This Content Downloaded From 185.192.71.183 On Wed, 08 Mar 2023 19:16:33 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 185.192.71.183 On Wed, 08 Mar 2023 19:16:33 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 185.192.71.183 On Wed, 08 Mar 2023 19:16:33 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Brill is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Phronesis
FRANCISCO J. GONZALEZ
' Some modem philosophers of course recognize the existence of what is called "know-
ledge by acquaintance," but they do not consider this to be the kind of knowledge that is
contrasted with belief. See, for example, H. H. Price's claim that the distinction between
knowledge and belief is always a distinction between "knowledge that" and "belief that"
(Belief [London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1969], 79).
2 "Knowledge and Belief in Republic V," Archiv fUr Geschichte der Philosophie 60
(1978): 121-39; "Knowledge and Belief in Republic V-VII," in Epistemology, ed. Ste-
phen Everson (Cambridge University Press, 1990), 85-115.
In the following outline I list only the major steps in order to render clear
the structure of the argument. I also briefly describe the important transi-
tions.
Before the argument begins, Socrates has made a distinction between
philosophers and lovers of sights and sounds. The latter, unlike the former,
are unable to distinguish beauty itself from beautiful sensible objects and
therefore deny its existence. For this reason, Socrates claims, they possess
only belief and no knowledge. Acknowledging that they will fight this
claim, Socrates proposes to convince them by means of an argument. Ask-
3 The view that Republic V assigns knowledge and belief to "two worlds," the intelligi-
ble and the sensible, has also been rejected by J. C. Gosling ("Doxa and Dunamis in
Plato's Republic," Phronesis 13 [1968]: 119-30), on the basis of the same kind of
veridical reading defended by Fine and criticized below, and by Julia Annas (An In-
troduction to Plato's Republic [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 19811, 209-15), whose very
different reasons are also examined below. For a critique of Gosling's interpretation in
particular, see Nicholas P. White, Plato on Knowledge and Reality (Indianapolis: Hack-
ett, 1976), p. 106, n. 9.
4 For a critique of Fine's "coherentist" reading of Republic VI-VII see ch. 8 of my book,
Dialectic and Dialogue: Plato's Practice of Philosophical Inquiry, forthcoming.
' Fine's interpretation of Republic V is assumed both in Terence Irwin's Plato's Ethics
(New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), 267 and in Fine's own On Ideas (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1993): see, for example, 59-60 & 91-4.
246
Socrates then proceeds, with the following argument, to prove that there is
in fact something between knowledge and ignorance and that it is belief
(60'a).
(5) Different powers (b5vacLEt;) do different work (6 drEQydirTcat) and are set
over different objects (np' () fcrL, 477c6-d6).
(6) Knowledge and belief are different powers because they are infallible (dv-
acidQTryTov) and fallible, respectively (477e6-478a2).
(7) Therefore, belief and knowledge must do different work and be set over
different objects (478a3-b2), i.e., what is known cannot be the same as what is
believed (478bl-2).
(8) Since according to (1) knowledge is set over what is, and since according to
(7) what is known cannot be the same as what is believed, what is believed
cannot be what is (478alO-b5).
(9) Belief also cannot be set over what is not, since it cannot believe nothing
([L'6Ev) (478blO-c8).
(10) Since according to (2) ignorance is set over what is not, belief can no more be
identified with ignorance than with knowledge (478c8).
(11) Belief is darker than knowledge and brighter than ignorance (478clO-15).
(12) Therefore, belief must be between knowledge and ignorance, rather than
above knowledge or beneath ignorance (478d 1-4).
(13) Belief is set over what is between pure being and absolute not-being, i.e.,
what both is and is not (478dS-12).
