Alexander Pope A Poet On The Margins and
Alexander Pope A Poet On The Margins and
Alexander Pope A Poet On The Margins and
63 Pope’s Recusancy
Peter Davidson
179 Alexander Pope, the Ideal of the Hero, Ovid, and Menippean
Satire
Ulrich Broich
233 Contributors
ABBREVIATIONS AND ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Citations for quotations from Pope’s poems and letters are given in
parentheses in the text. Pope’s letters are quoted from The Correspondence
of Alexander Pope (George Sherburn, ed. 5 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1956), with the abbreviation Corr. followed by book and page numbers.
When not signaled otherwise, all poems have been quoted from the
Twickenham Edition of the Poems of Alexander Pope (John Butt, gen. ed. 11
vols. London: Methuen, 1939–69), with the abbreviation TE followed by
book and page numbers.
I would like to thank Helen Deutsch, Claudia Thomas Kairoff, Laura
Tosi, Jane Stevenson, Peter Davidson, Hermann Real, and Thomas
Woodman for encouraging me to start and continue this project at various
stages of its development; Gregory Dowling at Ca’ Foscari University for
assisting me in the linguistic revision of the articles; Murray Brown, Lori
Howard, Heather Medlock, Yvonne Richter, and the SLI staff for their
invaluable editorial assistance; Thomas and Pearl McHaney for their sup-
port and, along with all the friends at the English Department at Georgia
State University, and Allan Ingram at the University of Northumbria,
for discussing a preliminary version of my introduction; the staff of the
British Library, Bodleian Library, Cambridge University Library, Reading
University Library, Biblioteca Marciana di Venezia, and the library of the
Dipartimento di Studi Europei e Postcoloniali at Ca’ Foscari University for
their help. Last but not least, I would like to thank—il va sans dire—all the
contributors to this collection for their patient and active collaboration.
Flavio Gregori
Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia
Flavio Gregori
Studies in the Literary Imagination 38.1, iSpring 2005 © Georgia State University
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
in order to assert his own centrality “within a specific Tory tradition” that
reiterated clichés about the connection of whiggism and enthusiasm, com-
mercialism, mediocrity, illiteracy, and poverty, and promoted the restora-
tion of conservative values that, in Pope’s implicit opinion, should have
his own poetics and works as its representative. The Dunciad was “the
epitome of this Scriblerian obsession with the demarcation and defini-
tion of culture,” locating Pope “as the supreme arbiter of poetic merit”
(Williams, Poetry and the Creation 49). On the other hand, Pope’s project
was anachronistic and missed the mark both politically and culturally
because it was informed by the same Restoration agenda supporting works
such as MacFlecknoe or Roscommon’s and Oldham’s satires. Pope was out
of tune with his times, Williams adds, and his analysis of modernity was
“profoundly problematic, since in many ways it was retrospective, a form
of satirical shorthand tailored to an opponent that no longer existed”
(Poetry and the Creation 55). Thus, Pope’s centrality was contradictory,
to say the least, and showed his de facto marginalization from the dis-
courses of sociopolitical power and hegemony. In other words, Pope was a
privileged witness of the further separation of the literary and the political
fields, in which separation the field of cultural production was becoming,
to use Bourdieu’s words, “the economic world reversed,” and, we may
add, “the political world reversed.” When judged from the economical-
political viewpoint, Pope was excluded from human commerce.3 In fact,
Pope’s detractors maintained that his cultural maneuvers, variously called
resentful, vain, arrogant, impious, filled with knavery and ingratitude, and
indicating “many other Crimes of the like kind” (The Poet Finish’d in Prose
75),4 ultimately excluded him from the principal discourses of commercial,
political, and cultural development and earned him the status of marginal
poet, if not that of marginal human being: “whatsoever is the Definition
[of man], He [Pope] still appears excluded from the Human Species, which
may in some Measure account for, as well as excuse his ill Will to our Race”
(Pope Alexander’s Supremacy 18).5
Was Pope marginalized or was he central? Undoubtedly, many consid-
ered him the most talented poet in the Neoclassical tradition, and thought
him the fittest to represent his society as the epitome of rococo refinement
and politesse. Using his satiric art to censure modern bad taste, lack of
social ethos, and political corruption, he was the poet moral of his age,
to paraphrase Byron’s famous pronouncement.6 Many of Pope’s contem-
poraries considered him, as did Giles Jacob, “an excellent Poet, whose
Fame exceeds not his Merit,” whose works “are universally applauded”
(“tho’ some few of them have been cavilled at by the Criticks”), and whose
ii
Flavio Gregori
iii
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
himself to Swift, could see “no sunshine but in the face of a friend” (Corr.
2: 395; see also 1: 119, 2: 481, 3: 138, 4: 412).
Pope possessed a high sense of his own importance, seriousness, and
centrality for the culture of his age. He was clearly proud of himself.
He writes in the Second Dialogue of the Epilogue to the Satires of Horace,
Imitated,
So proud, I am no Slave:
So impudent, I own myself no Knave:
So odd, my Country’s Ruin makes me grave.
Yes, I am proud; I must be proud to see
Men not afraid of God, afraid of me.
(TE 4: 324)
iv
Flavio Gregori
to become an author; this, despite his aggressive criticism that the modern
book-trade produced “a deluge of authors” (TE 5: 49).
In 1735 he published a second edition of his Works in the same formats
and quality as the 1717 edition and of his Homeric translations, followed
by smaller, more affordable formats. In 1737 he published a beautifully
produced, “authorized” collection of his letters after another collection had
surreptitiously appeared in 1735, printed by Curll (with Pope maneuvering
the whole affair so as to be able then to publicize his 1737 volume as a sort
of “director’s cut”). Pope carefully revised and polished his correspondence
(with substantial alterations, and even replaced addressees, conflations,
and fabrications), through which he established himself as a respectable
author whose genius for sociability and amicability nobody could deny. In
January 1744, a few months before his death, he declared, “I must make a
perfect edition of my works, and then I shall have nothing to do but die”
(Spence 258). This “perfect” edition Pope received posthumously thanks
to the work of William Warburton. Pope, in fact, chose Warburton, the
scholar who had defended him from Jean Pierre de Crousaz’s attacks on the
Essay on Man, as the inheritor and editor of his collected works. Although
Pope’s choice of his editor and the edition itself were controversial (Nichol
xxxvii), the 1751 Works of Alexander Pope Esq. In Nine Volumes Complete
elevated Pope’s poetic status, as Donald W. Nichol explains:
If the 1717 Works were a monument to Pope’s vanity, the 1751 Works
showed Warburton’s huffiness, arrogance, and unprincipled lack of schol-
arly accuracy (in his notes). Warburton’s edition was not well received and
perhaps this is one of the reasons for Pope’s fading popularity.9 Yet a monu-
ment they were, like the material one that Warburton had erected in Pope’s
memory in the Twickenham parish church contrasting as it does with the
more modest burial site Pope had chosen for himself.10 Paradoxically, the
very fact that Pope did not have a proper monument at Westminster—that
“he remain[ed] without a place in the sacred repository of the departed
Genius” where only “his Epitaph on Mr. Gay, will supply the defect, and
v
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
“The life of a Wit is a warfare upon earth,” Pope admitted already in the
Preface to his 1717 Works, when he had not yet become the favorite butt of
the scribblers and his detractors; this betrays his anxiety over his disputed
status as arbiter of the public’s taste and poet of his age. Pope’s achieve-
ments were marked by his handicaps and his marginalization.
