Motion Time and Place According To William Ockham
Motion Time and Place According To William Ockham
Motion Time and Place According To William Ockham
JUL 23 1960
3601
LIBRARY
3163
by
DEUSMEUS ETOMNI
A
Published by
Philosophy Series
History Series
by
Published by
3601
.S143
nos. 13-15
PREFACE VI
INTRODUCTION
Objectives, Sources and Procedures
CHAPTER ONE
1. Ockham and the Metaphysical Foundations of Medieval Science 6
2. Science : General Notions 13
3. Signification and Supposition 15
4. Truth and the Physical World 18
5. Absolute and Connotative Terms 20
6. General Conclusions 22
VII
VIII Table of Contents
CONCLUSION
1. Ockham : Metaphysics and Science . 132
2. The Mechanics of Ockham's Approach 135
3. Ockham : The Philosophy of External Relations · 138
4. The Elimination of Abstract Entities . 141
BIBLIOGRAPHY . • · 145
1 Note on Abbreviations .
Quodl. refers to Ockham's Quodlibeta septem , Strasbourg, 1491 (H.
11941 ) . A reference to this work, followed by : " II, qu. 6,"
means: "Quodlibetum II , Question 6.
Sent. refers to Ockham's Quaestiones et decisiones in IV libros senten-
tiarum, Lyons, 1495 (H. 11942 ) . A reference to this work,
followed by: "I, dist. 17, qu . 8, b, " means : " Book I , Distinction
17, Question 8, Article b."
Phil. Nat. refers to Ockham's Philosophia Naturalis ( Summulae in libros
physicorum), Rome, 1637. A reference to this work, followed
by: "III, 14," means " Part III , Chapter 14."
In transcribing from the three works listed above, all contractions have
been expanded . Punctuation has been modernized , and, in many cases,
added. All translations have been kept as close to the spirit of the original
latin as was possible.
Tractatus. refers to Ockham's Tractatus de Successivis , edited by Philo-
theus Boehner ; Franciscan Institute Publication no. 1 , St. Bo-
naventure, N. Y. (1944) .
Logic. refers to Ockham's Summa totius logicae, (pars prima) , edited
by Philotheus Boehner ; Franciscan Institute Publication no. 2,
St. Bonaventure, N. Y. ( 1951 ) .
Altaris. refers to Ockham's De Sacramento altaris, edited and translated
by T. Bruce Birch ; Lutheran Literary Board , Burlington ,
Iowa, ( 1930) .
Expositio. refers to Ockham's Expositio super libros Physicorum . The
Prologue, edited by G. E. Mohan, is printed in Franciscan
Studies, vol. XXVI ( 1945 ) 235 sqq . Those portions which I
have used that have reference to Text 71 , are edited by E. A.
Moody, and appear in his article, " Ockham and Aegidius of
Rome," Franciscan Studies, vol . 9 , no. 4 (1949) , 417 sqq .
References to both of these excerpts from Ockham's Ex-
positio, followed by a page number, refers to the pagination
of the article in which they appear.
Quaestiones. refers to Ockham's Quaestiones super libros Physicorum . Those
portions relevant to Text 71 were edited by E. A. Moody and
appear in the same article as above . A reference to this work,
followed by: "Qu . 89, p . 429, " means : " (Ockham's) Question
89, p. 429 (of Professor Moody's article) . "
I
2 Introduction
have attracted the interest of many capable scholars. But that these
studies logical, ontological and epistemological represent but a
(not unimportant) portion of what Ockham had to say a portion
inadequate for a full understanding of his contribution to philosophical
thought is evidenced by the fact that there yet obtains profound
disagreement with respect to his position concerning certain fundamental
philosophical issues. For example : two outstanding medieval scholars ,
K. Michalski and E. Gilson , persist in viewing Ockham's philosophy as
displaying a propaedeutic " scepticism ;" two equally capable scholars
on the other hand , E. A. Moody and P. Boehner , are vigorously opposed
to this view of Ockham as a "humean precursor . " Patently, the two
adopted and authoritatively rendered stands are mutually exclusive :
Ockham cannot have been both sceptical and not-sceptical . Now the
present study is not undertaken as an attempt to resolve this, or any
other equally interesting and disputed question relative to Ockham's
actual views (although the author cannot always avoid partisanship
as will become apparent in the sequel) , but rather it takes its origin
from the observation that both sides, in discussing any moot point
almost invariably seek substantiation for their position by having
recourse to Ockham's logical writings . This suggests that further and
detailed examination of what Ockham said in his other writings would
most certainly prove helpful for the task of determining with a greater
degree of precision than was hitherto possible his signal contribution
to intellectual history . It is the general aim of the present study to widen
the field of debate by examining an area of Ockham's thought which
has not yet been accorded adequate scholarly exposition .
-
Ever since the appearance of Pierre Duhem's pioneering studies
studies illustrating the medieval origins of modern-classical physics
it has been the informed consensus that William Ockham's writings on
the physical sciences occupy a rôle analogous to that of drum-major
in the triumphal procession of physics from the fourteenth to the present
century. Since Ockham enjoys such an enviable reputation as a scien-
tist ,2 we deem it curious that there exists no abundance of detailed
but for no reason that we can as yet determine, only the first part was
actually attempted . It is this first part which constitutes the extant
text of Philosophia Naturalis.
Like so many details of Ockham's biography, the actual chronology
of his writings is still a mystery. This much, however, with regard to
their relative order, is patent : that Philosophia Naturalis, which con-
tains explicit reference to both Expositio aurea super artem veterem , and
Expositio super libros Physicorum , post-dates both of these . Again ,
insofar as Expositio aurea quotes from Ockham's Quaestiones et decisiones
in IV libros sententiarum , Philosophia Naturalis is obviously later than
this commentary. Now all of the available evidence indicates that
Philosophia Naturalis was composed at approximately the same time
as Summa totius logicae (terminus ante 1329) , which also makes reference to
the three works determined as antedating Philosophia naturalis . Un-
fortunately, since neither Philosophia naturalis , nor the Summa contain
any significant dates or cross-references, it is not yet possible to accurate-
ly establish their relative order. We submit, however that Philosophia
naturalis is the later of the two works for the reason that Ockham, in
the work on natural philosophy, utilizes with power and assurance the
logical tools which only realized their full expression in this last of his
4
works dealing specifically with logic. The most probable order of the
five writings then, as we see it, is : Quaestiones et decisiones in IV libros
sententiarum: Expositio aurea super artem veterem; Expositio super
Summa totius logicae; and Philosophia naturalis.
Aside from Philosophia Naturalis , there are three other writings by
Ockham exclusively concerned with natural philosophy : Tractatus de
successivis; Quaestiones in libros Physicorum; and the already mentioned
Expositio super libros Physicorum. The tract, de successivis , which we
shall have occasion to employ as a supplementary source, is an authentic
work of Ockham's in the sense that every word it contains was written
by him, although the tract itself appears to have been compiled entirely
from the text of Expositio by later and anonymous editors. Neither the
early Expositio, nor the later (terminus post 1333 ) Quaestiones — again
a work which appears to be largely based on the content of Expositio -
have ever been printed. Inasmuch as the attempt to collect, examine
and critically compare all the manuscripts of these works so as to render
them useful to our proposed program would be an arduous task which
we cannot hope to undertake at this time, we have chosen to restrict our-
selves to Ockham's printed works. Moreover, we have every reason to
believe that Ockham's printed works provide quite adequate sources
for our express purposes. So much for our aims and principal sources ;5
it yet remains for us to discuss our procedures.
CHAPTER ONE
I.
tine, the one science of God ; and the nature of that truth which the
human soul thus apprehends - by the very nature of its object — must
exhibit the characteristics of necessity, immutability, and eternality.
Thus, for Augustine, there is no external road to knowledge . The
very possibility of an empirical science is defeated at the outset by the
restless, contingent and fundamentally illusory character of an object
which cannot yield necessary, immutable and eternal truth. Only by
fixing on the given of internal experience, apprehended by internal
observation, can we hope to pierce the reflected veil of "things" and
attain to a vision of Things in their Truth. Hence introspection with
Augustine, is become the starting-point for philosophy ; and all science
is reduced to but one : mathematical science whose internally seen
certainties alone reflect the perfect Certainty of the Word.
It is perhaps tribute enough to St. Augustine's christian thought
to note that all of the questions to which his philosophy could offer but
stammering replies, or silence, were peripheral to orthodoxy as having
been raised originally by pagan philosophers. Although it is true that
the arrival in the thirteenth-century of the balance of the aristotelian
corpus - the writings on metaphysic, psychology and natural philosophy
together with their Arab commentaries - necessitated the sounding of
foreign accents and variegated emphases in the christian theatre, still
the central conflict of the medieval drama, as written by St. Augustine,
was to remain unaltered for some eight centuries.
St. Thomas Aquinas, a sincere disciple of Augustine's Divine Comedy,
sought to keep it in the public eye by absorbing into it those elements
responsible for the disturbingly popular appeal of the newly-produced,
Arab-edited, aristotelian writings. To the extent that the older theme
and central problem still shone through, Thomas' synthesis was a
success ; nonetheless, the exotic colloquialisms which he found it neces-
sary to inject, occasioned a unique emphasis which all but destroyed
the unity of Augustine's original work.
St. Augustine's one, necessary Truth is retained as a principle
fundamental to St. Thomas' doctrine. He views it , however, as totally
transcending the scope and grasp of man's finite intellect, and as ad-
equated only to the divine Intellect's apprehension of the relation of
all lesser acts of being to Itself. In contradistinction to Augustine's
view of man as being essentially a soul using a body, Thomas regards
the human soul as the form of its material body. As such , it has ceded
its augustinian capacity for approaching to the Intelligible, and must
direct itself to painfully compounding knowledge based on abstractions
8 Ockham: Motion, Time and Place
junction : "if you can't beat ' em, absorb ' em" --- "
'em" being the alarm-
ingly increasing number of pagan-inspired christian philosophers with
empirical-scientific proclivities . To be sure, he thus opened the way to
a naturalistic conception of science, but he was motivated everywhere
by the theological end of seeking to exhibit the necessitous relationship
to Augustine's ultimate Truth implied by the discovery of the lesser
truths of experience and reason . Faced, that is, with the problem of
bolstering the augustinian structure which threatened to collapse under
the telling blows of an aristotelian-inspired intellectual revolt, Thomas
dedicated his "naturalism" to indications that the way back to Augus-
tine's one, infinite Cause was in no way impeded by a concentration
on what empirical observation could only prove to be the completely
contingent character of Its finite effects. Apparently, Thomas was no
more a " man of science" in any strict sense, than was Augustine before
him.
John Duns Scotus, still absorbed in the central metaphysical problem
articulated by St. Augustine, completely inverts the thomistic approach.
With Thomas he yields his assent to the sensible original of all human
knowledge ; but where Thomas had felt himself restricted to indications
that the lesser truths engaged by the finite mind all required for their
ultimate explanation the necessary existence of Augustine's one Truth ,
Duns seeks within the context of the truths thus engaged for the ground
of an absolute certitude which will lead him back, with St. Augustine,
to a realization of that eternal Truth to which the finite mind aspires.
Where Thomas , that is, had seen the empirical content as offering up
a sensible realm peopled by contingents all requiring for their existence
the necessary existence of God, Duns sees the same realm as offering
up necessarily true statements independent of the experience which
occasioned them.
Duns is fully cognizant of the objections which might be raised on
the theoretical level against any program which sought to exhibit
infallible truths and certainties as internal to an order of truth deriving
from sensible experience . Even St. Augustine had held as deeply suspect
the evidence delivered by the senses , and if the data of experience were ,
indeed, at best but uncertain, and at worst, systematically -or worse
still, unsystematically delusory, how could one ever hope to attain
to truths other than those compounded on the internal experience of
immediate self-awareness ?
Duns' reply is clear and decisive. Even if we are being deluded in a
particular instance of perception, say of hot and cold, we can still know
2 Ockham : Motion
ΙΟ Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
with certainty, by analysis of what it means to be " hot" or " cold ," that :
"hot is not cold." Duns locates his basis of certitude in the formal relation
of the terms involved in the reasonings occasioned by our sensible ex-
perience. Thus, despite the fact that our senses appear to assure us that
two material bodies are occupying the same place at the same instant,
ultimate recourse to the analysis of the statement occasioned by this
particular sense report : "two bodies are simultaneously occupying the
same spatial location , " will reveal the perceptual fraud as well as guaran-
tee the truth of the principle that : "two bodies cannot occupy the same
place at the same time. " For Duns, the logician's analysis adequately
mirrors an entirely parallel synthetic structure in " things" and discovers
the purely formal relations which obtain between God and His creatures."
it becomes his main task to show how Aristotle's metaphysic was sufficient
to the task of providing all the ontological basis needed for the key concepts
of physical science. If we are correct, then Ockham's evident concern
to show that the terms " motion , " "time," and " place" do not signify
absolute entities distinct from individual substances and particular
qualities, arises as an expression of his metaphysical position that
whatever exists is a res singularis, and that these terms, therefore, are
reducible by logical analysis to expressions whose elements signify only
individual substances and qualities. The exposition which we intend,
then, may be seen as a first example, in medieval philosophy, of the
accomplishments possible in the natural sciences to a philosopher-
scientist concerned to show how the most basic concepts of dynamics
and kinematics can be defined in function of an ontology which offers
no place for metaphysical figments, hypostatized abstractions or un-
observable absolutes.
2.
Ockham does not mean that the scientist, armed with the fundamen-
tals pertinent to his science, and that knowledge of logic sufficient for
making explicit the conclusions entailed , is endowed with a " knowledge
of terms" for the purpose of confounding his opposition with a display
of dialectical pyrotechnics. Clearly, interest in the rejection of " false
arguments and errors" implies a concomitant interest in the establish-
ment of truth ; and if a " knowledge of terms " is requisite to the first
endeavor, it is of equal efficacy to the second.
That there obtains, in Ockham's view, this intimate relationship
between scientific truth and terminological knowledge, arises from his
conception of the content of science. Ockham writes :
natural philosophy considers, primarily, sensible substances and composites
of matter and form ... to the understanding of which it must be known
that all science is in respect of a proposition or propositions (complexi vel
complexorum). And just as it is that propositions are known through science,
so the terms (incomplexa) in which the propositions consist, are that in
which that science consists . Now, however, the propositions which are known
through natural science do not consist in sensible things , nor in substance ·
but consist in intentions, or concepts of the soul common to such things .
And , therefore, natural science, properly speaking, is not concerned with
corporeal and generable things, because such things are not the subject and
predicates known in the conclusions of natural science . . . However, speak-
ing improperly and metaphorically, natural science is concerned with
corruptibles and mobiles because it is concerned with the terms which
stand for (supponunt) such things.11
3.
Signification and Supposition
Broadly conceived , the term " sign" is properly applied to everything
which stimulates cognition of something previously known . Thus, when
the physical appearance of a puff of smoke on the horizon presents to
cognition anything at all — from "forest fire" to "Indians on the war-
path," both previously known to have some connection with smoke -
then the smoke is exercising a significatory function.12
Restricted, however, to the realm of language, it is the term -
written, spoken or conceived¹³which assumes the role of the "puff
of smoke. " A linguistic sign, that is, shares the condition with "sign"
Parisian university, were, in actuality, directed against the sceptical ten-
dencies of the teachings of Nicholas of Autrecourt.
12 Logic. , Ch. 1 , p . 9 : " (Signum accipitur) pro omni illo quod apprehen-
sum aliquid aliud in cognitionem facit venire, quamvis non faciat mentem
venire in primam cognitionem eius ... sed in`actualem post habitualem
eiusdem." For a dramatic presentation of the way in which this statement
of Ockham's owing to imprecise understanding, can be abused into con-
structing a " picture of Ockham as an anticipation of Hume, or as a sceptic, "
see P. Boehner's article, " Ockham's Theory of Signification, " Franciscan
Studies, n. s. VI ( 1946) ; and cf. C. D. Burns' article, "William of Ockham
on Universals, " in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, n. s. 14 ( 1914 ) .
Burns is one of those who sees a certain similitude between Ockham and
Hume.
13 In Logic. , Ch. 1 , p . 8, Ockham writes : "... triplex est terminus,
scilicet scriptus, prolatus, et conceptus. " Concerning the relation between
written, spoken and conceived terms, Prof. Moody (The Logic of William
of Ockham, op. cit. , p. 40) points out that : " Ockham concedes that in the
broadest sense of the word ' sign' the spoken word is a sign of the concept.
In this broad sense anything is a sign of its cause, or of whatever comes into
the mind when it is itself apprehended ; and since the spoken word is an
indication of the presence, in the mind of the speaker, of the concept cor-
responding to it, we may in this sense say that it ' signifies' the concept.
But we cannot say that the spoken word signifies the concept in the sense
that it means the concept, or in the sense that it denotes it in this sense
of the word ' signify, ' the spoken word signifies not the concept, but rather
the thing or things signified by the concept. The spoken or written word ,
in this sense, is a sign of the thing or things which it can denote, just as
much as the concept is. It is subordinate to the concept only because the
signification of the written or spoken word is established by convention ,
whereas the signification of the concept is established by the acts of under-
standing which brings it into existence . The concept, in other words, is a
natural sign of what it means, or of the things which it can denote, whereas
the written or spoken word is instituted by convention to be a sign of what
the concept corresponding to it signifies by nature."
16 Ockham: Motion, Time and Place
4.
Truth and the Physical World
Obviously, for Ockham, whether or not something is being correctly
predicated of some subject term cannot be divorced from a semantic
consideration of the terms involved . Ockham writes :
the diverse supposition of terms bears directly on the fact (bene facit ad hoc)
that with respect to some term, some predicate is truly affirmed or denied .
Whence, by the fact that this may be true : ' a mutable thing is a subject,
or that about which something is known, ' the supposition of this term
(“ mutable thing" ) is of key importance (bene facit suppositio istius termini) .
. . . For if this term " mutable thing, " supposits simply, for itself, then this
is true : “a mutable thing is (that about which something is known) ; " that
is, this common (term) " mutable thing, " is that about which something is
known. If, however, it supposits personally, then (the proposition) is false
because any singular is false . 22 And so the diverse supposition of the same
term bears directly on the fact that, with regard to the same term, something
is truly negated or affirmed . For if in this : "man is a species," "man"
supposits simply, this proposition is true ; and if in this : "man is not
species, " the same term supposits personally , this (proposition) is still true.23
Not for a moment, however, does Ockham forget that the scientific
enterprise deals in statements about natural entities and occasions. In
all cases the ultimate ground for the truth of the stated fact is the actual
being of the things about which the fact is true. Science presupposes the
5.
Absolute and Connotative Terms
Thus , “animal," signifies " oxen, asses, and men" primarily, and means
precisely the entities which it is used to denote.29 When, on the other
hand, the elements entering into the definition of a term do not all
signify the same individual entities for which the definiens is a sign,
then the term is connotative . In this way "shape" (figura) , for example,
is a connotative term , in that at least one part of its definition does not
stand for that which the term itself denotes : for what " shape" signifies
in reality, is some substance whose parts are arranged in a determinate
spatial ordering. Hence, the connotative term " shape " signifies one
―― -
thing primarily i. e., the subject which possesses the shape and
consignifies, or connotes, at the same time, its determinate physical
configuration.30
Now the furniture of the physical universe, so far as Ockham is
concerned, admits of but two varieties of actual existent : substance and
quality. Hence, there are but two kinds of absolute terms - terms properly
ordered under the category of substance³¹ (concrete absolute terms) , and
terms properly ascribed to the category of quality32 (abstract absolute
terms). Neither class of actual existent, however, is ever experienced in
abstraction from contingent circumstance . Substances, that is, are
never apprehended per se, apart from their accidental determinations ;
no more are the qualities ever experienced apart from change ; and
since the written, spoken, or conceived expression of these contingent
circumstances is invariably couched in connotative terms, it is the
29 Ibid.; "... sicut patet de hoc nomine, ' animal ' quod non significat
nisi boves et asinos et homines et sic de aliis animalibus, et non significat
unum primo et aliud secundario, ita quod oporteat aliquid significari in
recto et aliud in obliquo, nec in definitione exprimente quid nominis oportet
ponere talia distincta in diversis casibus vel aliquod verbum adiectivum .
Immo proprie loquendo talia nomina non habent definitionem exprimentem
quid nominis."
30 Logic. , ch. 10 , pp. 34-5 : " Sicut est de hoc nomine ‘ album' , nam
habet definitionem exprimentem quid nominis, in qua una dictio ponitur
in recto et alia in obliquo. Unde si quaeras , quid significat hoc nomen
' album' , dices, quod ista oratio tota , aliquid informatum albedine ' , vel,
' aliquid habens albedinem ' . Et patet, quod una pars orationis istius ponitur
in recto et alia in obliquo. Potest etiam aliquando aliquod verbum cadere
in definitione exprimente quid nominis ; sicut si quaeratur, quid significat
hoc nomen ' causa', potest dici, quod idem quod haec oratio aliquid ad
cuius esse sequitur aliud', vel, ' aliquid potens producere aliud', vel aliquid
huiusmodi.... ' figura ' , ' rectitudo ' , ' longitudo' , ' altitudo ' , . . . et huiusmodi
sunt nomina connotativa . " See below p . 72 ff.
31 Excepting essential differentiae which are connotative.
32 Not all of the species of quality can be considered as actual existents .
Habitus and figura, for example, are rather accidental . modifications of
substance, than existents per se . Only those qualities subject to alterative
motion stricte are res permanens . These are, essentially, the qualitative
contraries.
22 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
6.
General Conclusions
CHAPTER TWO
I.
39 Phil. Nat. , III , 2 : " Quod autem non sit talis res, (i . e. , aliqua res
secundum se totam distincta ab omni re permanente), probo, quia si sic,
sequeretur quod infinitae res totaliter distinctae, quandocumque aliquid
moveretur, essent destructae et perditae, quia infinita instantia sunt in
quolibet tempore in quo aliquid movetur, et per consequens infinitae mu-
tationes, si ergo mutationes essent tales res, sic infinitae res essent generatae
et corruptae. See also, Tractatus , p . 34 , beginning : "Impossibile est esse
res infinitas per naturam, quarum nulla est pars alterius nec faciunt per se
unum , sed secundum se totas sunt distinctae, et nulla facit per se unà cum
alia, generatas vel corruptas in tempore finito ..."
