Early Modern Philosophy by Stefan Heßbrüggen
In: Ontologia negativnosti (ed. E. G.
Dragalina-Chernaya), Moskva 2015, 50-58
Rationality in Action: Intentions, Interpretations and Interactions (ed. Elena Dragalina_Chernaya), 2015
The paper examines the interpretation of action in Bartholomaeus Keckermann's applied logic. It d... more The paper examines the interpretation of action in Bartholomaeus Keckermann's applied logic. It defends the thesis that Keckermann makes important and innovative distinctions: the description of a particular action does not focus on its moral evaluation, but on its circumstances, antecedents, and consequences. The reading of such a text containing descriptions, narrations, or interpretations of actions, however, must take the moral dimension of the actions described into account. Keckermann's distinction may have important implications for Keckermann’s understanding of history and the pre-history of hermeneutics in general.
Key words: Bartholomäus Keckerman
The paper discusses the concept of a subject as an actor’s category in early modern philosophy a... more The paper discusses the concept of a subject as an actor’s category in early modern philosophy and asks whether contemporary notions of subjectivity can be meaningfully related to this early modern understanding of the concept. When thinking about the early modern subject as an actor's category, we must distinguish three different meanings: the subject as a bearer of properties, as a reference point for predication, and as the foundation of a discipline. The paper defends the thesis that crucial elements of subjectivity in the modern sense, namely reflexivity and selfawareness, are at the same time characteristic features of a certain understanding of the subject of philosophy as a discipline in the early modern sense: namely for conceptions of philosophy as a transformation of the soul, most notably as a ‘medicine of the soul’. Such conceptions are, however, controversial: other early modern thinkers contend that such proposals do not conform to what we should expect from a definition of philosophy and that they are open to the objection of intellectualism: we need more than knowledge to better our souls, because knowledge in itself is not action-guiding. The paper traces conceptions of the subject of philosophy not only in various Ramist tracts, but also in writings of Melanchthon’s son-inlaw Heinrich Paxmann, the Helmstedt professor Duncan Liddell, and Reformed thinkers like Fortunatus Crell and Bartholomaeus Keckermann.
Early Science and Medicine (19), 2014
The paper examines controversies over the role of experience in the constitution of scientific kn... more The paper examines controversies over the role of experience in the constitution of scientific knowledge in early modern Aristotelianism. While for Jacopo Zabarella, experience helps to confirm the results of demonstrative science, the Bologna Dominican Chrysostomo Javelli assumes that it also contributes to the discovery of new truths in what he calls ‘beginning science’. Both thinkers use medical plants as a philosophical example. Javelli analyses the proposition ‘rhubarb purges bile’ as the conclusion of a yet unknown scientific proof. Zabarella uses instead hellebore, a plant that is found all over Europe, and defends the view that propositions about purgative powers of plants are based on their ‘identity of substance’, an identity that had become questionable with regard to rhubarb due to new empirical findings in the sixteenth century.
To appear in: Studia Neoaristotelica
Early modern commentary on Aristotle’s metaphysics contains a lively debate on whether experience... more Early modern commentary on Aristotle’s metaphysics contains a lively debate on whether experience is ‘rational’, so that it may count as ‘proto-knowledge’, or whether experience is ‘non-rational’, so that experience must be regarded as a
primarily perceptual process. If experience is just a repetitive apprehension of sensory contents, the connection of terms in a scientific proposition can be known without any experiential input, as the ‘non-rational’ Scotists state. ‘Rational’ Thomists believe that all principles of scientific knowledge must rely on experiential data, because experience consists in an apprehension of facts rather than objects. And it is only apprehension of facts that can justify knowledge of principles. In this context, the role of mathematical knowledge is special, because it is self-evident. So Thomists must either show that mathematical principles do rely
on experience, or that they do not express knowledge claims.
