DiscontinuousMaterialism
DiscontinuousMaterialism
DiscontinuousMaterialism
net/publication/361032607
Discontinuous Materialism
CITATIONS READS
7 144
1 author:
Javier Pérez-Jara
University of Seville
64 PUBLICATIONS 73 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Javier Pérez-Jara on 05 October 2022.
Javier Pérez-Jara
Abstract This chapter has two main complementary goals. First, it analyzes the
main ontological ideas of Gustavo Bueno’s discontinuous materialism in contrast
with other philosophical systems. Second, it explores some of the main ontological
questions and issues still open in this system of thought, while advancing some
possible paths of resolution. In order to do this, I follow a double general denition
of philosophical materialism. Positively, materialism, in general, names the branch
of philosophical worldviews that identify being (i.e. the “ὅντος” of ontology)
with matter, understood in its broadest sense as changeability and plurality (partes
extra partes). Negatively, materialism denies the existence of disembodied living
beings and hypostatized ideas. Within this general framework, I then locate the
specic ontological characteristic of discontinuous materialism in the rejection of
any attempt to hypostatize any element, property, state or relation of reality. Like
the Medusa’s gaze, hypostasizing metaphysics turns parts of the complex interplay
of continuities and discontinuities that constitutes reality into stone. I then conduct a
comparison between discontinuous materialism and other philosophies, in particular
Mario Bunge’s systemic materialism, physicalism, ontotheology, and speculative
realism(s). This approach aims at opening new avenues for philosophical research
for both metaphysics in general and materialist philosophy in particular.
J. Pérez-Jara ()
Beijing Foreign Studies University, Beijing, China
Yale University, New Haven, CT, USA
1 After all, thanks to the sociology of intellectuals, we know that the philosophical coherence of
a system stands, on many occasions, at a far remove from explaining its cultural impact or lack
thereof (Alexander 2004, 2011, 2016; Baert 2005, 2012).
3 Discontinuous Materialism 111
current societies. Bueno resolved the apparent contradiction between science and
philosophy through his theory of “rst degree” and “second degree” knowledge
(1970). First degree knowledge includes technologies and sciences, as well as eco-
nomic and political techniques. According to this, philosophy is not an autonomous
discipline, but a second degree knowledge that analyzes ideas, in capital letters, such
as the ideas of Reality, Existence, Law, Causality, Knowledge, Truth, Freedom and
God. Although this conception of philosophy as the analysis and systematization of
ideas has undoubtedly Platonic roots, Bueno devised it in opposition to any attempt
of hypostatizing ideas. Philosophical ideas (second degree) are always products
of complex historical and cultural processes (rst degree). The interplay between
philosophical ideas and rst grade concepts can be seen in a variety of examples.
Let’s take a very clear one: from the multiple and specic concepts of time that we
nd in multiple elds, from daily life, physics, psychology, linguistic, to geology
and astrophysics, arises the philosophical idea of Time. Neither one specic science
nor the combination of all of them can properly answer the question “what is time
in general?”. It belongs to the general eld of philosophy. At the same time, only a
pseudo-philosophy can analyze “time” in general while ignoring the developments
of modern sciences. The same can be said for philosophical ideas such as human
nature, causality, structure, reality or universe. Therefore, instead of killing it, Bueno
held that the development of modern sciences make philosophy a much richer and
deeper form of knowledge.2
According to Bueno, the structural dependence of rigorous philosophy on the
sciences was already present in Greek philosophy. It is not a coincidence that among
Presocratics there were such important mathematicians. For Bueno, geometry
and geometrical astronomy were the rst real sciences developed in the Western
tradition. Their cultural impact was deep: among other things, they provided a
canon of rationality supported on impersonal necessity. The so-called rst Greek
philosophers used that canon for understanding nature (φύσις), in opposition to
the anthropomorphism and zoomorphism characteristic of mythological thinking
(Bueno 1974, 2007). Philosophy and science, though, needed millennia to be well
distinguished theoretically and sociologically (Harrison 2015).
This idea could give the wrong impression that although philosophy needs
sciences, sciences can exist without philosophy. In Teoŕa del Cierre Categorial
(1992–1993) and What is Science? (2013b) Bueno further analyzed the relationships
between sciences and philosophy. Based on these clarications, philosophical
activity also inuences important parts of the scientic bodies. Every science has
2 From this point of view, one key criterion to measure the quality of a philosophical system
is its capacity to incorporate well established scientic theories and discoveries. Nevertheless,
although necessary, the necessity of being scientically up-to-date is not enough to develop good
philosophical theories. The best proof of this are all the good scientists that have bad or poor
philosophies. The idea of philosophy of a second degree discipline mainly supported on scientic
concepts and theories, can be coordinated with Mario Bunge’s and Gustavo E. Romero’s view
of “scientic philosophy”, i.e. a philosophy properly informed by updated scientic theories and
practices (Bunge 1977, 2003; Romero 2018).