40 Phil. Nat. , III , 2 : "Praeterea , si sit talis res, quaero in quo praedica-
mento ponitur : non in genere substantiae patet, quia tunc substantia
corrumperetur quandocumque mobile cessaret mutari , nec in genere quanti-
tatis, ut patet inductive discurrendo per omnes species quantitatis, nec
qualitatis vel relationis, nec ubi, nec habitus, nec actionis, nec passionis,
quia actio et passio non sunt tales res ..." See also Altaris . , p. 17, 25.
41 Phil. Nat., III , 2 : " Sed dicetur quod mutatio non est per se in praedi-
camento aliquo ; sed per reductionem tantum . . . hoc non sufficit, quia nihil
est in praedicamento per reductionem nisi sit pars alicuius per se existentis
in illo praedicamento, sicut materia et forma substantialis sunt per reduc-
Chapter Two. Motion: The Broad Sense 27
2.
proper signification , such as they have when first instituted . And as a trans-
lation is made . . . for a threefold cause (here Ockham introduces another
reason for the existence of derivative names ) : sometimes for the sake of
metre as in the poets ; sometimes for the sake of ornament as in rhetorical
speech ; sometimes for the sake of necessity , either brevity or utility, as in
philosophy; and in all of these ways a translation is made in theology . So
the application of such names . .... is made for a threefold cause ; namely for
the sake of metre, ornament, and utility or brevity. Although from the
previous causes many errors . . . originate among the simple-minded , who
wish to accept all the statements of the philosophers and of the Saints
according to a property of common speech, when it must be taken figura-
tively." See also pp. 53 , 55 , and Phil . Nat. , I, 13. Cf. the fourth prohibition
of the Parisian Statute of Dec. 29, 1340. It reads almost as though Ockham
himself had dictated it : “ Further, that no one shall say that no proposition
is to be conceded unless it is true in its literal sense ; because to say this ,
leads to . . . errors , since the Bible and the authors do not always use words
according to their proper sense . Therefore, one ought rather to attend to the
subject matter, than to the proper forms of speech, in affirming or denying
statements ; for a disputation concerned with the forms of speech and
accepting no proposition other than in its proper sense, is nothing but a
sophistical disputation . Dialectical and doctrinal disputations which aim
at the discovery of truth, have very little concern for names. " This trans-
lation from Chartularium Universitatis Parisiensis , II , n. 1042 , is by E. A.
Moody and appears in his article, " Ockham, Buridan and Nicholas of
Autrecourt," op. cit. , p . 129 .
62 Phil. Nat. , III , 4 : " Et quandocumque talia ponuntur in orationibus ,
resolvendae sunt orationes in alias, in quibus ponuntur dictiones proprie
sine omni tropo, et figura , et per tales orationes sunt alia (e) intelligendae ,
et secundum eas iudicandum est ( ab) veritate impropriarum. " See also,
Altaris ., p. 61 , ff. , Tractatus. , pp . 40-41 ; Phil . Nat. , III , 3 .
63 Tractatus ., p. 39 : " Verumtamen sciendum, quod hoc nomen mutatio
frequenter ponitur loco unius complexi . . . sicut sic dicendo : " mutatio est
acquisitio vel deperditio alicuius, " hoc nomen ' mutatio ' ponitur loco huius
complexi : ' quando aliquid mutatur ; ' et ista nomina, ' deperditio, ' ' acquisitio ,'
ponuntur loco istorum verborum, ' acquirit, ' ' deperdit' ... Verbi gratia ,
ista oratio : ' mutatio est deperditio vel acquisitio alicuius, ' ponuntur loco
Chapter Two. Motion : The Broad Sense 33
illius . . . ' quando aliquid mutatur, acquirit vel deperdit aliquid ; ' vel istius . :
' si aliquid mutatur, etc. '" See also p . 41 ff . for further examples of properly
"resolved" terms.
6 Phil. Nat., III , 4 : "... dicendum est, quod quando dicitur ' per
mutationem acquiritur forma' , iste est sensus, ' quando aliquid mutatur
acquirit formam', et ideo mutatio non est aliqua res distincta ab acquirente
formam et a forma acquisita . . ."
65 Phil. Nat., III, 4. 66 Ibid.
67 Ibid.: "Ista autem propositio, mutabile cessat mutari, non verificatur
per cessationem alicuius rei in esse reali ; sed ex hoc ipso , quod mutabile rem
aliam habet, quam prius non habuit : ... et ideo mutatio non est talis res,
quia frustra poneretur. ”
34 Ockham: Motion, Time and Place
thing, which does not seem consonant with the Philosopher's view, or it is
other than a permanent.68
Clearly, the supporters of the absolute view wish Ockham to yield both
that "mutation is something," and that " it is something other than a
permanent thing. " For these points being granted and to accept the
offered alternatives would make his own position untenable⁹ they
feel that the brief for absolute mutation is back once again on a stable
basis. Indeed , these are the assumptions upon which their own position
hinges.
Ockham, however, is quite equal to the occasion. He cordially grants
that both he and the "ancients" with whose views he claims constant
agreement would unhesitatingly yield both the desired points.
However, speaking properly, what they would be yielding by affirming
the proposition : " mutation is something, " is this :
when some mutable is changed, and it acquires or loses something, it is
something. 70
It is in this sense that Ockham would allow the truth of the proposition
at issue. "Moreover," he adds :
if you take this proposition, “ mutation is something, " in another way
namely, that “mutation ” stands for some determinate in the way in which
in this proposition : "white is something, " the subject stands for the subject
of the whiteness ; and in this proposition : "man is an animal, " in which
"man" stands for this and that thing which is a man then it is proper
that it (mutation ) may stand for some permanent thing. . . . If, however,
you say that it does not stand for a permanent thing in the way in which
"permanent thing " has been above denoted, . . . I say that mutation is not
something, because there is no such thing. "1
4.
Mutation, Conclusion
In fine, in his rejection of the absolute view, Ockham has made the
point that its supporters are culpable in that their approach to language
is uncritical and overly-literal. The absolute theory appears to him to
have its root origin in the naive belief that there exists, by nature, a
correlate for every distinct language-sign.74 And whereas Ockham ,
regards the noun "mutation" to be significative, primarily of a mutant
subject, while connoting, or consignifying, secondarily, some form
acquired "suddenly " by that mutant subject, the adherents of the ab-
solute theory, deluded by their correspondent view of language, are
forced to the vain postulation of a literally existent, although admittedly
supra-sensible "mutation ." Thus, as Ockham sees it, a proposition in
which the connotative term "mutation" appears, implies a proposition
in which some subject acquires or loses some form " suddenly. " " Muta-
tion," for Ockham, does not supposit for either a physical change, or
the physical changeling taken alone; nor does it supposit for anything
apart from either; it is, rather, both, taken conjunctively, which the term
signifies. "Mutation ," according to Ockham, is, precisely, a significative
term standing in a proposition , for a mutated subject and its mutated
form .
73 Ibid.: " Quando dicitur quod non est res permanens , dico ... quod
ista est vera : quia est sensus, quando mutabile mutatur, non mutatur ad
aliquid determinatum in diversis temporibus ; sed simul, et semel tantum .
Et quando infers, ergo est alia res a rebus permanentibus, non valet con-
sequentia."
74 Tractatus., p . 47-7 : "... dicendum, quod talis fictio nominum ab-
stractorum ab adverbiis , coniunctionibus, praepositionibus, verbis, syn-
categorematibus, facit multas difficultates, et multo (s) ducit in errores .
imagina (n) tur enim multi, per hoc, quod sicut sunt nomina distincta, ita
sint res distinctae correspondentes ..." In Phil. Nat. , III , 7 , Ockham
writes : "Et ideo hoc est principium multorum errorum in philosophia,
quod semper distincto vocabulo correspondeat distinctum significatum. "
In Altaris., p . 63 , Ockham writes : " And , indeed, many fall into various
errors by virtue of this, that they accept the passages of the ancients as
they sound according to the letter and according to a property of common
speech, which intent, however, the ancients have not held .'
am on
36 Ockh : Moti , Time and Place
CHAPTER THREE
I.
Arguments Against Hypostatization of Motion
Were one to inquire after the nature of this entity "motion," the
answer offered by a proponent of the absolute theory could be couched ,
conceivably, in this wise : motion is a certain "flux" - a continuous ,
uniform flow of "parts" of motion from being to non-being- so that
in the absolute coursing of units which comprise its totality, the corrup-
tion of one discrete part is continuously balanced by the institution in
being of yet another, thus keeping the flux streaming in infinite proces-
sion.
Within this theoretical frame, the single motions of individual moved
bodies would be accounted for, by our hypothetical absolute theorist,
by positing them to have been invested with a given objective portion
of "motion." Initial acquisition of this new quality was assumed to be
the precipitating ground for single motion ; while surcease of movement,
and final rest, were explained by its gradual depletion and eventual
loss.75
Ockham , however, will allow none of this. To begin with, he points
out that there is no better ground for assuming the absolute character
the presence of anything other than the subject, and its successive ,
linearly mensurable, quantitative gain.78
2.
regard for the sensible subject under discussion ; for he directs the seeker.
after the "what" of motion , first of all, to moved things ― to bodies in
motion. And for a body to be in motion, "it suffices," according to
Ockham ,
that ... (it) ... continuously without any interruption of time, or rest --
acquire or lose something, part-by-part (partibiliter) , one after another.79
79 Phil. Nat. , III , 6 : “Ostenso quod motus non est alia res a rebus
permanentibus ; videndum est, quid est motus. Ad cuius evidentiam viden-
dum est quando aliquid movetur. ... Et dico quod ad hoc, quod aliquid
moveatur sufficit quod mobile continue sine interruptione temporis, et
quiete, continue partibiliter acquirit vel deperdit . . ." etc. See also, Logic. ,
ch . 46, p. 134. For a body to be at rest, on the other hand, is, in Ockham's
view, for that body to fail to satisfy the conditions which qualify its being
designated as " moving . " " For, " Ockham writes, ( Phil. Nat. , III , 28 ) , “ if
a subject acquires nothing , nor loses anything, then it rests ... because
that is moved which acquires or loses something, but that which rests
neither acquires nor loses anything." Cf. Aristotle, Physics , III , 2 ; V, 2 ; V, 6.
80 Tractatus. , p. 45 : " Ideo dicendum est, quod motus non est talis res
distincta secundum se totam a re permanente, quia frustra fit per plura
quod potest fieri per pauciora , sed sine omni re tali possumus salvare motum
et omnia quae dicuntur de motu ; igitur talis res alia frustra ponitur. Quod
autem sine tali re addita possumus salvare motum et omnia quae dicuntur
de motu, patet discurrendo per singulas partes motus. "
40 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
motion, without any other thing whatsoever, can be saved by the fact a
body is in distinct places successively, and not at rest in any. 81
With regard to qualitative motion , all that is requisite for some body
to be said to be undergoing alteration , is that it - the subject itself -
receive the parts of some newly-impressed form, successively.
Therefore, beside a subject and the parts of a form , it is not proper to
posit some other thing, but it suffices to posit a subject, and the parts of
a form, which, however, are not acquired simultaneously . 82
3.
Objections and Resolutions
Ockham now allows his theory of motion as being a concept having
no extra-mental reality apart from moving bodies undergoing successive
change, to be subjected to the critical survey of his opponents. Accord-
ing to Ockham , these proffered objections once again evidence linguistic
naiveté, and he is obliged to remark, as preface to his solution of ob-
jections (solutio obiectorum) , that :
just as has been said concerning mutation, such words as " motion, " "muta-
tion," and consimilars, have been invented more to grace speech than
because of necessity ; since without these, which are in common employ,
we can sufficiently express all of our concepts . Therefore, propositions in
which such words as "motion , " "mutation, " " successive, " "succession,"
and the like are posited, are to be resolved in propositions in which such
words are posited : " is moved, " "moved, " "succeeds, " "succeeding, " and
the like and the propositions are to be seen according to these .
is the one to which his opponents subscribe. This is the forma fluens
conception of motion which Ockham has previously examined and found
wanting. 89 The alternate meaning - the one which he himself endorses-
regards "flux" in the properly "resolved" sense, to mean that,
when something is moved, it flows continuously ; that is, it continuously ac-
quires or loses something -- as when something is locally moved, it flows
continuously from one place to another - not due to (the presence of)
anything beyond a mobile and the place which it acquires , but because it
is always in one place and then another. "
The third argument assumes the fact that one can discuss the velocity
of motion, to be indicative of its divorce from permanent things. No
dermanent thing is ever spoken of as being " quick," or " slow," per se;
but motion is referred to in this way. "Motion ," then , on this account ,
must be a " thing" distinctly other than a permanent thing.93
The statement that "motion is fast or slow," as Ockham sees it , is
a reference to the mobile's rate of acquisition or loss. Speaking of a " fast"
motion implies nothing more than that some moved body has a quick
rate of acquisition or loss ; while a reference to the "slowness" of a
motion, would be informative of the fact that in the same temporal
span embraced by a “quick ” motion , the "slow" mobile acquires or
loses relatively less than when in "quick" motion . 94 Thus, in the case
of local motion, more " places" would be acquired in a given time-period
by a quickly moving body, than would be acquired in an equal time-
span by a slowly moving body.
Ockham discounts the fourth objection in that it commits the
"figure of speech " fallacy (fallacia figurae dictionis) .95 The objection
91 Phil. Nat. , III , 7 : " Secundo, motus est successivus , sed res permanens
non, sed tota simul." See also Tractatus . , p . 53 , argumenta (1) .
92 Ibid., see also Tractatus ., P. 54, (ad 1m) and ff.
93 Phil. Nat."", III , 7 : " Tertio, motus est velox, vel tardus ; sed res
permanens non .
94 Phil. Nat., III, 7 : "Ad tertium dico, quod per istam, motus est
velox, vel tardus ; datur intelligi ista : quando aliquid movetur tarde, vel
velociter movetur - hoc est, in parvo tempore acquirit multum, vel parvum. ”
Cf. Aristotle, Physics, IV, 14.
95 Prof. Moody (Logic of William of Ockham , op . cit ., pp . 294—5 ) ,
writes : "It is worthy of note that the one form of fallacy to which Ockham
Chapter Three. Motion : The Narrow Sense 43
itself maintains that since a permanent thing can exist without motion,
the two - motion, and permanent things must, therefore, be
distinct. The error involved in this type of reasoning, according to
Ockham, is similar to that involved in this argument :
whenever anything can exist without remaining things, they are distinct ;
but Sortes can exist without music ; therefore, music is distinct from Sortes .
For certainly Ockham yields that "a permanent thing can exist without
motion ;" but he does not find that this statement, and the statement
"motion is not another thing apart a permanent thing," are mutually
exclusive, any more than the true proposition , "Socrates can endure
without whiteness, " excludes the truth of, "Socrates is white . " 96
The fifth objection to Ockham's view, seizes on the supposed fact
that motion is a quantity distinctly other than the quantity of a perma-
nent thing. The truth of this premise stems, according to the absolute
theorists, from the oft-reiterated statement that motion has a successive
quantity, and therefore it cannot be equated with permanent things , which
possess a permanent quantity.97
Motion does not possess some quantity distinct as regards itself as a whole
from the quantity of a permanent thing,
devotes many pages of detailed discussion (at the end of Logic .) , is that of
'figure of speech . ' This is perhaps the most frequent source of error in
philosophy, for it is involved in the attribution of characteristics and dis-
tinctions that belong to signs, to the things of which they are signs . This
habit, which in the long run reduces to the equivocal use of terms with
respect to their significative and non-significative forms of supposition,
results in the confusion of logic, natural science, and metaphysics, and gives
rise to what may be called indifferently a ' logical realism ', or a ' metaphysical
nominalism .' Whatever name may be given to it, it is what Ockham opposes
as the worst error in philosophy, destructive of all truth, reason, science,
and of the whole philosophy of Aristotle. ”
96 Phil. Nat. , III , 7 : Quarto, res permanens potest esse sine motu ,
sed non sine re permanente . " "Ad quartum dico, quod res permanens
potest esse sine motu ; . . . unde sicut ista conceditur , ' Sortes potest existere
sine albedine ' et cum hoc stat, quod Sortes vere est albus, ita istae stant
simul : ' res permanens potest esse sine motu , ' et tamen : ' motus non est alia
res a re permanente . ' Sed contra, quando aliquid potest separari ab aliquo,
distinguitur ab illo ; sed res permanens potest esse sine motu, ergo, etc. Dico
quod in tali modo arguendi est fallacia figurae dictionis . . . quia . . . sicut
quando arguitur quandocumque aliquid potest existere sine reliquo, illa
distinguntur ; sed Sortes potest existere sine musico, ergo musicum distingui-
tur a Sorte."
97 Ibid.: " Quinto, motus est quantitas alia a quantitate rei permanentis ;
quia non habet quantitatem permanentem, sed tantum successivam . "
98 Ibid.: " Ad sextum ( !) dico, quod motus non habet quantitatem
aliquam distinctam secundum se totam a quantitate rei permanentis ,
aliquid tamen intelligitur per hoc nomen, quantum, magnum, parvum et
44 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
one to say: "a great deal of motion is present ," or something of the sort,
what is meant by this statement, is that some moved body is enjoying
an intense amount of successively acquisitive, or disquisitive , activity .
4.
Divisions of Local Motion
Ockham proposes next to extend his explication of motion, narrow,
to a consideration of the more important included species of local,
qualitative, and quantitative motion. First of all, he addresses himself
to the several varieties of local motion.99
The path described by a mobile undergoing actual motion of trans-
lation is the first means by which Ockham classifies local motion . It
appears, also , in this connection, that the geometric configuration of the
mobile must be considered ; for whereas the characterization of rectilinear,
circular, or mixed motions of translation exhaust all possible cases
describing the course of a locally moved subject, yet only a spheric
mobile can undergo circular motion , while a mobile of any physical
shape whatsoever can be moved either rectilinearlyor in a mixed manner. 100
The appellation, rectilinear motion , is properly ascribed in all cases
in which a subject of any shape is translated in a continuous line from
some place of motive initiation , to some place of final rest. This con-
trasts with circular motion in that the subject suffering circular motion
rotates about a fixed orbit - and hence, is forever in the "same place"
with respect to the total motion. There is no properly demarcated
beginning, nor any proper end-point to true circular motion ; but the
motion is regarded as a totality ; and so, relative to change of position ,
it can be considered as always remaining in the same place. This, how-
ever, is not the case where the parts of the circularly moved subject are
concerned. For these do relative to surrounding place constantly,
and successively, acquire new places ; and so the whole mobile is said,
properly, to be in motion . "When something is truly moved in a circular
motion," Ockham writes :
101 Phil. Nat. , III , 10. In Ibid. , III , 9, Ockham writes : "Motus rectus
est quando mobile secundum lineam rectam movetur sursum, vel deorsum,
et secundum alias differentias loci respectu corporis caelestis . Quando autem
sic movetur, totum mutat locum ita quod totum est in alio, et alio loco,
tam in fine motus , quam in principio, vel in medio . Motus autem circularis
est quando mobile semper manet in eodem loco secundum totum, quamvis
partes suae mutent locum, et tale motum non posset esse nisi mobile
sphaericum, vel ovale. Quia si aliquis angulus esset in mobili , tunc totum
mobile, quando movetur . . . mutaret locum ; ita quod totum esset successive
in diversis locis totalibus . . ." Cf. Aristotle, Physics, VI , 9 ; VIII , 9 .
m n
46 Ockha : Motio , Time and Place
motion, there is no legitimate ground for holding that one is moved more
swiftly, or more slowly, than another.
The case, however, in which a mobile is said to be undergoing circular
motion in the broad sense (large) , is of a different character. For these
mobiles, despite the fact that their total motion is still circuitous, do
change total place: i. e. , they are undergoing local motion along a circular
path. The fact that distances traversed by mobiles being moved in such
a manner can be protracted on a rectilinear scale allows us to compare
the swiftness or slowness of any two such mobiles. "It is in this mode ,"
Ockham concludes ,
that a heavenly body can be said to be "more swiftly" or " more slowly”
102
moved : in this, that according to itself as a whole, it does change place.¹
The mixed motions are those aberrant cases which can neither be
properly classed as circular, nor as rectilinear . A sphere revolving about
its axis, and at the same time undergoing a rectilinear displacement,
is one example of a mixed motion ; while the parabolic arc described by
a flung projectile would be yet another. Mixed motions, Ockham writes,
are all those which are
neither rectilinear nor circular. That is, when a mobile is not moved accord-
ing to a direct line, nor does it always remain in the same place, but is moved
tortuously as when something (is moved) in an angular path, or is twisted
about (volvitur) , or rolled round and round ( vertitur) .103
102 Phil . Nat. , III , 31 : “ Est . . . sciendum, quod motus circularis dupli-
citer accipitur, scilicet large et stricte . Stricte dicitur motus circularis
quando aliquid movetur et non mutat locum secundum totum, sed semper
manet in eodem loco. Large dicitur quando motum secundum se totum
mutat locum, tamen movetur secundum spatium circulare . Primus motus
circularis nullo modo est compar(a) bilis, quia motui recto illi motus sunt
comparabiles quorum uno pertransitur maius spatium quam alio, quod
non potest accidere in proposito quantum ad motum totius. Secundo modo
circularis est in aliquo comparabilis recto, quia maius spatium potest esse
unum quam aliud, quod potest stare ex hoc : quod magnitudo super quam
motus circularis dictus sic fertur, potest fieri recta, et ita est maior, vel "
minor, alia, et illo modo pars caeli circuit, et circulariter movetur . .
This whole question arose in the context of Ockham's discussion of how it
was possible to compare motions with respect to their velocitas and tarditas .