Hubertus Busche (ed.), Philosophische Aspekte der Ökonomie, 2011
Daniel Schubbe / Jens Lemanski / Rico Hauswald (Hg.) Warum ist überhaupt etwas und nicht vielmehr nichts? Wandel und Variationen einer Frage, Hamburg: Meiner 2013, 2013
"This contribution to a volume on the“ultimate why-question” discusses ambiguities in Leibniz’s f... more "This contribution to a volume on the“ultimate why-question” discusses ambiguities in Leibniz’s formulation of the question, “[. . . ] pourquoi il y a plus tôt quelque chose que rien”. This formulation poses two problems: Leibniz does not explain how to understand the concepts of “something” and “nothing”. And it is not clear, whether “something” and “nothing” are contradictory opposites, so that there is either nothing or something, or whether both concepts denote principles which are effective in the world at the same time. My analysis rests on the hypothesis that the relevant context for Leibniz’s question is the theology of creation.
Hence, the paper compares eight different approaches to “creation from nothing” (Thomists, Scotists, Taurellus, Lubinus, Timpler, Keckermann, Kircher, Knorr von Rosenroth, van Helmont). Candidates for the nihil the world was created from include absolute non-being, thoughts in God’s mind, unformed matter, imaginary space, or a self-contraction of the Divine spirit. These different approaches can be translated into different versions of the “ultimate why-question”. The paper concludes that Leibniz’s formulation contains a comparison between two Divine acts of creation, because not only “something”, but “nothing” as well owes its subsistence to the Divine will. This rises substantial questions: either God created first an imperfect entity in order to create the world as a whole, or Leibniz subscribes to an emanative understanding of creation that either levels the difference between creation and (natural) generation or is based on misunderstanding God as a material entity."
Kant by Stefan Heßbrüggen
Kant’s Dreams of a Spirit Seer has puzzled most of its readers since its publication in 1766. Her... more Kant’s Dreams of a Spirit Seer has puzzled most of its readers since its publication in 1766. Herder complained in general terms about the lack of unity and coherence of the book as well as Kant’s dialectical method of presenting both sides of a problem without offering his own solution. Mendelssohn was in doubt about whether Kant wanted to ridicule metaphysics or make a case for Swedenborg’s visions. Another exegetical puzzle has not been noted yet: Dreams discusses not one, but three different versions of a ‘metaphysics of spirits’. All of them are mutually incompatible. In other words, the two versions of a metaphysics of spirits that Kant criticises in the first part of the book are both of them different from Swedenborg’s own claims, as they are discussed in the second part. And the two versions discussed within the first part are not homogeneous, either: the metaphysics discussed in the first chapter of the first part (the ‘tangled knot’) and those that seem to form the foundation for the second chapter of the first part (the ‘fragment of occult philosophy’) are again incompatible. And neither of them fits with what Kant analyses as Swedenborg’s metaphysical position in the second part: The position of the ‘tangled knot’ can tentatively be labelled as ‘crypto-materialist’. Swedenborg’s own position is characterised in the text as ‘idealist’. The ‘fragment of occult philosophy’ in contrast is probably best described as ‘dualist’. If this diagnosis is correct, it reinforces Herder’s complaints about the lack of coherence of Dreams as well as Mendelssohn’s worry about its targets. And it adds the additional challenge to explain how there can be a ‘crypto-materialist’ metaphysics of spirit-seeing. I propose to weaken the impact of these problems by identifying a second target of Kant’s scorn in Dreams – a metaphysical position Kant could be sympathetic with as far as its fundamental intentions are concerned, but that draws his ire because of an equally comprehensive failure in the realisation of these intentions. This target is Georg Friedrich Meier who published the second edition of his metaphysics in 1765, one year before the publication of Dreams.
