, of ships, of ... more The battle is not yet joined, and the poet has listed for us the array of warriors, of ships, of forces. “tell me now,” the poet of The Iliad has sung, in Richmond Lattimore's translation, “you Muses who have your homes on Olympos. / For you, who are goddesses, are there, and you know all things, / and we have heard only the rumor of it and know nothing. / Who then of those were the chief men and the lords of the Danaäns?” (2.484-88). Then the catalog: the list. In the Homeric tradition, a catalog unrolls under the guarding eye of the Muses, the witnesses, under the keeping and inspiring eye of divine and distant figures who have seen the scene, whose witnessing we imagine, from whom we borrow the faint authority we wear when we begin our own songs. These Homeric lists seem to us scattershot today—this ship here, that one there, a warrior next to another warrior simply on the grounds that, yes, there he stands. And yet to the extent that they turn on the authority of the fact, of a divine witness who reports this disorder and from whom we take the rumors of the fact, Homer's lists are at core structured, signed, legitimated. The Iliad is not only the story of the encounter between Trojans and Achaeans; it is also the story of the encounter between two phenomenologies—one envisioning orders of events, names on a list, as they present themselves to us, rumored, accidentally, contingently; another envisioning the order of what presents itself according to the signature of the presiding Muse, according to an immanent principle of structure derivable, if at all, from the totality of the list. These two encounters and these two phenomenologies don't line up; they're fought on different fields and at different levels; they have different scopes. One phenomenology is in principle endless—there's always another matter at hand; we cannot foreclose the possibility that another ship will appear; and the chaos of the battle always means that another figure, foe or friend, may step before us when we least expect it. The other is always bounded, limited on both sides by the immanent unfolding of its principle: that this or that friend or foe should have appeared makes manifest, sub specie aeternitatis, the reason for his, or her, appearing.
<p>This chapter seeks to show how the most consequential contemporary critiques of mediatio... more <p>This chapter seeks to show how the most consequential contemporary critiques of mediation—found in the work of Quentin Meillassoux and Alain Badiou—reinstall a form of species-humanism under cover of a procedure of mathematical abstraction that Marx (and Melville) have already put in question. Here—and returning to the distinctive imbrication of things with the matter of poetic expression and with the expression of what comes to be called subjectivity that so captivates Marx about Lucretius's poem—it is John Donne, Pablo Neruda, and again Freud who provide us with a contemporary account of de-theologized fetishism on which to build a critico-political project in the wake of Marx's writing.</p>
Alain Badiou’s Seminar: The One – Descartes, Plato, Kant (1983-1984) inaugurates "The Semina... more Alain Badiou’s Seminar: The One – Descartes, Plato, Kant (1983-1984) inaugurates "The Seminar," the collection of transcribed and edited seminars that Badiou chose for publication from the sessions he held over his career. To its place opening "The Seminar" other, perhaps more important functions should be added, however. The Seminar: The One serves, with the companion seminar on the Infinite (1984-1985), as a bridge between Badiou’s Theory of the Subject (1982) and the work for which he is best known, Being and Event (L'Être et l'Événement, 1988; English translation, 2005).1 (His play Incident at Antioch, whose first drafts are written during the years that Badiou holds the seminars on The One and The Infinite, builds another, rather different, bridge.) At once quite technical and rather chatty, The One – Descartes, Plato, Kant offers a genealogy for two decisive steps in Badiou’s thought: his description and his axiomatization of the operation “count...
Regress threatens throughout Lyotard’s Differend, especially where the argument appears to make n... more Regress threatens throughout Lyotard’s Differend, especially where the argument appears to make normative ethical or political claims. How a term, a case or an example “links onto” a phrase serves as a way of examining how instituting can be non-regressively grounded, and with what consequences for abstract political subjectivity. The essay offers an alternative to liberal philosophical (Arendt, Nussbaum) and jurisprudential (Marbury v. Madison) schemata of political institution.
Le séminaire "La vie la mort" de Derrida opère, comme d'avance motivé par ses suites et comme con... more Le séminaire "La vie la mort" de Derrida opère, comme d'avance motivé par ses suites et comme contresigné par ce nom qui n'apparaît pas-le nom d'Épicure-un virage vers un matérialisme non productif, non représentationnel, dépourvu en quelque sort de statut ontologique, voir non ontologisable, triomphant, normatif, voué à une économie de la cause. Nietzsche, lecteur antagonique d'Épicure (Lettre à Ménécée: "Accoutume-toi à considérer que la mort n'est rien pour nous")-constitue son écran-substitut. Nietzsche, dont la lecture sert à fermer-ouvrir les grandes boucles du séminaire de Derrida. Il s'agit donc de fouiller "La vie la mort" à la recherche des traces de la rencontre Nietzsche-Épicure-une rencontre définitive, elle, bien qu'invisible et silencieuse, bien que presqu'illisible dans le texte de Derrida, au sujet du rapport "la vie la mort."