In this connection, it is important to know that Ockham feels that, "not
all motions are comparable, one to the other, as regards their swiftness or
slowness. Just as local motion is not swifter nor slower than an alteration ;
nor is heating swifter or slower than a rectilinear motion . " Ockham writes
that in order for two changes to be thus compared, it is only requisite that
they be specifically the same : "the motions . . . of the same species are
comparable, just as two rectilinear motions are comparable ; for that (mo-
bile) is swifter which covers more space (than another) in an equal time.
Similarly, two alterations of the same species are comparable ; for that
whitening is ... more swift than another in which (the latter subject) does
not acquire a whiteness as intense (as the former subject) in the same time."
This discussion occurs in Phil . Nat . , III , 31. See also Logic. , ch . 55 , p . 165 ;
Sent. , II, 9, q ; and cf. Aristotle, Physics, VII , 4 . 103 Phil. Nat. , III , 9.
Chapter Three. Motion : The Narrow Sense 47
Since the terms, "rectilinear," "circular," and "mixed ," are equiv-
ocally employed, another distinction which embraces them in a rather
simple fashion is allowed by Ockham as valid. Rectilinear and circular
motion, in this second " division ," are called the simple motions ; while
all mixed motions, on the other hand, are subsumed under the single
rubric, composite . 104
Next, for his third "division ," Ockham seizes upon the fact that the
-
various types of motive institution and prolongation — i . e . , natural,
-
violent, or mixed (composito) — provide a mode for further classifying
locally moved subjects. Natural motion originates from the "intrinsic"
physical constitution of the moved itself. Thus, the natural motion of
the heavy directs it downward, just as that of a light body is inclined
upward as a result of its intrinsic nature.105
Now the heavenly motions were said to be natural, and yet the
motion of the heavenly bodies was assumed to be occasioned by the
extrinsic agency of moving " intelligences." There seems , then, an obvious
discrepancy between this use of the word "natural," and the one upon
which Ockham is insisting ; and it is with an eye to accounting for this
aberration that Ockham introduces two ways in which “ natural motion"
can be understood narrow and broad.
104 Phil. Nat., III , 9 : "Aliter stricte utitur ... istis vocabulis, ' motus
rectus,' ' circularis, ' et ' mixtus' . . . quod non obstat praedictis cum vocabula
valde sumantur aequivoce. Unde, et ista potest esse secunda divisio motus
localis, quia motus localis quidam est simplex , quidam compositus . Simplex
dividitur in motu(m) rectum . . . et motum circularem ... Motus autem
compositus sive mixtus . . . patebit inferius." Cf. Aristotle, Physics, V, 6 ;
VIII , 4.
105 Phil. Nat ., III , 9 : "Terti (a) distinctio motus localis potest esse ,
quia motus localis quidam est naturalis, quidam violentus, et potest addi
tertium membrum, quod quidam est mixtus ex istis . Motus naturalis est,
quod est a principio intrinseco ... sicut motus gravis deorsum et motus
levis sursum . . ." Cf. Aristotle, Physics, V, 6 ; VIII , 4.
ham ion e ce
48 Ock : Mot , Tim and Pla
extrinsic agency, they are yet moved in a way which is not counter to
their "natural" propensity for motion.106
Violent motion is instituted as a result of contraverting the natural
inclination of some body to move by virtue of its intrinsic nature. In
this way, were one to fling a heavy body upward, thus frustrating its
natural inclination to travel in a downward direction, this body would
be violently moved.107
A mixed motion has its origin from both intrinsic and extrinsic
factors.
Just as if a small stick were bound to a stone and moved downward, then
it is moved according to the inclination of the stick as well as that of the
stone, and therefore it (the stick) is more swiftly moved than if it were let
drop by itself.108
106 Phil. Nat., III , 32 : " Sed ad hoc, quod sit motus naturalis, requiritur
quod sit a principio intrinseco activo, et hoc proprie, et stricte, accipiendo
motum naturalem. Large, vero accipiendo motum naturalem est ille, qui
non est contra inclinationem aliquam ipsius moti, et sic motus corporis
caelestis ab intelligentia potest dici naturalis , quia quamvis sit ab extrinsece ,
quia tamen non est contra inclinationem aliquam ipsius moti, ideo dicitur
naturalis." Ockham also gives (Phil . Nat. , III, 29) as the most elegant
example of motions which are one in number and regular, the motion of the
heavenly bodies, which move uniformly, with constant velocity, over a
path of constant magnitude . Motions which are one in number and irregular,
are those which exhibit either changes in magnitude, or inconstancy with
regard to velocity in their passage from place to place (or, in the case of an
alterative motion , from terminus to terminus) . In general, for any motion
to be regarded as one in number, it must satisfy three prescriptions : unity
of subject ; unity of goal ; and unity of time . Ockham writes : “În order that
some motion be one in number, three things are required : namely the
unity of number of that which is moved for if two things are moved,
there can
- be no unity of motion of these ; unity of termini ad quem is re-
quired for if something is moved with respect to whiteness, and locally,
it is not one motion numerically ; and third is required unity of time, con-
tinuously and without interruption for if something is moved in some
mode, and thereafter rests, and thereafter is moved further, it is not one
motion numerically. " Motions can also be related in terms of their being
one in genus, or one in species. Motions which are generically "one" all
occur within the frame of any one category : thus all the motions of any one
(or more) mobile(s) with regard to place, or all of a mobile's qualitative
changes, can be regarded as being "one" one in genus. “A motion , ”
Ockham writes, “ is called one in species which is ad terminos of the same
species . Whence, just as every change of place, and every alteration is in
the same genus as every other change of place and alteration, so every
'blackening' is in the same species with every blackening, and every ‘whiten-
ing' with every whitening." Cf. Aristotle, Physics, V, 4 ; VII, R.
107 Phil. Nat. , III , 9 : "Motus violentus est quod est contra inclinationem
moti, sicut grave quando movetur sursum, et leve deorsum. " Cf. Aristotle,
Physics, V, 6.
108 Phil . Nat. , III, 9.
Chapter Three. Motion: The Narrow Sense 49
Nor is it proper to posit some local motion which is neither natural, nor
violent, nor mixed ; since all local motion in which something can be moved
is either according to the inclination of the moved, or against its inclination.109
109 Ibid.
110 Ibid.: " Motus autem violentus dividitur in septimo huius (Aristotle,
Physics,VII , 2) , in impulsionem (read : pulsionem) tractionem , vectionem, verti-
ginem. Pulsio est communis impulsioni et expulsioni . Impulsio est quando
pellens coniungitur mobili , quamdiu ipsum mobile movetur, ita quod cessante
movente, quiescit motum. Expulsio est quando pellens non coniungitur ""
mobili continue dum movetur sicut est in proiiciente lapidem a se .'
111 Phil. Nat., III , 9 : "Tractio est quando movens movet aliud ad se,
vel ad alterum trahit. Vectio est quando aliquid adhaerens alteri movetur
ad motum ipsius. Vertigo est quando aliquod vertitur, et est ibi pulsus et
tractio." (A grindstone, for example, provides an instance of vertiginous
motion. For it revolves in a manner which allows analysis of its motion into
the upward "push" of one-half, and the downward "pull " of the other. ) It
must be noted that pulsion and traction are not always instances of violent
motion. For it is quite possible that such motions act in a direction which is
not counter to the natural inclination of the moved . When this circumstance
comes about, the motion is more properly classified as mixed, than as
violent. Thus, if a mover situated at some height were to fling a heavy body
downward, he would be acting in accord with the intrinsic nature of the
moved, and this body, according to Ockham, " would be more swiftly moved
than if it were allowed to drop of itself. " In this instance, both intrinsic and
extrinsic factors are operative, hence the motion is properly of the mixed
variety. Ockham writes (Ibid) : "Est autem notandum quod pulsio et
tractio non sunt motus violenti, scilicet contra inclinationem omnino moti ;
sed etiam sunt motus mixti : quia in pulsu et tractu possibile est quod
pulsum et tractum moveantur secundum inclinationem sicut, si aliquis
existens sursum proiiceret lapidem deorsum, iste lapis velocius movetur ...”
etc. There is no conflict here between natural motion large, and mixed
motion ; for in a mixed motion the body is moved more swiftly than it would
have been moved if moved by natural motion large . Natural motion, large,
it is true, consists also in a combination of extrinsic and intrinsic factors,
nevertheless, the net result of the combination of extrinsic and intrinsic
50 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
5.
Objections and Resolutions
To be moved (in the narrow sense), as Ockham has repeatedly
stressed, is to acquire or lose " something" in a successive manner. His
opponents maintain that an actual, objectively inhering new quality
is the what which is acquired or lost by the locally moved ; and if Ock-
ham is to persist in denying that a locally moved body acquires or loses
"something" he must be prepared to face the counter-charge that this
denial violates the definition which he has himself endorsed .
His adversaries , indeed, level three objections against the view that
denies the successive acquisition or loss of something as a new quality
-to the locally moved subject. In the first place, were Ockham to
insist that the moved is constituted in exactly the same way before and
- that is , as neither having gained
after suffering a local displacement —
nor lost anything - how could he seriously maintain that it was moved
at all ? 112
Secondly, his opponents held that the necessary condition which
cails for the successive verification of contradictories in any motion,
could not be satisfied except by positing the successive production or
destruction of a something in the moved. Therefore , since Ockham refuses
to yield the actual acquisition or loss of something in the locally moved,
can he explain the phenomena of local motion ? 113
In the third place, his opponents are quick to point out, were every-
thing to be equal in the moved both before and after local motion, as
Ockham holds, there could be no better reason for a subject to be in
any one place, than in any other. In short : without the acquisition or
loss of some inhering " thing" in the moved as loss or gain of "motion"
-
why should a body move at all ? ¹¹4
Ockham commences his reply to these objections by saying that a
body does, in his view, have
something which it previously had not ; not, however, that it "has ” it as if
a thing inhering in it as in a subject ( subiective) -
— but as a place. . . . I say
that such locally moved things do not acquire something inherent, in the
factors active in a natural motion, large is not to move a body with a greater
or lesser velocity than it has a natural propensity to assume.
112 Phil. Nat ., III , 10 : " Et ... dicas (his opponents argue) , si motum
nihil habeat quod prius non habebat, ergo non movetur."
113 Ibid.: "Et si dicatur ulterius, quod contradictoria non verificantur
de aliquo successive , nisi propter aliquam destructionem alicuius, vel
productionem, ergo si nihil novum acquiritur nec aliquid destruitur, non
movetur. "
114 Ibid.: "Praeterea, si omnes res nunc sunt quae prius erant, et non
aliae, non est maior ratio quod hoc sit in hoc loco nunc, quam prius."
Chapter Three. Motion: The Narrow Sense 51
way that a substantial form is in matter, or heat in fire, but they acquire
only surrounding place . . . . Further, it is against the opinion of the Philos-
opher that when something is moved , something inheres in it . . . for indeed,
when something is locally moved it is not that something is "in" the moved,
but that the moved is in something — in a place · where it was not previous-
ly, 115
To the next objection , he points out that
contradictories can be successively verified without the production or de-
struction of any thing, through this alone : that a mobile changes place,
and goes from one place to another . Whence , by this itself, that a body,
without any other thing, is in this place , and it was not previously in his
place, contradictories can be verified.116
6.
motion, when brought into contact with a mobile. Yet, the empirical
fact is that this can not be the true cause of projectile motion , since the
effect does not always follow :
for my hand can be moved slowly to some body, and then it will not move
it locally ; and it can be moved swiftly ... and then brought to some body
in the same way as in the previous case, and then it will cause motion, and
it previously would not. 122
The cause, then, of the sustained motion of a projectile, after it has been
released by the projector, is not to be thought of as a "power" trans-
mitted from one to the other. Indeed , the very seeking of a cause for
the projectile motion effect is not allowed by Ockham as a valid enter-
prise, insofar as in his view, local motion is not a new effect at all ;
if you say that a new effect has some cause, but local motion is a new effect ;
I say that local motion is not a new effect ... since it is nothing else but that
a mobile coexist in diverse parts of space.¹123
In the vein with which we are now familiar, Ockham insists that the,
movement, in such a motion, after the separation of the mobile from the ....
projector, is the moved itself according to itself (and) not by virtue of some
power in it. 124
"It would be astonishing," says Ockham concluding this review of
projectile motion, "if my hand could cause some power in a stone by
the fact that ... it touched the stone ." 125
122 Sent., II , qu . 26, m : " Item notandum quod in motu proiectionis est
magna difficultas de principio motivo et effectivo illius motus ; quia non
potest esse ... virtus in lapide : quia quaero a quo causatur illa virtus : non
a proiciente: quia agens naturale aequaliter approximatum passivo aequa-
liter causat semper effectum. Se (d) proiciens quantum ad omne absolutum
et respectivum in eo potest aequaliter approximari lapidi et non movere
sicut quando movet. Potest enim manus mea tarde moveri et approximari
alicui corpori ; et tunc non movebit eum localiter ; et potest velociter ...
moveri, et tunc approximatur eo modo sicut prius, et tunc causabit motum
et prius non. "
123 Ibid.
124 Ibid.
125 Sent., II , qu . 26, m . Ockham can almost be thought of as arguing
directly against Franciscus de Marchia here . Franciscus writes in Book IV
of his own Commentary on Peter Lombard's Sentences : “... Unde est scien-
dum , quod est duplex virtus movens aliquod grave sursum . . . et ista virtus
manus ; alia virtus est motus exequens inchoatum et ipsum continuans et
ista est causata sive derelicta per motum a prima. Nisi enim ponatur aliqua
virtus a prima, impossibile est dare causam motus sequentis ... Et si
quaeratur qualis sit huiusmodi virtus, potest dici quod nec est forma simpli-
citer permanens nec simpliciter fluens, sed quasi media, quia per aliquod
tempus permanens, sicut caliditas ab igne genita in aqua non habens esse
permanens simpliciter sicut in igne, nec simpliciter etiam fluens ut cale-
factio ipsa , sed habet esse permanens ad determinatum tempus. "" This
portion of Franciscus de Marchia's text is edited by Anneliese Maier, and
is printed in her Zwei Grundprobleme ... op. cit. , pp. 166–180 . The above
quotation appears on p . 172.
54 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
7.
Ockham and Text 71
and Galileo, " in Journal of the History of Ideas, vol . XII , no . 2 and 3 ( 1951 ) .
Some of the same material, though less extensively treated , can be found
in Professor Moody's article, " Ockham and Aegidius of Rome, " op. cit . I
have drawn heavily on these two articles for my background discussion of
the controversy centering about Text 71 .
128 Avempace's criticism of Aristotle is known to us only through
Averroes who cites it in his own exposition of the Aristotelian text. See
Aristotelis Opera Omnia cum Averroes Commentariis , Venetiis ( 1560) , Tomus
IV . fol. 131 V. ff.
129 Avempace's argument is translated and printed in Prof. Moody's
article, "Avempace and Galileo, " op. cit., pp. 184-5 . Moody writes
(Ibid., p. 192) : "Avempace's criticism of Aristotle and his alternative law
of velocities, though known to the western scholastics only as ‘ Avempace's
theory' , had been stated, and its implications developed clearly and fully
by a Christian Neo-Platonist of Alexandria , Joannes Philoponus . For in
the commentary which Philoponus wrote on Aristotle's Physics , immediately
after his exposition of Text 71 of Book IV, we find a lengthy ' digression'
devoted to criticism of Aristotle's law of velocities and of the dynamic
assumptions on which it was based . ” For a treatment of projectile motion ,
indicating Philoponus as the forerunner of fourteenth century dynamics,
see P. Duhem, Le Système du Monde, ( Paris, 1913 ) , vol . I , esp . pp. 313-320.
56 Ockham : Motion , Time and Place
142 Expositio., P. 435 : " Sed contra ista dicitur esse Commentator,
primo, quia reprobat Avempace propter hoc quod ponit duplex tempus
requisitum ad motum, sive unum naturale propter distantiam terminorum,
et aliud propter resistentiam medii . Sed hoc idem ponitur in praedicta
declaratione ; quia ponitur quod se solum termini distarent, adhuc motus
gravium esset in tempore ; et manifestum est quod tempus requiritur propter
resistentiam medii , secundum Philosophum et Commentatorem hic ; ergo
ista opinio coincidit cum opinione Avempace, quam reprobat Commentator,
dicens : ' Et si hoc quod dicit Avempace concedatur ... (etc. , Ockham here
gives the quotation from Averroes' commentary on Text 71 ) ... Ex isto
patet quod de intentione Commentatoris est, quod motus talis non est in
tempore propter solam distantiam terminorum, et quod tarditas motus non
est accidentialiter a resistentia medii ."
143 Ibid. 144 Expositio., p. 435.
62 Ockham: Motion, Time and Place
149 Phil. Nat., III, 12 : " Et primo ... quae est rarefactio, de qua dico,
quod secundum intentionem Philosophi per talem augmentationem non
acquiruntur aliquae res, nec aliqua quantitas, nisi locus tantum ; hoc est,
quando aliquis sic augetur, vel rarefit, non acquiritur moto, nisi locus
tantum; hoc est, quando aliquid augetur, illud rarefit sine adventu rei
inhaerentis, sed partes moti dilata(n)tur, et extenduntur, et fiunt in maiori
loco ... Patere poterit, quomodo diminutio est motus ad quantitatem ,
non quod in diminutione, quae est condensatio, aliqua quantitas deperdatur,
ita quod aliqua quantitas destruatur, sed quia partes rei motae fiunt minus
distantes quam prius, sine destructione cuiuscumque rei, et ita tunc motum
non perdit aliquam quantitatem sibi inhaerentem; sed tantum perdit
locum; quia sit in minor loco quam prius propter hoc : quod partes eius
fiunt minus distantes . . . quam prius, sine omni destructione cuiuscumque
rei ." Cf. Aristotle, Physics, IV, 9.
Chapter Three. Motion : The Narrow Sense 65
150 Phil. Nat. , III , 12 : “ . si illa sit augmentatio, et non est ad quanti-
tatem - quia nulla quantitas acquiritur ; nec ad qualitatem, ideo illa non
magis est ad quantitatem, quam ad qualitatem : quia non erit plus quanti-
tatis quam qualitatis . . . si aliquid rarefit (vel condensit) et non acquiritur
nisi locus, augmentatio (et diminutio) ... non differet a motu locali . "
151 See above, n. 78.
152 Phil. Nat., III , 12 : ". . . secundum intentionem Philosophi , quantitas
non est res distincta a substantia et qualitate, ita quod non est aliqua res … ..
quae sit subiective in substantia, sicut multi moderni ponunt et falso
imaginantur ... Quod autem non sit talis res (ostendo) . nam si quando
aliquid rarefit aliqua nova quantitas acquiritur, quaero : aut tota quantitas
praecedens corrumpitur, aut tota manet, aut una pars manet, et alia non .
Sed si nullam istorum potest dici , sequitur quod nulla nova quantitas
acquiritur, ergo cum rarefactione potest stare quod nova non acquiritur. "
66 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
153 Ibid.: " Quod autem tota praecedens non manet, si nova quantitas
acquiritur, ostendo : quia si manet, aut manet in eodem subiecto in quo
prius, et tunc duae quantitates essent in eodem subiecto, vel una migravit
de subiecto in subiectum, quorum utrumque est impossibile apud Ari-
stotelem ."
154 Ibid.: " Quod autem tota non corrumpatur patet . Primo, quia si sic,
quandocumque aliquid rarefieret, partes infinitae secundum se totas di-
stinctae essent generatae et corruptae : quia ex quo sunt infinita instantia
in quolibet illorum erit nova quantitas generata, et praecedens corrupta . ”
155 Phil. Nat. , III , 12 : " Secundo, quia non apparet aliquod agens quod
potest quantitatem praecedentem destruere, et sequentem generare, quia
ex quo sunt eiusdem rationis naturaliter, idem non potest esse corruptivum
unius, et productivum eiusdem rationis naturaliter."
156 Ibid .: "Tertio , quia si sic, cum accidens corrumpatur ad corruptionem
sui subiecti immediate . . . sequeretur quod etiam omnes qualitates rarefacti
corrumperentur ; et continue novae generarentur, cum tamen nullum agens
possit dari, quod potest tales qualitates generare. " This third argument
presupposes the view of his adversaries that qualities inhere in substance
only by way of quantity . This is to say that the theory he is here challenging
held for the extensive , divisive , and numerable character of substances and
qualities as a result of the accidental inherence in them of a distinct entity
called "quantity. " Professor E. A. Moody has conclusively shown this to
be the theory (immensely important for Eucharistic doctrine) propounded by
Aegidius Romanus ; see “ Ockham and Aegidius of Rome, " by Prof. Moody
in op. cit.; see also G. Buescher, The Eucharistic Teaching of William Ockham
(Franciscan Institute , St. Bonaventure, N. Y. , 1950) . Cf. St. Thomas,
Quaestiones Quodlibetales, Quodlibetum 7, qu . 4, art. 3, where he holds that
God can make a sensible quality lacking in quantity, as well as a quantity
lacking a substance .
Chapter Three. Motion: The Narrow Sense 67
-
and a part being destroyed — Ockham makes the point that in a subject
possessing distinct and absolute parts, all of which are presumably
equivalent in every respect, there would be no better reason for one
part to be destroyed , than for any other. The second reason for his
rejecting this notion , repeats what he has pointed out before— that is ,
either one has to commit himself to the position that there are two
"quantities" (not making one, per se) after rarefaction , in the same part
of the same subject ; or that one of them has migrated to another subject
— both of which possibilities were previously rejected on Aristotle's
authority.157
Finally, Ockham shows that, as before , since the qualities of the
parts of the subject whose previous quantity has been partially destroyed ,
would be destroyed incidentally, there is still wanting a natural causative
agent capable of accomplishing the requisite task of destruction and
generation this time “ partial” — of both subject and accidents, 158
"Thus, I say therefore ," Ockham concludes,
157 Phil. Nat., III , 12 : ". . . Quod autem non possit dici quod una pars
corrumpatur et alia praecedens manet, patet . Primo quia non est maior
ratio quod una pars corrumpatur quam alia ... Secundo, quia hoc dato,
illa pars, cuius quantitas manet, non esset rarefacta, nisi accidens migrareret
de subiecto in subiectum, vel ponerentur duae quantitates in eadem parte
subiecti."
