Stuart M. Brown-PhilosophicalReview-1963
Stuart M. Brown-PhilosophicalReview-1963
Stuart M. Brown-PhilosophicalReview-1963
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Duke University Press and are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Philosophical Review
250
how wills must be written and witnessed. With these are conjoined
the three sorts of secondary rules. None of these primary or secondary
rules, from the point of view of those subject to them, is a mere empirical
generalization. So far, there is nothing specially perplexing about this
idea of a rule, and the concept of law may, perhaps with profit, be
defined in terms of it.
Surprisingly, Hart does define law in just these terms. This is
surprising, because in stating his problem and talking about it, he
everywhere insists that law cannot profitably be defined and that, in
particular, it cannot be defined in terms of rules. In the special section
which he devoted to definition (pp. 13-17) he makes three main
points. (i) The concept of law cannot be defined in the traditional
manner, because it is an open concept. (2) If it were definable in the
traditional way per genus et differentiam, the genus would be rules of
behavior. But any such definition would fail, because the idea of a rule
is as perplexing as the idea of law itself. And (3), although there are
methods of defining other than the traditional one, no formula concise
enough to count as definition can satisfactorily answer the question
"What is law?"
Nonetheless, Hart defines law; that is, he specifies the necessary and
sufficient conditions for the use of the concept. A set of primary rules is
one necessary condition. A set of secondary rules is another. These two
conditions together are sufficient: the satisfaction of them entails a
genuine case of the concept. That Hart defines the concept is implied
by the manner in which he treats it. But at one point, he is quite
explicit about it:
There are therefore two minimum conditions necessary and sufficient for
existence of a legal system. On the one hand those rules of behavior which are
valid according to the system's ultimate criteria of validity must be generally
obeyed, and, on the other hand, its rules of recognition specifying the criteria
of legal validity and its rules of changes and adjudication must be effectively
accepted as common public standards of official behavior by its officials [p. I I 3].
251
But if what I have said here is correct, the concept of law in Hart's
treatment is confused. He describes the concept in one way when he is
talking about his problem, whereas his solution describes it in a different
and incompatible way. The problem, as Hart states it, is to elucidate a
concept which cannot profitably be defined and, in particular, cannot
be defined in terms of rules. The problem, as he solves it, is to formulate
a definition in precisely these terms. On the first account, the concept
of law is open, and the idea of a rule obscure and perplexing. On the
second, the concept of law is closed, and the idea of a combination of
primary and secondary rules is apparently clear enough to provide a
most powerful tool for analysis. Something has gone wrong. As the
following statement made at the beginning of his last chapter shows,
the difficulty persists throughout the book:
Though the idea of the union of primary and secondary rules has these virtues
[that it permits the multiple relationships between law, coercion, and morality
to be seen and considered afresh], and though it would accord with usage to
treat the existence of this characteristic union of rules as a sufficient condition
for the application of the expression "legal system," we have not claimed that
the word "law" must be defined in its terms. It is because we make no such
claim to identify or regulate in this way the use of words like "law" or "legal,"
that this book is offered as an elucidation of the concept of law, rather than a
definition of "law" [p. 208].
The difficulty is that Hart does not establish and makes no attempt
to establish either the precise sense in which the concept of law is
assumed to be open or the precise bearing which this important fact
is assumed to have upon the issues treated systematically in the book.
In consequence, he fails to see that if his treatment of the issues is
correct the concept cannot in any clear sense be open in respect to
them. One important issue, to which Hart devotes the first quarter of
his book, is the theory of law as coercive orders. He subjects the theory
to sustained, illuminating, and devastating criticism. The theory is
false, on his account, because it is inapplicable to any genuine case of
law whatsoever. If this theory could account for some genuine cases
of law and were false only because it could not account for all cases,
then one might argue that the concept of law is open in respect to what
is at issue and that the theory is defective because it treats the concept as
closed. But clearly this is not what Hart claims to be the case. In
respect to what is at issue between this theory and his own, the concept
of law is closed. It is closed also in respect to what is at issue in his
account of the contention that there is some logically necessary con-
nection between law and morality. If one held that, in some but not
252
253