Cet étrange anneau ne dit oui à la vie que dans l'équivoque surdéterminante du triomphe de la vie... more Cet étrange anneau ne dit oui à la vie que dans l'équivoque surdéterminante du triomphe de la vie, du triomphe sur la vie, du triomphe marqué dans le sur d'un survivre. Derrida, "Survivre" 1 En tout cas la traduction étrange de Sache par cause est portée par la suite, lorsque Heidegger enchaîne, "die Sache, der Streitfall", la chose, le cas litigieux est en soi-même "ist in sich selbst Aus-einander-setzung." Derrida, "La vie la mort" 2 Mais non, il n'est pas là, rien à voir, on n'y touche pas, Épicure, dans le séminaire que nous lirons ensemble, le séminaire de Jacques Derrida "La vie la mort," conduit durant les années 1975-1976. "Mes chances," le grand essai de Derrida sur l'Épicurisme et sur la chute, le cas, cadere et fallentel le cas-chute, si peu dévié, qui hante la Sache quand elle devient der Streitfall (litige, différend)n'arrivera que sept ans plus tard, en 1982. Lucrèce, lui, "disciple sombre, mais venu à la clarté," comme 3 l'appelle Nietzsche; Lucrèce, qui est toujours en retard, ou qui arrive trop tôt comme le dit toujours Nietzsche, Lucrèce n'apparaîtra chez Derrida qu'en 1989, dans le cadre du séminaire "Manger l'autre." C'est là que Derrida commentera des vers du De rerum natura, seulement certains, se gardant dans ces pages toujours inédites de faire paraître le poème complet-et, même là, dans ce séminaire, ce ne sera qu'au travers de la traduction-adaptation que fait Michel Deguy du poème Latin. 4 Or, bien en avance de ces "rencontres" (je vois que vous devinez déjà le registre, l'institution même, que je "sup-pose" ici), bien en avance de ces rencontres explicitement épicuriennes, Derrida se meut déjà dans le jardin qu'enclosent, ou qu'ouvrent, les phrases célèbres que j'ai un peu mâchées pour en faire mon titre. Le lexique de la cause, celui qui noue les trois boucles du séminaire "La vie la mort," y joue constamment, à travers, ou de travers, comme obliquement : comme si, dans les matériaux que manie Derrida (le Nietzsche de Heidegger, les textes de Jacob, ceux de Nietzsche), quelque chose de cette "rencontre" qui reste encore à venir entre Derrida et Épicure était "portée par la suite" de certaines rencontres, comme enchaînée. Sans qu'on puisse pour autant dire qu'il y a, au sens classique, au sens
Regress threatens throughout Lyotard's Differend, especially where the argument appears to make n... more Regress threatens throughout Lyotard's Differend, especially where the argument appears to make normative ethical or political claims. How a term, a case or an example "links onto" a phrase serves as a way of examining how instituting can be non-regressively grounded, and with what consequences for abstract political subjectivity. The essay offers an alternative to liberal philosophical (Arendt, Nussbaum) and jurisprudential (Marbury v. Madison) schemata of political institution.
What do we need to know about “art” or “class struggle” before considering their relation to one ... more What do we need to know about “art” or “class struggle” before considering their relation to one another? Could you describe a specific work or text that might serve as an illustration of class struggle or as an exploration of the problem of representing it? Let us say that visual art, broadly speaking, does express the worldview of the dominant class. What kind of art then expresses the worldview of, say, hedge fund managers? Does the dialectic of the visible and invisible still hold for conceptual and post-conceptual art? What alternative critical apparatus would you propose, since neither Lenin nor John William Cooke seemed to care much for art. Why should we?
This essay describes and addresses the difficulty that Hispanism has in imagining its foundations... more This essay describes and addresses the difficulty that Hispanism has in imagining its foundations and origination. It reads Cervantes’s novela ejemplar “El licenciado Vidriera” as an allegory of disciplinarity and disciplinarization, which the novela treats as a matter inextricable from the sense of touch. This Cervantic, early-modern account of the primal relation between discipline and touch, the essay suggests, anticipates and allows us to see unexpected consequences to Derrida’s quite radical approach to disciplinarity.