Kant Yearbook, vol. 6, 2014
This is the final submitted manuscript. The printed version can be found here: http://dx.doi.org/... more This is the final submitted manuscript. The printed version can be found here: http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/kantyb-2014-0103
The majority of Kant scholars has taken it for granted that for Kant the soul is in some sense present in space and that this assumption is by and large unproblematic. If we read Kant’s texts in the context of debates on this topic within 18th century rationalism and beyond, a more complex picture emerges, leading to the somewhat surprising conclusion that Kant in 1770 can best be characterised as a Cartesian about the mind. The paper first develops a framework for describing the various positions on the place of the soul in space as varieties of ‘localism’, since German philosophers of the 18th century all agreed on the fact that the soul is in some sense present in space. Strong localists (Crusius, Knutzen) maintain that the soul occupies a place that cannot at the same time be occupied by a material substance. The Königsberg Wolffian Christian Gabriel Fischer is an ‘epistemic localist’ defending the view that our knowledge about the presence of the soul in space is limited. Bilfinger holds that the soul only represents itself as being present in space, he is a ‘representational localist’. The Cartesians, including Leonhard Euler and his teacher Samuel Werenfels, assume that the soul is effective in a region of space without truly being present there. They are ‘virtual localists’. Kant’s attitude towards this problem before the 1760s is a bit unclear. But his writings in this period are at least compatible with the strong localism defended by Knutzen. In the Herder transcripts (1762-1764) and other texts after 1760, Kant begins to distance himself from this view, but he does not articulate clearly his own position. This trend culminates in Dreams of a Spirit Seer (1766), where Kant oscillates somewhat uneasily between epistemic and virtual localism and criticises explicitly the Cartesian thesis that the soul’s presence in the body is limited to a determinate region. The dissertation from 1770 marks another radical change in Kant’s views on the place of the soul. Here, he subscribes to virtual localism and its concomitant thesis that the soul itself is, properly speaking, nowhere. Together with the thesis that the soul knows that it belongs to the mundus intelligibilis this makes Kant in 1770 a Cartesian about the mind.
Contemporary Philosophy by Stefan Heßbrüggen
In: E. G. Dragalina-Chernaja, V. V. Dolgorukov, Sledovanie pravilu: rassuzhdenie, razum, racional'nost', SPb.: Aletejja, 2014, 267-277
Wilfrid Sellars is one of the most important analytic philosophers in the second half of the 20th... more Wilfrid Sellars is one of the most important analytic philosophers in the second half of the 20th century. His work influenced thinkers as diverse as Daniel Dennett, Ruth G. Millikan, John McDowell, Robert Brandom, and Richard Rorty. The paper analyses one of his lasting contributions in metaphilosophy: Sellars introduces two fundamental perspectives on «man-in-the-world»: The «manifest image» of man in the world is built around the notion of persons as its basic entities. The «scientific image» of «man-in-the-world» regards humans exclusively as organisms or biological systems. Whereas Sellars is hopeful to resolve the conflict between these two images in a «synoptic vision» of both of them, the paper defends the thesis that this philosophical project is either superfluous or overreaching. First, the clash of both images is reformulated as a conflict about the origin of norms guiding their construction. This shows that both images lack the resources to address reflectively their own normative foundation. With regard to the manifest image, Sellars explicitly acknowledges its shortcomings. He hopes to save its normative language by integrating it into the scientific image, thereby acknowledging the ultimate authority of science in deciding ontological questions: science tells us what there is. The paper argues that the introduction of normative language into the scientific image does not alleviate its deficits: if it can be shown within the scientific image why its epistemic authority is compulsory, a philosophical argument for the preponderance of the scientific image of man is superfluous. Nature will take care of itself. If we need philosophical arguments for the preponderance of the scientific image, these arguments must inevitably be formulated in the language of the manifest image, because on Sellars’s own terms, philosophy is inextricably intertwined with the conceptual resources of a world view that regards humans primarily as persons: philosophers cannot negate or ignore the fact that they argue with persons as persons. A philosopher is always «one of us».