Socrates at this point has yet to prove to the lovers of sights and sounds i)
that there is such a thing as "what is and is not" and ii) that the sights and
sounds which they love fall into this category. He needs one more premise
to prove this:
(14A) The beautiful things loved by the lovers of sights and sounds are also not
beautiful, the just things are also not just, the pious things are also not pious,
247
As already noted, Fine sees this argument as primarily addressing not the
objects of knowledge and belief but their propositional content. But in
assigning knowledge to "swhat is" and belief to "what is and is not," is not
the argument clearly assigning them to different objects? Not if, according
to Fine, we read the word "is" in the argument as neither existential nor
predicative in meaning, but veridical. On this reading, premise (1) above
must be understood as assigning knowledge not to what exists nor to what is
F (where F stands for some property), but to what is true. Similarly, conclu-
sion (13) assigns belief not to what exists and does not exist, nor to what is
F and not F, but to what is true and false (1978, 123-6; 1990, 87-9). Fine,
however, rejects the "degrees of truth" interpretation, according to which
each proposition contained in the content of belief is both true and false,
maintaining instead that the set of propositions included under belief is
disjunctively true and false, i. e., some are true and some are false (1978,
126; 1990, 89-90). Understood in this way, the argument does not restrict
knowledge or belief to specific kinds of objects, but simply assigns them to
different contents, namely, true propositions in the one case and the set
containing both true and false propositions in the other. Fine explains the
reason for such an assignment by interpreting the controversial steps (5)-(7)
as maintaining the following: because knowledge is infallible, it succeeds in
collecting only truths; because belief is fallible, it collects both truths and
falsehoods (1978, 128-9; 1990, 90-1). Thus, what the distinction between
knowledge and belief in the argument comes down to is simply the claim
that knowledge entails truth, while belief does not (1978, 139). Nothing is
said here about their objects.
Fine must, of course, acknowledge that at premise (14A) the word "is"
has a predicative, rather than veridical sense: in saying there that something
248
Assuming for the moment that Fine's "veridical" reading is consistent with
the text, what reasons do we have for accepting it over its rivals, the exist-
ential and predicative readings? Fine does not go so far as to claim that
these other readings are incompatible with the text. Instead, she argues that
they violate what in 1978 she calls the principle of noncontroversiality, and
in 1990 the dialectical requirement: i.e., the principle that an argument
should use only claims that are believed to be true and that the interlocutors
accept.6 Fine maintains that on the existential or predicative readings, So-
6 See 1978, 125 and 1990, 87. The "dialectical requirement" was already central to
Gosling's interpretation (121), as it is to that of Michael C. Stokes' ("Plato and the
Sightlovers of the Republic," Apeiron 25, n. 4 [1992], 109). However, Stokes takes the
principle one step further than Fine: if the premises of the argument are chosen accord-
ing to what is acceptable to the lovers of sights and sounds, why assume that Plato is
committed to them? Thus Stokes can argue, contra Fine, that these premises support a
"two worlds theory," while still agreeing with Fine that this theory "need not be accept-
ed as an item of Plato's own stock of beliefs on the basis of Republic 5 ..." (132).
Similarly, Theodor Ebert has maintained that the argument does not represent Plato's
249
view, but is meant to reveal the deficiencies of the interlocutors (Meinung und Wissen in
der Philosophie Platons [Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1974], see especially 107-9, 121,
130). My reading of the argument does not rule out this dialectical interpretation ("Pla-
to" can be understood in this paper as shorthand for "what is defended without being
refuted in Plato's dialogues"), but it does reject the reasons that have been offered for
seeing the premises as unworthy of Plato (see, e.g., Stokes, 120-1, 123, 130, and notes
12, 24, 31, 36 and 50 below).
7In her statement of step (4) in 1978, Fine leaves out the crucial qualification: "if there
is such a thing" (123). This misreading only becomes more prominent in 1990 where
Fine is not sticking as closely to the text.
8 The existential reading is defended by, among others, R. C. Cross and A. D. Woozley,
Plato's Republic: A Philosophical Commentary (London: Macmillan & Co. Ltd., 1964),
and Michael C. Stokes, in the article cited above.
250
In 1978 Fine does not argue that any of these premises need be contro-
versial; the only premise she finds controversial is the one that, as we have
seen, does not exist. In 1990, however, she sees a problem with (le):9 she
allows that it is plausible if "one takes knowledge to be some sort of ac-
quaintance," "But it is unclear why we should assume at the outset that
knowledge consists in or requires acquaintance with what is known" (89).
But why should we assume at the outset that the knowledge in question is
propositional?'? If we instead regard the structure of knowing as parallel to
that of perceiving, (le) becomes perfectly plausible: in this case it is natural
to assume that one can no more know what does not exist than one can see
what does not exist." This parallel is also needed to explain (2e), which
might otherwise appear blatantly false: for is it not obvious that I can be
ignorant of things that yet exist?'2 We need to recognize that Socrates is
here talking about what ignorance is "set over," what its object is. In being
totally ignorant of the form of beauty, the object of my ignorance is not the
form of beauty - it is not an object for me at all - but nothing. If knowl-
edge, like seeing, is a direct cognitive relation to some object, then igno-
rance, like blindness, is simply the absence of such a relation or, stated
differently, a relation to nothing.