Pope was handicapped by his birth: he was not a nobleman (his father
was a wealthy linen merchant), and, although throughout his life he tried
vi
Flavio Gregori
to put on the superior pose of a true aristocrat, his condition set him at
the margins of a social world dominated by the court, the nobility, and the
political establishment. The imaginary portrait of his father in the Epistle
to Dr Arbuthnot, in which the positive qualities of the man (honesty, expe-
rience, health) are preceded by a long series of negatives (“Born to no
Pride, inheriting no Strife,” “Nor marrying Discord,” “Stranger to Civil and
Religious Rage,” “No Courts he saw, no Suits would ever try,” “Nor dar’d an
Oath, nor hazarded a Lye,” “he knew no Schoolman’s subtle Art,” etc.; lines
392–99; TE 4: 126), shows Pope’s anxiety about moving his “humble” and
marginal origins from social status to an atemporal, asocial axiology (“The
good Man walk’d innoxious thro’ his Age”) that should shield him (and
Pope himself, by implication) from the accusations of being an unwelcome
interloper in English society. This anxiety is even clearer in the note Pope
appends to line 381, where he literally invents the existence of his father’s
quartering of nobility:
Very little of this is true (see Sherburn 30). Yet, such a misleading account
of his family perhaps arises “not so much through a deliberate fictional-
ising, as through a genuine uncertainty over the distance [Pope’s] career
had taken him from his origins” (Hammond, Pope 18). Pope’s edgy rela-
tionship with the nobility and his endeavor to be on a par with aristocracy,
while also independent from it, belie his characterization of himself as
“[h]e who ne’er cared, and still cares not a Pin” that he wrote as his own
epitaph (TE 6: 386).12
When his flirtatiously extravagant relationship with Lady Mary Wortley
Montague deteriorated, Pope attacked her in the poem The Capon’s Tale:
To a Lady who father’d her Lampoons upon her Acquaintance (though he
did not acknowledge it; TE 6: 258), and, notoriously, portrayed her as the
“furious Sappho” who was “P-x’d by her Love, or libell’d by her Hate” in
The First Epistle of the Second Book of Horace Imitated (lines 83–84; TE 4:
vii
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
13). Pope underestimated the noble woman’s capacity for retaliation from
a loftier aristocratic perspective. She (with the help of Lord Hervey) was
able to dismiss Pope’s poetry as vulgar abuse, the product of a “wretched
little Carcass” (Guerinot 226) who “can ne’er invent but to defame”
(Guerinot 240), showing the false taste of the nouveau riche (Guerinot
241). Pope’s miscalculation proceeded from his inability to come to grips
with his own social position and class: any given member of the aristocracy
must perceive a non-aristocrat like Pope as a plebeian whatever the refine-
ment of his artistic production. Lady Mary and Lord Hervey’s attacks were
very different from the usual Grub Street assaults Pope could reject with
nonchalant aloofness: theirs was the socially acknowledged aristocratic
loftiness that could condemn a middle-class poet to perpetual exclusion
from the domain of the elite. Pope was reminded that while he might be
a patrician among the literati, among the nobility he was still a plebeian
on a par with those scribblers he so much despised. Lady Mary and Lord
Hervey’s criticism of Pope might seem similar to that of the scribblers in
tone and substance, but it was something more: it flaunted their distance
from both the scribblers and from Pope himself (qua scribbler); above all,
it told Pope where to go—to his own cave of poverty (or avarice)13 and
poetry. Along with the pamphlets attacking Pope in the 1730s, many of
which were orchestrated by Walpole in an attempt to crush an oppositional
voice, the two aristocrats’ vilification of the poet is an instance of a power
dispositif, if I may adopt the Foucauldian notion. What particularly worried
Pope was that the ridicule to which the “two Top wits of the Court” (Corr.
3: 366) exposed him would lend authority to those who questioned the
morality of his poetry—those he held as inferior and unreliable because he
judged them as socially and culturally plebeian. If the nobility considered
Pope on the same level with Grub Street, what could distinguish his satire
from that of his censurers who were condemning him for his preferring
“Words” to “Manners” and being slave to “Craft and Avarice” (Characters:
An Epistle 7–8)?14 Accusations like this were buttressed by those aristo-
crats who disliked Pope’s sermonizing and concentrated on the difference
between Pope’s verbal and practical virtue—as runs one of Hervey’s libels
(Guerinot 299–301).
In a letter to Arbuthnot, who was trying to persuade his friend to be
more cautious and less direct in his attacks against the patricianship, Pope
proudly reaffirmed his right and duty to censure the world, including his
superiors precisely because of his lower social position: “in my low Station,
with no other Power than this [writing satire], I hope to deter, if not to
reform” (Corr. 3: 423). Linda Zionkowski observes that Lord Hervey was
viii
Flavio Gregori
Were it the mere Excess of your Lordship’s Wit, that carried you
thus triumphantly over all the bounds of decency, I might consider
your Lordship on your Pegasus, as a sprightly hunter on a mettled
horse; and while you were trampling down all our works, patiently
suffer the injury, in pure admiration of the Noble Sport. But should
the case be quite otherwise, should your Lordship be only like a Boy
that is run away with; and run away by a Very Foal; really common
charity, as well as respect for a noble family, would oblige me to stop
your career, and to help you down from this Pegasus. (Cowler 443)
ix
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
As a matter of fact, Pope had to confuse money with poetry. This was the
only way for him to remove himself from the risk of becoming “like a
poor Animal” sacrificed to “cement a lasting League” among his powerful
enemies (Cowler 446). His distaste for commercialism paradoxically trans-
lated into the equation: poverty = dullness (which, as Abigail Williams
notices, was a Tory cliché),20 and his poise as an amateur poet who wrote
“because it amused [him]” (as he stated in the Preface to his 1717 Works)
is equally paradoxical because his professionalism associated him with
Grub Street (see Hammond, Professional Imaginative Writing 292–302).
This last paradox was emphasized by most of his contemporary enemies,
scribblers and aristocrats alike, who accused Pope of writing out of avarice
and self-aggrandizement:
x
Flavio Gregori
Pope looke for, but ultimately (and inevitably) could not find his position
within the class-system of the age that made him a “neither/nor” person
(neither aristocratic nor plebeian, neither amateur nor specialist, neither
reliant on patrons nor fully independent, etc.). This is revelatory of the
ambiguous condition between marginalization and centralization, inclu-
sion and exclusion, that modernity would impose on individuals (because
individuals).
xi
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
xii
Flavio Gregori
xiii
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
… now all the old canards came circling back to light upon his head
and hang about his neck. He was a Jacobite, a traitor, a plagiary,
a defrauder of the public, a would-be despot … the long-hack-
neyed plays upon his name could be revived, as in Pope Alexander’s
Supremacy and Infallibility Examin’d (1729), whose engraved fron-
tispiece shows the poet crouched over a stack of his own works
and wearing a papal tiara. He was also, to be sure, a lump, a toad, a
venomous spider, and a monkey dropping filth.… his names could
be tortured into A-P-E; and, in the engraving above mentioned,
his tiara-crowned head rests on a monkey’s shape. (Alexander Pope
491)
xiv
Flavio Gregori
xv
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
xvi
Flavio Gregori
image and for ownership of meaning (i.e., his struggle with the literary
world to keep the control of the true meaning of his work against the
malevolent interpretations of his enemies) conflicted with the fact that his
“originality” could be understood as “oddity” or “monstrosity.” According
to Deutsch, Pope found a way of taming this frightful uniqueness of being
in his imitation of the ancient classics:
This special poetics of deformity was a perilous attempt to find form for
deformity, this by incorporating the loss of form into the frame of repre-
sentation (217) and by sublimating the grotesque into radiant classical
forms, which would mark, as said a Newcastle visitor to Twickenham “the
Taste of the finest Genius that this or any other Age has produced” (qtd. in
Deutsch 128); and yet it was also the metonymic reminder of the fetishist
phantasmagoria from which it originated (128–30).
