Oup Accepted Manuscript 2016
Oup Accepted Manuscript 2016
Oup Accepted Manuscript 2016
SOHAIRA SIDDIQUI
Georgetown University, Qatar
1
Hannah Arendt, ‘What is Authority’ in Between Past and Future: Six
Exercises in Political Thought (New York: The Viking Press, 1961), 95.
2
Ibid, 122.
3
Ibid, 124.
ß The Author (2017). Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the Oxford Centre for Islamic
Studies. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email: [email protected]
2 of 29 sohaira siddiqui
authority for Arendt is the Roman Empire, whose sacred myth enables it
to survive many transformations, the most important being from
republic to Christian empire. The secularization of the empire, coupled
with the loss of religion, destabilized this trinity and jeopardized
tradition and authority, eventually bringing about what Arendt charac-
terizes as the modern crisis of authority in which power and authority
are conflated, and the importance of tradition, religion and authority is
neglected. Luckily, however, ‘the loss of worldly permanence and
reliability—which politically is identical with the loss of authority—
does not entail, at least not necessarily, the loss of the human capacity for
building, preserving and caring for a world’4 and societies can continue
6
The overall issue of the Caliphate, referred to in kal:m treatises as a
discussion on the Im:mate, was first and foremost a theological issue which
established the basic conceptualization and defence of the Sunni doctrine of the
Im:mate. In the texts these discussions usually came last and focused on four
primary issues: (1) the necessity of the Caliphate, (2) whether this necessity is
established via reason or revelation, (3) the fallibility of the im:m (which was in
response to the Sh;6; doctrine of infallibility), and (4) the order of the im:ms or
Caliphs after the death of the Prophet (also in response to the Sh;6; belief that 6Al;
was the only true successor). Later juridical discussions built upon the
foundations erected by the kal:m texts.
7
In the debate of who was considered to be a Muslim, in addition to the
Kh:rij;s and proto-Shi6is, the Murji8a also played a crucial role. Standing in
contrast to the Kh:rij;s, the Murji8a understood faith (;m:n)—to the exclusion of
action—as the decisive criterion and deferred judgment on the faith of individual
believers, arguing that only God could adequately pass judgment. Their doctrine
of postponed judgment (irj:’) meant that to the extent that leaders proclaimed
themselves to be Muslim, they were legitimate. Early polemics between the
Kh:rij;s, Murji8a and proto-Shi6is can be found in Wilfred Madelung, ‘Early
Sunn; Doctrine concerning Faith as reflected in the Kit:b al-;m:n of Ab< 6Ubayd
al-Q:sim b. Sall:m (d. 224/839)’, in Studia Islamica, 32 (1970), 233–54; Joseph
van Ess, Das Kit:b al-Irǧ:8 des Easan b. MuAammad b. al-Eanafiyya, in
Arabica, 21 (1974): 20–52; and Patricia Crone and Fritz Zimmermann, The
Epistle of S:lim ibn Dhakw:n (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
8
The Kh:rij;s espoused the most stringent criteria for legitimate leadership
constructed upon their rejection of faith without works, which entailed the
apostasy of a sinner. If the leader was a known sinner the Kh:rij;s averred that his
immediate removal was obligatory, by force if necessary, and also their
excommunication from the community. When the Kh:rij;s split later into the
Najdis and Azraqis, the former would only excommunicate individuals if they
committed a grave sin, though they maintained the overall puritanistic doctrine
with regard to legitimate leadership.
4 of 29 sohaira siddiqui
was their recognition that physical power was essential to create and
maintain a pious polity.
Eventually when hereditary succession became the norm under the
Ummayad dynasty, and new areas, cultures, and peoples came under the
purview of the Caliph in Damascus, the emphasis on Arendt’s notion of
authority as tradition waned and was replaced by discussion of physical
power in order to address the complexities of governing a vast and
diverse empire.9 From the fifth/eleventh century onward, jurists and
philosophers contributed to the growing theorization of the Caliphate,
each writing with a unique set of influences and concerns.10 Issues
addressed within these treatises ranged from the selection of a legitimate
12
Anjum (Politics, 61–2) Polargues that the community-centred vision had
five central elements: ‘(1) It places the umma, the community of all believers, as
the recipient of the Prophet’s mission to humankind. . ..(2) It requires rendering
qualified obedience to authorities from among themselves. (3) It requires sh<r:,
the practice of participation and consultation in collective affairs and, (4) by
corollary, considers the Community’s collective affairs in need of rational human
management. Finally, . . .(5) This vision considers the caliph answerable to those
he rules, the Community’.