Would, then, this parallel between knowing and perceiving be contro-
versial to the lovers of sights and sounds? The opposite is clearly the case.
At this point the lovers have no reason not to assume that "what is" in-
cludes, or is even restricted to, their sights and sounds and that knowing is
9 For the same objection, see Annas, 196, and Charles Kahn, "Some Philosophical Uses
of 'to be' in Plato," Phronesis 26 (1981): 112.
'1 J. Hintikka has claimed, I think rightly, that with the Ancient Greeks there was a
"tendency to think of knowledge in terms of some sort of direct acquaintance with the
objects of knowledge, e.g., in terms of seeing or of witnessing them" ("Time, Truth and
Knowledge in Ancient Greek Philosophy," American Philosophical Quarterly 4, no. 1
[1967]: 6).
" As Neil Cooper comments, "One could no more know something which did not exist
than meet someone who 'wasn't there"' ("Between Knowledge and Ignorance," Phrone-
sis 31, no. 3 [1986]: 234). At Theaetetus 188e-189b Socrates infers from the impossibil-
ity of seeing, hearing or touching what is not, the impossibility of believing what is not.
When Republic V 478b6-c6 also declares impossible believing what is not, we have
reason to assume that the same analogy made explicit in the Theaetetus is here implied.
12 This is Stokes' objection. In order to avoid this problem, he interprets Socrates as
meaning at 477a9-bl that "All non-existents are the objects of ignorance," rather than,
"All and only non-existents are the objects of ignorance" (114). Yet Stokes recognizes
that the stronger reading is the one found later in the argument (125).
251
'3 This is recognized by Stokes, who even claims that the antecedent of the conditional
(3e) must at this point appear a contradiction to the lovers of sights and sounds, and from
a contradiction anything can be granted to follow (1 13).
14 The predicative reading is supported by, among others, Vlastos, "Degrees of Reality
in Plato," in Platonic Studies (Princeton University Press, 1973), 63, and Annas, ch. 8.
15 Annas' defence of the predicative reading misses the point: "1 can only know of
something that it is long if it is long. If it isn't long, I can't know that it is long" (198).
But Fine's question is: If it isn't long, why can't I know that it isn't long? Cooper makes
the same objection (233), though he recognizes that the predicative reading is not im-
plausible if understood as compatible with the existential reading: "Of course, he [Plato]
could have meant that anybody who knows something, knows something which is F for
some F, since something which, for all F, was not F, could not be known. To be is to
have a property. Plato could well have meant something as complex as this and if he did,
we may regard the predicative and the existential interpretations as being compatible"
(233-4, my emphasis). This is a suggestion that will be defended below.
252
253
16 "'F' is a name, a name whose prime designate is a Form: 'F' names the F' (R. E.
Allen, "Participation and Predication in Plato's Middle Dialogues," in Plato: A Collec-
tion of Critical Essays, vol. 1, ed. Gregory Vlastos [Garden City, New York: Anchor
Books, Doubleday, 1971], 169). Allen concludes that Plato's is "a theory of predication
without predicates" (170).
'7 As Allen observes, particulars "have no independent ontological status; they are pure-
ly relational entities, entities which derive their whole character and existence from
Forms" (181); as "exemplifications" they are "not ... substances in which qualities inhere
but ... relational entities, entities in which resemblance and dependence so combine as to
destroy the possibility of substantiality" (183). In the dialogues, this point is most force-
fully stated at Timaeus 52c2-5. Rafael Ferber rightly characterizes as a misunderstanding
the view "daB Plato seine Sinnendinge wie Aristoteles als Dinge (ousiai aisthetai) kon-
zipiert hat," and chooses instead to speak of "Sinnesphanomenen" (Platos Idee des
Guten, 2d ed. [Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag Richarz, 1989], 27).
254
255
256
21 At 505e1 -2 the soul is described as perplexed (deuoQEiv) about what the good is (rt
7roT' ot?iv) in language that parallels the later description of the soul as perplexed about
what hardness is (524a7-8). At 505e 1 Socrates makes clear that this perplexity does not
prevent the soul from dno0JiavTEvo[v1q TL ctvatL.