Therefore, while coming to terms with the issues of his deformity, Pope
actually split the beautiful-ugly dichotomy apart; in doing so he violated
the unity of Neoclassical poetics and its equation of form, poetry, morality,
and theodicy—a modernized version of the classical kalos kagathos. Pope
incorporated the ugly and the deformed in his poetry, following Boileau’s
dictum that “[t]here’s not a Monster bred beneath the Sky / But, well
dispos’d by Art, may please the Eye” (Canto III, lines 1–2; Boileau 29); but
then Pope also strove to demonstrate that his own deformed body housed
a beautiful mind (his aequum animum; see Corr. 1: 275). This stood in
contrast to his enemies who were inwardly deformed and corrupt and,
therefore, must be portrayed as ugly—although this ugliness was often
concealed beneath a beautiful shape (as in the case of Hervey-Sporus).
Paradoxically, the “deformed” Pope would be able to redeem all that ugli-
ness with the perfection of his rhyme and reason. Nonetheless, the result
was not the production of classically beautiful poetry; rather, Pope’s poetry
seemed perpetually attracted by the vortex of centrifugal anarchy, where
the (absent) centripetal force of the beautiful was replaced by an interesting
mind (as Friedrich Schlegel thought modern poetry was doing; Schlegel
221–23).
xvii
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
xviii
Flavio Gregori
perennius, one needs to accept the raw material of one’s actual experience,
the marble, stone, or clay of life. Pope perceived that material as dan-
gerous, unmanageable, and heterogeneous. He invented a protective aura
of classicism for himself that was hardly based on reality, and confided in
the expectation that the public would accept an elevated image of himself
and of his relation to the world, though, in his satire, this world was ugly
and utterly corrupt. Not only did Pope’s distance from the actual realm of
facts and events increase in his later works, when he satirically dissociated
himself from an immoral and corrupt world, but also the contradiction
between the omnipresence of his moralizing poetic persona and the lack
of any positive, concrete definition of this vocal presence: we do not know
much of the poet beyond his poetic voice. The result is that, in his poetry,
Pope can be seen only for what he is not (not like the world’s scribblers
and dunces; not like the the dishonest politicians; not like the vicious aris-
tocrats, etc.), thus becoming a kind of loquacious dieu caché.
Despite his reliance on traditionalism,25 Pope was modern in his refusal
of the way of the world. For example, Pope was able to capture the unpre-
dictable volatility and at the same time the political will-power of the mob,
the Hobbesian multitudo dissoluta which, threatened by its own disorder,
closes its ranks and, with a gesture worthy of the Baron of Münchausen,
extricates itself from its disorder by imposing rule and law (Cavalletti 60).
In other words, Pope was able to capture the intersection of anomy and
nomos that complement each other in the formation of a new, more pow-
erful nomos. As Pope reproduced it, dullness is a political phenomenon
aiming at the conquest of the world through the substitution of nomos with
a new nomos; it is anomy possessing the power of lawmaking through a
perpetual state of emergency that incessantly transforms itself and does not
allow us to capture its center; it is an apparently lawless power structure
that imperceptibly imposes itself as the law in such a way that it is diffi-
cult to interpret it as totalitarian (or paving the way for totalitarianism).26
In his capacity as mock-portraitist of a shifting reality that confirmed the
political status quo, Pope was an attentively observing outsider in the
center of modern reality. However, in addition to the pars destruens of his
satire, he was not able to capture the implicit demand coming from the
reshuffling of marginality/centrality of his age and transform it into a pars
construens. Instead of condemning the mob simply qua recipient of power,
and instead of trying to liberate the genuine claim for recognition of the
marginalized ones against the nomenklatura, Pope’s classicism appropri-
ated the relationship of exclusion/inclusion, incorporating the ugly only to
make it disappear (“for though a scribler exists by being … incorporated,”
xix
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
xx
Flavio Gregori
see Pope’s retirement and “moral, political and cultural combat” (these are
the words of Carole Fabricant) as a form of narcissism, and “overriding
obsession with self,” which transforms contemporary issues “into a stage
for [Pope’s] performance[s], an arena in which he can display his intel-
lectual dexterity and verbal wit” (Fabricant 46), a place for self-tribute
and self-preoccupations devoid of any larger and more objective issues
and scope. In other words, Pope tried to transform the ongoing social and
political marginalization of his position (not being a poet at court), and
inject it into the center of the political and moral discourses of the age.
There may be doubts about Pope’s actual combativity and effectiveness,
corroborated by his recurrent gloom. Apart from the occasional “sad-
dog pose” that he affected in order to appear a man of the world (Mack,
Alexander Pope 152), Pope often felt a sense of inanity, if not a contemptus
mundi, in contemplating the “Incongruous Animal … Man, … [who is]
enough to make one remain stupefied in a poise of inaction, void of all
desires, of all designs, of all friendships,” as he wrote in a famous letter
to John Caryll (Corr. 1: 185–86). In his copy of Montaigne’s essays, Pope
glossed the following lines: “[My manners] had not other vice but Sloth
and want of Mettal. There is no fear that I would do ill, but that I would do
nothing…” with the words: “Alter Ego” (Mack, Collected 427). His melan-
choly (Corr. 2: 337; 3: 5) and sadness before the “glory, jest, and riddle of
the world” (TE 3–1: 56) was however less the result of a calculated, self-
conscious Entsagung before the way of the world, than a reaction to his not
finding a place in it and not having his voice heard.29
Pope’s way of getting over his psychological and social despondency
was his dedication to the cult of poetry and his literary career. Claude
Rawson, and Thomas Woodman in this collection, rightly draw attention
to the fact that some kind of hauteur is present in the process of becoming
a spokesman for a conservative ideology without ever being part of the
establishment (Rawson 252–58). As Thomas Woodman has shown in his
Politeness and Poetry in the Age of Pope, Pope’s attempt to mediate between
the values of the old gentry, based on status and blood, and the modern
notion of virtue and politeness (that “worth makes the man”) reflected
the decline of the old aristocratic ideology he wanted to represent, and
became a myth devoid of an objective correlative (30–54). The model of
poetry in which Pope believed was that of the Renaissance court poet who
provided the prince and the country with moral and political ideals that
the prince should then put into practice. As we have seen, the oligarchy
that Pope confronted was far from being interested in being instructed and
patronized by him, and, generally speaking, by any poet. The new Whig
xxi
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
According to Pope’s view of poetry, modern society needs the bard who
with his moralizing song should help it to free itself from the fetters of
corruption and helps it achieve a renewed balance between the court and
the country, the nobility and the people, and ethics and realpolitik. Yet, the
bare facts of reality dissolved Pope’s dream and made him emerge as the
only possible hero of his poetry (Gregori 252–53). Pope’s hero, however,
as those verses suggest, is neither an epic nor utopian/idealistic one; rather,
it is an elegiac hero.31
Pope tried vigorously to defend a humanist conception of literature
and poetry, at the same time elegant, learned, and moral, as a reminder
of a moral society that has disappeared but that should not be forgotten.