Studia philosophica , 2007
The paper discusses Sellars’s view of philosophy and its relation to the (natural) sciences. It a... more The paper discusses Sellars’s view of philosophy and its relation to the (natural) sciences. It argues for three interrelated theses. First, philosophy has no specific subject matter. Second, we ask ourselves questions which cannot be answered from a purely scientific point of view. Third, philosophical standards are contingent, but this does not mean that philosophy is to be abandoned. Pace Sellars, the specific achievement of philosophy consists in «a view of the whole», which enables us to «know our way around» with respect to the different domains of expertise we are familiar with. Philosophy thus reflects a commonsense perspective of ourselves and the world we live in, which rests on the assumption that we are obliged to regard ourselves, as well as those sharing our lives, as persons. This in turn implies that our most basic ways of relating to the world (knowledge and action) are governed by norms. Getting a view of the whole of man thus means that we must regard ourselves both as participants of a norm-governed «Lebensform» [lifeform] and as complex biological systems. Philosophy and the sciences complement one another. Science aims at knowledge. This aim cannot be properly understood within science itself, because science does not concern itself with the normative perspective inherent in the very concept of knowledge. Philosophy, in turn, cannot risk ignoring the results of the sciences, because their insights form an essential part of what we must take to be the whole of the world that philosophy has in view. Even though philosophy should not aspire to achieve a complete revolution of the norms and standards governing our attempts to make sense of this world, it is nevertheless indispensable because it shows that these norms themselves are always open to reflection and revision.
Archiv Fur Geschichte Der Philosophie, 2004
Books by Stefan Heßbrüggen
В сборнике представлены материалы международного трансцендентального семинара, цель которого сост... more В сборнике представлены материалы международного трансцендентального семинара, цель которого состояла в обсуждении трансцендентального поворота в философии, в лице трех главных ‘трансцендентальных’ традиций: кантианства и неокантианства (континентальная традиция), аналитического (англосаксонского) кантианства и трансцендентальной феноменологии. В названии семинара (сборника) сформулирован главный вопрос обсуждения, а именно: что собой представляет трансцендентальный поворот в [современной] философии; это — новая метафизика, теория опыта/опытного познания или теория сознания? Издание ориентировано на исследователей, занятых философскими проблемами онтологии, эпистемологии, философии науки и философии (теории) сознания.
The volume presents proceedings of the transcendental workshop, the purpose of which is to discuss the transcendental turn in [contemporary] philosophy, in the three main 'transcendental' forms: Kantianism and Neo-Kantianism (continental philosophy), analytical (Anglo-Saxon) Kantianism and transcendental phenomenology. In the title of the workshop the main question of the discussion is formulated: what is a transcendental turn in philosophy; is it the new metaphysics, or the theory of experience (experiential knowledge), or the theory of consciousness? The volume is devoted to the problems of ontology, epistemology, philosophy of science and philosophy of consciousness.
Papers by Stefan Heßbrüggen
Natur und Freiheit, 2018
Kant’s Dreams of a Spirit Seer has puzzled most of its readers since its publication in 1766. Her... more Kant’s Dreams of a Spirit Seer has puzzled most of its readers since its publication in 1766. Herder complained in general terms about the lack of unity and coherence of the book as well as Kant’s dialectical method of presenting both sides of a problem without offering his own solution. Mendelssohn was in doubt about whether Kant wanted to ridicule metaphysics or make a case for Swedenborg’s visions. Another exegetical puzzle has not been noted yet: Dreams discusses not one, but three different versions of a ‘metaphysics of spirits’. All of them are mutually incompatible. In other words, the two versions of a metaphysics of spirits that Kant criticises in the first part of the book are both of them different from Swedenborg’s own claims, as they are discussed in the second part. And the two versions discussed within the first part are not homogeneous, either: the metaphysics discussed in the first chapter of the first part (the ‘tangled knot’) and those that seem to form the foundation for the second chapter of the first part (the ‘fragment of occult philosophy’) are again incompatible. And neither of them fits with what Kant analyses as Swedenborg’s metaphysical position in the second part: The position of the ‘tangled knot’ can tentatively be labelled as ‘crypto-materialist’. Swedenborg’s own position is characterised in the text as ‘idealist’. The ‘fragment of occult philosophy’ in contrast is probably best described as ‘dualist’. If this diagnosis is correct, it reinforces Herder’s complaints about the lack of coherence of Dreams as well as Mendelssohn’s worry about its targets. And it adds the additional challenge to explain how there can be a ‘crypto-materialist’ metaphysics of spirit-seeing. I propose to weaken the impact of these problems by identifying a second target of Kant’s scorn in Dreams – a metaphysical position Kant could be sympathetic with as far as its fundamental intentions are concerned, but that draws his ire because of an equally comprehensive failure in the realisation of these intentions. This target is Georg Friedrich Meier who published the second edition of his metaphysics in 1765, one year before the publication of Dreams.