22 Though the relation between doxa and perception is not made clear in the text, it must
be a very close one, since the characteristic of being both F and not-F that makes
sensibles objects of doxa is the same characteristic they have as objects of perception
(compare 479b6-7 and 524al-0). In the Timaeus we are told that what becomes is b66n
3 ET' Ctto Eoetos 3EQLXr1t6V (52a7).
3 Stokes points to an apparent problem with characterizing doxa as a dunamis assigned
to objects, namely, that "the Lexicon suggests the absence of any external object for the
verb 'opine' (doxazein) in normal Classical Greek. One can know, but apparently not
'opine' something externally.... This might seem a solid obstacle to taking the things
opinion stands 'over against' in this argument as external rather than internal objects"
(124). Yet Stokes himself recognizes an unambiguous exception: Theaetetus 209b2-3,
where at 6bo~taov means "I had a belief about you." Pace Stokes, there is no in-
dication that Socrates' Greek is here unnatural or forced (see also 190d4 & d7).
257
Fine makes two related philosophical objections against the existential read-
ing. The first is that it requires a notion of degrees of existence that makes
24 In a very important paper, Nicholas D. Smith argues that "we must construe Plato's
concept [of episteme] to be a blend of knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge what"
("Knowledge by Acquaintance and 'Knowing What' in Plato's Republic," Dialogue 18
[1979]: 283). Platonic episteme, according to Smith, involves acquaintance because it
has a direct object (282; he sees the word epi as an indication of this); it also involves
"knowledge what" because it requires having certain truths that are essentially related to
the nature of the object (282). Though Smith seeks to distinguish this latter "knowledge
what" from propositional "knowledge that," the only real difference appears to be that
"knowledge what" is restricted to propositions about a thing's essence. Smith's account
therefore leaves unclear how exactly this propositional "knowledge what" is "blended"
with acquaintance. My own suspicion is that even what Smith calls "knowledge what"
can be nonpropositional and that therefore what he characterizes as a "blend" is more of
an identity. In defending a "predicative" against an "existential" reading, Annas charac-
terizes episterne solely as propositional "knowledge what" (192) or understanding (193,
200, 212) achieved, not through an intuition of objects nor through a justification that
provides certainty, but through setting the propositions one affirms in the wider context
of other propositions one affirms and their mutual explanatory relationships (200). In
thus maintaining that one's beliefs become knowledge through systematic mutual expla-
nation, Annas comes very close to Fine's view that Plato was a "coherentist." For a
critique of this view, see chapters 7 & 8 of my Dialectic and Dialogue: Plato's Practice
of Philosophical Inquiry (forthcoming).
258
25 Annas asserts that "the notion of degrees of existence does not make sense" (196).
Vlastos' well-known argument that "degrees of reality" in Plato cannot be "degrees of
existence" is based primarily on the same assumption: "As we commonly use the word
'existence,' degrees of it (as distinct from degrees of perfection of things in existence)
make no sense whatsoever; the idea of one individual existing more, or less, than another
would be a rank absurdity. It would take strong, unambiguous evidence to establish that
Plato had any such thought in mind when he spoke of some things as being more, or less
real, than others" ("Degrees of Reality," 65). But why assume that Plato's understanding
of "existence" was the same as the one common today? And given this assumption, what
could possibly count as "strong, unambiguous evidence" of Plato's commitment to de-
grees of existence? The studies by Charles Kahn discussed below undermine Vlastos'
approach in showing that the Greeks did not possess our concept of existence. (In his
presidential address to the American Philosophical Association, Vlastos goes so far as to
claim, in a leap far beyond any of the evidence he presents, that the Greek language
itself "rules out as a monstrosity a tertium quid between existence and non-existence":
"A Metaphysical Paradox," in Platonic Studies [Princeton University Press, 1973], 49).
Ferber, in defending the notion of "Existenzgrade" (25-6), rightly criticizes the Vlasto-
sian objection as fixated on contemporary usage. Vlastos' "common sense" objection
that Plato would not want "to undermine our faith in the existence of the beds we sleep
on, buy and sell, etc...." ("Degrees of Reality," 65) is besides the point. The meta-
physical question of whether or not a bed exists as fully as its form is irrelevant to our
getting a good night's sleep.
