IV Unit
IV Unit
IV Unit
Unit-IV
Ramesh Arjun
LEGAL RIGHTS
Wrongs
B
efore attempting to define a right, however, it is necessary to define two
other terms which are closely connected with it, namely, wrong and
duty.
A wrong is simply a wrong act-an act contrary to the rule of right and
justice.
A synonym of it is injury, in its true and primary sense of injuria
In the secondary sense of harm or damage whether rightful or
wrongful, and whether inflicted by human agency or not.
There are two kinds of Wrongs or injuries, those are either moral or
legal.
A moral or natural wrong is an act which is morally or naturally
wrong, being contrary to the rule of natural justice.
A legal wrong is an act which is legally wrong, being contrary to the
rule of legal justice and violation of the law.
It is an act which is authoritatively determined to be wrong by a rule
of law, and is therefore treated as a wrong in and for the purposes of
the administration of justice by the state.
a moral wrong may or may not be a wrong in law.
Every legal wrong is punished.
Duties
A duty is roughly speaking an act which one ought to do,
An act the opposite of which would be a wrong.
The duty and the act, however, are not strictly identical.
2
satisfaction of it does them harm. Here there is clearly a moral though not a legal
duty. Finally, there is both a moral and a legal duty not to steal.
When the law recognizes an act as a duty, it commonly enforces the
performance of it, or punishes the disregard of it.
But this sanction of legal force is an exceptional cases absent.
A duty is legal because it is legally recognized, not necessarily
because it is legally enforced or sanctioned.
Rights
We have seen that in the strict sense a duty is something owed by one person to
another. The master has a right against his servant, the parent against his child and
so on. Rights are concerned with interests, and indeed have been defined as
interests protected by rules of right, that is by moral or legal rules.
Yet rights and interests are not identical.
Interests are things which are to a man’s advantage.
He has an interest in his freedom or his reputation.
His rights to these, if he has such rights, protect the interests, which
accordingly from the subject of his rights but are different from them.
To say he has an interest in his reputation means that it is to his advantage to
enjoy a good name;
To say he has a right to this is to imply that others ought not to take this
from him.
Rights like wrongs and duties are either moral or legal.
A moral or natural right is an interest recognized and protected by a rule of
morality.
An interest the violation of which would be a moral wrong, and respect for
which is a moral duty.
4
Just as there are imperfect and unenforceable legal duties, so there are
imperfect and unenforceable legal rights.
The question has been debated whether rights and duties are necessarily
correlative.
According to one view, there can be no right without a corresponding duty, or duty
without a corresponding right any more than there can be a husband without a
wife, or a father without a child. For on this view every duty must be a duty
towards some person or persons, in whom therefore, a correlative right is vested.
And conversely every right must be a right against some person or persons, upon
whom, therefore a correlative duty is imposed.
Every right or duty involves a bond of legal obligation by which two or
more persons are bound together.
There can therefore be no duty unless there is someone to whom it is due;
There can be no right unless there is someone from whom it is claimed;
and there can be no wrong unless there is someone who is wronged, that is
to say, whose right has been violated.
The characteristics of a legal right
Every legal right has the five following characteristics
1. It is vested in a person who may be distinguished as the owner of the right,
the subject of it, the person entitled, or the person of inherence.
2. It avails against a person, upon whom lies the correlative duty. He may be
distinguished as the person bound, or as the subject of the duty or as the
person of incidence.
3. It obliges the person bound to an act or omission in favour of the person
entitled. This may be termed the content of the right.
4. The act or omission relates to something which may be termed the object or
subject matter of the right.
6
5. Every legal right has a title, that is to say, certain facts or events by reason of
which the right has become vested in its owner.
Thus if A buys a piece of land from B, A is the subject or owner of the right
so acquired.
The persons bound by the correlative duty are persons in general, for a right
of this kind avails against all the world.
The content of the right consists in non-interference with the purchaser’s
exclusive use of the land.
The object or subject matter of the right is the land.
And finally the title of the right is the conveyance by which it was acquired
from its former owner.
Every right, therefore, involves a threefold relation in which the owner of it stands.
i. It is a right against some person or persons.
ii. It is a right to some act or omission of such person or persons
iii. It is a right over or to some thing to which that act or omission relates.
We cannot say that it belongs to no one for the reasons already indicated.
We must say that it is presently owned by the unborn person, but that his
ownership is contingent on his birth.
A right, as we have said, serves to protect an interest;
And the object of the right is the thing in which the owner has this interest.