“It goes without saying that but little use can be made of Lucretius” [Es versteht sich, dass Luc... more “It goes without saying that but little use can be made of Lucretius” [Es versteht sich, dass Lucretius nur wenig benutzt werden kann].1 So, by way of preface or prophylaxis, opens the fourth of Marx’s Notebooks on Epicurean Philosophy, composed around 1839 as Marx was preparing his doctoral dissertation. A long list of citations from De Rerum Natura (DRN) follows, and then Lucretius is put to use—as Plutarch’s antagonist, in the long battle over the Epicurean tradition. In these early, informal notes by a young dissertator the reception of Lucretius hangs in the balance; what Althusser refers to as an “underground current” of the materialism of the encounter surfaces and is soon, over the course of the next 15 years, rechanneled or resubmerged.2 An account of mediation at odds with the mechanics, the economics, of use presents itself here, to be translated, never entirely successfully, first into the great Hegelian lexicon that the young Marx and his preceptors were unfolding, then into the languages of political economy. What sorts of use can be made of a thing? In what respects is Lucretius something to be used?
Translatability in natural languages today supports, and can only be understood in the context of... more Translatability in natural languages today supports, and can only be understood in the context of, economic globalization, and the universalization of market logic. ‘Untranslatability’, as it is most often construed, does not provide a critical alternative to this logic: it bolsters it. A different account of untranslatability (and, by extension, of what it means for expressions in natural languages to be ‘translatable’) is required: this essay seeks to provide such. It finds in passages in Marx and in Derrida's Monolinguisme de l'autre, and in different translations of those texts, an untranslatability which is not one, irreducible to mathematical identity.
The battle is not yet joined, and the poet has listed for us the array of warriors, of ships, of ... more The battle is not yet joined, and the poet has listed for us the array of warriors, of ships, of forces. “tell me now,” the poet of The Iliad has sung, in Richmond Lattimore's translation, “you Muses who have your homes on Olympos. / For you, who are goddesses, are there, and you know all things, / and we have heard only the rumor of it and know nothing. / Who then of those were the chief men and the lords of the Danaäns?” (2.484-88). Then the catalog: the list. In the Homeric tradition, a catalog unrolls under the guarding eye of the Muses, the witnesses, under the keeping and inspiring eye of divine and distant figures who have seen the scene, whose witnessing we imagine, from whom we borrow the faint authority we wear when we begin our own songs. These Homeric lists seem to us scattershot today—this ship here, that one there, a warrior next to another warrior simply on the grounds that, yes, there he stands. And yet to the extent that they turn on the authority of the fact, of a divine witness who reports this disorder and from whom we take the rumors of the fact, Homer's lists are at core structured, signed, legitimated. The Iliad is not only the story of the encounter between Trojans and Achaeans; it is also the story of the encounter between two phenomenologies—one envisioning orders of events, names on a list, as they present themselves to us, rumored, accidentally, contingently; another envisioning the order of what presents itself according to the signature of the presiding Muse, according to an immanent principle of structure derivable, if at all, from the totality of the list. These two encounters and these two phenomenologies don't line up; they're fought on different fields and at different levels; they have different scopes. One phenomenology is in principle endless—there's always another matter at hand; we cannot foreclose the possibility that another ship will appear; and the chaos of the battle always means that another figure, foe or friend, may step before us when we least expect it. The other is always bounded, limited on both sides by the immanent unfolding of its principle: that this or that friend or foe should have appeared makes manifest, sub specie aeternitatis, the reason for his, or her, appearing.
The introduction to Untranslating Machines: A Genealogy for the Ends of Global Thought (Rowman Li... more The introduction to Untranslating Machines: A Genealogy for the Ends of Global Thought (Rowman Littlefield 2017)
Lucretius and Modernity is an edited collection that brings together essays by distinguished scho... more Lucretius and Modernity is an edited collection that brings together essays by distinguished scholars in the disciplines of philosophy, classics, literary studies, and the history of science to examine the relationship between the roman poet Lucretius—author of the poem De Rerum Natura (On the Nature of Things)—and modernity. The volume understands “modernity” to encompass a number of topics when paired with Lucretius: Lucretius’s relation to the thought of his time and to the literary and philosophical traditions on which he drew; Lucretius’s role in inaugurating the historical period of European modernity (through his Humanist readers and in the work of writers from Machiavelli to Montaigne, Descartes, and Spinoza, among many others); and the influence of Lucretius’s thought on contemporary approaches to poetry, philosophy, and literary studies (his influence on contemporary materialist thought, both philosophical and scientific; on theology; on literary criticism).