26 See also Kahn, "Philosophical Uses," 113.
27 See "The Greek Verb 'To Be' and the Concept of Being," Phronesis 26 (1981):
259
105-34 (especially 247-9 & 259) and "Why Existence Does Not Emerge as a Distinct
Concept in Greek Philosophy," Archiv Pfir Geschichte der Philosophie 58 (1976): 324-
334. In addition to the existential and predicative meanings, Kahn also recognizes a
veridical meaning that, unlike the one appealed to by Fine, understands truth objectively,
not simply as the property of propositions ("The Concept of Being," 250; "Existence,"
328; "Philosophical Uses," 106, 115, 126; Kahn contrasts his own veridical reading with
Fine's on p. 130, n. 18; for his recognition, however, that Plato does not always keep
distinct the two senses of truth, see "Philosophical Uses," 126, and "The Concept of
Being," 252). The objective veridical meaning of being is, according to Kahn's own
account, compatible with the existential and predicative meanings: in fact, he sees the
latter two as only special cases of the veridical, which he considers to be the funda-
mental meaning of being for the Greeks ("The Concept of Being," 251-2). Ferber also
defends what he calls an "alethische" reading of the "is" (he intentionally avoids the
term "veridical"; see p. 281, n. 8), while denying that the truth in question here is the
truth of propositions: "Offensichtlich ist mit dieser Wahrheit keine Aussage- oder Ur-
teils-, sondern eine ontische Wahrheit gemeint: Ihr Sitz ist nicht der Mensch, sondern
das Sein" (22). He identifies this truth with Echtheit. An account of how an objective
sense of truth restricts knowledge to the forms is to be found in Sprute, Der Begriffder
Doxa, 78. It can be argued, therefore, that Fine's "veridical" reading does not even do
justice to Plato's conception of truth.
28 Elsewhere Kahn makes this point by asserting that "Every truth for Plato can properly
be expressed in the copula form 'X is Y.' Even the existential proposition can be so
expressed ... . 'Justice exists' is expressed as 'Justice is something (ti)" ("Linguistic
Relativism and the Greek Project of Ontology," in The Question of Being [University
Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1978], 39). After pointing out that "the cop-
ula proposition in turn is to be interpreted ontologically in terms of participation: 'X is Y'
is true only if and because X participates in Y-ness or in the Y' (39-40), Kahn concludes:
"In the last analysis, I suggest, Plato's concept of being is the being-of-a-Form, or the
being-related-to-a-Form by way of participation" (40), so that, Kahn implies, there is no
concept of being as existence distinct from either.
29 "Being in the Sophist: A Syntactical Enquiry," Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,
vol. 4 (1986): 56. Brown criticizes G. E. L. Owen's sharp distinction between a com-
plete use of the word "is" (as in "X is," i.e., exists) and an incomplete use (as in "X is
F'), a distinction upon which Owen rests his thesis that only the incomplete use is to be
found in the Sophist ("Plato on Not-Being," in Plato: A Collection of Critical Essays,
vol 1., ed. Gregory Viastos [Garden City, New York: Anchor Books, Doubleday, 197 1 1,
223-4). Brown also criticizes Vlastos' attribution to Plato of a parallel sharp distinction
260
between existential and predicative ("real") senses of the word "is" ("Metaphysical
Paradox," 46-9; "Degrees of Reality," 59-66; for the criticisms see Brown, 56, 64).
Brown provides a detailed and clear account of the distinction between complete and
incomplete uses of the "is" on pp. 52-7. What enables her to reject the sharp distinction
made by Owen and Vlastos is the description of a complete use that, while having no
complement, allows a complement (53). This allows Brown to claim, in addition to what
is cited above, that Plato does not draw a distinction "between the non-existent and that
which isn't anything at all" (62; see also 60, 61, n.16). Brown's general conclusion is
that the complete and incomplete uses are related as follows: "X is (complete use) entails
X is something and X is F entails X is. X is not (complete use) entails X is not anything at
air' (69). Ferber appears to be getting at a similar point when he characterizes the
modem use of the existential "is" as "nonindexical" and Plato's in contrast as indexical
(25). He specifically argues that Plato's existential "is" stands in relation to "Dauer" and
"Wahrheit bzw. Echtheit": i.e., that which "is more" exists more genuinely and longer
than that which "is less" (25).
30 Even Kahn, who opposes reading the distinction back into the Ancient Greeks (see n.
28 above), appears to take it for granted when he rejects the existential reading of
Republic V in favor of the veridical and predicative readings ("Philosophical Uses,"
112-3). Stokes assumes the same dichotomy in defending an existential reading, with the
consequence that he must explain the "leap" from the predicative "is" of step (14) to the
existential "is" of the rest of the argument (129). Yet not only is his explanation inade-
quate (as he appears to recognize, since he makes the lovers of sights and sounds
responsible for step [14], 130), but it is unnecessary, since there is no leap here. Ferber,
on the other hand, who also defends an existential reading, argues that the existential
"is" is not ruled out, but rather presupposed, by the predicative or "copulative" is (21-3).