3 Discontinuous Materialism 149
Inspired by Henri Poincaré, some philosophers have talked about “brute facts”
as facts that either have no explanation (Fahrbach 2005) or that we cannot explain
(Hospers 1997). As such, the concept of “brute fact” is related to reality’s primordial
facticity. But it cannot be identied, since the concept of brute fact is usually
opposed to either an innite regression of explanations or to the principle of
sufcient reason.70 And both innitism and radical rationalism point to a ultimate
feature of reality that does not have an explanation, i.e. point to reality’s primordial
facticity.
God(s), Tao (㐨), Kami (⚄), Musubi (⤖ࡧ), Brahman, Sunyata, χάος, ἀρχή, math-
ematics and logic, matter and so on are attempts to conceptualize this facticity in
some way. The search for this ultimate facticity goes beyond the contents and also
inquires into reality’s primordial structure and mechanisms that allow everything
else. For instance, does reality’s primordial facticity allow real change and novelty
or only an illusion of them? Whatever answer we choose, it does not have an
explanation.71
A signicant number of philosophers often go through loops or hit metaphysical
short circuits when they try to analyze reality’s primordial facticity. Leibniz himself
answered the question on why there is something rather than nothing through the
ontotheological God: as the necessary Being, the World is contingent and has been
freely created by a personal God. But God and His divine properties do not have
any kind of explanation, since they are the last presupposition of everything else.
And since God is a Being who necessarily exists, He does not answer the question
about “being and existence” in general. The question of reality’s primordial facticity
cannot be answered by any particular being (even if it is the Supreme Being). Every
entity presupposes beingness and existence in general. Before Heidegger, Schelling
and Schopenhauer approached this view through their ideas of being as Abgrund
(abyss) and Grundloss (without reason) respectively. No theological metaphysics
or materialist philosophy can go much further than that. This is no epistemological
limitation, but the result of confronting existence’s primordial facticity.
The metaphysical short circuits that unfold when trying to take reality’s primor-
dial facticity into account are not, therefore, the monopoly of ontotheologians. Let’s
take an interesting present-day example. Following Heidegger in his own peculiar
way, Markus Gabriel denes facticity as “the fact that there is something rather than
nothing—that is, that there exists anything at all.”72 But his denition of existence
“as the property of elds of sense, namely that something exists in them”73 falls
70 The concept of reality’s primordial facticity is even further from the (on the other hand very
interesting) concept of “contextual” brute facts held by Anscombe (1981).
71 If we hold (as I do) that change is an essential characteristic of reality, we could argue, for
into circular reasoning. This is because every property and “eld of sense” implies
existence in general. Furthermore, Gabriel does not give a much deeper account of
reality’s primordial facticity aside of stating that the World in capital letters does not
exist, only an innite plurality of elds of sense composed of entities that we can
know as they are in themselves. For a materialist philosophy, furthermore, there is
no “sense” without humans or other kinds of animals, so there cannot be an actual
innity of “elds of sense”.
Humans’ radical dependence on reality’s primordial facticity also explains,
among other things, what I called “reality’s muzzle” in the face of relativism.
Without any doubt, human societies can create all manner of extravagant and even
surreal narratives and mythologies and believe in them blindly (Bueno 1996). And,
indeed, in these extreme cases reality seems powerless to muzzle symbolic process.
But, if we trust calm reasoning and logic, at the end of the day, reality’s facticity will
impose its muzzle over us, marking what is imaginary and what is not, what is totally
distorted and what is more accurate. Even if many radical social constructionists and
idealists alike decide to downplay it, we can only ignore the muzzle at our own risk.
Despite the doubtless depth of Bueno’s ontological analyses, he never used a
concept similar to reality’s primordial facticity or seemed particularly interested
in what it implies. Nevertheless, it is easy to translate the ontological ideas that
Bueno considered most important to the question of reality’s primordial facticity. In
such translation, key dimensions of reality’s primordial facticity are the interplays
of continuities and discontinuities that structure matter, the necessarily corporeal
nature of every living being, and the structural and necessary co-dependence
between animals and their organoleptic worlds.
Through the analysis of such facticity, and remembering the Platonic concept
of χωρισμός,74 we can safely say that there is no “absolute chorismos” between
our organoleptic and theoretical World and absolute reality. On the contrary, I have
defended that there is a set of absolute convergences and a wide eld of analogies
that oscillate between weak and strong. Hoping to capture some of them, I have
recommended following and expanding the traditional Japanese concept of Yūgen
from the perspective of a materialist philosophy.
For a truly materialist philosophy, such as Bueno’s, there is no cosmic or supra-
cosmic τέλος for the appearance of animals and humankind; reality’s primordial
facticity only allows, under certain circumstances, the emergence of living beings.
As a part of this facticity, literal living beings require a solid organic or paraorganic
body. Such living beings, in turn, and under some circumstances, allow for the
emergence of metaphorical living beings, such as our dead ancestors’ cultural
weight or characters of ction, from the Sumerian gods to the Joker. Although they
would fade away without human beings, these cultural creations have a metaphorical
“life” of their own, even if it is not corporeal. Furthermore, they often exert an
inuence on human beings stronger than many literal living beings. For that reason,
References
Alexander, J.C. 2004. Cultural pragmatics: Social performance between ritual and strategy.