158 Ibid.: "Tertio, quia tunc aliquae qualitates, scilicet qualitates partis ,
cuius quantitas corrumpitur, corrumperentur, et novae generarentur."
159 Phil. Nat., III , 12 See also Altaris ., p. 115 : “When a thing becomes
rare from dense, I ask whether or not there is there another new quantity ;
but it is precisely the same quantity numerically ; if it is new there, then
any preceding quantity is corrupted, which seems false. If a part be new :
I ask about the subject of that quantity, for it is necessary that there be a
whole rarefied substance or a part of it ; not the whole, because then the
two quantities would be at the same time, which they deny who think thus.
If a part, the same argument follows, or that an accident might travel
subject into subject, as would be able to be clearly shown, but it is omitted
for the sake of brevity . . ."
68 Ockham: Motion, Time and Place
It has now become clear in what manner the second question — i. e.,
how does quantitative motion differ from local motion ? which arose
as a result of his positing place , and place only , to be the " what" succes-
sively lost or gained by the quantitatively moved, is to be answered .
The subject of local motion, that is, never suffers physical alteration as
a result of its motion, but is the same in value , quantitatively, both
before and after its motion . Not so, however, with the quantitatively
moved body, which is of certain linearly mensurable proportions prior
Through what has been said before, with regard to the argument that
rarefaction and local motion do not differ, it must be said that " local motion"
is taken in two ways : namely broad, and narrow (large et stricte) . Broad,
for all motion in which place is acquired ; and thus augmentation, which is
rarefaction, is local motion. " Local motion" is taken in another way, narrow;
and then motion is called "local motion " when something is moved locally,
and there is no greater or less quantity (i . e. , more or less distance between
its parts) . And in this way augmentation differs from local motion. 162
Ockham's investigations have made sufficiently clear what he
conceives the true nature of quantity to be. " Quantity " is a connotative
term suppositing, in a proposition , directly for some substance or quality
signified by an absolute term , while consignifying the theoretical
capacity of this individual substance or quality to be divided into an
infinitude of really distinct parts.
9.
figura. Sed praeter istam divisione (m) potest poni alia divisio qualitatis,
quod quaedam est qualitas sensibilis, quae ab aliquo sensu particulari potest
sentiri, cuiusmodi sunt calor, frigus, color, sapor et sic de aliis . Alia est
autem qualitas quae non est sensibilis ab aliquo sensu particulari, cuiusmodi
sunt ipsae sensationes, quia ipsa visio oculi non potest videri, nec ab aliquo
sensu sentiri . Sed talis qualitas est imaginatio interior, et actus appetendi,
et intellectio, et volitio." See also, Logic. , ch . 55 , p . 165. Cf. Aristotle,
Physics, VII , 2 .
164 Phil. Nat., III , 14 : " Oportet autem scire, quod alteratio ... est
motus successivus, quo aliqua qualitas inhaerens subiecto acquiritur, vel
amittitur, ita quod vere res nova acquiritur, si sit motus acquisitivus, vel
res antiqua deperditur si sit motus deperditivus. " As the sequel will prove,
M. de Wulf was in grave error when he wrote (Histoire de la Philosophie
Médiévale, 6th ed. , Louvain, 1947 ; vol . III , p . 33 ) , that in Ockham's theory,
"à leur tour les qualités corporelles se confondent avec la substance.'
Later (p. 43) , de Wulf adds confusion to confusion , for he writes here that
for Ockham, "la qualité étant réduite à la quantité . . ." In truth, as we
shall see, only certain qualities were regarded by Ockham as not being
divorced from substance ; while quantity is never found distinct and apart
from substance or from quality. See also Logic. , ch . 55 , p . 164 : " Sunt autem
quaedam in genere qualitatis, quae important res distinctas a substantia,
ita quod illa res non est substantia, sicut sunt ‘ albedo' et ‘ nigredo ', ' color',
' scientia', 'lux' et huiusmodi . Quaedam autem sunt, quae alias res a praedictis
qualitatibus et substantia non important, cuiusmodi sunt ' figura' , ' curvi-
tas' , ' rectitudo' , ' densitas', ' raritas' et huiusmodi . See also Quodl . VII ,
qu. 10: "Utrum qualitas differat realiter a substantia."
165 Phil . Nat. , III , 14 : " Sed oportet scire, quod alteratio accipitur
dupliciter, large pro omni inductione qualita (tis) vel deperditione, sive sit
conveniens , sive disconveniens subiecto in quod inducitur, sive successive
sive subito in subiecto inducitur, et sic aer alteratur quando illuminatur...”
etc.
166 Ockham does not himself use the term stricte for this application
of "alteration , " preferring merely to say : "Aliter accipitur alteratio . . . ”
Chapter Three. Motion: The Narrow Sense 71
170 Ibid. See also Altaris. , pp . 83-93 ; Logic. , ch. 55 , p . 165. Ockham
is here taking arms against those who posit, as he writes in Logic. , ch. p . 165 :
"formam et figuram... distingui realiter a substantia et qualitatibus aliarum
specierum . Unde etiam dicunt, quod quando aliquod corpus rectum cur-
vatur, vere unam rem absolutam amittit et aliam rem absolutam novam
acquirit."
171 Phil. Nat. , III , 15 : " Est autem sciendum quod figura non est alia
res ... sicut figura aeris non est alia res ab aere, nec figura albedinis est
alia res ab albedine , et sic de aliis. Quod autem non sit alia res patet : quia
per solam separationem unius rei ab alia non fit nova res. Sed frequenter
aes, vel lign(um ) , fit alterius figurae per separationem partium ab aere,
vel ligno, ergo non est aliqua res nova . In Altaris. , p. 213, Ockham writes :
"When wood is divided into two equal parts, no substance new as regards
itself as a whole is generated ; but there are now two substances really
distinct locally ; for otherwise, when wood is divided into halves, the acci-
dents would remain without a subject in one-half ; from which, therefore,
no substance new as regards itself as a whole is generated . It is necessary,
that those two substances, each of which is a certain whole after division,
were previously making one whole wood , and were not at the same time in
thesa me place ; therefore, there were before two parts of one total wood
separate in situation ."
172 Phil. Nat. , III , 15 : " Item , per solum motum localem alicuius cor-
poris non fit nova res in corpore, sed quandocumque corpus fit alterius
figurae per solum motum localem partium, sicut patet de virga recta si
curvetur, et de multis talibus," ergo tunc non fit nova res, et per consequens
figura illa non est nova res. See also Logic. , ch . 55 , p . 164 .
173 Phil . Nat. , III , 15 : " Item, talis res nova potest fieri ab aliquo agente,
quia ibi nullum est agens " , quod habeat virtutem producendi talem rem ,
sicut patet inductive.'
Chapter Three. Motion: The Narrow Sense 73
prohibits the same thing from being in diverse categories. That is, nothing
prohibits the same thing from being signified through the predicables of
diverse categories . These names, therefore, "triangular," "quadrangular,"
"circular," and others of similar status, are in the category of quality
regardless of the fact that they signify a thing of the genus of substance .
The reason for assigning predicables from diverse categories to one and
the same subject , is the circumstance that :
through one of these is made answer to the question asked concerning the
"what" of an individual substance, and through the other is made answer
to the question concerning characteristics (quale) accidentally in the same...
individual.
That is, should one ask a question concerning the " what" (quid) of a
piece of wood , he is most conveniently answered with predicables drawn
from the category of substance. Thus, any question relative to the
subject which evokes a response such as : "a substance, " "a plant," or
"a body" (substantia, planta , corpus) , would be in answer to a query
concerning the "what" of the piece of wood . Should , however, the question
beg a reply of the sort : "square," "round" or "triangular, " etc. , (qua-
dratum, rotundum, triangulare, et huiusmodi) , then the question asked
has been relative to the "character" of the piece of wood.
It must therefore be said that through one (predicable) is answered
conveniently the question asked in reference to the "what" of an individual
substance, since that signifies such an individual no matter how its parts
are situated, just as no matter how the parts of the piece of wood are situated ,
always, while it is itself in the nature of things, it is signified through the
word (ly) "substance, " and through this name "body, " and thus through
other predicables in the genus of substance .
It is not signified through this name " square, " however, unless its parts
are situated in such a way ; since, if they are situated otherwise through
being locally moved, it ceases immediately to be signified by this name
"square" regardless of the fact that it itself (i. e . the substance) remains in
the nature of things. One, therefore, is predicated contingently, and the
other necessarily, and still through one is answered conveniently the question
asked concerning the " characteristics " (which is the contingent designation) ,
and through the other the question concerning the "what" (the necessary
designation).176
Having thus explained in what manner the same thing may be "in"
diverse categories (quomodo eadem res sit in diversis praedicamentis) ,
Ockham can turn to examine three objections which his opponents
offer to his position that shape is nothing apart from the shaped .
176 Phil. Nat. , III , 16. See also Altaris. , p. 249 ; Logic . , ch. 40, p . 102 ff.;
ch. 41 , p. 106 ; ch . 46 , p . 134. In both Altaris . , and Logic., Ockham cites
St. John Damascene as authority for his view.
Chapter Three. Motion : The Narrow Sense 75
II.
Alterative Motion Broad: Habitus
qua(e)libet talis : ' aes est materia statuae, ' ' lignum est materia lectuli, ’
quia per tales intelliguntur tales : ' aes fit forma, ' ' aes fit statua, ' 'lignum fit
lectulus, ' vel, ‘lignum fiebat lectulus, ' et sic de aliis. Sunt autem, usitatae
tales locutiones propter aliquam similitudinem subiecti respectu formae,
et aeris, vel rei naturalis respectu formae, vel statuae ; sicut enim subiectum
supponitur formae quam recipit, et postea recipit, sic res naturalis prius
est lignum vel aes, quam fiat statua. Similiter, sicut potest non recipere
subiectum formam, ita aes, aut lignum, potest non esse statua non per
alicuius rei destructionem, sed per solam diversum partium situationem,
et propter consimiles similitudines dicitur quod aes est subiectum, vel
materia statuae, sicut homo dicitur quod est subiectum albedinis, et materia
est materia compositi ... Ad secundum per idem ; quia ex aere dicitur
fieri statua quoniam aes fit statua. Nec aliud intelligunt loquentes recte,
quando dicunt quod ex tali re naturali fit res artificialis, nisi quod res
naturalis fit artificialis sicut lignum fit lectulus, et aes fit statua, sine omni
novitate rei, sed solum per diversam partium situationem ... Ad tertium
similiter dicitur, quod haec est figurative locutio : ' corpus fit alterius figurae
nunc, quam prius, ' quia per istam intelligitur ista : ' corpus quod erat trian-
gulare vel quadrangulare, fit pentagonum, vel exagonum, ' non quod sint
alterius figurae, sed quia primo res est triangularis, et postea quadrangularis
propter solam diversam situationem partium. Quod accidit ex solo motu
locali partium, sicut eadem res quae est primo recta postea fit curva propter
solum motum localem, quo partes appropinquantur, quae primo distabant
in rectum quantum poterat absque hoc de novo fieret aliquid, et ita in rei
veritate una figura non succedit alteri , nec sunt ibi diversae figurae succes-
siva, quia illa eadem figura quae primo est triangularis postea est qua-
drangularis, vel e converso . Sic sicut illa res, quae primo est rectitudo postea
est curvitas, et e contra, sine omni novitate, et diversitate rei . Dicitur
tamen secundum communem modum loquendi, quod sunt diversae figurae,
quia eadem res est aliter et aliter figurata, se (d) sine novitate rei inhaerentis,
licet non sine motu locali partium . . . " Cf. Aristotle, De Generatione, I, 18.
179 Ibid. III , 17 : "Non solum autem non est alteratio secundum for-
mam et figuram , sed nec est alteratio secundum habitus. " Cf. Aristotle,
Physics, VII , 3.
180 Phil. Nat., III , 17 : "Ad quod faciliter intelligendum oportet con-
siderare quod habitus quidam est corporalis, quidam spiritualis.” See also,
Logic., ch. 55, p . 164.
Chapter Three. Motion: The Narrow Sense 77
someone beautiful can become ugly solely through the abcission of a part.
For if the nose, or eyes, or legs are removed from such a one, he becomes
181 Ibid.: " Corporalis vere dupliciter dicitur . Quidam enim sumitur
unus numero , sicut habitus derelictus in aliquo organo ex frequentibus
actibus, sicut patet in cantore, cui ex frequentibus actibus cantandi, dere-
linquitur cantori quaedam habilitas in organo ad bene cantandum, qualis
non habetur sine habitu cantandi . Quidam autem est habitus corporalis ,
qui non simpliciter unum numero . . . sed est aggregatio multorum, quibus
habitis dicitur habens se habere bene, vel male, et sic sanitas dicitur habitus,
quia est debita proportio humorum. Et pulchritudo dicitur habitus . . . ”
etc.
182 Ibid.: " Et similis distinctioni potest dari de habitu spirituali ...
scilicet stricte et sic tantum intellectu ... aliter large, sic est in parte sensi-
tiva."
183 Ibid.: "Habitus autem qui est in anima intellectiva subdividitur :
quia quidam est intellectualis et quidam est moralis . Similiter ... potest
dividi habitus in parte sensitiva, quia . . . quidam est apprehensivus et
quidam appetitivus . "
184 Phil. Nat. , III , 18 : ". . . secundum habitus corporales qui non sunt
aggregati ex diversis ... non est necesse fieri alterationem . Accipitur enim
habitus large pro omni eo, quod per assuefactionem actuum aliquid redditur
habilius et facilius ad actus consimiles, sicut aliquis per assiduitatem scribendi
... redditur aptior, vel promptior ad scribendum ... et sic de consimilibus .
Et secundum tales habitus non est necesse alterari : quia taliter potest
aliquis habituari quandocumque per alicuius indispositionis ammotionem,
sine omni qualitate adveniente, et per consequens non est necesse tale
alterari ." See also, Sent . , III , qu . 4 , 10, 11 .
m n
78 Ockha : Motio , Time and Place
ugly; and yet there is no induced quality nor any rejected quality .
Therefore, (a subject) can become ugly, or healthy, or ill, without any such
quality advening to it, or receding from it. Therefore, with regard to such
qualities, it is not ... alteration.185
That is, the mere act of separation of a part from a whole can so
vary the "proportion of humors " as to generate a corporeal habit
and such separation, in which no new quality is induced or destroyed,
is not true qualitative motion.186 So much for the corporeal habits.
If "alteration" be taken in its broad sense - as a designation , that
is, covering all cases in which a distinct quality is induced in a subject
then Ockham will grant that the second of his broad divisions of habit
(i. e., habitus spiritualis) , is subject to alteration.187 It yet remains for
him, however, to relate in what mode these habits, couched in the
intellective and sensitive souls, are distinct, induced, qualities.
the sensitive soul (or the intellective soul) cognizes, or appetits something,
a quality really distinct from a subject is induced hence, alteration
occurs here . . . It is proved , for such a cognitive or appetitive act is a true
quality, which I prove thus : the perfection of any perfectible is either a
substantial or an accidental form . But the cognitive or appetitive act is a
perfection of the intellective or sensitive soul it is , therefore, either a
substantial or an accidental form - and it is nothing other than a quality.
Therefore, the proposition stands . 188
possible to affirm that some subject did not formerly love some object,
which it does now love, contradictories of the quality "love " have
become verified ; hence, alteration broad, can be said to have transpired
in the institution of this new, and distinct , quality.190
None, however, of the mental habits thus induced within the scope
of alteration, broad, have been induced in a successive manner. Hence,
despite the fact that contradictories of such induced qualities can be
verified ; and that a new quality can be demonstrated to be present
owing to alterative motion these yet cannot be accounted alteration ,
narrow. For those mental habits instituted via alteration broad, are,
according to Ockham, induced , instantaneously (in instanti) .191 Thus,
one part at a time of the sensitive soul, in the induction of an appetitive
habit, is moved once, and once only, by one, and only one, part of the
newly induced quality. Similarly, in the instance of the induction of an
intellective habit , as “ love, " or "charity," each part of the soul is moved
once, and once only, by an induced portion of this new and distinct
quality.
12.
In restricting her source for Ockham's position with regard to the intension
and remission of forms to his Sent. , ( I , dist . 17, qu . 4-7) , Dr. Anneliese
Maier, Zwei Grundprobleme ... op. cit., overlooked this facet of Ockham's
theory. Dr. Maier sees Ockham's treatment of intension and remission of
forms as expressing (p. 75) " der allgemeinen Tendenz des Nominalismus,
ontologische Probleme als logische anzusehen, " and accordingly accents
the logical-grammatical side of Ockham's approach to intension and remis-
sion . Ockham , however, certainly can not be included in the roster of those
who might possibly qualify as exhibitors of such a " general tendency . ” As
Prof. Moody ably shows (Logic of William of Ockham, op. cit. ) , Ockham was
greatly concerned with maintaining the distinction between Metaphysics,
the discursive real sciences, and Logic : which fundamental concern is
indicated by his division of significant terms into terms of first intention
(which alone may enter into statements of the real sciences) ; and terms of
second intention (which alone belong in the statements of logic) . See above,
Chapter One, p. 11 ff. , 19 , 23.
194 Phil. Nat.,
" III , 22 : "Dicit enim Philosophus ... ' omne quod movetur
partim est . etc. See Aristotle, Physics, VI , 4 .
195 Ibid. : 'Sed (istis ) (that is, the Philosopher's authority given as a
ground for the second theory ) non obstantibus , oppositum tenendum est,
nam si remanea (n)t tales gradus remissi , puta gradus albedinis , quando
dealbatum denigratur , sequeretur , quod simul , et semel , esset album et
nigrum , nam ille gradus est vera albedo , quia si sit aliquod oportet quod
sit qualitas , sive gradus , et non nisi albedo, igitur est vera albedo , et per
consequens subiectum habens ipsum erit vere album . Et eodem modo
gradus nigredinis est vera nigredo , et per consequens subiectum informatuu
illo gradu est vere nigrum et ita simul , et semel . esset album et nigrum .”
82 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
cold, sweet and bitter, etc. , could no longer be regarded as prime con-
traries, but only
as "heat intense, " and "cold intense ; " just as corporeal qualities and mental
qualities are not contraries or as joy and sadness (are not contraries) , but
only "this joy, " and "this sadness . '' 196
And, finally, it was argued against the position which insisted that
a replaced quality could remain in a remiss grade, that
if white and black are simultaneously in the same (subject) , since the vision
of white does not impede the vision of black, nor conversely, as is obvious
through experience , and further, by the fact that the visions of contraries
are not contraries, it would follow that such a body would be judged simul-
taneously by a vision of white and of black . . . Therefore, white and black
are not (both) there.197
It is to the first theory - the one which holds for the total expulsion
of the former, prior to the successive advent of the latter quality that
Ockham subscribes. It remains for him, therefore , to attempt to reconcile
this view with the apparently contradictory aristotelian statement
quoted as support for the "remiss grade" theory. He proceeds immediately
to do this, and to carefully and clearly restate what he considers to be
the true explanation of how sensible qualities are altered .
"When something is successively moved with regard to some quality,"
Ockham writes :
it does not acquire that whole (new) quality simultaneously, but successively ;
and so while it is moved , it is partly in a “ terminus from which ” — that is ,
it loses some part of the previous form ; and it is partly in a " terminus to which"
- that is, it has some other part which it previously had not. Whence, when
something is altered from one quality to another, the subject is continuously
remitted, and the contrary form is expelled ; and this whole having been
expelled, the other quality, contrary to the preceding, is continuously and
successively acquired . So that at first there precedes the disquisitive motion
of the prior quality, which is followed by the acquisitive motion of the
posterior quality, and no grades of these qualities are simultaneous.198
196 Phil. Nat. , III , 22 : " Non videtur quoque maior repugnantia inter
gradus intensos, quam gradus remissos , igitur si gradus remissi stent simul,
et intensi . Confirmatur : quia si gradus remissus caloris staret simul cum
gradu remisso frigiditatis, calor et frigus non essent primo contraria, sed
tantum calor intensus et frigus intensu (m) . . ." etc.
197 Ibid.
198 Phil. Nat. , III , 22 : Ockham seems, then, to be wedded to the view
that any motion of contrariety consists, actually, in two motions one
wholly acquisitive in character, and the other, similarly distinct, and
deprivative in character. Despite this, he explicitly espouses the position
that any motion of contrariety is one - and he is faced with the problem of
explaining away these two, apparently contradictory stands. " It must be
known," he writes in explanation ( Phil. Nat. , III , 30), " that although when
something is truly moved from one contrary to another, there are diverse
Chapter Three. Motion : The Narrow Sense 83
13 .
Intension and Remission
motions there : namely, the expulsion of one quality, and thereafter the
introduction of the contrary . Still these two motions are called one motion
because they are of necessity concomitant to each other, so that one can
not be without the other following. For if something is changed from white to
black... that motion is of necessity a motion of acquisition of black, or of
some other mediate color, in that the mobile can not be without any color —
and on this account it is said to be one motion . " The destruction , that is,
of some quality necessarily implies the concomitant induction of a contrary,
insofar as a subject cannot be, and totally lack the contrary of a destroyed
quality. For the destruction, say, of " heat " in a subject, does not leave
that subject temperatureless , but it does imply the concomitant induction
of " cold." Similarly, the destruction of the color " white" does not leave
the subject transparent, or totally lacking in all color, but this destruction
is uniformly coupled to the advent of a new color. See also above, p. 272 ;
Sent., IV, qu. 3 , d ; in Altaris . , p . 263-5 , Ockham proves that one quality
can not be the subject of another quality, which is implied by holding that
a quality can remain in a remiss degree in another quality. See also, Quodl.
III , q. 4.