Uploads
Early Modern Philosophy by Stefan Heßbrüggen
Key words: Bartholomäus Keckerman
primarily perceptual process. If experience is just a repetitive apprehension of sensory contents, the connection of terms in a scientific proposition can be known without any experiential input, as the ‘non-rational’ Scotists state. ‘Rational’ Thomists believe that all principles of scientific knowledge must rely on experiential data, because experience consists in an apprehension of facts rather than objects. And it is only apprehension of facts that can justify knowledge of principles. In this context, the role of mathematical knowledge is special, because it is self-evident. So Thomists must either show that mathematical principles do rely
on experience, or that they do not express knowledge claims.
Hence, the paper compares eight different approaches to “creation from nothing” (Thomists, Scotists, Taurellus, Lubinus, Timpler, Keckermann, Kircher, Knorr von Rosenroth, van Helmont). Candidates for the nihil the world was created from include absolute non-being, thoughts in God’s mind, unformed matter, imaginary space, or a self-contraction of the Divine spirit. These different approaches can be translated into different versions of the “ultimate why-question”. The paper concludes that Leibniz’s formulation contains a comparison between two Divine acts of creation, because not only “something”, but “nothing” as well owes its subsistence to the Divine will. This rises substantial questions: either God created first an imperfect entity in order to create the world as a whole, or Leibniz subscribes to an emanative understanding of creation that either levels the difference between creation and (natural) generation or is based on misunderstanding God as a material entity."
Kant by Stefan Heßbrüggen
The majority of Kant scholars has taken it for granted that for Kant the soul is in some sense present in space and that this assumption is by and large unproblematic. If we read Kant’s texts in the context of debates on this topic within 18th century rationalism and beyond, a more complex picture emerges, leading to the somewhat surprising conclusion that Kant in 1770 can best be characterised as a Cartesian about the mind. The paper first develops a framework for describing the various positions on the place of the soul in space as varieties of ‘localism’, since German philosophers of the 18th century all agreed on the fact that the soul is in some sense present in space. Strong localists (Crusius, Knutzen) maintain that the soul occupies a place that cannot at the same time be occupied by a material substance. The Königsberg Wolffian Christian Gabriel Fischer is an ‘epistemic localist’ defending the view that our knowledge about the presence of the soul in space is limited. Bilfinger holds that the soul only represents itself as being present in space, he is a ‘representational localist’. The Cartesians, including Leonhard Euler and his teacher Samuel Werenfels, assume that the soul is effective in a region of space without truly being present there. They are ‘virtual localists’. Kant’s attitude towards this problem before the 1760s is a bit unclear. But his writings in this period are at least compatible with the strong localism defended by Knutzen. In the Herder transcripts (1762-1764) and other texts after 1760, Kant begins to distance himself from this view, but he does not articulate clearly his own position. This trend culminates in Dreams of a Spirit Seer (1766), where Kant oscillates somewhat uneasily between epistemic and virtual localism and criticises explicitly the Cartesian thesis that the soul’s presence in the body is limited to a determinate region. The dissertation from 1770 marks another radical change in Kant’s views on the place of the soul. Here, he subscribes to virtual localism and its concomitant thesis that the soul itself is, properly speaking, nowhere. Together with the thesis that the soul knows that it belongs to the mundus intelligibilis this makes Kant in 1770 a Cartesian about the mind.
Contemporary Philosophy by Stefan Heßbrüggen
Books by Stefan Heßbrüggen
The volume presents proceedings of the transcendental workshop, the purpose of which is to discuss the transcendental turn in [contemporary] philosophy, in the three main 'transcendental' forms: Kantianism and Neo-Kantianism (continental philosophy), analytical (Anglo-Saxon) Kantianism and transcendental phenomenology. In the title of the workshop the main question of the discussion is formulated: what is a transcendental turn in philosophy; is it the new metaphysics, or the theory of experience (experiential knowledge), or the theory of consciousness? The volume is devoted to the problems of ontology, epistemology, philosophy of science and philosophy of consciousness.