Sociological Theory 22: 527–573.
Alexander, J.C. 2011. Performance and Power. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Alexander, J.C. 2016. Dramatic Intellectuals. International Journal of Politics, Culture and Society
29(4): 341–58.
Alexander, S. 1920. Space, Time, and Deity (2 vols). London: Macmillan.
75 And we do not yet know whether future developments in AI will be able to generate psychic
contents from articial biosystems.
152 J. Pérez-Jara
Anscombe, G.E.M. 1981. The Collected Philosophical Papers of G. E. M. Anscombe. Volume III:
Ethics, Religion and Politics. Oxford: Blackwell.
Baert, P. 2005. The Existentialist Moment: The Rise of Sartre as a Public Intellectual. Cambridge:
Polity.
Baert, P. 2012. Positioning theory and intellectual interventions. Journal for the Theory of Social
Behaviour 42(3): 304–325.
Bennett, J. 2010. Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things. London: Duke University Press.
Brassier, R. 2007. Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment and Extinction. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmil-
lan.
Bryant, L. 2014. Correlationism. In The Meillassoux Dictionary, eds. Gratton, P., P.J. Ennis.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Bueno, G. 1970. El Papel de la Filosof́a en el Conjunto del Saber. Madrid: Editorial Ciencia
Nueva.
Bueno, G. 1972. Ensayos Materialistas. Madrid: Taurus.
Bueno, G. 1974. La Metaf́sica Presocrática. Oviedo: Pentalfa.
Bueno, G. 1990. Ignoramus, Ignorabimus! El Basilisco 4: 69–88.
Bueno, G. 1992. En torno a la doctrina losóca de la causalidad. In La Filosof́a de Gustavo
Bueno. Madrid: Editorial Complutense, pp. 207–227.
Bueno, G. 1992–1993. Teoŕa del Cierre Categorial (5 Vols). Oviedo: Pentalfa.
Bueno, G. 1996. El Animal Divino. Oviedo: Pentalfa.
Bueno, G. 1997. Los Ĺmites de la Evolución en el Ámbito de la Scala Naturae. In Evolucionismo
y Racionalismo, eds. E. Molina, A. Carreras, J., Puertas. Zaragoza: Institución Fernando el
Católico & Universidad de Zaragoza, pp. 49–87.
Bueno, G. 2000. Televisión: Apariencia y Verdad. Barcelona: Gedisa.
Bueno, G. 2004a. La Vuelta a la Caverna. Terrorismo, Guerra y Globalización. Barcelona:
Ediciones B.
Bueno, G. 2004b. Confrontación de doce tesis caracteŕsticas del sistema del Idealismo trascen-
dental con las correspondientes tesis del Materialismo losóco. El Basilisco 35: 3–40.
Bueno, G. 2007. La Fe del Ateo. Madrid: Temas de Hoy.
Bueno, G. 2009. El Puesto del Ego Trascendental en el Materialismo Filosóco. El Basilisco 40:
1–104.
Bueno, G. 2013a. Ensayo de una Denición Filosóca de la Idea de Deporte. Oviedo: Pentalfa.
Bueno, G. 2013b. Sciences as Categorical Closures. Oviedo: Pentalfa.
Bueno, G. 2016a. El Ego Trascendental. Oviedo: Pentalfa.
Bueno, G. 2016b. Primer memorándum de Materialismo Filosóco. El Catoblepas 168: 2.
Bueno, G. 2019. The Happiness Delusion. Debunking the Myth of Happiness. Oviedo: Pentalfa
Bunge, M. 1977. Treatise on Basic Philosophy. Vol. 3: The Furniture of the World. Dordrecht:
Reidel Publishing Company.
Bunge, M. 1980. The Mind–Body Problem: A Psychobiological Approach. Oxford: Pergamon
Press.
Bunge, M. 2003. Emergence and Convergence: Qualitative Novelty and the Unity of Knowledge.
Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Bunge, M. 2006. Chasing Reality: Strife over Realism. Toronto: Toronto University Press.
Bunge, M. 2009. Political Philosophy: Fact, Fiction and Vision. New Brunswick: Transaction
Publishers.
Bunge, M. 2010. Matter and Mind: A Philosophical Inquiry. New York: Springer.
Churchland, P.M. 1984. Matter and Consciousness: A Contemporary Introduction to the Philoso-
phy of Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Churchland, P.S., and T.J. Sejnowski. 1993. The Computational Brain. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown.
Dupré, J.1993. The Disorder of Things. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Engels, F. 2012[1883]. Dialectics of Nature. London: Wellred.
Ennis, P.J. 2011. The transcendental core of correlationism. Cosmos and History: The Journal of
Natural and Social Philosophy 7(1): 37–48.
3 Discontinuous Materialism 153
154 J. Pérez-Jara