Legal Rights: Anamika Singh and Shriya Badgaiyan
Legal Rights: Anamika Singh and Shriya Badgaiyan
Legal Rights: Anamika Singh and Shriya Badgaiyan
LEGAL RIGHTS
ABSTRACT
Rights are conditions important for development of character of man. According to Laski, rights are
those state of affairs of social life without which no man can be at his best. The theory of natural
rights is the essential. Locke is the main exponent of this theory. According to this theory, men have
certain natural rights that are inherent in man and cannot be taken away from him. These rights are
relied on natural reason.
According to Locke, rights of person, liberty and property are natural and lead the state and are an
obligation on the state. But, this does not offer a proper basis of rights. These are not the only rights
that man needs. In fact, right of property in absolute terms may become an anti social organization.
The concept of natural reason is ambiguous. Another theory is the historical theory. According to
this theory man should be guaranteed rights that he enjoyed in the past like the right of property. It
is also scarce theory. Rights in the present cannot be relied on the past. Some of the rights enjoyed
in the past may become outdated and may not be required.
1
Damodaram Sanjivayya National Law University, Visakhapatnam
Research Methodology:
For this project the research is doctrinal. The information and data for the project will be from
various books, articles and other online resources. The research will include publication research,
and other relevant sources, and will include both present and historical information related to topic.
The case study of various past cases related to the topic will be referred in this project. Articles and
laws related to the topic and also if there is an amendment in the previous law will also be taken into
consideration.
Limitations:
The important limitation of this study is the reliance on secondary data. As the study is not empirical
so the information and research is confined to books, online resources, articles in the newspapers
and magazines.
Introduction
Law consists of certain types of rules regulating human conduct and that the administration of
justice is concerned with enforcing the rights and duties created by such rules. The concept of a
right is accordingly one of fundamental significance in legal theory. Two terms which are closely
connected with Right are, wrong and duty. A wrong is simply a wrong act, an act contrary to the rule
of right and justice divisible into two kinds, being either moral or legal. A moral or natural wrong is
an act which is morally or naturally wrong, being contrary to the rule of natural justice. A legal
wrong is an act which is legally wrong, which is contrary to the rule of legal justice and a violation of
the law. In all ordinary cases the legal recognition of an act as a wrong involves the suppression or
punishment of it by the physical force of the state, this being the essential purpose for which the
judicial action of the state is ordained. A duty is roughly speaking an act which one ought to do, an
act the opposite of which would be a wrong.
Rights
The word right is used in a variety of context. There are Fundamental Rights, Human Rights, Legal
Rights and Moral Rights. There are also rights of specific groups as rights of children, rights of
women, rights of minorities, rights of refugeesetc. The English word ‘right’ literally has two
meaning. In one sense, it means what is correct or just to do and the other speaks about a person’s
right to do something.
A legal right is commonly defined as an interest recognized and protected by law. Law cannot
recognize and protect all the interests of the people. Thus it selects some interests as worthy for legal
protection. Ihering regards legal rights as such of these interests which have obtained legal
protection. According to him, one can be said to have a right only when there exists for one some
advantage, which is protected by the state.2 In every case, the existence of a legal right is dependent
upon the circumstance that some human interest has secured the protection of the state.
According to Holland, a right is “a capacity residing in one man of controlling, with the assent and
the assistance of the State, the actions of other”.
2
N.H. Jhabvala, The elementsof Jurisprudence, C. Jamnadas and Co., 2013, P.140
Salmond defines legal right as an interest recognized and protected by a rule of justice. The word
‘interest’ implies any interest, respect for which is a duty and disregard of which is a wrong. This
definition contains two essential elements, legal recognition and legal protection. Both these
elements should simultaneously and concurrently be present in an interest for its transformation as a
legal right. A legal recognition of an interest without legal protection does not make it enforceable in
a court of law, as for example, time barred debts. So also legal, protection of an interest without its
legal recognition cannot make it a legal right.
The second part of Salmond’s definition is that a legal right is any interest, respect of which is a duty
and disregard of which is a wrong. Whether a person’s interest amounts to a right or not depends on
whether there exists with respect to it a corresponding duty imposed upon any other person. Further
the right is an interest, the violation of which would be a wrong. Rights like wrongs and duties are
either moral or legal.3 A moral or natural right is an interest recognized and protected by moral or
natural justice, violation of which would be a moral or natural wrong and respect for which is a
moral duty. A legal right on the other hand is an interest recognized and protected by a rule of legal
justice.4
Salmond further states that rights and duties are necessarily correlatives. He also stated that,’ there
can be no right without a corresponding duty and duty without a corresponding right any more that
there can be a husband without a wife and a father without a child.’5 It is because every duty must be
a duty towards some person or persons in whom a correlative right is vested. Conversely, every right
must be a right against some person or persons upon whom a correlative duty is imposed.