Legal rights in a wider sense of the term (Hohfeld’s)
We have confined our attention to legal rights in the strictest sense in which they
constitute the correlatives of legal duties. We must now consider the wider use of
the term, according to which rights, do not necessarily correspond with duties. In
this generic sense a legal right may be defined as any advantage or benefit
conferred upon a person by a rule of law.
Of rights in this sense there are four distinct kinds. These are
1. Rights (in the strict sense)
2. Liberties
3. Powers and
4. Immunities.
Each of these has its correlative, namely
1. Duties
2. No-rights
3. Liabilities and
4. Disabilities
The four pairs of correlatives may be arranged in the following table, the
correlatives being obtained by reading downwards.
8
As we shall see, the four concepts within each rectangle are intimately related to
each other, whereas there is not the same relationship between the concepts in the
one rectangle and the concepts in the other rectangle.
Having already sufficiently considered rights and their correlative duties, we shall
now deal briefly with the others.
1. Liberties and No-rights-
Just as my legal rights are the benefits which I derive from legal
duties imposed upon other persons,
so my legal liberties are the benefits which I derive from the absence
of legal duties imposed upon myself.
They are the various forms assumed by the interest which I have in
doing as I please. They are the things which I may do without being
prevented by the law.
It is clear that the term right is often used in a wide sense to include
such liberty.
I have a right (that is to say, I am at liberty) to do as I please with my
own;
But I have no right and am not at liberty to interfere with what is
another’s.
I have a right to express my opinions on public affairs, but I have no
right to publish a defamatory or seditious libel.
9
If “A” brought a watch from “B”, there is a positive legal duty on the part of B to
hand over the watch to B if price of watch has already been paid. If A is the owner
of a house in a locality then there is a negative legal duty on the other persons not
to disturb A in peaceful enjoyment of land.
My right to the peaceable occupation of my farm is in rem, for all the world
is under a duty towards me not to interfere with it. But if I grant a lease of the farm
to a tenant, my right to receive the rent from him is in personam, for it avails
exclusively against the tenant himself. A right in rem, then, is an interest protected
against the world at large, a right in personam is an interest protected solely against
determinate individuals. Almost all rights in rem are negative, and most rights
in personam are positive, though in a few exceptional cases they are negative.
The distinction lies in the fact that proprietary rights are valuable, and
personal right are not. The former are those which are worth money; the latter
are those that are worth none. The former are the elements of man’s wealth; the
latter are merely elements in his well-being.
women, but not the personal rights and duties existing between her and her
husband.
Thus the right of a landowner may be subject to, and limited by, that of a
tenant to the temporary use of the property.
(6) Principal and accessory rights. These rights are also known as
antecedent and remedial right, and primary and accessory right. Pollock calls them
substantive and objective right. When a right has its own independent existence, it
is called principal right. When some other right is associated with principal right
then so associated right is called accessory right. This accessory right does not
enjoy an independent existence, generally violation of former, bring accessory
right into function. As for example, A has principal right that no one should
interfere in his peaceful enjoyment of premises, in case anybody does so A can
invoke his right to receive damages, which is an accessory or remedial right.
This concept is based on the maxim accessorium soquitur principle, that is the
accessory right follows the principal.
(8) Legal and equitable rights in England there were formerly two systems
of law, administered respectively in the courts of common law and the Court of
Chancery. These were to a considerable extent discordant. One of the results of this
discordance was the establishment of a distinction between two classes of rights,
distinguishable as legal and equitable. Legal rights are those which were
recognized by the courts of common law. Equitable rights (otherwise called
equities) are those which were recognized solely in the Court of Chancery.
Although all rights, whether legal or equitable, now obtain legal recognition in
all courts, the distinction is still of importance. The methods of their creation and
disposition are different. A legal mortgage of land must be created by deed, but an
equitable mortgage may be created by a written agreement or by a mere deposit of
title-deeds.
18
Equitable rights have a more precarious existence than legal rights. Where
there are two inconsistent legal rights claimed adversely by different persons over
the same thing, the first in time generally prevails. A similar rule applies, in
general, to the competition of two inconsistent equitable rights . But when a legal
and an equitable rights conflict, the legal will prevail over and destroy the
equitable , even though subsequent to it in origin, provided that the owner of the
legal right acquired it for value and without notice of the prior equity. As between
a prior equitable mortgage, for example , and a subsequent legal mortgage
,preference will be given to the latter. The maxim is :Where there are equal
equities, the law will prevail.
Ownership
Ownership denotes the relation between a person and an object forming the
subject-matter of his ownership. It consists in a complex of rights, all of which are
rights in rem, being good against all the world and not merely against specific
persons. Though in certain situations some of these rights may be absent, the
normal case of ownership can be expected to exhibit the following incidents.