George, Baron Lyttelton, one of the main opponents to Walpole’s adminis-
tration, and staunch supporter of the opposition hero Frederick, Prince of
Wales, wrote to Pope (to encourage him to continue with his project of an
epic on Brutus, which was eventually abandoned):
xxii
Flavio Gregori
xxiii
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
xxiv
Flavio Gregori
and poses as moral superiority. This is also true of the ways in which Pope
articulated his discourse of the true poet as it contrasts with the Grub
Street hack. He wanted to affirm the centrality of Renaissance aesthetics
and values but did so only by implication, through the usage of a virtual
litotes that the reader should perceive in the overpowering presence of
scribblers and bad critics appearing in his notes and other textual para-
phernalia. Unconsciously and unwillingly, Pope transformed his villains,
whom he would like to marginalize (“intombe,” Warburton would say)
forever and ever, as the heroes (for us) of the only viable modern epic
poetry, an epic that cannot take itself too seriously. However, Pope would
not want us to take his heroes as such: the true hero should be his dis-
dainful verse, his art of creating out of the destruction of civilization: “Yet
may this Verse (if such a Verse remain) / Show there was one who held it
in disdain” (Epilogue to the Satires Dia. 1, lines 171–72; TE 4: 309).
A mythographer of his own self and a diviner of a lost social personality,
a censor and exploiter of the world, a scribe of chaos and a chiseller of
harmonious forms, a transgressor and a right-minded person, a bourgeois
professional and a would-be aristocratic amateur, a defender of outsiders
and their stifle—indeed “a contradiction still”—Pope could not be the
sole faber fortunae suae, let alone the arbiter of his age.32 Though “disdain”
never rhymes with “in vain” in his poetry, his life, battles, works, pains,
ambiguities, status, all show that he could not always master self as much
as he would have liked. Sometimes, in his most Montaignesque moments,
he addressed the profound reasons for his marginality, shedding doubts
on all pretensions to wholeness, concord, and self-consistency; at other
times he cultivated his dream and myth of his worthiness to mount the
Parnassus of his or any other age, and firmly asserts his self-sufficiency
and self-confidence. To us, it is of the highest importance that Pope found
himself involved in the game of inclusion and exclusion that is typical of
the modern public sphere: the continuous interplay between marginality
and centrality that is visible in Pope’s poetry and career sheds light on the
ways in which the eighteenth-century public sphere developed and func-
tioned. This was not the field of rational agents producing and confronting
each other with fully self-conscious, transparent, self-reflexive discourses,
where reason was universal and ideal speech attainable; its agents, in fact,
were conditioned by inequalities, differences, handicaps, and lacked aware-
ness of their position in the field (Bourdieu, Pascal Meditations 67).33 The
position Pope struggled to attain, one which he claimed but his enemies
called into question, resulted from a battle of books and the cultural field
was a contested battlefield. Brean Hammond, in his article in this collec-
xxv
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
tion, shows how both the physical and the imaginative space of production
of values was, in Pope’s poems, a contested space. Pope was an organizer
of that space but also a pawn in the larger play on the cultural field and in
the public sphere—central and marginal at the same time in producing his
texts and in being produced by the contexts that originated, structured and
determined his texts and life.
xxvi
some pages may be
missing
Flavio Gregori
reveal some kind of community, one that encircles the poet and his poem:
that is, a world which is larger than the word that would want to embrace
all. If, according to Foucault, the ship is the heterotopia par excellence,
The Dunciad could be this “floating piece of space, a place without a place,
that exists by itself, that is closed in on itself and at the same time is given
over to the infinity … [going] as far as the colonies in search of the most
precious treasures they conceal in their gardens … [a] great instrument
of economic development … [and] simultaneously the greatest reserve of
the imagination” (185). It could be also a Narrenschiff arriving nowhere,
its passengers enchanted by the illusionary magic of a self-induced trance
that makes them believe that somewhere, perhaps on the boat itself, there
exists a wonderland. Perhaps it could be both, and the fact that Pope left
this question open, after all and despite of himself, is the fascinating aspect
of this centrally marginal poet.
NOTES
1 E.g., Howard Erskine-Hill: “Pope was a phenomenon. Born into the marginal Roman
Catholic community when it had lost its chance of power, he won his way by talent, friend-
ship, patronage, and industry to the center of his country’s civilization” (Poetry of Opposition
111); Helen Deutsch: “Pope made his mark at once in the center and on the margins of a
historical moment he both celebrated and deplored” (3); Pat Rogers analyzes the ways in
which Pope overcame his being “a parvenu and an outsider” asserting “the power and value
of his art in a society which offered him reduced citizenship” in “Pope and the Social Scene”
(131, 133).
2 In other words, Pope tried to intervene in what Bourdieu calls the habitus (“principles
which generate and organize practices and representations that can be objectively adapted
to their outcomes without presupposing a conscious aiming at ends or an express mastery of
the operations necessary in order to attain them” [qtd. in Johnson, “Editor’s Introduction” 5–
6]). Since the habitus is rather a generative than a predetermined system, one cannot choose
one’s habitus although one can move within it and make some (relative) choices. The habitus
is partly unknown to individuals (it is “embodied history, internalized as second nature and
so forgotten as history”; Bourdieu, The Logic of Practice 56); therefore any individual attempt
to radically modify it is ineffectual. This impossibility is unperceived, for instance, by satire,
which misunderstands the habitus as character, ethos, i.e., one’s individual adherence to (and
capacity to fully comprehend and project) those principles organizing social and cultural
practices. Here, I do not mean to hypostatize the notion of habitus to the point of reducing
Pope to a set of habiti, and I am aware of criticism of Bourdieu’s insufficient recognition of
volitional reflexivity (Bohman); I just want to underscore Pope’s difficulty in gaining access
to his and his age’s habitus. John Barrell provides an analysis of the complex relationship
between the eighteenth-century description of society as a “machine” and more traditional
ideas of personal virtue (17–49).
xxxv
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
3 The literary and artistic fields have relative autonomy but, according to Bourdieu, are
still contained within the field of power (The Field 37–38). Significantly, the literary field
possesses a relative autonomy with respect to its own economic and political principles of
hierarchization. When he speaks of the autonomy of the literary field (“the economic world
reversed”) within the field of power, and of the artist having an ambivalent relation to the
economic values of the field of power, Bourdieu has in mind the late nineteenth-century
French literary field that was founded upon the principle of art for art’s sake and the rejec-
tion of bourgeois philistinism and whose position, nonetheless, was allowed by financial
strength (Flaubert is his example). The eighteenth-century literary field was not yet able to
distinguish itself from the power field. If I am allowed to make a little twist on Bourdieu’s
concept of field, Pope’s position in the rising separation of the symbolic and power fields was
emblematic of what was to happen in future ages, for his distancing (independence) from
the politics and policies of his age (corrupted commercialism) and yet partaking, within that
system of hierarchies, of the commercial success provided by a (good) work of art, which
however was not yet so socially acknowledged as it would be in the next centuries. In his
personal separation of the two fields, Pope could be inside and outside of a commercial axi-
ology, which he accepted when it accommodated itself to the hierarchies of his artistic world,
and which he did not accept when it corresponded to the hierarchies of the field of power.