Papers by Stefan Heßbrüggen
Key words: Bartholomäus Keckerman
primarily perceptual process. If experience is just a repetitive apprehension of sensory contents, the connection of terms in a scientific proposition can be known without any experiential input, as the ‘non-rational’ Scotists state. ‘Rational’ Thomists believe that all principles of scientific knowledge must rely on experiential data, because experience consists in an apprehension of facts rather than objects. And it is only apprehension of facts that can justify knowledge of principles. In this context, the role of mathematical knowledge is special, because it is self-evident. So Thomists must either show that mathematical principles do rely
on experience, or that they do not express knowledge claims.
Hence, the paper compares eight different approaches to “creation from nothing” (Thomists, Scotists, Taurellus, Lubinus, Timpler, Keckermann, Kircher, Knorr von Rosenroth, van Helmont). Candidates for the nihil the world was created from include absolute non-being, thoughts in God’s mind, unformed matter, imaginary space, or a self-contraction of the Divine spirit. These different approaches can be translated into different versions of the “ultimate why-question”. The paper concludes that Leibniz’s formulation contains a comparison between two Divine acts of creation, because not only “something”, but “nothing” as well owes its subsistence to the Divine will. This rises substantial questions: either God created first an imperfect entity in order to create the world as a whole, or Leibniz subscribes to an emanative understanding of creation that either levels the difference between creation and (natural) generation or is based on misunderstanding God as a material entity."
The majority of Kant scholars has taken it for granted that for Kant the soul is in some sense present in space and that this assumption is by and large unproblematic. If we read Kant’s texts in the context of debates on this topic within 18th century rationalism and beyond, a more complex picture emerges, leading to the somewhat surprising conclusion that Kant in 1770 can best be characterised as a Cartesian about the mind. The paper first develops a framework for describing the various positions on the place of the soul in space as varieties of ‘localism’, since German philosophers of the 18th century all agreed on the fact that the soul is in some sense present in space. Strong localists (Crusius, Knutzen) maintain that the soul occupies a place that cannot at the same time be occupied by a material substance. The Königsberg Wolffian Christian Gabriel Fischer is an ‘epistemic localist’ defending the view that our knowledge about the presence of the soul in space is limited. Bilfinger holds that the soul only represents itself as being present in space, he is a ‘representational localist’. The Cartesians, including Leonhard Euler and his teacher Samuel Werenfels, assume that the soul is effective in a region of space without truly being present there. They are ‘virtual localists’. Kant’s attitude towards this problem before the 1760s is a bit unclear. But his writings in this period are at least compatible with the strong localism defended by Knutzen. In the Herder transcripts (1762-1764) and other texts after 1760, Kant begins to distance himself from this view, but he does not articulate clearly his own position. This trend culminates in Dreams of a Spirit Seer (1766), where Kant oscillates somewhat uneasily between epistemic and virtual localism and criticises explicitly the Cartesian thesis that the soul’s presence in the body is limited to a determinate region. The dissertation from 1770 marks another radical change in Kant’s views on the place of the soul. Here, he subscribes to virtual localism and its concomitant thesis that the soul itself is, properly speaking, nowhere. Together with the thesis that the soul knows that it belongs to the mundus intelligibilis this makes Kant in 1770 a Cartesian about the mind.
The volume presents proceedings of the transcendental workshop, the purpose of which is to discuss the transcendental turn in [contemporary] philosophy, in the three main 'transcendental' forms: Kantianism and Neo-Kantianism (continental philosophy), analytical (Anglo-Saxon) Kantianism and transcendental phenomenology. In the title of the workshop the main question of the discussion is formulated: what is a transcendental turn in philosophy; is it the new metaphysics, or the theory of experience (experiential knowledge), or the theory of consciousness? The volume is devoted to the problems of ontology, epistemology, philosophy of science and philosophy of consciousness.