III. It is a right over to some thing to which that act or omission relates.
Ownerless rights are not recognised by English law. This is because, there would be nothing to
prevent such a concept being used in legal reasoning. Ownership of a right may be merely
contingent or uncertain. The owner of it may be a person indeterminate.
3
S.R. Sarkal, Nature and Sources of the Law, SAGE publications, 2nd Edn. P. 147.
4
N.K Jayakumar, Lectures on Jurisprudence, lexis Nexis, P. 58.
5
Ibid, P. 180.
Salmond analysed right by splitting a legal right into the following five essential elements.
i. The owner or the subject of the rights: A person in whom the right is vested may be
called the owner or the subject of a right. He is the person entitled or the person of
inherence. The owner of a right need not necessarily be certain or determinate. When the
owner is an unborn person, the person entitled is uncertain. When the right is owned by
society at large, the owner is indeterminate.
ii. The person of incidence: he is the person bound by the duty and may be called the subject
of duty. He is the person against whom the right avails.
iii. Content: the act or forbearance, which the person in whom the right resides can exact, is
called the content of the right. It is an act or omission, which is obligatory on the person of
incidence to the person of inherence.
iv. The object: Something to which the act or omission relates is the object of the right. The
thing over which the right is exercised is the object. This may also be called the subject
matter of the right. Holland points out the possibility of rights which have no object.
Holland says that the object of the right should be some material thing. Salmond on the
other hand observes that the term ‘object’ need not be narrowly defined. The object of a
right is as essential an element in the idea of right as the subject of right itself.6
v. Title: Title denotes certain facts or events by virtue of which the right has become vested in
its owner.
An example is that, A buys a piece of land from B. here A is the subject or owner of the right so
acquired. The persons bound are the public at large, for it is a right available against persons
generally. The content of the right consists in non-interference with A’s exclusive use of the land.
The land itself is the object of the right. The title is the conveyance by which the land was acquired
by A from B.
A subject in whom the right inheres and an object in respect of which it exists are the essential
elements in the right. It is impossible to think of a right without an owner, though the owner may be
uncertain or indeterminate. Similarly there cannot be any right without an object7.
1) Rights over material things Here the object is land, house, furniture, car, watch etc.
6 th
Friedmann W., Legal Theory (5 Edn.) p. 30.
7
Ibid, P. 57.
ii. I have a right not to be physically injured or assaulted. The object is my body, health and
integrity.
2) Rights of reputation: The object is the good name of a person, which constitutes an asset
as valuable as any material thing.A person has a right not to be libeled. Such a right has
obtained legal recognition and protection
4) Rights in respect of other rights: if A enters into an agreement with B to sell his land
within one year, B acquires a right against A to have the land transferred to him within the
stipulated time. B’s present right is a right to have the ownership of land transferred to him
at the stipulated time.
Liberty or privilege denotes the absence of restraint.8 It is a legal freedom on the part of one person
as against another to do given act or a legal freedom not to do a given act.
The view of Austin is that” liberty and right are synonymous. The liberty of acting according to
one’s will would be illusory if it were not protected from obstruction”. When law affords such
protection, it is in fact conferring a right and so liberty and right are synonymous.
Salmond writes: Rights are what others are to do for me; liberties are what I may do for myself.”
There is no suitable word to express the co-relative of liberty. As the co-relative of liberty would be
the jural contradictory of right, Hohfeld has suggested that the word “no right” may be used as the
co-relative of liberty.9
8
John D. Finch, Introduction to Legal Theory (2nd Edn.) P. 70.
9
J.B. Saral, Province of Jurisprudence Determined, Lexis Nexis, P. 114.
A power may be defined as the ability conferred upon a person to determine, by his own will
directed to that end, the rights, duties and abilities or other legal relations eithet of himself or of
other persons. The right of a person to make a will with regard to his properties, his right to alienate
his property, the power of sale vested in a mortgagee, a landlord’s right of re-entry upon his land, a
right of action, the right to rescind a contract for fraud, the right of taking out execution in
judgments, powers vested in judges and other officials for the due fulfilment of their functions are
examples of power. The distinction between power and liberty consists in the fact the liberty is what
one may do innocently without committing a wrong while power is what one may do effectively and
validly.