In other words, through his understanding of the separate condition of the cultural field he
was able to appreciate the power of cultural capital, at the same time rejecting the forms
(commercial society) through which the field of commercial relationship was restructuring
itself in his age. This rejection, in turn, allowed him to silence the paradox of his ability to
capitalize (also economically) on his cultural power and his rejection of commercialism.
Pope could survive the paradox of being in and out, included in, and excluded from society
at the same time. Yet, he could not perceive the fact that “his” cultural, autonomous field was
always inscribed in the other, larger field that he rejected (and by which he was rejected); he
also did not acknowledge that that interplay of exclusions/inclusions was part of a conflict
for the acquisition of primacy in the literary field, for the acquisition of cultural capital.
4 These terms of abuse occur in almost all the pamphlets attacking Pope.
5 This is a pamphlet viciously attacking Pope’s deformity, among other things, written per-
the national poet of mankind,” Byron said (qtd. in Bateson and Joukovsky 206). Byron was
one of very few Romantics to take sides with Pope.
7 Jacob’s entry on Pope might have been seen and improved by Pope himself, as Jacob
himself would confess after his relationship with Pope became strained, because of an
unpleasant remark about him in The Dunciad (see McLaverty, “Pope and Giles Jacob”).
8 “Industrious, civil Pope” is the phrase of Saverio Bettinelli, Jesuit father, polymath, and
author of the Lettere inglesi (English Letters, 1766). Bettinelli considered Pope the most per-
fect of all poets in all ages (“io non conosco il più perfetto, tra tutti gli antichi e i moderni
poeti, di Pope”; Lettere 708).
9 This edition presented many controversial aspects, all depending on the interventions of
Warburton, who was authorized by Pope’s will to edit his works without altering the texts,
but who provided a set of new notes, in addition to Pope’s, that were criticized for being
centered on the vested interests of the “militant divine” (as Mark Akenside called him; qtd.
in Macdonald 226; see also Nichol xxxiii–iv). Joseph Warton, in the “Advertisement” to his
1797 edition of Pope’s works, says that “the reason for undertaking it, was the universal
complaint, that Dr. Warburton had disfigured and disgraced his Edition, with many forced
and far-sought interpretations, totally unsupported by the passages they were brought to elu-
xxxvi
Flavio Gregori
cidate” (The Works of Alexander Pope … With Notes and Illustrations by Joseph Warton 1: v).
Commenting on a letter in which Pope entrusts Warburton with his works, Warton writes,
“Without incurring, I hope, the censure of being a short-sighted and malevolent critic, I
venture to say, that our author’s fond expectation of his commentator’s setting his works in
the best light, was extremely ill-founded” (9: 377). Macdonald however notices that Warton
made things worse, in effect adopting his predecessor’s method, adding notes of his own and
digressive materials, and too often quarrelling with Warburton (320–21).
10 Warburton’s inelegant inscription,
that was perceptible everywhere, that is, in his very exclusion from the canon and in the
substitution of his poetics with anti-Popean poetics (Griffin).
12 The attribution is doubtful, as the TE editors, Norman Ault and John Butt, write in a
tuous Men; / And not the Dashes of a Madman’s Pen” (7) were verses whose substance Pope
would have subscribed to, yet this is a pamphlet attacking him (eventually for allegedly
supporting Prince Frederick and the Patriots).
15 Zionkowski analyzes the implications of this new version of masculinity that allows Pope
to attack Hervey’s sexuality as “Lord Fanny” (in The First Satire of the Second Book of Horace)
and as “Sporus” (in The Epistle to Dr Arbuthnot).
16 In his note, Warburton says that
This Letter bears the same place in our Author’s prose that the Epistle to Dr. Arbuthnot
does in its poetry. They are both Apologetical, repelling the libelous slanders on his
Reputation: with this difference, that the Epistle to Dr. Arbuthnot, his friend, was chiefly
directed against Grub-street Writers, and this Letter to the Noble Lord, his enemy, against
Court-Scribblers. For the rest, they are both Master-pieces in their kinds; That in verse
more grave, moral, and sublime; This in prose, more lively, critical, and pointed; but
equally conductive to what he had most at heart, the Vindication of his Moral Character.
(The Works of Alexander Pope 8: 253)
17 And yet, Rosemary Cowler notices how Pope, “[s]uperior and aloof as [he] may seek
to appear in this work, he is from time to time betrayed by his feelings” and tries to elicit
distress from the reader, when instead the general tone of the letter is and should remain
ironic (438). Cowler’s introduction and notes to the Letter to a Noble Lord are of extreme
importance to the understanding of Pope’s relationship with nobility at the time he decided
to stoop to truth and moralize his song (433–83).
18 McKeon would probably rubricate Pope’s attitude under the heading “conservative
ideology,” which defended noble lineage “not for its intrinsic value but for what Swift calls
its ‘imaginary value’” (170). Pope certainly did share the conservative opinion that the
progressive ideology was “money and power without merit”; however, his taking part in
the commercialization of literature and his unparalleled assault on aristocratic amateurish-
ness complicated his conservative vision, despite his adherence to Bolingbroke’s “romantic”
ideology (McKeon 210).
xxxvii
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
19 For instance the Duke of Chandos, the object of a vitriolic assault in Pope’s Epistle to
Burlington; see Guerinot xxiv, 206, 208, 211–13, 216, 225, 227, 245–46, 302–03, 312–13.
20 Grub Street retorted:
We are told, that, Men are not Bunglers because they are Poor, but they are Poor because they
are Bunglers. I only ask, How false is this in Fact? It is not well known, and has it not been
as justly observed, “That the great Lord Bacon was suffered to die Poor and Miserable;
and the great Spenser to Starve? Ben Johnson was more than once sacrificed to his worth-
less Rivals. Milton who was an Honour to Great Britain, and an Ornament to Human
Kind, continued long neglected and obscure.” (And could get but fifteen Pounds for his
Bungling Poem called Paradise Lost, tho’ Mr. Pope has some Thousands for his surprizing
Translation of Homer). (The Curliad 2)
21 Pat Rogers has written a recent, excellent study of Pope and Stuart ideology, Pope and
the Destiny of the Stuarts (Oxford: Oxford UP, 2005), which appeared too recently for me to
discuss here.
22 According to Kristina Straub, Pope’s fears of attacks on his sexuality were strictly linked
Descartes was considered a materialist philosopher (because of his theory of vortexes and
the pineal gland; see Kerby-Miller 286–87).
24 Colly Cibber thought he knew how to explain Pope’s supposed malevolence. In his Letter
modern poet.” In my opinion, Woodman is right in contesting Damrosch’s idea that Pope
“left the Renaissance behind and knew that he was doing so” and embraced the age of the
novel (qtd. in “Wanting Nothing but the Laurel,” 56). Yet, I agree with Damrosch that
Pope’s very refusal of modernity (of the world as it is) makes him a modern poet, modern
by half, since he could not accept any notion of progress or of utopia. Pope actually left the
Renaissance behind but did not know that he was doing so.