First, the owner will have a right to possess the thing which he owns.
He may not necessarily have possession,
For he may have been wrongfully deprived of it or may have
voluntarily divested himself of it.
If A’s watch is stolen by B, the latter has possession but the former remains the
owner with an immediate right to possession. If A lends his watch for hire to C, A
now had neither possession nor an immediate right to possess. He is still the
owner, however, for he retains a reversionary interest in the watch, i, e., a right to
repossess it on the termination of the period of hire; And though he lacks in
English law the remedies available to a possessor for wrongful interference, he is
protected by a remedy in the form of an action on the case against interference
damaging his reversionary interest.
o Secondly, the owner normally has the right to use and enjoy the thing
owned:
o The right to manage it, i.e., the right to decide how it shall be used;
o And the right to the income from it.
o Whereas the right to possess is a right in the strict sense, these rights
are in fact liberties:
20
o The owner has a liberty to use the thing i.e., He is under no duty not to
use it, in contrast with others who are under a duty not to use or
interfere with it.
o Thirdly, the owner has the right to consume, destroy or alienate the
thing.
o The rights to consume and destroy are straight-forward liberties.
o The right to alienate, i.c., the right to transfer his rights over the object
to another, involves the existence of power.
o Fourthly, ownership has the characteristic of being indeterminate in
duration.
o The position of an owner differs from that of a non-owner in
possession in that the latter’s interest is subject to be determined at
some future set point, whereas the interest of the owner can endure
theoretically forever.
o The interest of a bailee or lessee comes to an end when the period of
hire or of the lease determines;
o The owner’s interest is perpetual, being determined neither by any set
point nor by the owner’s death,
o Because the property owned can descend to the owner’s heir or next-
of-kin,
o and if he had sold the property prior to his death, then the new
owner’s interest would continue unaffected by the previous owner’s
death.
Fifthly, ownership has a residuary character.
residual rights, i.c., the rights remaining when all these lesser rights remaining
when all these lesser rights have been given away.
Thus he may have a profit a prendre to catch and take fish from A’s land; a
debt of Rs.100 owing him from B; shares in C Co. Ltd, various patents, copyrights
and other industrial property; and an interest in various trust funds.
Yet none of these is a material or physical thing. They are in fact nothing
other than rights:
In the first place many rights, such as the right of free speech or of
reputation, do not appear to be fit subjects of ownership at all:
a man does not own a right to his reputation; that is a right which he
has.
22
It could provide that the air and the sea might be owned, sold, bought,
rented and so forth, as may be done with the subsoil of the ocean:
Effective control is no longer impossible with regard to these
elements, and it would be perfectly feasible to allow one man to
charge another for breathing the air or crossing the sea.
Even such objects as the sun, which, we may guess, will never be
subject to human control, are not things to which the notion of
ownership is completely inappropriate.
A system of law under which the king owned the sun and was entitled to
charge a fee from those who benefited from its rays would be perfectly
possible.
Thirdly, the thing may fall into a man’s ownership without any human act,
as would be the case if a piece of land were to break off from an island in a river
and attach itself to my land on the opposite bank.
individual power, while at the same time much that was formerly in private hands
has been transferred to public ownership.
But the public ownership of such things as the railways, airlines, coal
mines and so on is not necessarily a satisfactory solution to the problem.
For in the first place, whether in private or public hands, they must still be
managed, and the managers may have all or much of the power formerly possessed
by the previous owners.
In any case, the development of the trust on the one hand and the limited
company on the other, has brought about a division between management and
ownership, resulting in power being in reality in the hands of the former rather than
the latter.
Classification of Ownership
In case the ownership vested in the single person only it is called sole
ownership. Ownership vested in more than one person is called co-ownership.
Partnership, trust, coparcenary are example of co-ownership. In co-ownership the
subject matter of the ownership is common. All the co-owners enjoy the common
right over the subject. Tenants in common and joint tenants are co-owners of the
tenancy. The co-owner may become sole owner after having their respective share
from the subject matter.
Partners, for example, are co-owners of the chattels which constitute their stock-in-
trade, of the lease of the premises on which their business is conducted, and of the
debts owing to them by their customers. It is not correct to say that property owned
25
Each partner is entitled to the whole sum, just as each would owe to the bank the
whole of the firm’s overdraft. The several ownership of a part is a different thing
from the co-ownership of the whole. So soon as each of two co-owners begins to
own a part of the thing instead of the whole of it, the co-ownership has been
dissolved into sole ownership by the process known as partition. Co-ownership
involves the undivided integrity of what is owned.