Powers are divided into public and private. Public powers are those vested in a person as an agent of
the state. The powers vested in judges or executive officers by law are public powers. Private powers
are those possessed and exercised by individuals in their private transactions. Power may be either
ability to determine the legal relations of other persons or to determine one’s own legal relations.
Exemption from the power of another is immunity. The correlative of immunity is disability. A
foreign sovereign enjoys immunity from legal proceedings in our courts. Immunity stands to power
in much the same relation as liberty is to right. Liberty arises from the absence of a right in another
and the absence of a duty in oneself. Immunity arises from the absence of a power in another and
the absence of liability in oneself10.
Hohfeld brought out the distinction between the different kinds of rights by saying “A right is one’s
affirmative claim against another; a liberty or privilege is one’s freedom from right or claim of
another.11 A power is one’s affirmative control over a given legal relation as against another, whereas
an immunity is one’s freedom from that legal power over control of another as regards some legal
relations.’ Putting the distinction in a slightly different way, Salmond says: ‘a right in the narrow
sense is that which other persons ought to do in my behalf. A liberty is that which i may do
innocently. A power is that which i can do effectively in respect of mine’.
Legal rights have been variously classified. According to Salmond, a perfect right is one which
corresponds to a perfect duty. A perfect duty is one which is not merely recognised by law but also
enforced by law. In all fully developed legal systems, there are rights and duties which, though
recognised by law, are not of perfect nature. Those rights are called imperfect rights. Examples of
10
V.D Mahajan, Jurisprudence & legal theory, Eastern Book Company( 5th Edn.), P.69.
11
Berolzhmeir, Legal Philosophies, P. 261.
imperfect rights are the claims barred by the lapse of time, claims which cannot be enforced on
account of the absence of some special form of legal proof, claims against foreign States or
sovereigns, claims which cannot be enforced as they do not lie within their local limits of the
jurisdiction of the court, debts due to an executor from the estate which he administers. In these
cases, the rights and duties are imperfect as no action lies for their maintenance. An imperfect right
may be good as a ground of defence, though not good as a ground of action. An imperfect right may
become perfect. The right of action may be dormant and not nonexistent12.
When a duty, which corresponds to a right, is a positive duty, that right is called a positive right. The
person on whom the duty lies shall do some positive act on behalf of the person entitled. A negative
right corresponds to a negative duty that is a person bound shall refrain from some act, which would
operate to the prejudice of the person entitled. Positive right is a right to be positively benefited;
negative right is merely a right not to be harmed. In the case of a negative right, others are restrained
from doing something. The satisfaction of the positive rights results in the betterment of the
position of the owner. In case of negative rights, the position of the owner is merely maintained as it
is.
The law is more concerned with prevention of harm than enforcement of positive benefit. Liability
for harmful acts of commission is the general rule, but liability for acts of omission is the exemption.
A real right or right in rem is a right over a res or a thing. According to Salmond, a real right
corresponds to a duty imposed upon persons in general. The right in personam or personal right
corresponds to a duty imposed upon determinate individuals. It is said that a right in rem is available
only against the whole world, while right in personam is available only against particular persons. It
is an interest protected solely against determinate individuals. In a sense, a right in rem is a right to
be left alone by other persons, that is, a right to their passive non-interference.13
The proprietary rights of a person include his estate, his assets and his property in many forms.
Proprietary rights have some economic and monetary value. Proprietary rights are valuable and
personal rights are not. Proprietary rights are elements of the wealth of a man. Personal rights are
12
Ibid, p. 180.
13
Friedmann W., Legal Theory (5th Edn.) P. 276.
merely elements of his well-being. Proprietary rights merely not merely possess judicial but also
economic importance. Personal rights possess merely judicial importance14.
A right is inheritable if it survives its owners. It is uninhabitable if it dies with him. Proprietary rights
are inheritable but personal rights are uninhabitable. The heirs of a proprietary owner become
owners after his death. In the case of personal rights, they die with the owner and cannot be
inherited.
Jus ad rem is a right to a right. It is a right in personam. Eg, a contract to assign property in future, a
promise of marriage etc. Here, two rights are involved. The right, which is to be transferred, may be
either a right in rem or a right in personam, but the other right, that is a right to a right will always be
a right in personam only15.
A right in re aliena, which is also called an encumbrance, is one which limits or derogates from some
more general rights belonging to some other person in respect of the same subject matter. All other
rights are rights in re propria. The owner of a chattel has jus in re propria or a right over his own
property. The pledge has jus in re aliena or a right over the property of someone else. Rights in re
propria are rights in one’s own property. Rights in re aliena are rights over the property of another
person.