Though Gerasimos Santas, like Ferber and unlike Kahn or Stokes, claims that the formu-
la "is and is not" can include both predicative and existential claims ("Knowledge and
Belief in Plato's Republic," in Greek Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science,
ed. Pantelis Nicolacopoulos, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 121
[Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1990], 52), his account of the forrns depends
on keeping these claims sharply distinct (52-4).
31 Vlastos accuses Plato of "defective analysis" in failing to explain the difference
between the predicative "is," which admits of degrees, and the existential "is," which
does not ("Metaphysical Paradox," 56).
261
262
32 These claims are listed by Fine only in the 1978 paper (123 & 130). Fine on pp.
130-131 appears to recognize the problems these claims present. For a criticism of her
attempted solution, see below.
3 "Knowledge and Belief," 49.
263
"Now, sight, hearing and the other senses are capacities each distinguished from
the others by both province and effect. Notoriously you cannot see sounds, smell
colours, hear tastes, touch smells; each sense has in that way its own province ....
Of course their effects are different too: to see is not the same as to hear, and so on.
Once we set Socrates' point in its original context of an argument against the
sightlovers, it becomes clear" (120).
This is why when Socrates introduces the notion of dunamis his examples
are none other than seeing and hearing (477c3). Would, then, Socrates'
characterization of the dunameis of believing and knowing as analogous in
structure to the dunameis of seeing and hearing be acceptable to the lovers
of sights and sounds? This question answers itself. Furthermore, Socrates'
assumption has legitimacy beyond its plausibility for the lovers if knowl-
edge and belief are understood to involve some sort of direct acquaintance
with objects.34 The important conclusion in the present context is the fol-
lowing: an "objects analysis," which sees belief and knowledge as assigned,
like seeing and hearing, to objects and not to propositions, can at least make
as much sense of the argument in steps (5)-(7) as Fine's "contents analy-
SiS."35
However, I wish to go further and argue that Fine's "contents analysis"
cannot make sense of the present passage nor of the argument's general
thesis that knowledge, belief and ignorance are "set over" different things.
As we have seen, Fine explains steps (5)-(7) as follows: the work of knowl-
edge does not err and therefore succeeds in collecting only truths; belief errs
in its work and therefore collects both truths and falsehoods (1978, 128).
34 Stokes does not attribute to Plato himself the view that the powers of sight and
hearing are analogous to those of belief and knowledge, but asserts that "what is true for
Plato is irrelevant in an argument designed to convince the sightlovers" (123). Michael
L. Morgan likewise sees the "dunamis-object" principle as appealing to the preoccupa-
tion with seeing and hearing on the part of the lovers of sights and sounds and as "not
even intended as a rule Plato is committed to" ("Belief, Knowledge, and Learning in
Plato's Middle Dialogues," Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Vol. 9
[19831: 97).
3S It may appear that the analogy between knowing and perceiving is incompatible with
the characterization of knowledge as infallible. Thus Stokes sees the switch from gnosis
to episteme in the course of the argument as necessary to introduce infallibility. "'Gnow-
ledge' (sic) is discernment, realisation, recognition, and there is nothing obviously in-
fallible about any of these" (I 15). Yet Plato might have considered the "seeing" of the
forms infallible in the way waking is infallible in comparison with dreaming. There is no
reason to assume that the infallibility in question here is the infallibility of propositions.
I see no evidence for Vlastos' claim that "logical certainty" is a "less inflated, more
exact" term for what Plato calls "infallibility" ("Degrees of Reality," 73).
264
Though Fine grants that these sets overlap, she maintains that they differ in
not being co-extensive. Yet it is clear that Fine does not mean that their
contents could not be co-extensive, since she later grants that some believ-
ers could conceivably have only true beliefs, while others could conceiv-
ably have only false beliefs (1990, 93). The difference this interpretation
allows in that over which knowledge, belief and ignorance are set is not
36 In 1978 Fine rejects this view because she sees it as having the "unintuitive" result
that knowledge and belief have irreducibly different contents, knowledge ranging over
truths, and belief over partial truths (1978, 126; see also 137-8). In 1990, Fine steps back
from this position, admitting that it might be possible to make sense of the notion of
partial truth; now, however, she claims that such a notion is controversial and thus
violates the dialectical requirement (1990, 89). Gosling, on the other hand, characterizes
belief as being of "partial truth" (130).
