Essay Infinity

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 3

Nguyen 1

Professor Robert DiSallle

Philosophy 1807

November 23rd, 2023

“…Finally, the attributes "equal," "greater," and "less" are not applicable to infinite, but only

to finite, quantities.” Galileo,”Infinity,” p. 2.

With just a simple yet complex sentence above, Galileo effectively portrayed his view

of mathematics and pinpointed the flaws within the same field of discipline and ultimately

changed how we view modern-day mathematics. In his book “Discourses and

Demonstrations Concerning Two New Sciences” featuring two mathematicians, Simplicio

and Salviati, Galileo’s (or Salviati in his book) idea of the infinite is that our prior knowledge

of basic mathematics couldn’t be applied to the concept of the infinite. Things like natural

numbers, which can be easily determined whether or not they are equal, greater or less than

another natural number by simply observing the number and its properties such as the tenth

or the thousandth of the said number. But once we declare a set of numbers as infinite, we

cannot compare such a set to another set of infinite numbers and determine whether or not

they are equal, greater or less; simply because they are infinite.

Galileo, in his effort to prove that we can’t simply compare sets of infinite, proposed

the idea of “one-to-one correspondence”. This idea entails pairing a natural number and its

squared number, hence the term one-to-one correspondence. For instance, the first pair would

include one and one, the second pair would be two and four, three and nine and so on

indefinitely. From the perspective of an amateur mathematician, it would appear that the set

of infinite natural numbers possesses much more numbers than the set of perfect square

numbers since it (the set of natural numbers) contains imperfect squares like two, three, five,

six, and seven and so on as well as the perfect square numbers itself, thus the set of square
Nguyen 2
numbers must be less than the set of natural numbers. However, in his work, Galileo argued

that since every natural number can indefinitely pair with another square number

corresponding to it, regardless of how many numbers lie between each pair, therefore there

must be as many square numbers as there are natural numbers.

The same theory could be applied to the case of two different lines of different length

which puzzled Simplicio (page 1). The idea, as I understand it, involves us deciding a point

of each line and pairing them together. For instance, we can connect the midpoint of both

lines, then the quarter points, and so forth, continuing this process infinitely. By doing so, it

becomes evident that they both share an infinite amount of points, regardless of their sizes

and length. Ultimately establishes that the two sets are neither equal nor lesser or greater than

one another; instead, they are in a one-to-one correspondence, implying there are as many

points in the shorter line as there are in the longer line.

By comprehending the fact that infinity itself had exploited the flaws and challenged

the fundamental principles of mathematics at the time and thus creating many complex

paradoxes. We adapted to the idea of infinity thanks to the genius thinkers from the past like

Galileo and a well-known philosopher Zeno and his motion paradoxes, together they had

constructed the foundation of a field beyond basic mathematics. By using this foundational

works, many mathematicians and physicists at the later time such as Sir Isaac Newton and

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, together had ultimately created a new field of mathematics using

the concept of infinity as its core, which we now refer to as “Calculus”. This branch of

mathematics embodied the pinnacle of mathematical revolution and forever altered how we

perceive not just numbers but the world and its limits.

Bibliography (MLA)
Nguyen 3

Hugget, Nick. "Zeno's Paradoxes." Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 30 Apr. 2002,

plato.stanford.edu/entries/paradox-zeno/. Accessed 21 Sept. 2023.

Look, Brandon C. "Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz." Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 22

Dec. 2007, plato.stanford.edu/entries/leibniz/. Accessed 21 Sept. 2023.

Machamer, Peter, and David M. Miller. "Galileo Galilei." Stanford Encyclopedia of

Philosophy, 4 Mar. 2005, plato.stanford.edu/entries/galileo/. Accessed 21 Sept. 2023.

Smith, George . "Isaac Newton." Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 19 Dec. 2007,

plato.stanford.edu/entries/newton/. Accessed 21 Sept. 2023.

You might also like