For example, a landowner wishing to provide for his sons. A and B, may
constitute them co-owners of it. Alternatively he might divide the land into two
parts, giving one part to each as sole owner. A third method would be to convey
the land to A for life and thereafter to B in fee simple. In this case neither son
26
becomes sole owner of a separate estate or interest in the land; nor would they be
co-owners. Each is sole owner of a separate estate or interest in the land. A has a
life estate, which is vested in possession; B has a fee simple remainder vested, not
in possession, but in interest. The value of this third method is that it enables the
owners to make provision for both sons, while ensuring that the land remains
intact.
As for example if X takes the property in trust for Y, then X is the trustee of
the property and B beneficiary of the property. Here X is having trust ownership
while B is enjoying the beneficial ownership. Law imposes certain limitations on
the person having trust ownership.
f. Both trust ownership and beneficial ownerships different from each other,
one can be transferred or encumbered without affecting other.
a. In case the trustee sells the trust property to the bonafide purchase for a
value without knowledge of trust then he will get a good title.
b. A trustee is personally liable for contracts entered into in relation to the trust
property.
c. Sometime trust is created by an unilateral act, a person may become bound
by a trust by his conduct.
d. Beneficiary of a trust can take remedial action in case of breach of trust even
if he is not a party to the creation for the trust.
4. Legal and equitable ownership
Closely connected but not identical with the distinction between trust and
beneficial ownership is that between legal and equitable ownership. One person
may be the legal and another the equitable owner of the same thing or the same
right at the same time. Legal ownership is that which has its origin in the rules of
the common law, while equitable ownership is that which proceeds from rules of
equity divergent from the common law. The courts of common law refused to
recognize equitable ownership, and denied that the equitable owner was an owner
at all.
Salmond says, ownership is either vested or contingent. It is vested when the title
of the owner is already perfect. It is contingent when his title is yet imperfect, but
is capabl3 of becoming perfect on the fulfillment of some condition. In the former
the ownership is absolute while in the latter it is conditional.
If X gives his car in gift to Y then Y acquires vested interest in the property. If X
gives car in gift to Y provided he gets a driving license within 10 days, here Y has
contingent interest in the car. In case he gets license within given period then the
contingent interest will become vested interest.
POSSESSION
Possession in fact
Things not in any way amenable to human control cannot from the subject-matter
of possession.
A man cannot be said to possess for example the sun, the moon or the stars. Now
to say that something is under my control is not to assert that I am continuously
exercising control over it. I can have a thing in my control without actually holding
or using it at every given moment of time. In the ordinary sense of the word, I
retain possession of my coat even if I take it off and put it down beside me; and I
continue in possession of it even though I fall asleep.
Now whether in any given case I can be said to have sufficient control
(whether actual or potential) to be in possession of an object will depend on a
variety of factors. Possession of small objects may involve holding them or else
having them near to hand; a fairly ungovernable object such as a wild animal is
capable of being possessed by being confined in a cage, without the possessor’s
being able to lay hold of it himself; a large or immovable object, such as a ship
or a house, could be said to remain in my possession even though I am miles
away and able to exercise very little control, if any.
32
without such exclusion are odd exceptions; the example of the man on the island is
an unusual and marginal situation.
So far no distinction has been made between the mental and physical aspects
of possession. Many jurists have distinguished two such elements. Salmond
considered that possession consisted of a corpus possessionis and an animus
possidendi. The former, he thought, comprised both the power to use the thing
possessed and the existence of grounds for the expectation that the possessor’s
use will not be interfered with. The latter consisted of an intent to appropriate
to oneself the exclusive use of the thing possessed.
Can we say then that what the possessor needs is at least a minimum
intention, an intent to exclude others from whatever may be in his pocket? To this
there are two replies. First, in its widest and loosest sense, the sense in which
“possesses” simply means “has”, I can be said to possess such things as a stout
heart or a good sense of humour-without any question of intent arising.
Secondly, in the narrower sense, where the subject –matter of possession consists
of material objects other than parts of the possessor’s own body, it is misleading to
assert that the possessor must actually be intending anything at all. If I possess
something, then it is true that if my possession is challenged or attacked I shall
probably display an intention of excluding such interference. But unless my
34
Possession in law
By such civil and criminal remedies the law can safeguard a man’s de facto
possession. Possession in law would be identical with possession in fact; Even with
such a legal system, however, there would no doubt arise borderline questions to
which lay usage gave no answer but which the law would have to resolve: if A
loses his golf-ball on B’s golf-links and the ball is found by C, we cannot proceed
35
with the matter of safeguarding possession until we know who in such a case
actually has possession. Yet, at the moment when C has found the ball but has not
yet picked it up, it is by no means clear which of these three parties would
ordinarily, and outside the law, be held to be in possession. A legal system’s
solutions to such marginal problems would inevitable refine the notion of
possession and produce divergences between the factual and the legal concepts.