265
37 Already in 1978 Fine in a note distinguishes between the token contents of belief and
knowledge, on the one hand, and the sets of belief contents and of knowledge contents,
on the other (1978, 130, n. 14). The token contents of belief and knowledge can be the
same, but "the set of belief contents is not the same as the set of knowledge contents,
since it has one different property: containing true and false members, and not only true
members" (1978, 130, n. 14). Therefore, even here the difference between what is
believed and what is known is a difference between sets, and not between specific
contents.
38 Gosling's reading also in effect eliminates the tnC by reducing it to a difference in
work (124). J. Hintikka has seen the argument as doing the opposite: as reducing the
difference in work or function to a difference in objects ("Knowledge and its Objects in
Plato," in Patterns in Plato's Thought, ed. J.M.E. Moravcsik [Dordrecht / Boston: D.
Reidel, 1973], 7-18; also in Knowledge and the Known: Historical Perspectives in
Epistemology [Dordecht / Boston: D. Reidel, 1974]). Hintikka sees this reduction as
explaining Plato's "tendency to view knowledge as some sort of direct relation between
the knower and the objects of knowledge" (18), or "knowledge by acquaintance."
Against both interpretations, Santas has shown that the text clearly distinguishes the
objects of belief and knowledge from their functions ("Hintikka on Knowledge and its
Objects in Plato," in Patterns in Plato's Thought, ed. J. M. E. Moravcsik [Dordecht,
Holland: 1973], 36-42). Santas' own solution (see "Hintikka on Knowledge," 46, 48-9)
nevertheless depends on Hintikka's claim that knowledge for Plato is a direct relation to
objects (as Santas explicitly acknowledges in "Belief and Knowledge," 55).
39 Fine explicitly maintains that in claiming that what is known and what is believed
cannot be the same, "Plato might only mean that the properties of being known and
being believed are different properties" (1990, 91). However, she distinguishes this
interpretation from the one that attributes to Plato the supposedly stronger claim that
"the set of propositions one can believe is not co-extensive with the set of propositions
one can know" (91). As I try to show, however, there is no real difference here. Fine
appears to acknowledge this in deed, since she makes no use of the distinction between
the two interpretations nor defends one against the other.
266
40 Stokes appears to think that the word epi itself rules out Fine's reading (116-7).
267
4' Fine appears to shy away from a veridical reading of 478el-2. She recognizes that
this passage is problematic for her reading (1978, 132), but brushes it aside with the
assertion that it "claims quite generally that whatever is between being and not being is
what is believed" (133). Fine cannot be allowed to leave the terms "being," "not being"
and "between" here vague and general (what about participation?) when she has forced
a very definite meaning on the rest of the argument.
42 Annas makes a similar objection to the veridical reading (198), though she does not
acknowledge Fine's distinction between "false" and "very false" beliefs.
268
43 In 1990 Fine does not discuss the assignment of ignorance to "what is not," but only
refers us to the 1978 paper (1990, p. 87, n. 6). Therefore, the later paper provides no new
way of explaining the distinction between belief and ignorance.
44 Fine asserts: "Nor is this line of argument DT [the degrees of truth interpretation].
Plato's claim is now only that totally false beliefs are assigned to ignorance, and not that
all false beliefs are" (1978, 131). Yet I simply cannot see how this interpretation can
avoid assuming degrees of truth. What can prevent a belief from being totally false and
therefore assigned to ignorance except its partial truth? In general, if Fine accepted the
"degrees of truth theory" she could still avoid the "two worlds theory" (as she recog-
nizes, 1978, pp. 138-9, n. 23), while having a much more coherent interpretation, though
one still vulnerable to my other criticisms and plagued with new problems attending a
belief in "degrees of truth."
269
45 Fine also requires the perhaps less problematic assumption that "knowledge is pos-
sible" (1990, 93). Since, however, the knowledge in question here is defined quite
strictly and distinguished from perception, there appears to be no reason why the lovers
of sights and sounds should grant that such knowledge exists.