193 For the pre-scholastic sources pertinent to the discussion of intension
and remission in general, see A. Maier, op. cit. , Part I, esp. ch . 2,3 . Of im-
mediate interest is Dr. Maier's statement (p. 12-13 ) , that for the scholastics ,
"die eigentliche Hauptstelle für die Interpretation der intensiven Größe
und der Intension ist nun aber eine Frage aus den Sentenzen des Petrus
Lombardus, lib. 1 , distinctio 17 : Utrum concedendum sit quod Spiritus
sanctus augeatur in homine, vel magis vel minus habeatur vel detur . Denn
84 Ockham : Motion , Time and Place
die charitas soll mit dem Heiligen Geist identisch sein, anderseits nimmt
aber die charitas im Menschen zu und ab und ist zu verschiedenen Zeiten
verschieden groß. Ist nun anzunehmen, daß der Heilige Geist im Menschen
zu- und abnimmt oder mehr und weniger besessen wird ? Das würde eine
Veränderlichkeit des Heiligen Geistes voraussetzen, die mit der schlecht-
hinigen Unveränderlichkeit Gottes unvereinbar wäre. Also müßte entweder
die charitas nicht mit dem Heiligen Geist zusammenfallen, oder sie müßte
im Menschen nicht zu- und abnehmen können. Petrus Lombardus gibt die
Antwort : die charitas ist schlechthin unveränderlich , empfängt in sich
kein magis oder minus ; aber im Menschen oder richtiger für den Menschen
kann sie zu- und abnehmen und wird mehr oder weniger gegeben und be-
sessen, sicut Deus dicitur magnificari et exaltari in nobis, qui tamen in se
nec magnificatur nec exaltatur . " See also P. Duhem , Études . . ., III , ch . 12 ,
pp. 314-46 ; and P. Doncoeur, " La Théorie de la Matière et de la Forme
Chez Guillaume d'Occam, " in Revue des Sciences Philosophiques et Théologi-
ques, (1921) .
200 Sent., dist. 17, qu . 4, a. Ockham makes this flat statement in re-
sponse to several arguments against the augmentation of charity. Typical
of these, are the following : ". . . si charitas augeretur ergo charitas movetur.
Consequens est falsum, ergo et antecedens praeterea, augmentatio et
alteratio sunt motus distincti ; et motus distincti habent terminos distinctos ;
et charitas est terminus alterationis, ergo non est termin(us) augmentationis,
et per consequens non augetur ... praeterea, illud quod augetur est subiec-
tum augmentationis ; sed charitas non est subiectum augmentationis , ergo
non augetur." etc.
201 Ibid. qu. 4, b.
202 Ibid . qu . 5.
203 Sent., I, dist. 17, qu . 5 , b : "Ad quaestionem dicitur quod in augmen-
tatione charitas praecedens corrumpitur et alia nova succedit sibi ; et ita
Chapter Three. Motion : The Narrow Sense 85
The argument offered in support of this view points out that since
the termini of any motion are incompossible ; and the preceding grade
of charity is one terminus (the terminus a quo) , while the succeeding
grade is the other terminus (the terminus ad quem) ; one of them (ob-
viously the preceding grade) must be destroyed . 204
In refutation, Ockham points out that alterative motion consists
in passage between positive termini. The results of a true alterative
passage are verified by the fact that a once white subject, (for example),
is now black. But those who argue for the first theory are positing a
privative alterative terminus ; maintaining that the destroyed degree
(the terminus a quo) is merely less intense than the new degree. Thus, to
posit the previous degree of charity to be one terminus, and the following
degree to be the other, is not to posit acceptable, positive, alterative
termini at all.205
The first of these holds that all qualitative intension and remission
derives from the separation of contraries. A qualitative intension is a
function of the degree of freedom from mixture with its contrary, enjoyed
by one member of a contrary qualitative pair. Thus " cold " is intensified
the more it is separated from " heat ;" "white" is intensified owing to
its being further freed from admixture with "black," and so on. This
theory, then, offers a negative reply to Ockham's question , for its
adherents do not concede the addition of any new parts to the previously
existent charity, but feel that its augmentation derives only from the
fact it is now more separate from its contrary.208
Ockham rejects this theory on two counts : in the first place, he
demonstrates , there exist qualities which undergo an intensification ,
or a lessening of intensity, which do not have contraries.209 In itself,
merely listing such examples would suffice to render this theory
vacuous, but Ockham points out further, that
it follows from this theory (opinio) that no form is augmented but that the
contrary form is ( also) augmented . . . Since I want heat to be augmented ,
then, according to this theory, the augmented heat is itself less mixed with
cold ; therefore cold is less mixed with heat; therefore the cold is augmented .
If it is nothing other for a form to be augmented than that it is less mixed
with its contrary, therefore, it follows from first to last that : “ heat is aug-
mented, therefore cold is augmented . "' 210
The next theory which Ockham examines, also answers his question
in the negative. Charity, the proponents of this theory feel, is augmented
as a result of the deeper participation of its subject (secundum participa-
tionem subiecti) in the form. Thus, just to the degree in which a subject
participates in a certain indivisible qualitative form , to just that degree
does it possess the quality. Should it be augmented, it is obviously
participating more in the quality; while should a lessening of intensity
occur, the subject has withdrawn a degree or so from participation.211
that a thing is said to be " more such" some variation either of the parts
of a subject, or the parts of its form is requisite . If it is said that this
variation is owing to the fact that a subject participates at first less , and
then more, in a form -— against : it is impossible to pass from a contradictory
to a contradictory without local motion, or the production or destruction
of something ; but in the (proposed explanation) everything remains the
same in situation and place ; therefore, it is proper that either something is
destroyed or produced and it is certain that nothing is destroyed except
it be posited that something is produced therefore , something is produced
here, and (it is not produced) in a subject's parts, hence in the parts of a
212
form.21
The next theory which Ockham turns to evaluate, agrees that the
augmentation of charity does involve formal addition. This addition is,
however, seen to be of a singular character ; for the strength of any
individual qualitative grade is contained, so this view goes, in that of the
following, more intense, grade. Each quality, this theory contends,
which can be thought of as undergoing a waxing and waning of intensity,
contains essentially, in a potential state, all the grades of intension
which it can exhibit. The intensive grade of any quality is thus seen to
be a function of the amount of actualized degrees, each of which con-
tains in itself the intensive strength of the previous, less intense , degree.213
formam et partem, quod neutrum potest dici . " See also, Sent. , III , 6, b.
Among the scholastics who supported this view were St. Thomas Aquinas,
Aegidius Romanus and Richard of Middleton. See A. Maier, op. cit.
212 Sent., I, dist. 17, qu . 6, f . See also Sent. , III , 6, c.
213 Sent. , I , dist . 17 , qu . 6 , g : "Alia est opinio quod forma non suscipit
magis et minus propter esse suum in subiecto , sed est gradualiter unum , quod
cum magis et minus suscipit per crementum et decrementum , illud fit per
partium appositionem vel subtractionem, secundum quas illud, scilicet
quod dicitur aliquid magis vel minus, dicitur in se magis vel minus, ita
quod qua(e) libet forma secundum quam aliquid dicitur magis vel minus ,
in sua natura habet partes vel paucas vel multas. Secundum quas potest
diversimode in diversis gradibus sistere inter terminos, et dicitur in se,
secundum illas partes magna vel parva, et subiectum maius vel minus.
Aliter enim secundum nullam formam diceretur aliquid magis vel minus
omnino. Et considerande sunt iste partes in formis simplicibus secundum
quantitatem spiritualis virtutis in perfectione secundum naturam rei in se,
et in vigore eius ex comparatione ad opus proprium , et hoc, per similitudinem,
ad quantitatem mobilis acceptam secundum rationem continui vel discreti .
Et quemadmodum ibi quod maius est , mobile continet quod minus est
pluries vel semel et aliquam eius partem ... Consimiliter, maius in virtute
continet in se minus secundum partes perfectionis. Et quemadmodum in
longitudine extensa corporaliter sunt infiniti gradus in potentia signandi
ratione quorum est motus localis, sic in calid (it)ate extensa virtualiter inter
summum et primum sunt infiniti gradus in potentia signandi . " See also
Sent., III, 6, b, c.
88 Ockham: Motion, Time and Place
214 Sent., dist. 17, qu . 6, i .: " Ista opinio videtur includere contradictio-
nem in hoc, quod ponit quod qua(e) libet talis forma augmentatur per
acquisitionem partis, et tamen quod partes non realiter distinguantur.
Quia impossibile est aliquid succedere alteri quod est idem realiter cum
illo. Sed part(i) una pars succedit alteri, ergo ista pars non est realiter illa,
et utraque illarum partium est ; ergo, realiter distinguitur haec pars ab illa. '
215 Sent., I , dist, qu . 6, k : " Ideo dico aliter ad quaestionem quod aug-
mentatione cuiuslibet formae vere aliquid reale differens realiter a priori
addatur quod etiam postquam additur realiter distinguitur ab eodem et
facit per se unum cum eo. "
216 Ibid. Among those of the scholastics who felt that intensive and
remissive were contained in the qualitative essence, was Henry of Ghent
(See A. Maier, op. cit. , p . 31 ) . Hervaeus Natalis , according to Dr. Maier,
(p. 33) , felt that each subsequent degree contains the strength of the prior
within it.
Chapter Three. Motion : The Narrow Sense 89
is true : " a is charity, " taking " a" to signify the whole of the preceding
charity, therefore " a" remains and is not destroyed . This will always be
true : "a is charity." But after augmentation "a" does remain and is not
destroyed ; therefore , this is true : "a is charity ; " therefore it is true to say
of a part of charity that it itself is charity, because "a" is then a part. But
there is no better reason for one part of charity to be charity, than for any
other; therefore any part of charity is truly and really charity. If it is said
that it is not "whole charity" (charitas integra) , this is not valid , because
"whole charity" means "charity which is not a part of another. " Thus, it is
manifest that it is not "whole" charity, and in the same way it must be
conceded that a part of water is not "whole" water, because a part of water
is a part. Hence, my theory does not contain a contradiction ; because the
added charity is truly a part of charity. Similarly, it would follow (from
Aureoli's theory), that a part of quantity distinct in location and situation
from another part, would not be quantity which is manifestly false and
self-negating.219
CHAPTER FOUR
CONCERNING TIME
I.
Whence, they posit that there is continuously another and another instant,
and that it is itself a certain thing which cannot possibly remain through
time. Indeed, they say it is distinguished from all permanent things.223
226 Tractatus., p. 120 : " Et quod instans non sit talis res raptim transiens
secundum se totam distincta ab omni re permanente, sicut moderni ponunt,
ostendo breviter sic : tum quia aut est substantia aut accidens ; non sub-
stantia, quia nec materia nec forma nec compositum. Nec accidens, quia
quaero de subiecto eius primo : aut est divisibile aut indivisibile . Non primum,
quia quando subiectum primum est divisibile, ipsum accidens existens in eo
est divisibile. Si detur secundum, scilicet quod subiectum primum est in-
divisibile, tunc quaero de isto subiecto : aut est substantia aut accidens ;
non primum, quia nec substantia corporea nec incorporea, sicut patet
inductive ; nec accidens, quia quaerendum est de subiecto eius primo, et sic
in infinitum ." The same argument can be found in Phil. Nat. , IV, 1 , with
this deviation : " tum quia esset subiectum instantis divisibile, cum non
possit esse nisi in mobili , et cum non est maior ratio quare sit in una parte
mobilis quam in alia, erit in qualibet parte mobilis, et ponitur a nonnullis
tota esse in toto corpore et in qualibet parte, vel erunt diversa instantia
in diversis partibus, quorum utrumque est impossibile. Non est ergo accidens
indivisibile secundum extensionem, nec est accidens divisibile secundum
quod sit extensum ad extensionem subiecti , quia tunc esset longum, latum,
et profundum, quod videtur absurdum . "
227 Phil. Nat. , IV, I.
228 Phil. Nat. , IV, 2 : " Per aliquas rationes priores potest probari quod
tempus non est alia res secundum se totam distincta ab omni re permanente. "
In Tractatus., p. 96, Ockham writes : ". . . tempus non est aliqua res distincta
secundum se totam ab omni re permanente et ab omnibus rebus permanen-
tibus. " As the sequel will show, Ockham is combatting the theory of time
as a forma fluens.
94 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
229 Phil. Nat. , IV, 2 : " Primo : quia cum tempus non possit esse substantia
talis oportebit quod sit accidens. Sed non est accidens indivisibile, cum sit
in corpore subiective, ergo est divisibile, et per consequens extensum habens
partes simul existentes, quod est contra Philosophum qui dicit quod partes
temporis non sunt simul. (Cf. Aristotle, Physics, IV, 10). Si dicas quod
tempus est extensum non secundum partes simul existentes, sed sibi invicem
succedentes, hoc non valet, quia subiectum temporis est extensum secundum
partes simul existentes, ergo , etc." See also Sent., II , 12 , vv ; and cf. Aristotle,
Physics, IV, 10.
230 Phil. Nat., IV, 2 : "Praeterea, tempus est in toto caelo, vel ergo est
in qualibet parte caeli , vel in nulla ; non in nulla, quia tunc non esset in toto :
quod enim, nec secundum se, nec secundum aliquam suam partem est in
aliquo, non est in toto, ergo tempus est in qualibet parte caeli ; sed non est
totum in aliqua parte caeli, quia nullum accidens tale est in caelo, igitur
una pars temporis est in una parte caeli , et alia pars in alia, et ita tempus
est extensum secundum partes simul existentes, et erunt plura tempora
simul, quia quaelibet pars temporis est tempus. " See also, Altaris. , p. 19 .
Chapter Four. Concerning Time 95
2.
231 Phil. Nat., IV, 2. See also : Logic., ch. 44, p. 127, ch. 46, p. 134 ;
Tractatus., p. 96-7 ; Sent. , II , qu . 12, a ; Quodl. , VII , qu . 7.
232 Phil. Nat. , IV, 3 : “Ostenso quid non est tempus, dicendum est quid
est tempus ... Sunt autem aliqua praemittenda. Primum est quod tempus
est mensura motuum quorum quantitas est nobis ignota, hoc est, per tempus
certificamur quamdiu aliquid movetur, et quod unum mobile diutius movetur
quam aliud, illud enim dicitur diutius moveri quod in maiori tempore
movetur. Aliud est, quod tempus est mensura rerum temporalium : per
tempus certificamur quod una res permanens diutius durat quam alia.
Aliud est, quod sicut per tempus mensuratur motus, et res temporalis, ita
etiam tempus est mensura quietis, quia per tempus certificamur quae res
diutius quiescat et quae minus, et quae aequaliter quiescit cum alia. Et ista
sunt principalia, vel praecipua propter quae ponitur tempus, et propter
quae cognitio temporis est nobis necessaria. (Cf. Aristotle, Physics, IV, 12).
Ex quibus sequitur quod cum quantitas mensurae debeat esse nobis notior
quam quantitatis mensurati, quia propter quantitatem mensurae certifi-
camur de qualitate mensuratorum, quod natura temporis quantum ad suam
quantitatem sit notior nobis, quam quantitate motuum mensuratorum ;
ex quibus sequitur quod tempus non est res latens incognoscibilis, sicut
aliqui dicunt, immo est nobis notum ..." See also, Sent. , II , qu . 11 , a.
233 Phil. Nat., IV, 3. Ockham adds : " (dicendum est) autem tempus
valde ignotum propter multas difficultates emergentes tractantibus de
m n
96 Ockha : Motio , Time and Place
when someone does not know for how long something is moved, he can be
rendered certain through some motion known to him ; for by considering
and applying the motion of the sun (which is) known to him, to that other
motion, and noting that that other mobile is moved from such a point to
such a point, he knows for how long it was moved.235
What Ockham is driving at, then, when he defines time as
the measure of all things whose duration can be certified by the intellect
236
by means of something else better known to it,23
is that time is a certain non-spatial dimension of motion.
It is the ordered, progressive, natural sequence of motion , Ockham
contends, which allows us to cognize, and employ as a measure, its
temporal dimension . The clearly demarcated character of some one
mobile's present physical constitution , or situation, as contrasted with
still another such achieved condition or location, validates the temporal
designations "prior, " and "posterior. " From here it is but a short step
to supplying numerical values to the continuous sequential passage from
the prior to the posterior stage or situation ; and time is precisely this
numerical statement of motions' uniform aspect. Ockham, then, ex-
presses himself as being in perfect accord with Aristotle's definition
of time as " the number of motion with respect to prior and posterior." 237
It is not, Ockham continues, that we stand in time and number
motion by correlating the prior, and posterior, and all intermediates, with
this, and this, passing moment - — quite the contrary : time is gleaned
from the physically prior and posterior, and is the numerical expression of
this ordered aspect of the moved. Time is not number by which we number
(quo numeramus); but is, rather, the numbered number (numerus numera-
tus), which is itself a part of the numbered thing (pars rei numeratae) .238
3.
quidem tempus autem est quod numeratur, et non quod tempus est numerus
numeratus, quia est pars rei numeratae . " Ockham continues : "Frustra
ergo ponitur aliud a motu, et prius ostensum est quod motus non est alia
res a rebus permanentibus , ergo nec tempus est aliquod accidens inhaerens
moto, vel motui ." See also, Tractatus. , pp. 110-111 ; and cf. Aristotle,
Physics, IV, 11 .
239 Phil. Nat., IV, 6 : "... tempus est motus sub isto intellectu : quod
per hoc, quod aliquid movetur uniformiter, potest aliquis certificari de
diuturnitate rei. Non tamen est universaliter verum quod omne per quod
sic cognoscitur, scilicet quantum est, est tempus illius motus, cum ista res,
scilicet tempus non potest competere cuiuscumque motui. Quia quamvis
per motum inferiorem difformem mensuremus motum uniformem; quia
quando quis cognoscit horam diei per motum suum et exercitium, et cognoscit
in quo situ in caelo est sol, et etiam per motum talem mensuramus alios
motus, tamen hoc non potest fieri per certitudinem, nec competit ex natura
rei, sed magis propter defectum aliquem, ideo non cuiuslibet motus est
tempus, sicut non quilibet pannus est ulna, quamvis per pannum possit
certificari de aliquo quod sit ulna."
240 Ibid .: ... Aliquis enim sciens quo(d) ulnarum est pannus, per illum
pannum, potest certificari de aliquo ligno ... quod est ulna ; et tamen ille
pannus non est ulna, quia de natura sua habet magis quod debet mensurari
quam mensurare, et ita est de motu uniformi respectu motuum difformium,
quia potius debet mensurare difformia, quam mensurari ab eis."
Chapter Four. Concerning Time 99
for the entire universe . True time, then, must be affirmed to be a passion
(passio) of this prime agency of motion.241
"Time," Ockham writes,
is a passion of the first motion just as mensurability is a passion of an ell ,
and risibility of a man. Just as, notwithstanding that a man is truly risible,
and yet we say that risibility is a passion of man, so we can say that first
motion is time, and yet time is a passion of first motion, because such
propositions which appear to be repugnant are verified through diverse
suppositions of terms . Just as in this : " man is risible, " the terms stand in
personal and significative supposition ; but in this : " risibility is a passion of
man, " this term “man” is used in simple, or material supposition . . . Simi-
larly, here : "first motion is time, ” the terms are used in personal and signif-
icative supposition, because through this nothing more is denoted except
that the prime mobile is uniformly and swiftly moved, through which
(motion) the intellect can ascertain of other things how long they endure,
move or rest. In this, however : "time is a passion of the first motion, " the
terms are used in simple or material (supposition) ; for it denotes that time
is predicated ... of motion ... just as measure is predicated of an ell.242
"It is obvious," Ockham concludes,
from what has been said, that time is not something other than the prime
motion, because through the prime motion . . . we know for how long temporal
things endure, move, or rest. And still "time, " and " prime motion, " differ
in definition, since " time" imports a soul which is certified, and other things
of which it is certified ; and so it does not import other than permanent things,
although it may import that some of these permanent things are moved.243
241 Phil. Nat., IV, 7 : "Patet ex iam dictis cui motui compet(i) t esse
tempus, scilicet primo motui primi mobilis, uniformiter et velocissime moti,
quamvis per motum solis possimus metiri motum multarum rerum, tamen
ratio ipsius magis convenit illi motui primo, quia quantum est ex se, magis
natus est certificare de aliis motibus, quam motus soli ; immo, per illum
motum natus est intellectus certificari de motu solis, et aliorum planetarum,
ergo tempus est passio primi motus. " See also, Tractatus ., p. 107 ; and cf.
Aristotle, Physics, IV, 14. Philotheus Boehner, (in his article : "Scotus'
Teachings According to Ockham, " Franciscan Studies, n. s. vol. 6 ( 1946)
p. 101 writes : " Passio is a technical term (for the scholastics) and indicates
that a term is predicated in the second mode of per se predication about
its subject. The first mode of per se predication is given when the predicate
defines the subject ; for instance ' rational' is predicated in the first mode
of per se predication about the subject ' man ;' the second mode of per se
predication is given, when the subject enters the definition of the predicate
as for instance ' risible, ' for its definition would be : man who is able to laugh . "
Ockham (Phil . Nat. IV, 11 ) , writes : “tempus non sequitur motum sicut
res inhaerens sibi, sed dicitur sequi motum quia praedicatur per se secundo
modo de primo motu . " See also, Tractatus. , p. 119 ; Logic. , ch. 37, pp. 96—8.
242 Phil. Nat. , IV, 7. See also, Sent. , II, 12 , c, ss.
243 Phil. Nat., IV, 7. See also, Sent. , II , 12 , c, ss. In Tractatus . , p. 11I,
Ockham is much more direct : "... dico quod tempus primo et principaliter
significat illud quod significat motus, quamvis consignificet tam animam
quam actum animae, quo cognoscit prius et posterius illius motus secundum
modum praeexpositum. Et ideo supponendo dicta de motu, et quod pro-
100 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
4.