13
In explicating the rule-centred vision, Anjum states (ibid, 71), ‘In this new
vision, we find subjects of the caliph as passive recipients of his guidance and
discipline. Their obligation is to obey God and hence the caliph appointed by
God, whose job it is to establish God’s Shari6a—obedience to the caliph is
tantamount to obedience to God’.
14
Anjum, Politics, 85–107.
15
On al-Baqill:n;’s political thought see Yusuf Ibish, The Political Doctrine of
al-Baqillani (Beirut: American University of Beirut, 1966).
16
See Ab< Mansk <r 6Abd al-Q:hir b. F:hir al-Baghd:d;, Kit:b Us k <l al-d;n,
(Istanbul: Ma3ba6at al-Dawla, 1928).
17
There are a variety of places where al-Ghaz:l; discusses his political
thought. The primary one is Fad k :’ihk al-b:3inyya (ed. 6Abd al-Rahm:n Badaw;;
6 of 29 sohaira siddiqui
Ahk mad Ibn Taymiyya (d. 728/1328).18 Ibn Taymiyya, for Anjum,
champions a return to the community-centred vision which is the only
legitimate and authentic model when measured against Prophetic
practice.19 Placing Anjum’s arguments within the framework of
authority and power as argued by Arendt, the early community-
centred vision would reflect a focus on authority, tradition and
religion, while the later rule-centred vision would primarily be centred
on power.
While I largely agree with the astute observations made by Anjum, in
focusing on Ibn Taymiyya he does not fully evince the thought of other
22
Historically it is important to note that when al-Juwayn; was writing the
Ghiy:th; power politics in the region were anything but straightforward. In
Baghdad the 6Abbasid caliphate retained the formal seat of power, but actual
power had been transferred to dynastic rulers, the most important at the time
being the Seljuks. Niz:m al-Mulk (d. 485/1092), albeit just a vizier by title, was
_
at the zenith of his power. This power was expanded by the death of Alp Arslan
in 465/1072. The throne passed to his adolescent son Maliksh:h (d. 485/1092),
necessitating the continuation of Niz:m al-Mulk’s virtual control of power. Al-
Juwayn; was astutely cognisant of these _ political realities: the second section of
his book provides insight into al-Juwayn;’s opinion of the political situation
during the time of Alp Arslan (d. 465/1072) and Maliksh:h. It is also important
to note that the Ghiy:th; itself was written at the behest of Nizk :m al-Mulk
himself and, in the second section of the book, after discussing what is to be done
in the absence of a qualified individual for the im:mate, al-Juwayn; digresses
briefly to praise his patron directly: see Ghiy:th;, 532–6. In addition to providing
political guidance, Niz:m al-Mulk introduced policies directed at the social and
intellectual betterment _ of the Muslim Empire such as his creation of the
Niz:miyya madrasas. For a complete biography of Niz:m al-Mulk see H. Bowen
and_ C. E. Bosworth, art. ‘NiC:m al-Mulk’, EI2. http://referenceworks.brillonline.
_
com/entries/encyclopaedia-of-islam-2/nizam-al-mulk-SIM_5942; last accessed 21
February 2014. For a more extensive biography See Sajid Rizvi’s, Nizam al-Mulk
Tusi: His Contribution to Statecraft, Political Theory and the Art of Government
(Lahore: Sh. Muhammad Ashraf, 1978).
23
Fu8:d 6Abd al-Mun6im AAmad and MuBtaf: Hilm; elaborate on the
differences between al-Juwayn; and al-M:ward;_ in the _ introduction of their
POWER, AUTHORITY AND ISLAMIC POLITICAL THOUGHT 9 of 29
intellectually defend this position in the introduction to his book he
emphasizes his cardinal principle that matters pertaining to the im:mate
are lacking in certainty (mas:8il mazn<na), naturally opening them up
for contestation and reformulation.24_ Thus when al-Juwayn; veers from
previous positions on the im:mate, he invokes this principle, reminding
the reader that the majority of matters within Islamic political thought
are uncertain due to the scant mention of them in the Qur8:n or
Prophetic had;th. Also, he does not demarcate political thought as an
independent _ discipline apart, as wholly distinct from other disciplines.
On the contrary, he examines the various disciplines, exploring religious,
25
See Ann. K. S. Lambon, State and Government in Medieval Islam: An
Introduction to the Study of Islamic Political Theory: The Jurists (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1981), ch. 7. Al-Juwayn;’s thought is summarized at
103–6, with the rest of the chapter to p. 129 being devoted to al-Ghaz:l;.
26
Patricia Crone, God’s Rule: Government and Islam (New York: Columbia
University Press, 2004), 234–7.