Apart from this type of development however, the two concepts could quite
easily coincide. Nor need such coincidence restrict legal protection to cases of
actual possession. If A wrongfully takes possession of B’s watch, the law can still
afford all its possessory remedies to B, on the ground that B did originally have,
and therefore ought to have Possession. The fact that the law regards as possessors
only those who are actually in possession need not prevent it from protecting those
who are not in possession but who in the general view of society ought to be.
Indeed the protection of possession would be of little point if legal protection
ceased the moment possession was lost; the protection of possession entails
supporting the dispossessed against the dispossessor.
But when a system of law allows possessory rights and remedies to persons
not in actual possession, it may do so, not by considering them simply as entitled to
possession and its attendant rights, but by regarding them as being for legal
purposes in possession. Thus we may find that one who is not actually a possessor
is nevertheless considered as such in the eyes of the law; and conversely one who
actually has possession may be looked on by law as non-possessor. Accordingly
the concept of legal possession parts company still further from the ordinary notion
of possession, as law tends to invent instances of constructive possession, that is
cases where something less than possession in one person is deemed possession in
36
law, and where conversely the actual possession of some other party is reduced to
something less than legal possession.
It should be noted that there was nothing logically inevitable in this sort of
development; in order to catch dishonestly which is outside the strict meaning of
the definition of larceny, the law has extended the meaning of certain terms in the
definition; it could equally well have extended the definition itself.
37
This indeed has been done to cope with the case of the dishonest bailee. In
common law a bailee is one who is given possession of goods on the understanding
that he is to deliver them in specie to the bailor or at the bailor’s directions. Such a
person acquires possession of the goods in law as well as in fact. Suppose then that
he misappropriates them? Having already got possession, he cannot, it would
seem, be guilty of larceny. First, the courts created a peculiar rule that the bailee
only got possession of the container and not of its contents; If he subsequently
“broke bulk” by opening the container and misappropriating the contents, he
became guilty of larceny. Later, however, legislation provided that if a bailee
fraudulently misappropriated the goods bailed to him he would be guilty of
stealing, thus providing that a baileee who has lawful possession can nevertheless
commit larceny of the goods he possesses. Here then the definition of larceny was
extended by extending the terms in the definition.
Similar to the problem of the baileee is that posed by the delivery by one
person to another of an object which, unknown to either of them, contains inside it
certain valuable items of property. A sells B a bureau, which, unknown to both,
contains jewels in a secret drawer. Who has possession, A or B? Ordinarily
perhaps we should consider that a person with possession of a container gets
possession also of the contents, and that the buyer in the above example would
simultaneously take possession of the bureau and the valuables. Common law,
however, holds that in such a case, unless the deliverer intends the deliveree to
obtain possession of the contents, the latter does not acquire legal possession of
them until he discovers them and that if at this stage he decides dishonestly to
misappropriate them, he accordingly becomes guilty of larceny.
In the above cases the physical possession of the accused is regarded as less
than legal possession, because the accused is unaware that he has the object. Yet in
38
common law possession does not always involve knowledge of the presence or
existence of the subject matter. If A unknowingly takes something which is in B’s
possession, he nevertheless takes possession and commits a trespass against B. So
in the famous case or R.V. Riley the accused was held to have taken possession of
sheep which belonged to the prosecutor and which he unknowingly drove with his
own flock to market.
common law is not normally concerned with the question who has the best right to
possess; it is concerned with the question which of the parties before the court has
the better right to posses. If A momentarily hands his wallet to B, from whom it is
stolen by C, who then loses it on D’s property, where it is then found by E, the
question who has the right to possess – which is often considered the same as the
question who has legal possession – will depend on who bring action against
whom.
Against all subsequent parties E’s title would prevail, for finding confers a
good title. In an action between D and E, however, it would seem that D would
have the better right if he could show that the article was found on property from
which he had a general intention to exclude others. Bridges v. Hawkesworth
decided that notes found on the floor of a shop passed into the possession of the
finder rather than of the shopkeeper. This case, which has been much criticized
was distinguished in South Stafffordshire Water Co. v. Sharman on the ground that
the notes were found in the public part of the shop, but would seem to have been
followed in Hannah v. Peel where a soldier, who found a brooch in a requisitioned
house, was held entitled to the brooch as against the owner of the house. Here,
however, the owner had never been in possession of the house.
the place where it was lost than from a finder whose whereabouts may be
unknown. On the other hand, if there is no likelihood of the true owner’s
appearance to claim the property, perhaps the fairest course would be to treat the
object as a windfall and to divide the proceeds of sale between finder and occupier
equally.