Objections
To hold, as Ockham does, that time is motion, even after his carefully
stated qualifications, is to raise a host of dissenting voices. The first
objection to his view wields the potent weapon of Aristotelian authority ;
for Aristotle, this dissenting opinion points out, holding any part of time
to be time, proved that time could not be circular motion, as it is not the
case that any part of circular motion is, itself, circulation.245
If there were many heavens, this argument runs, then there must be
admitted to be many prime mobiles ; hence, in terms of Ockham's
equivalence, there is implied an " inconvenience " - i . e. , the possibility
of a plurality of "times."246
Again, motion and mutation were shown by Ockham not to be other
than individual moved and mutated subjects ; hence, his own theory
of motion seems to run counter to his equation of time and motion ; for
time, which he claims to be of a generalized and uniform character
obtaining equally among all moved substances , can not itself be
identified with any one motion or mutation.247
Next, a speculative extrapolation of Ockham's equation of motion
and time purports to demonstrate the inconsistency of his position.
Finally, motions may be fast or slow, but time is the equable,
uniform measure which lends verity to these designations : " fast," and
"slow," and is not, in itself, "fast ," or " slow. " Time, on this account,
obviously cannot be motion. 248
Similarly, Ockham's claim for the substantial unity of the temporal
moment and the prime mobile comes in for its share of criticism. If an
instant were, in actuality, one and the same with the substance of the
prime mobile, Ockham's opponents argue, how can one account for the
fact of time's successive character ? For the fact that one moment follows
on another? And to deny that time is continuous in nature, is to fly
in the face of Aristotle's express views on this subject.249
Again, mutation, it is argued, occurs instantaneously ; but Ockham
has not claimed the substantial unity of mutation and the prime mobile ;
how then can he maintain the substantial unity of an instant and the
prime mobile ? The measure of motion is a unit of time, and not the
substance of the prime mobile ,250
Further, since time, as any continuum , is divisible, and must consist
in more than one terminus ; and since an instant is, in fact , the terminus
246 Phil. Nat., IV, 9 : “ Item , si motus esset tempus, ergo si essent plures
caeli primi, essent plures motus primi , ergo essent plura tempora, quod est
inconveniens. " See also, Tractatus . , p . 114.
247 Phil. Nat., IV, 9 : " Item, motus et mutatio tantum sunt in ipso
mutato vel moto, sed tempus est simul ubique et apud omnes, ergo tempus
non est motus nec mutatio. " See also, Tractatus., p . 114.
248 Phil. Nat., IV, 9 : “ Item , motus est velox vel tardus , sed tempus nec
velox nec tardus, ergo etc., minor patet quia velox et tardum certificantur
tempore et etiam diffiniuntur. " See also Tractatus. , p. 114.
249 Phil. Nat., IV, 9 : “Item, quod instans non sit ipsa substantia mobilis
videtur, quia si esset substantia mobilis, nullo modo esset aliud et aliud
instans, quod est contra Philosophum. " Cf. Aristotle, Physics, VI, 2 .
250 Phil. Nat., IV, 9 : " Item, mutatio est in instanti ; sed mutatio non est
in substantia primi mobilis ; ergo, etc. Item, mutatio mensuratur in instanti,
et non mensuratur substantia primi mobilis ."
102 Ockham: Motion, Time and Place
of time, time must consist in many instants - but there cannot be many
substances of the prime mobile ; hence, it follows that any instant, and
the substance of the prime mobile, are distinct things.251
Finally, Ockham's adversaries point out, the " now" - the moment
of time -links the past and the future ; and no one could seriously
maintain that this " link" corresponded in any way to any mobile.252
5.
Resolutions
255 Phil. Nat., IV, 11 : "...dico quod Philosophus non intendit improbare
istam conclusionem ; motus primus non est tempus, nec per consequens,
istam : motus non est tempus, nec econverso ; sed intendit probare istam
conclusionem : motus primus sive circulatio non sunt cum tempore idem
diffinitione. Similiter, istam : motus et tempus non sunt idem diffinitione,
hoc est, non habent eandem diffinitionem. Et ista fuit opinio Aristotelis . . .
tempus et circulatio non sunt idem diffinitione, hoc est, non habent eandem
diffinitionem, vel quod aliquod importatur per ' tempus ' quod non importatur
per ' motum ' vel eodem modo per ‘ circulationem , ' vel econverso . " See also,
Tractatus., p. 115.
256 Phil. Nat., IV, 11 : ". . . intendit Philosophus probare quod aliquid
importatur per ' motum ' quod non importatur per ' tempus ' , et econverso,
et hoc utrumque verum est, quia per ' primum motum' importatur, sive
per ' circulationem ' praecise totus motus et non pars ; per ' tempus' autem,
importatur tam pars motus, sive circulationis , quam totum simul ; cum hoc
per ' tempus' importatur anima, et motus, et alia de quibus anima debet
certificari per tempus ... Et patet evidenter, quod per istam (Aristotle)
... non intendit probare nisi quod isti termini non sunt idem diffinitione,
et aliquid importetur per unum , quod non importatur per reliquum, vel
saltem eodem modo . " See also, Tractatus . , p. 118-9.
257 Phil. Nat., IV, 11. In Tractatus . , p . 103 , Ockham writes : “ ... hoc
nomen ' tempus' aliquid significat vel consignificat , quod non significatur
vel consignificatur per hoc nomen ' motus ' quod quidem consignificatum
per ' tempus' est anima mensurans ."
104 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
258 Phil . Nat. , IV, 11. It is in an entirely different spirit that St. Thomas
Aquinas differentiates two kinds of time : one quantitatively discontinuous ,
which measures the motions of spiritual creatures, and one continuous,
which holds for all corporeal creatures. See Aquinas, Quaestiones Quod-
libetales, Quodlibetum secundum, qu . 3 , art. 1. See also his Commentum
in Librum I Sententiarum , dist. 37, qu . 4, art. 3 , where he writes : “ ... di-
cendum, quod non potest accipi aliqua proportio temporis in quo movetur
corpus, ad tempus in quo movetur angelus, quia tempus quo movetur
angelus, non est divisibile divisione continui, sed discreti in plura instantia
finita; in tempore autem quo movetur corpus, sunt infinita instantia in
potentia ; et ita nulla est proportio. " Taking into cognizance his stand (with
Avempace) in the controversy centering around the Aristotelian Text 71
(see above, pp. 266-274) , Aquinas adds : “ ... dicendum quod tempus istud
quo angelus movetur, divisibile est in duo, quae non copulantur ad unum
communem terminum, cum hoc tempus non sit continuum . Unde non sequitur
quod in medio instanti sit in medio spatii : quia non est necessarium accipere
medium instans. " The second objection to Ockham's theory is answered
differently in the Tractatus .; on pp. 117-8, Ockham replies in this fashion :
"per talem modum arguendi (non) convenit inferre pluralitatem ex pluralitate,
quando unum praedicatur de alio utroque sumpto significative, sicut non
sequitur: intelligentia prima est ens, igitur se sint plura entia, sunt plures
intelligentiae primae, et sic de multis aliis . Sed quando accipitur illa esse
eadem vel habere eandem definitionem, contingit tunc semper inferre
Chapter Four. Concerning Time 105
the terms "time," and "motion," are not convertible ---- i. e., they
differ in definition. 262
Owing directly to the premisses that the events which are measured
by time are of various duration , while the measure is itself uniform in
nature, one cannot conclude that the measure itself is not a motion ; 263
for time, as Ockham has demonstrated, is a motion — but a motion of
such rigorously constant velocity as to be normative for the entire
universe .
Strictly speaking, Ockham points out , it can not be properly main-
tained that time is "fast," or "slow ;" nevertheless, it would not be
incorrect, by virtue of a less rigorous mode of speech , to affirm that
time is "fast ," since it is an aspect of the swiftest motion in the universe ;
accordingly, in no mode ought it to be conceded that time is "slow,"
nor that since it is, in addition , an aspect of the most uniform motion
in the universe any one " time," varies in duration from another
"time."264
When it is held that "swift," and " slow," are defined by time, it
must be remembered, Ockham insists, that the term "time" connotes
the prime motion . That motion, accordingly, is more swift in which the
mobile moves from one point to another while the prime mobile enjoys
a greater amount of activity, than is that motion in which the moved
.
travels from one place to another while the prime mobile moves cor-
respondingly less than in the first instance. While should one object
that the motion of any mobile may provide a frame of reference by
means ofwhich the motion , rest or endurance of mobiles may be measured ,
Ockham would agree : but he points out that the degree of precision
suffers accordingly as these physical events are referred for measure
262 Phil. Nat., IV, 11 : " Ad quartum dico quod illud probat quod non
omnis motus est tempus, et quod motus et tempus habe (n) t diversas dif-
finitiones. Ex hoc enim, quod unus motus velocior alio, et unum tempus
non est velocius alio, sequitur quod motus et tempus non sunt adaequate
et convertibiliter idem, et quod non omnis motus est tempus - et hoc
concedo." See also Tractatus. , pp. 116—7.
263 Phil. Nat. , IV, 11 : "Unde, sicut non sequitur, unum lignum est
longius alio, sed ulna non est lignum, ergo ulna non est lignum (sic !) ita
nec alia consequentia (i. e . , the one which his opponents drew from the
premisses : " motions are fast and slow ; time is not fast or slow, etc. ") valet ."
Cf. Aristotle, Physics, IV, 10 ; IV, 12.
264 Phil. Nat., IV, 11 : " Probat Philosophus quod non omnis motus est
tempus, et quod differunt diffinitione, et ideo de rigore modi loquendi
numquam potest concedi quod tempus est velox vel tardum. Dico igitur,
quod de vírtute sermonis, secundum principia Philosophi, potest concedi
quod tempus est velox, quia tempus est velocissimus motus, sed non debet
concedi quod tempus est tardum, nec quod unum tempus sit velocius alio,
sicut nec motus primus sit velocior primo motu . " See also, Tractatus . , p. 116.
Chapter Four. Concerning Time 107
to any standard less constant than the uniformly swift motion of the
prime mobile.265
Ockham turns now to a critical evaluation of the objections launched
against his stand that the moment of time is, itself, substantially one
with the prime mobile. Temporal instants do, in fact, follow continu-
ously one on the other, Ockham replies to the first objection, but this
is not to be understood in the sense that each instant is an atomic
component which inexplicably arises, is somehow destroyed, and is
once again replaced in the absolute timestream ; but is rather to be
understood as connoting the successive changes in position (with respect
to its parts) , of the prime mobile. The parts of the prime mobile, that is,
successively acquire place after place, each instant of time consignifying
by its " now" that the prime mobile is " here. " 266 The constant velocity
of the prime mobile is guarantee for the perfect successive order, and
constant value, of each moment of time.
That Ockham will concede, quite cheerfully, the truth of the prop-
osition : "mutation is instantaneous," is, on the basis of his previous
handling of mutation, easily anticipated . It will be recalled that for
Ockham , endorsement of the truth of the statement under consideration
involves affirmation of the fact that there is no delimitable priority or
posteriority of stages exhibited by a mobile undergoing a sudden change ;
but rather that the mutant receives its form non-successively - i . e. ,
"in an instant ."267 Consequently, to employ the premise: "mutation is
265 Phil. Nat., IV, 11 : " Et quando dicitur quod velox et tardum diffini-
untur tempore, dico quod verum est quod diffinitur motu primo ; illud
enim est velocius quod dum movetur a tali puncto at tale (m) punctum ,
mobile primum plus movetur ; et illud tardius, quod dum movetur, mobile
primum minus movetur. Et si dicas quod tempus potest haberi de motu
a(li)quo, an sit velocior alio per alium inferiorem dico quod verum est;
sed non ita certitudinaliter, nec a tot, nec ita bene et faciliter a communitate,
maxime si motus sit primus. Unde, ille motus erit tempus, et alius non,
qui motus magis certificat quamcumque rem, et totam communitatem
certificare habet de aliis, quantum durant, moventur, vel quiescunt, et
omne(s) istae conditiones competunt primo motui. " Cf. Aristotle, Physics,
IV, 12.
266 Phil. Nat., IV, 12 : "Postquam solutae sunt rationes quibus probatur
quod tempus est alia res a motu , nun (c ) solvendae sunt rationes quibus
probatur quod instans est alia res a primo mobili . Unde, ad primum dico
quod instans non est aliud et aliud sic, quod sunt diversa instantia quae
sint diversae res totaliter ; sed sub isto intellectu potest concedi quod instans
est aliud et aliud ; hoc est, quod primum mobile est successive in diversis
locis, et alibi et alibi , ita quod primum mobile secundum diversas partes suas
nunc est hic, et nunc alibi . " See also, Tractatus. , p . 121 ; Sent . , II , 12, gg,
mm.
267 Phil. Nat., IV, 12 : " Ad aliud dico quod ista propositio : ' mutatio est
in instanti, ' conceditur sub isto sensu : quando aliquid subito movetur,
tunc quicquid acquirit, subito acquirit ; ita quod non est aliquid prius et
8.
108 Ockham: Motion, Time and Place
aliquid posterius acquisitum ; ita quod ista propositio : ' mutatio est in
instanti, intelligitur per illam aliam longam . " See also, above, Chapter 2.
268 Ibid.: "... ideo modus arguendi ex talibus : ' mutatio est in instanti, '
et universaliter ex his quae sunt improprie causa(n) t fallaciam aequivoca-
tionis, vel amphibologiae, et iudicandum est de eis, et de argumentis in
quibus ponuntur per illas quae per eas intelliguntur. Et ideo sicut non
sequitur: quando aliquid mutatur, totum simul acquiritur dum primum
mobile est in aliquo determinato situ , sed mutatio non est in substantia
primi mobilis , ergo instans est alia res -— quia semper est licitum propositio-
nem quae per aliam intelligitur poni loco ipsius.'
269 Phil. Nat., IV, 12 : “Ad aliud , quando dicitur : ' mutatio subita men-
suratur instanti , ' dico quod ista est falsa etiam secundum alios qui ponunt
instans esse aliam rem a substantia mobilis, et mutationem esse aliam rem
a motu et mobili et omni re permanente. Nam secundum eos tam mutatio
quam instans, est res indivisibilis ; sed numquam indivisibile quantum ad
suum esse mensuratur alio indivisibili . Sicut si esset aliqua magnitudo
indivisibilis, numquam mensuraretur alio indivisibili , quia non posset
mensurari quia intellectus tantum dubitat quantum est unum quantum
aliud et non potest per unum indivisibile de aliquo certificari quantum est . . .
Et eodem modo numqua ( m) potest intellectus certificari de aliquo quantum
est per aliud, nisi quando unu (m) est maius alio , vel quando unum est
divisibile et ignoratur utrum sit aequale , vel inaequale alteri indivisibili .
Dico, igitur, quod ista non est vera de virtute sermonis : ' mutatio subita
mensuratu(r) instanti ; ' si , tamen, per eam intelligatur ista : ' quando aliquid
mutatur subito, acquirit totum simul et non secundum prius et posterius , '
bene potest concedi . " See also, Sent. , II , 12 , ii.
Chapter Four. Concerning Time 109
6.
271 Phil. Nat., IV, 16 : " Quia philosophi faciunt difficultatem circa
tempus, an sit in anima, vel possit esse sine anima, ideo quomodo tempus
se habeat ad animam est sciendum." Cf. Aristotle. Physics, IV, 14 .
272 Phil. Nat., IV, 16 : "... patet quod si anima non posset esse, tempus
non posset esse tempus, cum nihil posset esse numerus vel mensura. Unde
motus primus, quamvis posset esse uniformissimus et velocissimus, si tamen
anima non posset esse, tunc ille motus non posset esse tempus . Ideo Philo-
sophus dicit quod tempus est ens in anima, et quod suum esse completum
est ab anima, nihil aliud intelligens, nisi quod motus extra non posset esse
tempus sine anima. " See also Sent. , II , 12 , ddd . In Tractatus . , p . 97 , Ockham
writes: "... dicit Commentator . (see Averroes, op. cit. , Comment 88,
f. 142г) , quod ' talia nondum habent esse completum, sed esse eorum com-
ponitur ex actione animae et ex eo, quod est in eis extra animam ; et entia
completa sunt illa in quorum esse nihil facit anima, ut postea declarabitur
de tempore.' Quod est sic intelligendum, quod talia, cuiusmodi sunt motus
et mutatio et huiusmodi, quae important successionem, nondum habent
esse completum, hoc est, non sunt entia completa secundum se tota distincta
a rebus permanentibus, nec sunt quaedam completa secundum se tota ...
composita realiter ex rebus permanentibus ; sed esse eorum componitur
ex actionibus animae in eo, quod est non-ens extra animam , hoc est, aliqua
importat per talia non habent esse extra animam, quamvis possint cognosci
ab anima et aliquid importatum ab eis est extra animam .”
273 Phil. Nat. , IV, 16.
Chapter Four. Concerning Time III
The same relationship, then, obtains between time and the prime
motion - i . e. , the intellect mediates, and brings to completed being
that uniform and sequential aspect of prime motion which is time.
Now there are two ways, Ockham maintains in an attempt to re-
concile the differences of opinion concerning the true status of time,
in which the intellect can be thought of as being involved in the definition
of time. The first way consists in defining time as being "that through
which the soul is rendered certain. " Conceived in this way, time would
be related to the prime motion only on those occasions when the in-
tellect, directing itself to the standard of the prime motion, sought
confirmation involving problems of individual rest , motion , or endurance.
Time, that is, thus conceived, would depend absolutely upon the in-
quiring intellect .
In the second way, the role of the intellect is immensely changed.
Time, in this conception , is held to be that which the soul uses to measure
the duration of other things. Seen in this light, time is, as an aspect
of the prime motion, always "there" for use by the intellect ; and it
exists, so long as the prime motion exists, whether the soul is actually
employing it to measure other motions, rests, periods of longevity, or not.
The intellect, thus, does not call time into being, but completes its being
by applying the mensurable propensity of real prime motion to concrete
physical situations requiring measurement. It is to this latter mode of
relating time, the intellect, and prime motion, that Ockham subscribes.274
Ockham concludes :
it is patent that that which is time is really outside the soul, and yet it
depends on the soul that it is time. Because time could not be time - or
274 Phil. Nat. , IV, 16 : "Oportet autem scire, quod dupliciter potest
intelligi quod anima ponatur in diffinitione temporis . Uno modo, ut denotetur
tempus esse illud per quod anima actualiter certificatur, ut ista sit descriptio
temporis : tempus est illud per quod anima certificatur. Alio modo, ut
denotetur quod tempus est illud quo anima potest mensurare alia, quamvis,
de facto, non mensuret, vel sive men(s) uret actualiter, sive non. Et tunc
talis potest esse descriptio temporis : tempus est illud per quod anima pot (est)
certificari de aliis. Si primo modo intelligatur descriptio temporis, dico
quod primus motus non est tempus, nisi quando anima per ipsum mensurat
alia, et tunc sub isto intellectu oportet concede (re) , quod si anima non
numeraret motum primum secundum prius et posterius mensurando alia per
ipsum, non esset tempus. Si autem secundo modo intelligatur, tunc debet
dici quod motus primus est tempus, sive anima mensuret vel numeret
primum motum, sive non ; et ita tempus est, sive anima mensuret, sive non. "
See also, Sent., II , 12, xx ; and cf. S. C. Tornay, Ockham , Studies and Selections
(Open Court Pub. co . , La Salle, Ill . ( 1938 ) . On p . 45 , Prof. Tornay writes :
"the distinctive feature of Ockham's conception (of time) lies in his sub-
jectivist approach. " As we have seen, however, Professor Tornay must be
in error. "Time, " for Ockham, is a connotative term signifying directly
the motion of an absolute existent -- i . e. , the prime mobile - and con-
signifying the soul which imparts number to this motion .
112 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
that which is time could not be time without the soul, just as a cause in
no way depends on its effect, and yet the cause could not be a cause without
its effect.2275
CHAPTER FIVE
CONCERNING PLACE
I.
place is not such a space, because either such a space is other than the
located, or not. If not, then place is the placed , and the same thing would
be in itself as if in a place . If other and it is manifestly not something
indivisible ― then it is divisible and extended ; (but it is not extended) any
more with respect to any one part than to any other ; therefore it is long,
broad, and deep, and is, consequently, a body - which cannot be said.280
278 Phil. Nat. , IV, 19 : " Si (locus sit) spatium medium . . . sequeretur
quod loci essent infiniti. Ista consequentia patet evidenter et potest declarari
multipliciter, uno modo sic : si spatium medium esset locus, tunc aliquid
diceretur in loco quia esset praesens spatio ; sed ita convenit cuilibet parti
totius esse praesens tali spatio sicut toti, aequaliter ergo totum est in loco,
et pars quaelibet ; sed sunt infinitae partes, ergo loca sunt infinita . ”
279 Ibid.: “... si locus sit spatium ergo locus est corpus . Sed omne corpus
est mobile, ergo illud spatium moveri poterit de loco ad locum, et ita Îoci
erit locus. Sed non est verisimile quod aliquod corpus quieverit per tempus
infinitum ; ex quo, ergo, illud spatium, si sit corpus, movebatur, et numquam
quievit continue per tempus infinitum, ergo infinities fuit motum, et per
consequens erunt infinita loca, quia infinita loca movebantur infinities ad
unum . " Cf. Aristotle, Physics, IV, 1 .
280 Ibid. Cf. Aristotle, loc. cit.
114 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
2.
be equivalent to the located, just as if some other thing were posited . There-
fore, place is not something other than surface . 284
284 Phil. Nat . , IV, 20. See also Logic. , ch. 61 , p . 174.
285 Phil. Nat., IV, 20 : "... si locus sit alia res a superficie, oportet quod
sit in genere quantitatis, qualitatis, vel substantiae ; et non potest poni in
genere qualitatis, nec substantiae, ut satis patet, ergo est in genere quantitatis .
Et si sic, vel est quantitas continua, vel quantitas discreta ; (Non est discreta)
certum est ; ergo est continua. Aut ergo est successiva, aut permanens .
Non successiva manifestum est, ergo permanens . Vel est ergo longitudo,
vel latitudo, vel profunditas, vel tales dimensiones, et per consequens est
linea, vel superficies, vel corpus. Confirmatur : omne quantum permanens
continue est longum, latum, et profundum, igitur locus est longus, latus,
et profundus, et nihil est cuiusmodi nisi sit linea , vel corpus, vel superficies . "
Further on (Ibid . ) Ockham writes : " Item notandum quod hoc nomen
'locus' est nomen relativum secundum Commentatorem, et tamen illud de
quod verificatur hoc nomen 'locus ' est vere quantitas ; et propter hoc ponit
Philosophus locum in genere quantitatis ... (see Aristotle, Categories,
ch. 6) . Sed quia hoc nomen 'locus ' est proprie relativum ideo non ponitur
per se in genere quantitatis, sed per accidens . " See also Logic. , ch . 46, p. 134.