There are four main classes of encumbrances, leases, servitudes, securities and trusts. A lease is the
encumbrance of property vested in one man by a right to the possession and use of it vested in
another. A servitude is a right to the limited use of a piece of land unaccompanied either by the
ownership or by possession of it. A security is an encumbrance vested in a credtor over the property
of his debtor for the purpose of securing the recovery of the debt. A trust is an encumbrance in
which the ownership of property is limited by an equitable obligation to deal with it for the benefit
of someone else. The owner of the encumbered property is called the trustee and the owner of the
encumbrance is called the beneficiary.
Principal rights exist independently of other rights. Accessory rights are appurtenant to other rights
and they have a beneficial effect on principal rights. A security is accessory to the right secured.
14
Dr Avtar Singh, Dr Harpreet Kaur, introduction to jurisprudence, lexis nexis Butterworths Wadhwa (3rd Edn.) P.
69.
15
Supra n.2
Servitude is accessory to the ownership of the land for whose benefit it exists. The rent and
covenant of a lease are accessory to the ownership of the property by the landlord. Covenants for
title in a conveyance are accessory to the estate conveyed. A right of action is accessory to the right
for whose enforcement it is provided.
Legal rights are those recognised by common law courts and equitable rights are those rights
recognised only in the Court of Chancery. Principles of equity evolved in English law in order to
mitigate the rigorous of ordinary law. In spite of the fusion of law and equity by the Judicature Act
1873, the historical distinction still survives and is relevant in some situations. When two legal rights
are found inconsistent, the first in time generally prevails. When a legal right and a equitable right are
in conflict, the legal right will prevail over the equitable right, even though subsequent in origin,
provided that the owner of the legal right acquired it for value and without notice of prior equity.16
A vested right is a right in respect of which all events necessary to vest it completely in the owner
have happened. No other condition remains to be satisfied. In the case of a contingent right, only
some of the events necessary to vest the right in the contingent owner have happened. According to
Paton “ When all the investitive facts which are necessary to create the rights have occurred, the
right is vested; when part of the investitive facts have occurred, the rights contingent until the
happening of all facts on which the title depends.
Primary are also called antecedent, sanctioned or enjoyment rights. Secondary rights are called
sanctioning, restitutory or remedial rights. Examples of primary rights are the right of reputation, the
right in respect of one’s own person, the right of the owner of a guardian etc. Secondary rights are a
part of the machinery provided by the state for the redress of injury done to primary rights.
CONCLUSION
With duties we may contrast obligations. Moreover a duty consists in positive acts, not in mere
abstaining from acting: a duty not to do something, except in so far as this is a manner of describing
a duty to do something else, a duty not to reveal something in a negative way of describing a positive
duty to keep it secret, is a duty of a rare and unusual sort17.
Duties like wrongs are of two kinds, being either moral or legal. These two classes are partly
coincident and partly distinct. When the law recognizes an act as duty, it commonly enforces the
16
J.K. Patron, The Elementary Principles of Jurisprudence, P. 48.
17
P J Fitzgerald, ‘salmond on jurisprudence’, universal publication(12th ed.)
performance of it, or punishes the disregard of it. A duty is legal because it is legally recognized, not
necessarily duties of imperfect obligation.
REFERNCES
N.H. Jhabvala, The elements of Jurisprudence, C. Jamnadas and Co., 2013,(10th Ed.) P.140-
152
S.R. Sarkal, Nature and Sources of the Law, SAGE publications, ( 2nd Ed.) P. 147-180
N.K Jayakumar, Lectures on Jurisprudence, lexis Nexis, (4th Ed.) P. 58-65.
Friedmann W., Legal Theory (5th Ed.) p. 30-65
John D. Finch, Introduction to Legal Theory (2nd Ed)P. 70-87
J.B. Saral, Province of Jurisprudence Determined, Lexis Nexis ( 2nd Ed.)P. 114- 119
V.D Mahajan, Jurisprudence & legal theory, Eastern Book Company( 5th Ed.), P.69- 75
Berolzhmeir, Legal Philosophies, P. 261- 267.
Friedmann W., Legal Theory (5th Edn.) P. 276-287
Dr Avtar Singh, Dr Harpreet Kaur, introduction to jurisprudence, Lexis Nexis Butterworths
Wadhwa (3rd Ed.) P.69- 74.
J.K. Patron, The Elementary Principles of Jurisprudence, (7th Ed.)P. 48-53.
P J Fitzgerald, ‘salmond on jurisprudence’, Universal Publication(12th ed.)P.68-78