In R.v.Harding for example, the accused was convicted of stealing a raincoat from
a servant, who, as against the master, had mere custody of the coat and could
herself have been convicted of larceny had she dishonestly made off with it.
Of all the divergencies between legal and actual possession this is the most
notable, like that outside the law possession is used in an absolute sense whereas
within the law it is employed in a relative sense. Outside the law we do not speak
of a person having possession as against someone else; we say that he either has or
has not got possession. In law we talk rather of possession as something which one
person has against another. If we overlook this, then decisions like R. v. Harding
and London Coporation v. Appleyard are unnecessarily difficult. How could the
servant in the first case have possession of the coat and yet at the same time not
have possession of it? If the law used possession in an absolute sense, then of
course she could not. As it is, she had possession as against the thief but not as
against her employer. Likewise the occupier of the land in the second case had
possession of the notes as against the workmen who found them he would not of
course have had possession as against the true owner, had the latter advanced his
claim.
It is said that English law has never worked out a consistent theory of
possession. But although there are many other parts of English law, which give rise
to difficult problems concerning possession and which cannot be further discussed
here, it would seem that underlying the concept of possession in English law is to
be found the ordinary notion of factual possession; that this has been refined by
extensions and restrictions in order to base the right to possess on actual
possession; and that the equating of the right with the possession has resulted in an
unnecessary and yet useful concept of relative possession. To provide a terse
42
Kinds of Possession
a. the first mediate possession is acquired through servant or agent. Here agent
or servant retains the possession on behalf of the principal. They don’t have
any personal interest in the thing possessed. The thing still carries in itself
interest or claim of the owner. In this type of cases the immediate possession
is with servant or agent while the mediate possession lies in principal or
master.
As for example if A sends his servant B, to get his coat pressed, the
immediate possession is with B on account of A, while A is having mediate
possession of the coat.
b. second kind of mediate possession is where an object is held by a person on
his own behalf as well as on another behalf but recognizes the superior right
of the latter, who can obtain in whenever he choose to demand. For example
if A took a book from B, then A is in immediate possession of it whiule B is
in mediate possession.
43
3. Concurrent possession
It was a maxim of the civil law that two persons could not be in possession
of the same thing at the same time. As a general proposition this is true; for
exclusiveness is of the essence of possession. Two adverse claims of exclusive use
cannot both be effectually realized at the same time. Claims, however, which are
not adverse, and which are not, therefore, mutually destructive, admit of concurrent
realization. Hence there are several possible cases of duplicate possession.
2. Two or more persons may persons may possess the same thing in
common, just as they may own it in common.
The modes of acquisition are two in number, namely Taking and Delivery.
Taking is the acquisition of possession without the consent of the previous
possessor. The thing taken may or may not have been already in the possession of
someone else, and in either case the taking of it may be either rightful or wrongful.
Delivery, on the other hand, is the acquisition of possession with the consent and
co-operation of the previous possessor.
a. Things which are lying loose on the land and are not in the knowledge of the
owner of the land are deemed in possession of first finder and he has better
title than the owner of the land.
Bridges v. Hawkesworth
In this case the plaintiff found a parcel of bank notes lying n the floor of the
shop. The court held, founder of the parcel had the better title than that of the
owner of the shop, against the whole world except the real owner.
45
Possession over the bank notes was acquired first by finder, animus was
lacking in shopkeeper, as he was not aware about the existence of the bank
notes at the premises of his shop.
In this case a soldier stayed in the house which was purchased by somebody
else. Soldier found a brooch lying on the top of the window frame. Owner of
the house took that brooch and sold it. it was held by the court that the
soldier had much better title than the owner as the owner had no knowledge
about the existence of the thing.
b. An owner/occupier of a land enjoys better title than the finder of the goods
in reference to the object under or attached to the land, whether he knows
about its existence on the land or not.
In this case the Plaintiff company owned a pool and employed defendant to
clean the pool. Defendant found two gold rings in it and denied to hand it
over to Plaintiff company. The plaintiff company held entitled to possession
of the ring. It was held that where a person has possession of a house or
land, with a manifest intention to exercise control over it and the thing which
may be upon or in it, then if something is found on the land whether by an
employee of the owner or by a stranger, the presumption is that the
possession of that thing is in the owner of the locus in quo.
In this case the defendant took on lease land belonging to the plaintiff. While
digging land, defendant found a prehistoric boat-six feet below the surface.