Jacques Lezra, On the Nature of Marx's Things: Translation as Necrophilology, Fordham University Press, 2018
In a book fragment written in 1982 and posthumously published with the title The Underground Curr... more In a book fragment written in 1982 and posthumously published with the title The Underground Current of the Materialism of the Encounter, Louis Althusser attempts to define a form of materialism entirely different from that of the tradition, a form of materialism that would escape the classic opposition between idealism and materialism, an opposition completely internal to the history of Western metaphysics. Althusser suggests a materialism of the rain, of contingency, of the aleatory-a materialism not dominated by the Leibnizian principle nihil est sine ratione. In this fragment, which was to be part of a book dedicated to Karl Marx, but has become a sort of text in its own right, Althusser sketches "an almost completely unknown materialist tradition in the history of philosophy," 1 a profound tradition that sought its materialist anchorage in a philosophy of the encounter . . . , whence this tradition's radical rejection of all philosophies of essence (Ousia, Essentia, Wesen), that is, of Reason (Logos, Ratio, Vernuft), and therefore of Origin and End-the Origin being nothing more, here, than the anticipation of the End in Reason or primordial order (that is, the anticipation of Order, whether it be rational, moral, religious or aesthetic)-in the interests of a philosophy which, rejecting the Whole and every Order, rejects the Whole and order in favor of dispersion (Derrida would say, in his terminology, "dissemination") and disorder. 2
This conference will explore the encounter between the thought of Spinoza and Marx, posing the qu... more This conference will explore the encounter between the thought of Spinoza and Marx, posing the question of how to conceive the two bodies of thought as a joint project. We seek to trace the traditions this encounter has given rise to, internationally and across the disciplines. What about Spinoza's thought lends itself to revival of Marxism? Is Marx's thought necessary for reevaluation of Spinoza? What is the Marx-Spinoza encounter today?
De la naturaleza de las cosas de Marx. Traducción como necrofilología expone la ligadura y la fug... more De la naturaleza de las cosas de Marx. Traducción como necrofilología expone la ligadura y la fuga entre la forma-valor económica y los principios de traducibilidad e intraducibilidad. De partida, sin embargo, y en contratapa, este enunciado está en retirada, pues el libro, a la vez, va de cosas –diría, quizás, Lezra–. Ante y antes, va de cosas, pero entre cita y cita como una cuestión de resonancias, intensidades, amagues, disensiones, ritmos, fuerzas, nombres: Lucrecio, Marx, Pierce, Spinoza, Freud, Schiller, Melville, Borges, Adorno... El texto pone en cuestión, declina, depone, los dispositivos de la práctica de producción del capital financiero y cognitivo y de la convertibilidad general. Lezra opera, pues, una suerte de contra-traducción interna que expone e interrumpe las formas de nombrar y legitimar de la economía de la equivalencia general. Esto no implica, sin embargo, una posición –setzung, thesis– reaccionaria o frontal. No se trata de un retorno a un origen prístino, adánico, ni del ejercicio filológico de la definición –que Quine llamaría lexicográfico–. Formal y temáticamente, se trata del amor a la lettres muertas, de las letras/cartas como la rature (litté-rature, diríase) de la producción del valor (global y/o local), de la mercancía traducible (cultural y/o económica), de la decisión soberana, es decir, del traductor(es) soberano(s) que dicta(n) lo intraducible o decide(n) traducir por equivalencia. Se trata de la apuesta por un trazo de división, dice Lezra, como instancia de radical y violenta intraducibilidad –trazo de división que es también la accidentalidad de su propia traducción: de nuestra tarea–. En este registro el libro de Lezra es una suerte de palimpsesto que no oblitera su borradura, y cuyo envite no permitiría desligar del todo el abandono y el donar desde ya inscrito en la experiencia de su traducción. La tarea está exigida e imposibilitada por la estrictura y soltura del texto. El resto de inequivalencia no es solo conceptual sino que atañe a lo que tentativamente podríamos denominar la parataxis de la escritura como una conexión desgarrada, defectiva: la interrupción, los adverbios, el tempo, los guiones como el efecto de superficie de un concepto o la elipsis de la función lógico-copulativa, no operan simplemente como un recurso secundario sino como advenimiento acontecimental, es decir, el acaecimiento, el suceso, la declinación que escinde la clausura disciplinaria y desmonta la seguridad del valor de lo posible. A la vez, dehiscencia de nuestra traducción (im)posible.
Valeria Campos Salvaterra, Javier Pavez, Mariana Wadsworth
Uploads
Papers by Jacques Lezra
Valeria Campos Salvaterra, Javier Pavez, Mariana Wadsworth