27
Wael Hallaq, ‘Caliphs, Jurists and Salj<qs in the Political Thought of
Juwayn;’, The Muslim World, 74 (1984): 26–41.
28
See n. 23, above.
29
Paul E. Walker (transl.), A Guide to the Conclusive Proofs for the Principles
of Belief: Kit:b al-Irsh:d il: qawati6 al-adilla f; uB<l al-i6tiq:d (Reading: Garnet
Publishing, 2000), Translator’s Introduction, xvii.
30
The most comprehensive study of al-Juwayn; in Western academia has been
Tilman Nagel’s, Die Festung des Glaubens: Triumph und Scheitern des
islamischen Rationalisms im 11. Jahrhundert (Munich: C. H. Beck, 1988). In
it, Nagel investigates the notion of decline and destiny of religious thought vis-à-
vis the production of scholars, focusing on the ideas of al-Juwayn;. He examines
all facets of al-Juwayn;’s scholarship, but his most important contribution is
illuminating the ostensible connection between al-Juwayn;’s socio-political
context and his religious scholarship. Nagel argues that al-Juwayn; in his
kal:m is primarily concerned with achieving certainty such that theological
questions have definitive answers.
POWER, AUTHORITY AND ISLAMIC POLITICAL THOUGHT 11 of 29
even scholars who undertake the study of al-Juwayn; himself often omit
the Ghiy:th; from consideration.
This article will attempt to address this lacuna but in assaying the text
the narrow focus will be on excavating his bifurcation between authority
and power, leaving future avenues for fruitful research open. To this
extent this article will be divided into two parts: the first will concentrate
on al-Juwayn;’s notion of power vis-à-vis his opinions on the selection of
the most legitimate candidate to lead the Muslim community, and the
second will concentrate on the location of authority in the absence of a
Caliphate.
http://referenceworks.brillonline.com/entries/encyclopaedia-of-islam-2/fatimids-
COM_0218; last accessed: 30 November 2014. Also see, Marshall Hodgson,
‘The Ism:6;l; State’ in The Cambridge History of Iran (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1968), v. 422–82.
33
Ghiy:th;, 82–96.
34
Ibid, 90.
35
al-Juwayn; utilizes numerous terms in the Ghiyath; to invoke the notion of
stability. The most frequently used are al-istiqr:r, al-ittis:q and al-intiz:m. And
though more than one term is utilized, all terms conceptually refer to the _ idea of
stable government which for al-Juwayn; entails no external threats, in the form
of foreign invaders, and no internal threats, in the form of rebels. Based on this,
security and orderliness are both inextricably connected to stability, which
explains why he uses different but related terms.
POWER, AUTHORITY AND ISLAMIC POLITICAL THOUGHT 13 of 29
select a suitable im:m and by virtue of their selection, shawka, and
behaving in accordance with a delineated method of selection, obedience
and stability are guaranteed.
After concluding his discussion on the qualifications of the electors, al-
Juwayn; turns to the opinions of his predecessors on the minimum
number of electors required to legitimately choose the im:m. In both
discussions he argues that his predecessors constructed parochial systems
of election which were fixated simply upon the fulfillment of certain
conditions. As an example, al-Juwayn; argues that al-Qad; al-B:qill:n;36
_
required that the electors be independent jurists (mujtahids), which he
considers to be a superfluous condition as it alone cannot fulfill the
44
Here al-Juwayn; argues that if the appointment of an ideal candidate (al-
k il) will lead to chaos (ikhtib:3) and unruliness (fask :d) but the appointment of
f:d
the inferior candidate (al-mafdk <l) will lead to unity (irtib:3) and order (sad:d)
then the appointment of the inferior is preferred: Ghiy:th;, 246.
45
Ibid, 170–1.
46
To see his complete discussion on when an im:m becomes characterized by
corruptness (fisq), see 141–50. For his discussion on piety as a defence against
blameworthy characteristics, see 225.
47
Ibid, 170–1.
POWER, AUTHORITY AND ISLAMIC POLITICAL THOUGHT 17 of 29
exception of competence are evaluated in accordance with what is most
congenial to the social and political needs of the polity at the time of
appointment.
Apparent from both al-Juwayn;’s exposition on the electors and the
qualifications of the im:m is his overwhelming political pragmatism. In
the case of the electors, while they initially seem to play an essential role
in ensuring the obedience of the masses, al-Juwayn;’s acceptance of the
powerful usurper demonstrates that the electors are indeed dispensable
and are primarily utilized to bolster the legitimacy of the im:m and the
stability of the appointment. As for the required qualifications of the
48
al-Juwayn;’s discussion on the deposition of the im:m is on pp. 138–64 with
his primary summary statement at 163.