46
It was held that the land lord being in lawful possession of land, was in
possession of not only of the surface but everything that lay down t the
centre of the earth.
c. So far cases of larceny are concerned law gives more marks to possession de
jure than possession de facto. Possession is deemed with the legal possessor
when possession is lost without the knowledge of the person legally entitled
to it.
In this case a bureau was delivered to carpenter, and there was money in the
secret drawer of the bureau. Carpenter appropriated the money. It was held
by the court that animus was lacking in the carpenter therefore money was
not in his possession until he found it therefore he was held guilty. Court
followed the same principle in Merry vs. Green case.
R v/s Ashwell
as existing where in fact it does not obtain; and this in turn may lead to the
development of the nation that in law I may have possession of an object as against
one person while not having possession of it as against another. Ownership, on the
other hand, consists not of a actual relationship but of certain legal rights, and is a
matter not of fact but of law. These two concepts of ownership and possession,
therefore, may be used to distinguish between the de facto possessor of an object
and its de jure owner, between the man who actually has it and the man who ought
to have it. They serve also to contrast the position of the whose rights are ultimate,
permanent and residual with that of one whose rights are only of a temporary
nature.
Conversely there are many rights which can be owned, but which are not
capable of being possessed. They are those which may be termed transitory. Rights
which do not admit of continuing exercise do not admit of possession either. They
cannot be exercised without being thereby wholly fulfilled and destroyed; therefore
they cannot be possessed. A creditor, for example, does not possess the debt that is
due to him; for this is a transitory right which in its very nature cannot survive its
48
exercise (a). but a man may possess an easement over land, because its exercise
and its continued existence are consistent with each other. It is for this reason that
obligations generally (that is to say, rights in personam as opposed to rights in rem)
do not admit of possession. It is to be remembered, however, that repeated exercise
is equivalent in this respect to continuing exercise. I may possess a right of way
through repeated acts of use, just as I may possess a right of light or support
through continuous enjoyment. Therefore even obligations admit of possession,
provided that they are of such a nature as to involve a series of repeated acts of
performance. We may say that a landlord is in possession of his rents, an annuitant
of his annuity, a bondholder of his interest, or a master of the services of his
servant.
Personality
Legal persons are beings, real or imaginary, who for the purpose of legal reasoning
are treated in greater or less degree in the same way as human beings.
The only natural persons are human beings. Beasts are not persons, either
natural or legal.
They are merely things often the objects of legal right and duties, but never
the subjects of them.
50
There are three things, in which the law will take notice of them.
But far the most important matter, however, in which the desires of dead men are
allowed by the law to regulate the actions of the living is that of testamentary
succession.
For many years after a man is dead, his hand may continue to regulate and
determine the disposition and enjoyment of the property which he owned while
living.
52
This, however, is a matter which will receive attention more fitly in another place.
Thus, in the law of property, there is a fiction that a child is a person in being for
the purposes of;
Finally, though the law imputes no rights to persons not yet even conceived, it may
protect their interests. If some of the beneficiaries of a trust are unborn persons, the
trust cannot be varied without obtaining the court’s consent on their behalf.
53
Legal persons
A legal person is any subject-matter other than a human being to which the law
attributes personality. This extension, for good and sufficient reasons, of the
conception of personality beyond the class of human beings is one of the most
noteworthy feats of the legal imagination.
The law in creating legal persons, always does so by personifying some real thing.
This is indeed, no theoretical necessity for this, since the law might, if it so
pleased, attribute the quality of personality to a purely imaginary being, and yet
attain the ends for which this fictitious extension of personality is devised.
Personification, however, conduces so greatly to simplicity of thought and speech,
that its aid is invariably accepted. The thing personified may be termed the corpus
(PÁ£ÀÆ£ÁvÀäPÀ ªÀåQÛAiÀÄ zÉúÀ) of the legal person so created, it is the body into which the
law infuses the animus (GzÉÝñÀUÀ¼ÀÄ) of a fictitious personality.
Although all legal personality involves personification, the converse is not true.
Legal personality is a definite legal conception; personification, as such, is a mere
artifice of speech devised for compendious expression. In popular language and in
legal language also, when strictness of speech is not called for, the device of
personification is extensively used. We speak of the estate of a deceased person as
if it were itself a person. We say that it owes debts, or has debts owing to it, or is
insolvent. The law, however, recognizes no legal personality in such a case. The
rights and liabilities of a dead man devolve upon his heirs, executors, and
administrators, not upon any fictitious person known as his estate. Similarly we
speak of a piece of land as entitled to a servitude, such as a right of way over
another piece. So also, in the case of common interests and actions, we personify
as a single person the group of individuals concerned, even though the law
recognizes no body corporate. We speak of a firm as a person distinct from the
individual partners. We speak of a jury, a bench of judges, a public meeting, the
community itself, as being itself a person instead of merely a group or society of
persons. But legal personality is not reached until the law recognizes, over and
above the associated individuals, a single entity which in a manner represents
them, but is not identical with them.