26 Hobbes’ key sentence, which establishes the priority of the salus populi, is: “The obliga-
tion of subjects to the sovereign, is understood to last as long, and no longer, than the power
lasteth, by which is able to protect them” (Leviathan, pt. 2, ch. 21; 147). Its mirror reverse is
the following sentence: “If the sovereign banish his subject; during the banishment, he is not
subject” (pt. 2, ch. 24; 148). Andrea Cavalletti’s interpretation, like my own, is inspired by
the ideas of the philosopher Giorgio Agamben, who studied a special form of the paradoxical
relationship of inclusion/exclusion that he finds prototypical of Western thought (see Homo
Sacer). According to Agamben, the legislating power captures the flux of life and regulates
it (i.e., makes it its own) in the paradoxical relationship of the sovereign power. This is
possible only through a relation that both includes and excludes what it rules: if it did not
exclude the ruled (i.e., what it is absolved of, freed from, absolutum) it would not be abso-
lute, yet there would be no object of exclusion if, beforehand, this had not been included
in the series of the objects virtually excluded. The norm becomes such only through an act
of exceptionality that cuts the rule from out of the indistinct flux of life, separating (and
declaring) the normal from the abnormal. It is as if indistinctness took itself out of itself,
like the Baron of Münchausen lifting himself with his own hand, and transforms itself into
xxxviii
Flavio Gregori
distinction. Sovereign power maintains itself in its capacity to suspend the law in a state of
exception that constitutes itself as a rule. The sovereign ban is the fundamental form of the
relationship of inclusion through exclusion (18) and finds its specimen in the figure of the
homo sacer who, under ancient Roman law, was included in the juridical order only on the
basis of his utter exclusion—his capacity to be killed but not sacrificed (82–83). On the
other hand, in The Dunciad, the behavior of this multitudo dissoluta might also be interpreted
in terms of interpassivity, activity that does not imply agency and that, instead, reinforces the
social device acting de facto in lieu of the agents (who therefore cannot aspire to any form
of utopia). On interpassivity see Žižek, The Plague of Fantasies, 117–19.
27 The Dunciad, for instance, is a clear example of the burden of the present that reclaims a
future for itself without acknowledging a past. Such recognition should be a prerequisite for
experience to become meaningful, in Pope’s opinion, so that The Dunciad’s world of experi-
ence is pure actuality with much pretension to future but with no future. It would, however,
be interesting to investigate the value Pope gives to imagination to bridge the gap between
experience and expectation, between satire and utopia. This would also entail a reconsidera-
tion of Koselleck’s ideas, so as to admit the possibility of a convergence between experience
and expectation, such as the one proposed by Anders Schinkel (42–54). David Fairer pro-
vides the most interesting discussion of Pope’s imagination (Pope’s Imagination).
28 “Courts I see not, Courtiers I know not, Kings I adore not, Queens I compliment not;
so I am never like to be in fashion, nor in dependance,” he wrote to Swift (20 April 1733;
Corr. 3: 367).
29 Entsagung, the act of giving up one’s juvenile dreams that the world can be made better
by the artist’s consciousness and works, would be typical of the late eighteenth-century and
Romantic Bildungsroman. Pope wrote: “Happy they! who are banish’d from us; but happier
they, who can banish themselves, or more properly banish the world from them! Alas! I live
at Twickenham!” (letter to Edward Blount, 27 June 1723; Corr. 2: 176).
30 In his poetry and correspondence, Pope became the mythographer of himself, to the
point that he anticipated the Preromantic and Romantic myth of the artist that is larger than
his heroes because “in addition to his ability to see in them their capacity for great moral
and spiritual actions, he has in himself the divine art to invent them … if an excellent writer
wants to portray a hero, he creates it from within himself; therefore he finds it in his own
soul,” as the late eighteenth-century Italian writer Vittorio Alfieri wrote (1: 157–58; my
trans.).
31 Pope’s oscillating between satiric and elegiac modes (his two governing modes) makes
him a fit specimen of Schiller’s sentimental poet, who, not being spontaneously natural
(naïve), looks for nature through morality and the representation of the ideal (in Pope’s
case, a lost ideal).
32 Howard Erskine-Hills rightly calls attention to Pope’s antipathy toward slavery (“Pope
and Slavery”). For a thoroughly opposed view, see Laura Brown’s accusatory interpretation
of Pope as supporter of imperialist stances (especially 6–45). John Richardson links Pope’s
discourses on slavery to the discourses of his own personal liberty (“So Proud, I am no
Slave”) (101 and passim).
33 I do not mean to reject Habermas’s notion of public sphere; on the contrary, I think
it is a useful tool to describe the competitive acquisition of knowledge and power. Yet,
Habermas’s description of the English eighteenth-century public sphere, as has been noted
by several commentators, Bourdieu included, is too abstract, idealized, and factually flawed.
For instance, it does not account for art’s capacity to assess its autonomy not only in agree-
ment but also in contradiction with, sometimes opposition to, the public (i.e., political)
sphere (Thorne 540). I agree with George Justice that if the “idealized public sphere offered
xxxix
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
by Habermas did not exist in eighteenth-century Britain … [the] idea of the public sphere,
nevertheless, lay behind the practices of eighteenth-century writers, publishers, and readers
… in rhetorical strategies, the marketing of books, and shifts in generic choices” (19). To
counterbalance the excessive (“whiggish”) idealism of Habermas’s theory, Lee Morrissey
proposes to read the eighteenth-century rise of the public sphere in Žižekian terms as the
struggle among competing subjects to be admitted in the debate, “including the debate about
the structure of the debate” (160), so that the emerging public sphere is not the public sphere
but one among the possible public spheres excluding other spheres and subjects.
WORKS CITED
Aden, John M. Pope’s Once and Future Kings: Satire and Politics in the Early Career. Knoxville:
U of Tennessee P, 1978.
Agamben, Giorgio. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Trans. D. Heller-Roazen.
Stanford: Stanford UP, 1998.
Alfieri, Vittorio. Scritti politici e morali. Ed. P. Cassani. 2 vols. Asti: Casa d’Alfieri, 1951.
Ayre, William. Memoirs of the Life and Writings of Alexander Pope. 2 vols. London, 1745.
Baines, Paul. The Complete Critical Guide to Alexander Pope. London: Routledge, 2000.
Barnard, John, ed. Pope: The Critical Heritage. London: Routledge, 1973.
Barrell, John. English Literature in History, 1730–80: An Equal, Wide Survey. London:
Hutchinson, 1983.
Barrell, John, and Harriet Guest. “On the Use of Contradiction: Economics and Morality in
the Eighteenth-Century Long Poem.” Hammond 117–29.
Bateson, F. W., and N. A. Joukovsky, eds. Alexander Pope: A Critical Anthology. Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1971.
Battestin, Martin C. The Providence of Wit: Aspects of Form in Augustan Literature and the Arts.
1st ed. 1974. Charlottesville: UP of Virginia, 1989.
The Beauties of Pope. A New Edition. London, 1783.
Bettinelli, Saverio. Lettere sopra vari argomenti di letteratura scritte da un Inglese a un
Veneziano. 1766. Opere di Francesco Algarotti e Saverio Bettinelli. Ed. Ettore Bonora.
Milano: Ricciardi, 1969. 685–790.