270
i) It leads to the patently absurd consequence that "No one can know, for exam-
ple, what actions are just or good; no one can know even such mundane facts
as that they're now seeing a tomato, or sitting at a table" (1990, 86).
ii) It contradicts Socrates' claim to have only doxa concerning the form of the
good (506c-e)
iii) It contradicts the description of the philosopher who returns to the Cave as
knowing the sensible things there (520c).
46 In conclusion Fine recommends her account of the argument as one "on which at least
its opening premises satisfy DR" (1990, 94). I do not see why an account on which later
but absolutely crucial premises violate the dialectical requirement is to be preferred over
an account on which the opening premises violate this requirement. For a similar crit-
icism, see Stokes, 123.
47 Similar objections against a "two worlds theory" are to be found in Annas, 194.
48 It is important to recognize that Plato sometimes uses episteme in a weaker sense that
corresponds more to our "justified true belief." As Cooper points out, in Book 4
271
(438c6-8) Socrates talks about "common or garden tAtTnjctLaL of such contingent mat-
ters as house-building and health (240). (This passage, incidentally, does not help Fine,
since she could not claim that house-building and health prove that there can be episteme
of sensible objects without having to assume that all house-builders and doctors have
knowledge of the forms). Sprute distinguishes between Erfahrungs-Erkenntnis and Ei-
gentliche-Erkenntnis (62).
49 Ebert has rightly drawn our attention to the need to reconcile the characterization of
belief and knowledge as two distinct dunameis with the characterization of belief at
476b-d as a deficiency (Mangel) of the power constitutive of knowledge (124). Unlike
Ebert, I take such a reconciliation to be possible. My interpretation here rejects Adriana
Bertozzi's claim that in the Republic doxa is "non piu un genere imperfetto di conoscen-
za, ma una conoscenza perfetta dell' imperfetto" ("11 termine 66ea nei Dialoghi di
Platone," Giornale di Metafisica 3 [19481: 41). Bertozzi's interpretation supports the
kind of extreme "two worlds theory" that would be vulnerable to Fine's criticisms ii) and
iii) above.
272
5o This is not to say that Socrates is on the same level as the lovers of sights and sounds.
While he does not know what the good is and can talk about it only in images, he
recognizes that the good exists and is distinct from any of the sensible objects that
participate in it. The importance of the Divided Line lies precisely in its introduction of a
level of cognition between the doxa of the lovers of sights and sounds and the highest
form of knowledge attainable by the philosopher: this intermediate cognitive state is
dianoia, which recognizes that its objects are not sensible, but must rely on sensible
images in talking about them (5 10d-51 lal). On this point see the excellent discussion
in Morgan, 84-92. There are important parallels between dianoia and doxa: just as doxa
is said to be something in between ignorance and knowledge, so is dianoia said to be
"something in between" ([LETaCtv. TL) doxa and nous (51 1d4-5); just as doxa is said to be
brighter than ignorance but darker than knowledge, so is dianoia said to be brighter than
doxa but darker than knowledge (?tLiJT'LTI; 533d5-6); dianoia, like doxa, is compared
to dreaming (533b6-c3). Though Socrates' dianoia is brighter and more awake than the
doxa of the lovers of sights and sounds, it is still dream-like and dark; though he
recognizes that the forms are distinct from their sensible images and has more to say
about them than what these images reveal (see 506d8-e3), he nevertheless can no more
dispense with these images than the mathematician can dispense with his diagrams. See
Fine 1990, 105.
273
s' The proportion upon which the Divided Line is based is the following: "4; To
8o0aYT&v Q6Og To yVW(TOT6V, OiTiO TtO 6poLwOAiwV nQ6O T6 @ b)ROL6OY)" (5 lOa9- 10).
274
52 It is their view that the objects of belief and knowledge must be "that-clauses" that
leads Cross and Woozley to find the argument of Republic V incoherent (169-75).
5 Elsewhere Fine writes that "even if Plato's primary concern is knowledge of objects,
this concern can readily be phrased in the modern idiom as knowledge that a particular
proposition is true" ("Knowledge and Logos in the Theaetetus," Philosophical Review
88 [Jan. 1979]: 366-7). This is precisely the way in which Fine attempts to rephrase
Republic V, against all appearances and, as I argue, unsuccessfully. For a general de-
fence of the thesis that knowledge of the forms is nonpropositional, see my "Nonpropo-
sitional Knowledge in Plato," forthcoming.
54 I wish to thank the editor and an anonymous reader for helping make this a better
paper.
275