54
Legal persons, being the arbitrary creations of the law, may be so as many kinds as
the law pleases. Those which are actually recognized by our own system, however,
are of comparatively few types. Corporations are undoubtedly legal persons, and
the better view is that registered trade unions and friendly societies are also legal
persons though not verbally regarded as corporations.
Corporate personality
Entities which enjoy legal rights and duties are, as we have seen, either natural or
legal persons. But what in fact is a legal person? If Smith has legal rights, then it is
a human being that has the rights in question. But if smith and co.Ltd, has legal
rights, what is it really that possesses these rights? Or if I make a contract with
Smith and Co.Ltd, what have I really contracted with?
Some writers, including Salmond, argue that corporations are mere fictions. To
speak of Smith & Co.Ltd, as having rights and duties is to treat as real an entity
which has no real existence. Just as the socientist finds it convenient to regard an
electric current as being like a current of water, so the lawyer finds it convenient to
look upon a coporation as a sort of person; and just as in reality the lectric current
is not a current at all, as the scientist well knows, so equally a corporation, as the
lawyer knows full well, is in reality not a person at all.
The misleading feature in this theory is the suggestion that the lawyer is indulging
in make-belief. The fact that Smith & Co. Ltd, is not the same sort of entity as
Smith need not compel us to conclude that it is the same sort of entity as Robinson
Crusoe. In a work of fiction the characters do indeed lack existence, although the
conventions of the art of fiction require us to imagine that they really lived. Indeed
without stepping outside the law, we can observe that John Doe and Richard Roe
56
were fictitious characters, who, as everyone was well aware, did not exist, but
whose fictitious existence enabled the courts to provide a convenient remedy for
dispossession of land. But Smith & Co. Ltd, is in quite a different case from
Robinson Crusoe, John Doe and Richard Roe; for in referring to Smith & Co. Ltd.
We are not suspending judgment, pretending or in any way imagining something to
be which is not the case. But the rejection of the fiction theory must not drive us to
the opposite extreme of asserting that a corporation is a real but mysterious entity
with a special type of existence. For this kind of realist theory, despite the appeal
which it has had, is even more unsatisfactory than the fiction theory. The merit of
the latter was that it at least attempted to provide some sort of explanation of the
nature of a corporation. To say that a corporation is a fiction devoid of real
existence does at any rate stress what actually happens in situations involving
corporations; to say that the smith & co.Ltd., with whom I contracted, is a mere
fiction does at least lend on to a description of the circumstances in which I may be
said to have contracted with this limited company. But to state that the company is
a real but mysterious entity explains nothing at all. Anyone who is puzzled by what
it means to contract with Smith and Co.Ltd, will be equally confused at the notion
of contracting with an entity such as the realist theory describes.
Common sense suggests that in truth a corporation is nothing other than its
members, and that statements about corporations are disguised abbreviations for
statements about all the members. But this too is not entirely satisfactory; for to say
that Smith & Co. Ltd, owes me $100 is not an abbreviated way of saying that
every member of the company owes me a debt. A limited company is not just the
same thing as its members, and statements about the former are not just
abbreviations for statements about the latter. On the other hand we could translate
statements like smith & Co. Ltd. Owes me $100 into other statements which do not
contain the words smith & co.Ltd. we could for example specify the circumstances
under which the statement would be true; and this would involve a descrption of
the legal rules about incorporation, management and extinction of limited
companies together with an account of the law relating to their contractual
liabliltiy. It would also involve a description of some events which would count by
law as incorporation of smith & co.Ltd. and as the incurring by smith & co. Ltd of
this debt to me. To complete the translation we should need to describe what
follows in law from the fact that the company owes me this debt; in other words,
57
we should need to list the legal consequences of the statement, showing who in fact
would be liable to pay, what effect this would have on the members of the
company and so on. To do all this would be to show the criteria for the truth of
statements about limited companies, but it would not be the same thing as an actual
statement about the company. for the proposition that smith & co. Ltd. Owes me
$100 states neither the relevant events which justify the proposition, nor yet again
the consequences of it; all these are implied but not expressed. Statements about
corporations are simple, unified methods of stating what would otherwise be
inordinately complicated.
But all modern societies have considered nation as a corporation. They can sue the
state, they can make the contracts, state can have its own transactions. No doubt in
this modern world nation exercising its functions as a big corporation.