286 Phil. Nat., IV, 20 : " Quod autem superficies non sit alia res secundum
se totam distincta probatur ... quia tunc esset accidens et haberet subiectum
primum. Tunc quaeritur de isto subiecto primo aut est corpus, aut aliud
à corpore. Si primum, tunc in qualibet parte istius corporis erit aliquid
116 Ockham: Motion, Time and Place
superficiei illius quod est manifeste falsum, quia in parte citra illam super-
ficiem non est illa superficies, aut alia pars eius. Nec subiectum primum est
aliud a corpore, quia tunc esset substantia ; sed omnis substantia extensa
est longa, lata, et profunda, igitur habet aliquam partem in profundo quae
non est sub aliqua parte illius superficiei , ergo, etc. "
Chapter Five. Concerning Place 117
place is not a thing apart from a surface, (and that) a surface is not a thing
apart from a body.287
3.
287 Phil. Nat., IV, 20 : " Similiter : si superficies sit alia res, accipio duas
partes continui et quaero utrum est eadem superficies terminans utramque
partem corporis continui, aut aliam et alia(m) ; si est alia et alia, igitur
superficies est immediata superficiei , quod Aristoteles improbat. Si sit una,
per divisionem corrumperetur, et generarentur duae superficies, quia non
est maior ratio, si remanet illa superficies post divisionem, quod remaneat
in una parte, plusquam in alia, et per consequens manet simul in utraque,
vel in nulla. Sed impossibile est quod per divisionem una superficies cor-
rumpatur, et duo generarentur, quia generans non destruit unum individuum
unius speciei, et generat novum individuum eiusdem speciei in eodem sub-
iecto. Tum quia accidens non destruitur, nisi vel per destructionem sub-
iecti sui, vel per inductionem sui contrarii, vel alicuius incompossibilis, vel
per absentiam suae causae, quorum nullum potest contingere in proposito .
Tum quia accipio substantiam quae est primum subiectum primae super-
ficiei, et quaero utrum illa manet, vel non . Si non manet, igitur aliqua
substantia per divisionem corrumpitur, et non materia, igitur forma . Tunc
quaero de materia quae erat sub forma corrupta, ubi manet, vel in utraque,
vel in neutra, vel in altera . Non in utraque, manifestum est, nec in neutra -
quia tunc separaretur, et esset nova inductio formae, et tunc non esset sola
divisio , quod est impossibile. Nec manet in altera . Tum quia non est maior
ratio quare sit plus in una quam in alia . Si primum subiectum manet, aut
igitur in utraque parte, aut in altera tantum, aut in neutra, et deducatur
idem quod prius . Propter istas rationes, et alias consimiles . .." etc. See
also, Logic., ch. 46, p. 134—5 .
288 Phil. Nat . , IV, 21 : Sed contra ista videntur aliqua argumenta .
Primo, quia ultimum continentis non est illud continens, quia idem esset
ultimum suiipsius ."
118 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
289 Phil. Nat., IV, 21 : " Ad primum dicendum quod aliquid ultimum
continentis est illud continens, et aliquod non ; nam accipiendo vas continens
aquam, ipsum vas vocatur ultimum continentis ... praeter, etiam , illud
continens ultimum, quaelibet pars vasis tangentis totam aquam vocatur
ultimum continentis, et quaelibet illarum distinguitur a vase continente ,
sicut pars a suo toto, et e converso, ita quod iste locus non est illud continens ,
hoc est, non est totum, sed est pars. " Although I translate ultimum continens
as: "the furthest limit of the containing body," what is meant in this context,
is: "the innermost limit of the containing body which is defined by its being
in immediate contact with the contained body. " For example : the place
of a bird in the air at any given moment would be the parts of the air in
immediate contact with the parts of the bird's body still, these parts
of the containing body are the furthest limits, with respect to its content,
and are the innermost surface with respect to the continent air.
290 Ibid. See Aristotle, Physics, IV, 2 ; and Averroes, op. cit. , Comment 33 ,
fol. IIIг.
Chapter Five. Concerning Place 119
place and the placed are equal ; but the containing body is not equal to the
contained ... therefore, etc.;
allows him to elaborate on the meaning of the term “ equal" which was
previously employed without that linguistic precision upon which he
characteristically insists. "When it is said, " Ockham writes ,
that place and the placed are equal, it is patent through what has gone
before in what mode they are equal ; because, namely, (they are equal)
according to the furthest parts which are in contact ... And yet this holds
with this : that ... the outer parts (of the containing body) , not touching
291 Phil. Nat., IV, 21 : " Item dicit Aristoteles quod totus aer non est
locus proprius alicuius, quia tunc locus et locatum non essent aequalia ;
et tunc, qua ratione totus aer non est locus alicuius, nec totum corpus est
alterius ; et tamen oportet quod aliquid illius sit locus alicuius, et non aliqua
pars, propter eandem rationem ; ergo aliquod aliud, quod non potest esse
nisi superficies."
292 Tractatus. , p. 77-8 : " Per idem patet ad aliud , quod non totus aer,
scilicet qui continet illud corpus et aliud, est locus proprius et primus illius,
et hoc quia habet multas ultimas partes, quae non tangunt illud corpus
praeter partes superiores, quae tangunt aliam sphaeram superiorem. Et ideo
non sequitur: totus aer non est locus proprius illius, igitur nec aliquod aliud
corpus totum est locus alicuius, quia multae sunt partes ultimae aeris
totius, quae non tangunt aliquam partem illius locati. Sed non est sic de
quocumque alio corpore, quia alicuius corporis nulla est pars ultima interior,
quin tangat aliquam partem ultimam illius corporis locati , et ideo est locus
primus illius corporis."
120 Ockham : Motion , Time and Place
the located body, may be longer or even broader (than the place of the
located) . 293
that the Commentator is speaking of the whole air containing many bodies ;
which is, therefore, not the first place of any of these bodies. But in that
whole air, a body is said to be located because it is in some part of the body
of air, and any furthest part directed against the located touches some part
of the located . And that the Commentator is speaking of the whole air, is
clear, because he says that the bound (i . e. , the furthest limit) of one thing
(i. e., the whole air) is the proper place of a thing which is said to be in the
air, and (the second place is) something else which contains itself and the
other. Verbi gratia : the bound of the whole air, and, therefore, the whole
air, is the second place ; but that air equal with respect to length, breadth,
and depth to the located, is its proper place ; and these two "airs, " so to
say, are distinguished as a whole and a part.295
Thus far the chief merit of Ockham's replies to his adversaries'
objections lies rather in their efficacy for removing those sophistical
difficulties raised on linguistic grounds, than in a constructive extension
of his view of place and the placed. This, however, is not to be the
case with regard to a final objection . For in his reply to this argument :
every body is mobile ... but place is immobile,296
designed, obviously, to demonstrate the independence of place from
the placed - Ockham expands materially on his initial thesis.
Now several previous attempts - two of which Ockham will ex-
amine to preserve the theoretical immobility of place have been, as
far as Ockham is concerned, dismally abortive . One school sought to
preserve that immobility upon which Aristotle has insisted, by the nice,
if devious method of marking a distinction between two ways in which
any extended object could be said to be " in a place : " materially, and
formally. Place is, of course, immobile when considered from the material
aspect - i. e., as being the place defined by the "furthest limit of the
containing body" in intimate contact with the surfaces of the located.
When, however, that extended body changes its place, its former place
can still be considered as immobile viewed from the formal aspect — i . e . ,
with respect to the order of the universe.297
This thesis, preserving under all circumstances the immobility of
place, can be illustrated by analogy. A ship tied at anchor in a flowing
stream is not always, in the material sense, in the same place, insofar
as its surfaces are in contact with first one , and then another, part of
the water in which the entire body of water consists . It is, however,
viewed formally, always in the same place - i. e., with respect to the
whole stream; and seen thus, in the formal sense, the place of each
part of the water, of the ship tied at anchor, and by further reference
the whole body of water itself, are all immobile.298
296 Phil. Nat. , IV, 20 : " Omne corpus est mobile ; secundu (m) Philo-
sophu(m) locus est immobilis ut patet in diffinitione, ergo, etc. " Cf. Aristotle,
Physics, IV, 4.
297 Phil. Nat., IV, 22 : “ Quantum ad ultimum argumentum de immo-
bilitate, est sciendum quod istam immobilitatem loci diversi diversimode
nituntur salvare. Dicunt enim aliqui, quod in loco est duo considerare ;
scilicet, illud quod est materiale ibi loci , et est superficies corporis continentis ;
et illud quod est ibi loci formale, scilicet ordo ad universum."
298 Phil. Nat., IV, 22 : " Sicut videmus quod quaelibet pars fluvii movetur,
totus autem fluvius est immobilis quodammodo, quia quamdiu durat cursus
aquarum, tamdiu cursus retinet eundem situm . Navis, enim, si ligetur ad
anchora(m) , ut non simul cum flum(ine) fluat, dicetur se (m) per esse in eodem
loco ; quia licet alia et alia aqua sit subter eam, et licet navis non semper
habeat eundem ordinem ad partes fluvii, quia partes illae sunt mobiles, quia
tamen quamdiu sit ligata est in eodem loco respectu ad totum fluvium,
propter quod totus fluvius dicitur quodammodo locus, quia locus navis
habet immobilitatem ex ordine ad totum fluvium." Ockham here appears
to be examining the theory of St. Thomas Aquinas. In Commentaria in
Octo Libros Physicorum Aristotelis, Lib. IV, Cap. IV, Lect. VI , 14 , St. Thomas
writes : "... sic igitur fluvius totus inquantum est immobilis, est locus
9 Ockham : Motion
122 Ockham: Motion, Time and Place
communis. Cum autem locus proprius sit pars loci communis oportet accipere
proprium locum navis in aqua fluminis, inquantum habet ordinem ad totum
fluvium ut est immobilis. Est igitur accipere locum navis in aqua fluente,
non secundum hanc aquam quae fluit, sed secundum ordinem vel situm
quem habet haec aqua fluens ad totum fluvium : qui quidem ordo vel situs
idem remanet in aqua succedente . Et ideo licet aqua materialiter praeter-
fluat, tamen secundum quod habet rationem loci , prout scilicet consideratur
in tali ordine et situ (ad) totum fluvium, non mutatur. Et per hoc similiter
accipere debemus quomodo extremitates corporum mobilium naturalium
sint locus, per respectum ad totum corpus sphaericum caeli ; quod habet
fixionem et immobilitatem propter immobilitatem centri et polorum. Sic,
igitur licet haec pars aeris quae continebat, vel haec pars aquae effluat et
moveatur inquantum est haec aqua ; tamen secundum quod habet haec aqua
rationem loci, scilicet situs et ordinis ad totum sphaericum caeli , semper
manet. Sicut etiam dicitur idem ignis manere quantum ad formam, licet
secundum materiam varietur consumptis et additis quibusdam lignis. "
This latter part of St. Thomas ' statement will come in for its share of criticism
by Ockham. See below, pp. 123-4.
299 Phil. Nat. , IV, 22 : "Similiter, et si quaelibet pars universi sit mobilis,
tamen universum non mutat locum suum secundum substantiam, et locus
sursum dicitur esse immobilis, quia concavum orbis Lunae semper est in
eadem distantia ad centrum, nec est in uno tempore plus sursum quam in
alio ; et sicut locus sursum est immobilis, ita locus deorsum. Est enim im-
mobilis, quia centrum immobilitatis perseverat, sic ergo in ordine ad uni-
versum habet locus immobilitatem. Et, ideo, si aliquid in terra quiesceret,
et vento flante moveretur, et tolleretur totus aer, qui est circa ipsum, non
diceretur mutare locum, quia eundem haberet ordinem ad totum universum
quem prius habuit, ergo. etc. Probat idem sic : quia licet te quiescente posset
moveri aer qui est iuxta te, vel aliquod corpus circumdans te, semper tamen
dicereris esse in eodem loco, quia semper es in eadem distantia ad centrum
et ad polos mundi qui sunt immobiles, et ideo per respectum ad ista locus
dicitur esse immobil (i)s."
Chapter Five. Concerning Place 123
300 Phil. Nat., IV, 22 : " Sed ist (i) non declarant immobilitatem loci,
quia si locus sit formali (ter) ordo, vel distantia ad centrum et ad polos mundi ,
ille ordo erit formaliter in corpore locante, et non in corpore locato, quia
si esset in corpore locato , sequeretur quod locus formaliter esset in corpore
locato formaliter, quod est contra Aristotelem. Si , ergo, ille ordo est in locante,
ergo mutato loca (n) te mutatur ordo, quia cum ordo sit quoddam accidens ,
secundum istum errorem, impossibile est ordinem illum esse immobilem
mutato habente eundem ordinem."
301 Ibid.
302 Ibid.
303 At this point the Tractatus. , p . 85, contains an additional passage :
"et si dicatur quod poli non sunt accidentia, sed substantiae contra :
9.
124 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
tunc in caelo esset aliqua pars caeli non mota localiter ; " which is not found in
Phil. Nat. The critical apparatus in Tractatus . , does not note this as an
omission in the Phil. Nat.
304 Phil. Nat. , IV, 22.
305 Phil. Nat. , IV, 22 : Alii magis veridici dicunt quod quando
aliquod tale corpus movetur circa quiescens, non manet idem locus numero,
sed (est) alius et alius numero, (et tamen idem locus) per aequivalentiam .
Ideo dicunt quod locus est alius, tamen dicunt quod locus est immobilis,
quia nullo modo potest moveri locus, sed quando superficies movetur ille
locus corrumpitur, et illa est relatio, quae corrumpitur subiecto illo moto
localiter." Ockham here appears to be examining Duns Scotus' theory.
See Scotus: Quaestiones in secundum librum sententiarum, dist. II , qu . 6:
"Dico ... locus habet immobilitatem oppositam motui locali omnino, et
incorruptibilitatem secundum aequivalentiam per comparationem ad motum
localem. Primum patet, quia si est aliquid modo mobile localiter, quantum-
cumque accipiatur per accidens , et ei assignari alius et alius locus , sicut
licet similitudo moveatur quasi accidentaliter per accidens, quia scilicet
in quarto vel in quinto gradu, quia primo corpus, et per hoc superficies,
et per hoc albedo, et per hoc similitudo ; tamen superficies , vel albedo, vel
similitudo, vere est, quando movetur in toto corpore in alio et alio loco.
Similiter tunc aliquid quiescens posset moveri localiter, nam quod habet
alium et alium locum successive, localiter movetur ; fixum autem posset
habere alium et alium locum continentem, si moveretur locus per accidens .
Secundo ... licet locus corrumpatur moto eius subiecto localiter, ita quod
moto aere localiter non manet in eo eadem ratio loci, quae prius ... Nec
eadem ratio loci potest manere in aqua succedente, quia idem accidens
numero non potest manere in duobus subiectis, tamen illa ratio loci succedens,
Chapter Five. Concerning Place 125
quae est alia a ratione praecedenti secundum veritatem, est eadem prae-
cedenti per aequivalentiam quantum ad motum localem, nam ita incom-
possibile est localem motum"" esse ab hoc loco in hunc locum, sicut si esset
omnino idem locus numero .' See also P. Duhem's article : "Le Mouvement
Absolu et le Mouvement Relatif, " (cinquième article) , in Revue de Philo-
sophie, vol . XII , March ( 1908 ) , where Duhem points out (p . 247 ) that
Ockham " se sépare nettement de Duns Scot au sujet de la nature même
du lieu. Pour le Docteur Subtil, le lieu est une certaine entité dont le fonde-
ment se trouve en la surface de contact du contenant au contenu ."
306 Phil . Nat. , IV, 22 : " Ista opinio est vera quantum ad hoc, quod ponit
quod est alius locus numero in tali casu quando corpus circumdans locatum
movetur localiter. Sed quantum ad hoc, quod ponit quod locus corrumpitur
per hoc, quod subiectum movetur localiter, fals(a) est, et procedit ex falsa
imaginatione, scilicet : quod locus sit quaedam relatio distincta realiter a
locante ... et ... talis relatio non est ultimum corporis continentis, ergo
non est locus .... " etc. For Ockham the category of relation (ad aliquid)
is similar to the category of quantity in this : that both quantitative and
relative terms are connotative, and in significative employ stand primarily
for either an individual substance, or an individual quality, and not for an
absolute and real relation or quantity . See the Tractatus de Praedestinatione ...
op. cit., the main thesis of which is concerned to prove that neither pre-
destination nor reprobation are real relations representing entities distinct
either from God or from the predestined or reprobated person . See also
the "Quaestio De Relatione attributed to William Ockham, " by Gaudens
E. Mohan, Franciscan Studies, vol. XI , no . 3 and 4 ( 1951 ) , which Tract,
although it appears to have been compiled by someone other than Ockham,
is nevertheless at one with his teachings on relation as found in Sent., I ,
dist. 30, qu . 3 ; Quodl . , VI , qu . 8—25 ; and VII , qu . 1—25 ; Logic. , ch . 49-55,
pp. 140-163 ; and Tractatus. , pp. 35-6. P. Boehner, in commenting on
the Tractatus de Praedestinatione ... (op. cit. , p . 50-51 ) , notes carefully
that "it is not easy to identify those Scholastics who were of this opinion
(i . e., that predestination and reprobation are real relations) . One thinks
of Scotus, but though Scotus admits that a relatio realis is a different entity
from the terms related , it is not certain, nor is it even probable, that he
admitted passive predestination or reprobation to be a real relation . For
he makes a clear distinction between relationes reales and relationes rationis,
and it seems that he did not consider even the relation of time or the prae-
dicamentum quando as a separate relation-entity. With some caution, we
dare to suggest that Walter Burleigh, a contemporary of Ockham, adhered
to the criticized opinion . At least he admits the category quando to be a
126 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
real entity that is added to the thing which is in time ." For more on Ockham's
theory of relation, see L. Baudry , " Apropos de la Théorie Occamiste de la
Relation, ” Archives d'Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen-Age. Vol. IX,
(1934) ; P. Doncoeur, "Le Nominalisme de Guillaume Occam," Revue
Néoscolastique, ( 1921 ) ; G. Martin, " Ist Ockhams Relationstheorie Nomina-
lismus ?" Franziskanische Studien, ( 1950), and by the same author, Wilhelm
von Ockham, (Walter de Gruyter and Co. , Berlin, 1949) .
307 For Ockham , the predication per se of an attribute to a subject
considers either an intrinsic element of the subject (which is a predication
per se primo modo) , or it is the predication of a property not expressed in the
essential definition, but follows from the essential definition (per se secundo
modo see above, p . 99, n . 241 , where "time" is predicated per se in this
second mode of " motion" ) .
A predicable per se is opposed to a predicable per accidens, in that the
predication per accidens may or may not belong to the subject. "Man is
rational" is a per se predication primo modo since " rational" is a part of the
definition of " man .'" 'Man is risible, " on the other hand, is a per se predication
secundo modo, since this predicate does not express an essential element
of the subject but expresses rather a property which follows necessarily
from the nature of man as a rational animal . See Logic . , ch. 37, pp. 96-98.
Chapter Five. Concerning Place 127
308 Phil . Nat. , IV, 22 : " Ideo, de virtute sermonis proprie loquendo debet
concedi quod locus est mobilis, quia nihil est in istis inferioribus generabilibus
et corruptibilibus quin sit mobile motu locali per se, vel per accidens, quia
omne quod est in istis inferioribus vel est substantia vel accidens. Si sit
substantia, sive sit materia, forma sive compositum, adhuc est mobile,
patet inductive. Si autem accidens , et suum subiectum sit mobile, est mobile
per accidens ; et ideo locus oportet esse mobile per se, vel per accidens . . .
Verumtamen pro intentione Philosophi est sciendum quod Philosophus
intendit dicere quod locus est immobilis per aequivalentiam , hoc est, quod
tantum valet locus ad salvandum omnia quae ponuntur de loco, ac si realiter
esset immobilis, et ita possunt in eodem loco sibi succedere diversa corpora
loco mutato, sicut possent si locus esset immobilis . Similiter est de omnibus
conditionibus propriis ipsius loci, quod ita possunt salvari sicut si locus
esset immobilis simpliciter, et nihil aliud intelligo per locum esse immobilem
secundum aequivalentiam . Unde quando aliquod corpus est secundum unam
partem in aliquo corpore ..." etc.
128 Ockham: Motion , Time and Place
by their relation to the center and periphery of the world, that is con-
sidered to be in one place, and at rest.
And this was the Philosopher's intent when he said that place is as a
transmutable vase ; because just as a vase, (it) can be transmuted , although
it remains immobile according to equivalence with respect to the water or
other contents of the vase.309
4.