Bohman, James. “Practical Reason and Cultural Restraint.” Shusterman 129–52.
Boileau, Nicholas. The Art of Poetry, Written in French by the Sieur de Boileau Made English.
London, 1683.
Bourdieu, Pierre. The Field of Cultural Production: Essays in Art and Literature. Ed. Randal
Johnson. Cambridge: Polity, 1993.
–––. The Logic of Practice. Cambridge: Polity, 1990.
–––. Pascal Meditations. London: Verso, 2000.
Brooks-Davies, Douglas. Pope’s Dunciad and the Queen of Night: A Study in Emotional
Jacobitism. Manchester: Manchester UP, 1985.
Brown, Laura. Alexander Pope. Oxford: Blackwell, 1985.
Cavalletti, Andrea. La città biopolitica. Mitologie della sicurezza. Milano: Mondadori, 2005.
Chapin, Chester. “Alexander Pope: Erasmian Catholic.” Eighteenth-Century Studies 6 (1973):
4–30.
Characters: An Epistle to Alexander Pope Esq; and Mr. Whitehead. London, 1739.
Cibber, Colley. A Letter from Mr. Cibber to Mr. Pope, Inquiring into the Motives that Might
Induce Him in his Satyrical Works, to be so Frequently Fond of Mr. Cibber’s Name. London,
1742.
xl
Flavio Gregori
A Compleat Collection of all the Verses, Essays, Letters and Advertisements … Occasion’d by the
Publication of Three Volumes of Miscellanies by Pope and Company. London, 1728.
Cowler, Rosemary, ed. The Prose Works of Alexander Pope. Vol II: The Major Works, 1725–
1744. Oxford: Blackwell, 1986.
The Curliad. A Hypercritic upon the Dunciad Variorum. With a Farther Key to the New
Characters. London, 1729.
Damrosch, Leopold, Jr. The Imaginative World of Alexander Pope. Berkeley: U of California
P, 1987.
Dennis, John. A True Character of Mr. Pope, and His Writings. London: 1716.
Deutsch, Helen. Resemblance and Disgrace: Alexander Pope and the Deformation of Culture.
Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1996.
Dickinson, H. T. “The Politics of Pope.” Nicholson 1–21.
Downie, J. A. “1688: Pope and the Rhetoric of Jacobitism.” Fairer 9–24.
Erskine-Hill, Howard. “Alexander Pope: The Political Poet in his Time.” Eighteenth-Century
Studies 15 (1982): 123–48.
–––, ed. Alexander Pope: World and Word. Oxford: Oxford UP for the British Academy,
1998.
–––. “Literature and the Jacobite Cause: Was there a Rhetoric of Jacobitism?” Ideology and
Conspiracy: Aspects of Jacobitism, 1689–1759. Ed. Eveline Cruickshanks. Edinburgh:
Donald, 1982. 48–69.
–––. Poetry of Opposition and Revolution: Dryden to Wordsworth. Oxford: Clarendon, 1996.
–––. “Pope and Slavery.” Alexander Pope: World and Word. 27–53.
–––. The Social Milieu of Alexander Pope: Example and the Poetic Response. New Haven: Yale
UP, 1975.
Fabricant, Carole. “Pope’s Moral, Political and Cultural Combat.” Hammond 41–57.
Fairer, David, ed. Pope: New Contexts. New York: Harvester, 1990.
–––. Pope’s Imagination. Manchester: Manchester UP, 1984.
Foucault, Michel. “Different Spaces.” Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology. Ed. James
Faubion. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1967. 175–85.
Foxon, David. Pope and the Early Eighteenth-Century Book Trade. Revd. and ed. James
McLaverty. Oxford: Clarendon, 1991.
Gabriner, Paul. “The Papist’s House, the Papist’s Horse: Alexander Pope and the Removal
from Binfield.” Centennial Hauntings. Eds. C. C. Barfoot and Theo d’Haen. Amsterdam:
Rodopi, 1999. 13–63.
Gay, John. Three Hours after Marriage. Eds. Richard Morton and W. M. Peterson. Painesville,
Ohio: Lake Erie College Studies, 1961.
Gerrard, Christine. “Pope and the Patriots.” Fairer 25–43.
Gellner, Ernest. Reason and Culture: The Historic Role of Rationality and Rationalism. Oxford.
Blackwell, 1992.
Graf, Arturo. L’Anglomania e l’influsso inglese in Italia nel secolo XVIII. Torino: Loescher,
1911.
Gregori, Flavio. Rettorica dell’epica. La dissoluzione dell’epica neoclassica e le traduzioni ome-
riche di Alexander Pope. Milano-Bologna: Cisalpino, 1998.
Griffin, Robert J. Wordsworth’s Pope: A Study in Literary Historiography. Cambridge:
Cambridge UP, 1995.
Guerinot, J. V. Pamphlet Attacks on Alexander Pope 1711–1744. London: Methuen, 1969.
Habermas, Jürgen. The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into
a Category of Bourgeois Society. Trans. Thomas Burger and Frederick Lawrence.
Cambridge: MIT P, 1989.
xli
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
Hammond, Brean S. “‘And Hate for Arts that caus’d himself to rise’: The Epistle to Dr
Arbuthnot.” Hammond 143–63.
–––. Pope. Brighton: Harvester, 1986.
–––, ed. Pope. London: Longman, 1996.
–––. Professional Imaginative Writing in England, 1670–1740: “Hackney for Bread.” Oxford:
Clarendon, 1997.
Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. Ed. J. C. A. Gaskin. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1996.
Hoppit, Julian. A Land of Liberty? England 1689–1727. The New Oxford History of England.
Oxford: Oxford UP, 2000.
Hunter, J. Paul. “Literary Theory and Literary Practice: The Example of Pope.” Talking
Forward, Talking Back: Critical Dialogues with the Enlightenment. Ed. Kevin L. Cope and
Rüdiger Ahrens. New York: AMS, 2002. 319–36.
Ingrassia, Catherine, and Claudia N. Thomas (Kairoff), eds. “More Solid Learning”: New
Perspectives on Alexander Pope’s Dunciad. Lewisburg: Bucknell UP; London: Associated
UPs, 2000.
Jacob, Giles. The Poetical Register: or, the Lives and Characters of all the English Poets. With
an Account of their Writings. Vol. 2. London, 1723.
Johnson, Randal. “Editor’s Introduction: Pierre Bourdieu on Art, Literature and Culture.”
Bourdieu, The Field 1–25.
Johnson, Samuel. The Major Works. Ed. Donald Greene. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2000.
Justice, George. The Manufacturers of Literature: Writing and the Literary Marketplace in
Eighteenth-Century England. Newark: U of Delaware P, 2002.
Kerby-Miller, Charles, ed. Memoirs of the Extraordinary Life, Works, and Discoveries of
Martinus Scriblerus. New Haven: Yale UP, 1950.
Knellworth, Christa. A Contradiction Still: Representations of the Feminine in the Poetry of
Alexander Pope. Manchester: Manchester UP, 1998.
Koselleck, Reinhart. “Erfahrungsraum und Erwartungshorizont—zwei historische
Kategorien.” Vergangene Zukunft. Zur Semantik geschichtlicher Zeiten. Frankfurt am
Main: Suhrkamp, 1979. 349–75.
Macdonald, W. L. Pope and His Critics: A Study in Eighteenth-Century Personalities. London:
Dent, 1951.