49
In the case of deposition, the ideal for al-Juwayn; would be the removal of
the im:m by the electors and the simultaneous appointment of a qualified
candidate. If, however, the electors are unable to remove the im:m and his
continued presence leads to overall harm for the Muslim community, then he
allows for the people to rebel against the im:m in order to appoint a more
suitable leader. For more on al-Juwayn;’s position on rebellion see Ghiy:th;,
153–60; for an overview of the development of the Sunnii doctrine of rebellion
18 of 29 sohaira siddiqui
Extrapolating from the discussion on the appointment and deposition
of the im:m, it is clear that competency (kif:ya), obedience (t:8a), and
power are inextricably interrelated. Minimally, the im:m _ must be
competent because only a competent leader can guarantee the obedience
of individuals and establish stability. However, even though al-Juwayn;
primarily emphasizes the competency of the im:m, competency is a
manifestation of his political power, without which the obedience of the
people would be impossible. This focus is also seen in the section on the
electors where al-Juwayn; notes that their main qualifying trait is power
(shawka), and the only time the electors are superfluous is when the seat
of the im:m is usurped by another individual, who is arguably more
The discussion on the absence of a competent im:m for the im:mate and
the subsequent dissolution of government marks a distinct transition in
al-Juwayn;’s political thought. In his earlier discussion of the im:m al-
Juwayn; divides the duties of the im:m between those pertaining to
worldly affairs (duny:), and those pertaining to religious affairs (d;n).50
With the loss of the im:m, a lacuna forms within the realm of worldly
affairs and al-Juwayn; is forced to confront the shortcomings of relying
solely on political power. Whereas previously al-Juwayn; was over-
whelmingly concerned with power and obedience, once political
see Khaled Abou El Fadl, Rebellion and Violence in Islamic Law (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, [2001] 2002).
50
A discussion of the various duties of the im:m pertaining to worldly and
religious affairs is the focus for the first of the three sections of the Ghiy:th;. For
those related to d;n see 269–92 and for those related to duny: see 293–413.
POWER, AUTHORITY AND ISLAMIC POLITICAL THOUGHT 19 of 29
leadership deteriorates, he turns to thinking about continuity and
authority in a more nuanced way. In fact, Arendt in her article ‘What is
Authority?’ argues similarly and states that power is essential for
stability, but for permanence, durability and continuity, authority is
essential. In the absence of the im:mate al-Juwayn; turns to mujtahids,
muftis and the Shari6a, which together become the central mechanism to
ensure the continuity and durability of society and can thus emerge as a
source of authority with the demise of political power.
In the absence of the im:mate the larger political community is broken
into smaller indigenous communities with traditional solidarities tying
them to independent jurists (mujtahids) and muftis,51 or their preserved
53
Arendt, Between Past and Future, 124.
54
Ibid, 121–2.
55
Ibid, 122.
22 of 29 sohaira siddiqui
generalities and universal principles (um<r kulliyya),56 the depiction of which
will come in the following section, God willing.57
In this passage al-Juwayni makes clear that the primary reason for his
concern with legal continuity is the desire for continued legal respon-
sibility (takl;f) regardless of the presence or absence of mujtahids.
Therefore, although muftis are not intellectually or legally the equivalent
of mujtahids, they are sufficiently familiar with analogical reasoning
(qiy:s) and are conversant with the universal principles of the Shari6a
(um<r kulliyya) such that they can ensure legal knowledge and
continuity. Authority for the mufti is thus on the same basis as the
56
al-Juwayn; uses a variety of terms throughout the third section to refer to
broad principles of the Shari6a such as 6um<r kulliyya, al-mar:sim al-kulliyya , al-
qaw:6id al-shar;6iyya.
57
al-Juwayn;, Ghiy:th;, 632.
58
Ibid, 637.
POWER, AUTHORITY AND ISLAMIC POLITICAL THOUGHT 23 of 29
pertaining to the daily affairs of believers. Interestingly, in this section al-
Juwayn; only undertakes those matters related to worship (fiqh
al-6ib:d:t) and does not expand upon transactional matters (fiqh al-
mu6:mal:t), which occur between individuals, with the exception of
marriage. This absence may be due in part to al-Juwayn;’s belief that
cumbersome financial laws will quickly dissipate with the absence of
formalized political institutions overseeing them. Individual concerns
will therefore be directed inward and personal matters will be of primary
importance. And while the collective ethos generated by communal
adherence to universal norms of the Shari6a will sustain some connection
between individuals, social interaction will be strangulated as individuals
the interval). The question regarding their moral responsibility was one undertaken
by theologians and involved a great deal of disagreement. A recent monograph by