Whereas, that is, the ship is constantly changing places with respect
to one system (although it is not in local motion insofar as these places
are equivalent to but one) , it is, with respect to another system, to all
intents and purposes, at rest. Ockham continues , italicising the disparity
which may obtain between position in respect of one system as compared
to another, by pointing out "yet another reason
309 Phil. Nat. , IV, 22 : "Et si dicatur quod omne quod continue est in
alio loco et alio, movetur localiter, dicendum quod non -- sed solum illud
corpus, quod taliter se habet quod esset in alio et alio loco, etiam si locus
esset immobilis, vere movetur localiter. Et ita non est in proposito. Nam
isto casu posito, si locus esset immobilis, continue esset in eodem loco de
facto, quamvis posset esse in alio. Et hoc intendit Philosophus quando
dicit .. etc. Cf. Aristotle, Physics, IV, 4. Further on (ibid. ) Ockham
writes : "... locus et vas non differunt nisi secundum superius et inferius,
nec aliam differentiam intendit Philosophus et Commentator dare inter
locum et vas . Et si dicatur, quod si vas esset proprie locus, vere, quando
aliquid moveretur ad motum vasis, vel non moveretur, vel manens in eodem
loco moveretur dicendum est, quod tale motum vere est in eodem loco
sibi proprio, quando tamen idem locus numero est in diversis per aequivalen-
tiam, hoc tantum valet ad hoc, quod corpus existens in eo moveatur, ac
si esset aliud et aliud vas, et alius et alius locus . Et ideo concedo , quod idem
manens in eodem loco proprio movetur, non tamen manet in eodem loco
communi, nec iste idem est unus numero in eodem loco num(ero) , sed mutat
locum ; et ideo existens in eo movetur localiter. Unde in talibus est magis
difficultas vocalis quam realis, et magis potest deduci ad inconveniens vulgo,
quam sapientibus . '
310 Phil. Nat. , IV. 22. Cf. Aristotle , op. cit. , IV. 4.
Chapter Five. Concerning Place 129
why the whole stream is said to be more the place of the ship than are some
of its parts. Because in the resting ship and the stream there is neither
augmented nor diminished, in the whole time, the distance between the
furthest parts of the stream and the ship itself, although the stream has, at
diverse times, diverse furthest parts. And this is not the case as regards
some part of the stream which was, previously, the place of the ship.311
Patently, this conception of systems within systems , as of contained
within containers, can be applied over and over : this water is at rest with
respect to its containing vase ; this vase, with respect to a containing
ship ; this ship, floating downstream , with respect to its proper place
while all of these subjects, contained and container alike, in respect
of the system provided by the relatively stable stream-banks are
in motion. Yet, when in this sequence of referential systems, the ultimate
system ―― the regular and majestic motion of the containing and un-
contained³12 heavens -— is approached, there is no fixed, absolutely im-
mobile, reference point. True, the motion of this outermost system is
uniform enough to provide the temporal yardstick by means of which
relatively difform " inferior" motions are numbered ; still, aside from
this normative regularity, the " superior" reference system is no way
privileged. The universe, as Ockham sees it, in respect of motion and
position, consists in a system of systems.313
et sic de aliis ; et tunc dico quod haec erit vera : hoc quadratum quiescit
sive caelum moveatur, sive non, dummodo non moveatur motu recto, sed
motu circulari. Et ita bene salvabitur quies illius corporis et aequalis distantia
ad caelum si quaelibet pars caeli moveatur circulariter, sicut si non moveren-
tur, et sicut si essent poli immobiles, sicut aliqui imaginantur, et ideo
immobilitas polorum nihil facit."
314 Phil. Nat., IV, 22 : “ Et si arguitur contra praedicta quod locus non
potest moveri , quia tunc locus esset locatus dicendum quod locus vere
movetur, et vere est in loco. Aer enim vere est locus alicuius, et tamen vere
est in loco, sicut qui continentur ab alio, non tamen est in loco per ultimas
partes contiguas locato, sicut non continetur ab alio manentibus illis partibus
quibus illae partes ultimae, et omnes partes ultimae contiguantur alteri ,
sed per eas continent, et non continentur, et hoc sufficit ad intentionem
Philosophi . "
Chapter Five. Concerning Place 131
some resting body and "runs together", and drains off, those parts
of the air which constituted the proper place of the located. In this
way place is moved , in that lacking a content it is no longer a place, but is
itself, now, in a place. In the second way, the proper place of some
body does not become " conjoined" , but retains its original properties
excepting only that it now possesses a content differing from the original
- i. e., it becomes the furthest limit of the containing body in respect
to another contained. In the first way, place was moved in that it sur-
rendered its content to return to the undifferentiated mass of the
continent ; in the second way, place was moved in that it surrendered
one content for another.315
315 Phil. Nat., IV, 22 : " Et si dicatur quod omne quod movetur requirit
aliquem locum in quem recipitur, sed locus non movetur per partes non
contiguas corporis continentis et movetur per partes contiguas contento,
per quas est locus, ergo per istas vere acquiret locum alium, et ita locus
ex ea parte qua est locus vere in loco esset - dicendum quod non omne
quod movetur, acquirit alium locum quantum ad omnes partes suas, et
ideo non movetur nisi quantum ad suas ultimas partes quibus contiguatur
contento, quibus acquirit alium locum. Sed potest moveri dupliciter per
istas partes: quia aliquando tales partes per hoc, quod moventur coniungun-
tur localiter ut cum pr(i)mo partes aeris concurrunt quando auferentur
a corpore quandoque circumdabant ; aliquando vero partes non coniunguntur,
sed remanentes semper aequaliter distant. In primo casu partes istae ultimae
quae primo erant contiguae locato, moventur, ut sint in alio loco et non
ut fiant locus alterius ; quia ex hoc ipso, quod coniunguntur, non sunt locus
quia nihil ab ipsis continetur. In secundo casu , non moventur partes istae,
ut sint in alio loco, sed ut sint locus alterius ; sicut, si aer continue fluat a
ligno, cuius est primo locus, ad lapidem contiguum illi ligno, movetur, ut
sit locus lapidis qui prius est locus ligni, et e converso."
132 Conclusion
or immobile, provided that that which is at the middle of the earth , always,
as concerns its furthest parts, is equidistant from the superior parts of
the heavens, and so with other (located) things. And , therefore, this identity
of place through equivalence is always attended , in inferior things, by equality
of distance with respect to the superior and inferior parts of the heavens. 316
CONCLUSION
I.
any such separate reality, or any theory of " inherence " in substances,
insisting that these categories signify nothing other than substances
and/or qualities, to which they are reducible by analysis or definition .
To hold, however, that the primary subject matter of physics con-
sists in individual determinate substances, must not be misconstrued
as an affirmation that only the material exists. Ockham is not blind
to the existence in experience of such things as patterns, functions and
relations of material structures and systems of such structures. He will ,
however, flatly reject any possibility that such patterns, functions, and
relations are themselves active in either their own actualization, or in the
actualization of anything else in the natural order. Ockham's conception
of natural process, as we have seen, leaves no room for the agency of
"occult" forces.
For Ockham, there is no question but that the plurality and variety
of existential modes displayed in the primary subject matter are entirely
-- not
real and irreducible components of the actual world we inhabit
symbolic and " inferior" concretions, or embodied " reflections " of
some more homogeneous, more perfect, supra-sensible substance. The
experienced orders and connections obtaining in the natural realm are
contingent relations-not material exemplifications of a pre - determined
and unified pattern of logically necessary dependencies.
In sum, the world which Ockham envisions as providing the raw
material for the physicist's inquiries is characterized by modal plurality
and real contingency. Despite the eminent "logiscibility" of its orders
and connections, it is a realm which yet defies the prior statement
of any metaphysical principle from which these, and other (yet un-
noted) orders and connections can be derived by deductive means.
Ockham's metaphysic does not provide a " basis" for his natural
philosophy in the sense that it proffers a set of substantive principles
serving to " save", in ultimate terms, the minutiae and flux of physical
occasions. The principles affirmed are offered neither as props, nor
alternates, for the specific findings accessible to the physical investigator.
Science, indeed, can get along quite nicely without metaphysic, while
it is hardly possible for the reverse to be true. Nor can Ockham's general
view of nature be regarded as the result of some highly esoteric form
of knowing. He draws no line between the inductive procedures of
common-sense and physics on the one hand , and those of metaphysic
on the other. The general account of things which he endorses, appears
to us as the broadest possible extracts from knowledge gleaned in the
course of everyday traffic with the finite beings in which the natural
Conclusion 135
2.
3.
4.
arguing that local motion does not involve the production of any new
entity, but consists solely in the fact that the mobile body is continuously
in successive places (or successive parts of the medium) . He argues further,
that the moving agent, or the body which pushes the patient body, is the
sole and immediate cause of the movement, merely by the fact that it is
itself in motion ; so that no new entity is produced in the process. In
the case of alterative motion, however, Ockham concedes that the agent
generates the acquired quality in the patient, so that in the instance
of alterative motion something new is produced. This is, of course, in
consonance with his own doctrine that qualities are real (particular)
entities. In the case of augmentative motion, on the other hand, Ockham
admits no new production , or new entity, and analyzes augmentation
in terms of the local motion of the parts of the augmented body. The
main burden of his whole discussion is that of disposing of fictive entities
such as "motion" supposedly acquired by the moved body, or such as the
"quantity" supposedly acquired by the augmented body and his
arguments illustrate concretely his technique for reducing scientific
abstractions to elements of experience .
Now Ockham defines motion as " mobile quod movetur " so that there
is involved the existence of immediate places through which the body
moves. The problem of " motion" , therefore (i. e. , local motion) , involves
the concept of place and that of time . Since Ockham's definition of
local motion involves the concept of " place" as that to which the moved
body has successively different relations, the problem naturally arises
as to what "place" is. Now the absolutists (much like the later New-
tonians) , conceived place as a reality distinct from bodies, a pure di-
mensionality in which bodies are found , and through which bodies move ,
but which is itself immaterial and unmoved . Ockham, on the contrary,
stuck rigidly to Aristotle's definition , whereby the "place" of a thing is
that body which surrounds it and whose inner parts touch the thing said
to be in place. Ockham rejects the theory that the place of a thing is
the " space" (or pure dimensionality) of the surrounding body, because
no such immaterial space or dimensionality exists. So he has to concede
that any place , being itself a body, is movable. In consequence , Ockham's
definition of local motion turns out to be a purely relativistic one -
all we can say, is that a body, B, is moved relatively to the surrounding
body (or medium), and it is always possible (or even certain) that this
surrounding body is itself moved in relation to the body which surrounds
it, and so on out to the outermost sphere which has no place and cannot,
therefore, be said either to be moved or to be at rest. Throughout the
Conclusion 143
middle ages there was controversy about the outer sphere , or about
the " place of the world," some holding that the outer sphere, being a
body, must be capable of being moved as a whole in a rectilinear manner ;
but to make this intelligible, they had to assume something through
which it would thus be moved . Consequently, they assumed an infinite
immaterial "space" outside the world , in relation to which the world
could be moved, and in relation to which it could be said to remain
at rest . Ockham, as we have seen, will have none of this : assuming that
there is no corporeal body outside the outer sphere, then, it is meaning-
less to say that the world is in motion or at rest . That is, Ockham denies
"absolute motion " as a consequence of denying " absolute space. "
Since, however, the physicist is concerned to treat of all bodies
in their movements, as a connected system, he has to choose a common
standard frame of reference for his descriptions of the movements of
bodies. And since the outermost (and largest) body is the " place” of
all the inner bodies, it conveniently serves as our spatial frame of re-
ference. Hence, Ockham treats it as the body at rest (i. e . , the body not
displaced as a whole, though it may rotate) , and he treats the internal
dimensions of the sphere as a constant stable " theatre" in which all
movements of inferior bodies occur. It is convenient to describe the
motions of inferior bodies as movements through this dimensionality
of "space" contained by the outer sphere, as if a projectile traversed
so much pure distance, instead of traversing so much corporeal air.
Ockham certainly grants this convenience, and the legitimacy, for
science, of using this fictive " space" as a frame of reference for the
description of motions. But he constantly warns against the danger of
transforming this conceptual instrument of measurement into an im-
material reality supposedly underlying the realm of corporeal bodies.
For this would be to hypostatize, into a metaphysical concept , a purely
logical construction ; an error of the same order as that of hypostatizing
the numbers by which we count things, into eternal objects supposedly
inhering in the things counted.
Ockham treats of time in an entirely similar manner. Time, for
Ockham , is the measure of motion with respect to a before and after.
Since motion, however, is nothing other than a body moved , time is a
measure of body, or it is body qua measured with respect to before and
after. Once again Ockham eliminates abstract entities . Although,
however, the time of a particular motion (or body qua moved ) may
be said to be nothing other than the body itself in its successive positions ,
we cannot measure this time except by making comparison with some
144 Conclusion
other body in motion (or some other time) in which case we have a
timed time, and a timing time. This presents a dilemma : which time
shall we choose to be the timing time, and which one the timed time ?
So we select, with Ockham, one body in motion (i. e. , in motion relative
to all other bodies) as the standard timing time i. e., as a universal
clock. The rotation (relative to the earth) of the sphere of the fixed
stars is chosen, because it makes the best and most useful clock ; the
most useful, because its circular path is geometrically regular , and being
larger than any other path, it is more easily divided into small segments
(minutes and seconds) . We then synchronize mechanical clocks with
the sidereal clock, and say that these clocks measure " the flow of time ."
This, so far as Ockham is concerned , is fine for convenience of speech
and of measurement ; but, he warns, let us not be led into thinking that
there is some even-flowing immaterial entity called "Time", which is
measured by our sidereal clock . On the contrary, for Ockham, the
sidereal clock is time, for it is itself the unmeasured measure of all
measurable times. Thus, if one, as a metaphysician, were to ask what
time, place and motion are, Ockham would suffer but one answer they
are all movable bodies, tangible observable things in our experience ,
given privileged functions in our calculations and measurements . For
convenience, it is quite allright to talk about time and space as if they
were immaterial absolutes to which movements of bodies are referred ;
but when we track them down , in their actual use, we find that they are
bodies, like other bodies, to which we have given privileged functions
for the measurement of the movements of other bodies.
I.
PRIMARY SOURCES
145
146 Bibliography
3.
SECONDARY SOURCES
Abbagnano, N.: Guglielmo di Ockham (Lanciano, 1931 ) .
Baudry, L.: "Les Rapports de Guillaume d'Occam et de Walter Burleigh,"
Archives d'histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen-âge, IX ( 1934) , 155 sqq.
Guillaume d'Occam, Tome I (Paris, 1950) .
- "A propos de la théorie occamiste de la relation, " Archives d'histoire
doctrinale et littéraire du moyen-âge , IX ( 1934) , 199 sqq .
Boehner, P.: " Scotus ' Teachings According to Ockham, " Franciscan Studies
VI ( 1946) , 100 sqq and 362 sqq.
Medieval Logic (Manchester, 1952).
- "The Notitia Intuitiva of Non-existents According to William Ockham , "
Traditio I, ( 1943 ) , 223 sqq.
"Ockham's Theory of Signification, " Franciscan Studies, VI ( 1946) ,
143 sqq.
"in propria causa . A. Reply to Professor Pegis , " Franciscan Studies V,
(1945), 37 sqq.
"Ockham's Theory of Supposition and the Notion of Truth, " Franciscan
Studies VI ( 1946) , 261 sqq .
- "The Realistic Conceptualism of William Ockham , " Traditio IV ( 1946) ,
307 sqq.
"Ockham's Theory of Truth, " Franciscan Studies V ( 1945) , 138 sqq .
"The Metaphysics of William Ockham , " Review of Metaphysics, 1 no. 4
(1948) .
Borchert , F .: “Die Lehre von der Bewegung bei Nicolaus Oresme , ” Beiträge
Zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters , xxi , 3 (1934) .
Buescher, G.: The Eucharistic Teaching of William of Ockham ( St. Bona-
venture, N. Y. , 1950) .
Burns, C. D .: "William of Ockham on Universals," Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, N. S. 14 ( 1914) , 76 sqq.
"Ockham's Razor, " Mind, Oct. ( 1915) , 508 sqq .
"William of Ockham on Continuity, " Mind, Oct. ( 1916) , 508 sqq .
Crombie, R. C.: Grosseteste and Experimental Science (Oxford, 1953) .
DeWulf, M.: Histoire de la Philosophie Médiévale, Tome Troisième (Louvain-
Paris, 1947).
Bibliography 147
"Avempace and Galileo, " Journal of the History of Ideas XII , no. 2 and 3
(1951 ) , 163 sqq., 375 sqq .
- "Laws of Motion in Medieval Physics," The Scientific Monthly, vol.
LXXII , no. 1 ( 1951 ) , 18 sqq.
Moser, S.: " Grundbegriff der Naturphilosophie bei Wilhelm von Ockham,"
Philosophie und Grenzwissenschaften , IV, no . 2 and 3 ( 1932) .
Pegis, A. C .: "Concerning William of Ockham , " Traditio II ( 1944) , 465 sqq.
"Some Recent Interpretations of Ockham, " Speculum 23 ( 1948) , 452 sqq .
Siebeck, H .: " Ockhams Erkenntnislehre in ihrer historischen Stellung,"
Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie X, no. 3 ( 1897) , 317 sqq.
Thorburn , W. M.: "Occam's Razor, " Mind, April ( 1915 ) , 287 sqq .
"The Myth of Occam's Razor, " Mind, July ( 1918) , 345 sqq.
Townsend, W. J .: The Great Schoolmen of the Middle Ages ( Stechert, 1920).
Tornay, S. C.: Ockham (La Salle, Illinois, 1938) .
Überweg-Geyer : Geschichte der Philosophie, (Basel, 1951 ) , vol . II .
Webering, D .: Theory of Demonstration According to William Ockham ( St.
Bonaventure, New York, 1953) .
ANALYTICAL INDEX
A C
"Absolute" Theory, theorists, 3 , 11, Causality 62, 112
12, 13, 24ff. , 35 , 36ff. , 54, 66, 73 , Chatton, Walter 85
91ff., 100, 104, 107ff., 113ff. , Cognitions, first and second 16ff.
133, esp. 135ff. Commentator, The see Averroes
Action-at-a-distance 52 Conceptualism 19, 20
Aegidius Romanus 12, 56, 87 Condensation, motions of 62ff.
Albertus Magnus 56, 86 "Container", common and proper
Aquinas, St. Thomas 7, 8, 9, 10, II , 118ff.
40, 56, 66, 87 , 104, 109, 121f. "Contrary disposition" 58ff.
Aristotle 2, 3, 7 , 10, 11 , 12, 13 , 19, "Correspondence theory of truth"
24, 25, 28, 34, 40, 43, 51 , 52, 54, 19, 20
55, 65, 66, 67, 69, 81 , 91 , 92, 94, Crombie, A. C. 36
95, 96, 97, 98 , 100, 102 , 103, 104, D
105, 106, 107, 109, 110, 112, 113, Damascene, St. John 74
114, 115, 116, 117, 118, 119, 120, Demonstration , strict 23
121 , 123 , 126, 127, 128, 129, 130, de Wulf, M. 70
131, 132, 139, 142 Doncoeur, P. 62, 84, 126
Augustine, St. 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11 , 139,
Duhem, P. 2, 36, 55 , 62 , 84, 125
140
Autrecourt, Nicholas of, 15, 52 Dumbleton, John 91
Duns Scotus, see Scotus
Avempace 55ff., 104
Averroes 55ff. , 109 , 110, 114 , 115 Dynamics 13, 55ff., 62
118, 120, 129, 131 E
Equivocation, equivocations 16, 43 ,
B 105, 108
Bacon, Roger 56
Essential, differentia 21
Baudry, L. 4, 5 , 12 , 126 Eucharist 133
Birch, T. B. I
"Everything-that-is-moved prin-
Boehner, P. 1 , 2 , 4, 14, 15 , 16, 17, ciple" 54ff., 62 , 81ff.
19, 20, 23 , 90, 100, 115, 126
Borchert , E. 36 F
Bradwardine, Thomas 62, 91 "figure of speech fallacy" 42, 43
Buescher, G. 66 Fluxus formae 36
Buridan, John 52, 62 forma fluens II , 36, 41 , 91 , 93
Burleigh, Walter 12, 125 Franciscus de Marchia 52 , 53
Burns, C. D. 15, 27. 38 Fuchs, O. 14
149
150 Analytical Index
G N
Giles of Rome , see Aegidius Ro- "natural signs " 15, 16, 135
manus Newtonians , 142
Gilson , E. 2 , 18 , 23 , 24
Godfrey of Fontaines 85 0
"Ockham's Razor" see " principle
H of economy"
Ockham's writings, order of 4ff.
Henry of Ghent 88
Hervaeus Natalis 88
P
Hochstetter, E. 16, 19, 20, 23 , 62
Hume, David, " humean, " 2, 15 Pegis , A. C. 16, 24
Peter Damiani 90
Peter John Olivi 56
I Peter Lombard 53 , 83
Inertia, law of 62 Petrus Aureoli 89, 90
intension and remission 8off. , 83ff. Petrus Hispanus 17
intelligible species 8 Philosopher, The see Aristotle
Intelligences 47 Place of the world 143
Intentions, see Terms Plato 6
Plotinus 6
J "poles of the world ” 122ff.
Joannes Philoponus 55 predication, contingent and neces-
John of Jandun 56 sary 74; per se primo modo, per se
secundo modo 99ff. , 126 ; per se
and per accidens 126
K
Primum Mobile 93 , 99ff., 105ff.,
kinematics 13 , 56ff. , 62 , 91
142, 143
Kugler, L. 19 Principle of Economy 27 , 93 , 114
L
Q
Lindsay, J. 18, 20, 23 Quandeitas II
"quiddity," "quiddities" 8, 10
M
Maier, A. 36, 52 , 53 , 57 , 81 , 83 , 85, R
86, 87, 88, 89 "rarefaction, " motions of 62ff.
Manser, G. 62 Relations 123ff. , esp . 125 , 133 , 137
Martin, G. 126 and esp . 138
mensura permanentium 96 Richard of Middleton 87
mensura successivorum 96 Ritter, H. 18
Michalski, K. 2 S
Mind-world chasm 12 Scotus, John Duns 9, 10, 11 , 36, 56,
Mohan, G. E. 1 , 125 124, 125, 140, 141
Moody, E. A. 1 , 2 , 12 , 14 , 15 , 16, sensible species 8
19, 22, 23 , 32, 42 , 52 , 54 , 55, 56, Siger de Brabant 56
62, 66, 81 , 91 signification 15ff.
Moser, S. 25, 62 Stagirite, The see Aristotle
Motus, large, stricte 25 ff. Statements, analytic 10, 12 ; con-
mutatio subita 24ff. tingent 10, 11 ; probable 24
Analytical Index 151
Theology Series
LIGNANIE '
3. Peter Aureoli, Scriptum super Primum Sententiarum, edit. E. M.
Buytaert, vol. I : Prologue and Distinction I , 1953. $ 5.00 . Vol. II :
Distinctions II - VIII , 1956. $ 8.50 . Vol. III - VIII in preparation.