Mack, Maynard. Alexander Pope: A Life. New Haven: Yale UP; New York: Norton, 1985.
–––. Collected in Himself: Essays Critical, Biographical, and Bibliographical on Pope and Some
of His Contemporaries. Newark: U of Delaware P, 1982.
–––. The Garden and the City: Retirement and Politics in the Later Poetry of Pope 1731–1743.
Toronto: U of Toronto P, 1969.
McKeon, Michael. The Origins of the English Novel 1600–1740. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
UP, 1987.
McLaverty, James. “Pope and Giles Jacob’s Lives of the Poets: The Dunciad as Alternative
Literary History.” Modern Philology 83 (1985): 22–32.
–––. Pope, Print and Meaning. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2001.
[Miller, James?]. Are these Things So? The Previous Question from An English-man in his
Grotto. To a great Man at Court. London, 1740.
[Morrice, Bezaleel]. To the Falsely Celebrated British Homer. An Epistle. London, 1742.
Morrissey, Lee. “Re-reading Reading in Eighteenth-Century Literary Criticism.” College
Literature 31.1 (2004): 155–78.
Nichol, Donald W., ed. Pope’s Literary Legacy: The Book-Trade Correspondence of William
Warburton and John Knapton. Oxford: Oxford Bibliographical Soc., 1992.
xlii
Flavio Gregori
Nicholson, Colin, ed. Alexander Pope: Essays for the Tercentenary. Aberdeen: Aberdeen UP,
1988.
–––. Writing and the Rise of Finance: Capital Satires of the Early Eighteenth Century.
Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1994.
Nussbaum, Felicity A. The Brink of All We Hate: English Satires on Women 1660-1750.
Lexington: UP of Kentucky, 1984.
Noggle, James. The Skeptikal Sublime: Aesthetic Ideology in Pope and the Tory Satirists.
Oxford: Oxford UP, 2001.
O’Grady, Deirdre. Alexander Pope and Eighteenth-Century Italian Poetry. Berne: Lang, 1986.
Paulson, Ronald. “The Rape of the Lock: A Jacobite Aesthetics?” Acts of Narrative. Ed. Carol
and Henry Susman. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2003. 130–45.
Pollak, Helen. The Poetics of Sexual Myth: Gender and Ideology in the Verse of Swift and Pope.
Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1985.
Pope Alexander’s Supremacy and Infallibility examin’d; And the Errors of Scriblerus and His Man
William Detected. London, 1729.
The Poet Finish’d in Prose. Being a Dialogue Concerning Mr. Pope And His Writings. London,
1735.
Rawson, Claude. “‘Neo-classic’ and ‘Augustan.’” Order from Confusion Sprung: Studies in
Eighteenth-Century Literature from Swift to Cowper. London: Allen & Unwin, 1985.
235–58.
Reeves, James. The Reputation and Writings of Alexander Pope. London: Heinemann; New
York: Barnes and Noble, 1976.
Richardson, John. Slavery and Augustan Literature: Swift, Pope, Gay. London: Routledge,
2004.
Rogers, Pat. “Apocalypse Then: Pope and the Prophets of Dulness.” Orthodoxy and Heresy
in Eighteenth-Century Society. Eds. Regina Hewitt and Pat Rogers. Lewisburg: Bucknell
UP, 2002. 112–33.
–––. The Alexander Pope Encyclopaedia. Westport, CT: Greenwood, 2004.
–––. “Pope and the Social Scene.” Essays on Pope. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1993.
–––. The Symbolic Design of Windsor-Forest: Iconography, Pageant, and Prophecy in Pope’s
Early Work. Newark: U of Delaware P, 2004.
Rousseau, G. S. “‘et in Arcadia homo’: Opera, Gender, and Sexual Politics in the Dunciad.”
Ingrassia and Thomas 33–61.
Rumbold, Valerie. Women’s Place in Pope’s World. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1989.
Sawney and Colley (1742), and Other Pope Pamphlets. Ed. W. Powell Jones. Los Angeles:
Augustan Reprint Society, no. 83, 1969.
Schinkel, Anders. “Imagination as a Category of History: An Essay Concerning Koselleck’s
Concepts of Erfahrungsraum and Erwartungshorizont.” History and Theory 44 (February
2005): 42–54.
Schlegel, Friedrich. “Über das Studium der Griechischen Poesie.” Kritische Friedrich-
Schlegel-Ausgabe. Bd. 1: Studien des klassischen Altertums. Ed. Ernst Behler. Paderborn:
Schöningh, 1958.
Sherburn, George. The Early Career of Alexander Pope. Oxford: Clarendon, 1934.
Shusterman, Richard, ed. Bourdieu: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Blackwell, 1999.
Siskin, Clifford. The Work of Writing: Literature and Social Change in Britain, 1700–1830.
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1999.
Spence, Joseph. Observations, Anecdotes, and Characters of Books and Men: Collected from
Conversation. Ed. J. M. Osborne. Oxford: Clarendon, 1966.
xliii
Introduction: Pope on the Margins and in the Center
Stallybrass, Peter, and Allon White. “The Grotesque Body and the Smithfield Muses.”
Hammond 200–19.
Staves, Susan. “Pope’s Refinement.” Hammond 26–40.
Straub, Kristina. “Men from Boys: Cibber, Pope and the Schoolboys.” Hammond 185–99.
Thomas (Kairoff), Claudia N. Alexander Pope and his Eighteenth-Century Women Readers.
Carbondale: Southern Illinois UP, 1994.
Thorne, Christian. “Thumbing Our Nose at the Public Sphere: Satire, the Market, and the
Invention of Literature.” PMLA 116 (2001): 531–44.
Vattimo, Gianni. “From Utopia to Heterotopia.” The Transparent Society. Trans. David Webb.
Oxford: Polity, 1992.
Warton, Joseph. An Essay on the Writings and Genius of Pope. London, 1756.
Williams, Abigail. Poetry and the Creation of a Whig Literary Culture 1681–1714. Oxford:
Oxford UP, 2004.
Williams, Carolyn D. Pope, Homer, and Manliness: Some Aspects of Eighteenth-Century
Classical Learning. London: Routledge, 1993.
Wimsatt, William K. The Portraits of Alexander Pope. New Haven: Yale UP, 1965.
Woodman, Thomas. Politeness and Poetry in the Age of Pope. Rutherford, NJ: Farleigh
Dickinson UP, 1989.
–––. “Pope: The Papist and the Poet.” Essays in Criticism, 46.3 (July 1996): 219–33.
–––. “‘Wanting Nothing but the Laurel’: Pope and the Idea of the Laureate Poet.” Fairer
45–58.
The Works of Alexander Pope. In Nine Volumes Complete. With His Last Corrections, Additions
and Improvements … Together with the Commentaries and Notes of Mr. Warburton. 9 vols.
London, 1751.
The Works of Alexander Pope, Esq. In Nine Volumes, Complete. With Notes and Illustrations by
Joseph Warton, D. D. and Others. 9 vols. London, 1797.
Zionkowski, Linda. “’A Good Poet is No Small Thing’: Pope and the Problem of Pleasure by
Sale.” Men‘s Work: Gender, Class, and the Professionalization of Poetry, 1660–1784. New
York: Palgrave, 2001. 97–128.
Žižek, Slavoj. The Plague of Fantasies. London: Verso, 1997.
xliv