The Normative Economics of Health Care Finance and Provision: Oxford Review of Economic Policy January 1991
The Normative Economics of Health Care Finance and Provision: Oxford Review of Economic Policy January 1991
The Normative Economics of Health Care Finance and Provision: Oxford Review of Economic Policy January 1991
net/publication/242012274
CITATIONS READS
74 1,930
1 author:
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Anthony John Culyer on 02 October 2014.
1
I am grateful for the helpful comments of Richard Amould, Gwyn Bevan, Paul Fenn, Alisudr McGuire, Gavin Mooney,
John Posnett, and Alan Williams. The usual disclaimer applies.
34 0266-903X/89$3.00 © OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS AND THE OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POUCY UMITED
A. J. Culyer
come to supersede in part) the 'welfarist' tradition inputs than were technically necessary to produce
of normative economics. an output, that cannot be cost-effective) and the
cost-effectiveness version of efficiency is also
A key concept underlying the current discussion is embodied in the next concept of efficiency. Being
'efficiency*. This is, however, far from being an cost-effective necessarily eliminates as 'inefficient'
unambiguous notion and, because it is also so some technically efficient combinations of inputs,
central a concept (one indeed that pervades the but it leaves unsettled the question of the efficient
entire debate) it is the one that preoccupies me in rate of production. In economic jargon, cost-
this paper. The practical context in which the effectiveness means 'being where an isocost line is
concept can illuminate is, evidently, scarcely less tangential to an isoquant*.
important. For the purposes of this paper, the ideal output: obtaining when cost-effective out-
practical context is taken to relate to broad policy puts are produced at a rate that i s ' socially' optimal
questions about the 'efficiency' (somehow defined)
35
OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POLICY, VOL. 5, NO. 1
The other approach, which might be termed 'extra- More recently an explicit departure from welfarism
welfarist', relaxes what its adherents see as an was advocated by Williams (1972) and discussed
undue information restriction in welfarism so that further by Sugden and Williams (1978) in the
other aspects of each social state are also embodied context of cost-benefit analysis. This is the 'deci-
in the judgement. Since, in the welfarist approach, sion-making' approach which is contrasted with
the basis of social welfare—or diswelfare—is only the 'Paretian' approach. The latter is one example
the utility got from goods and services (including of welfarist analysis in that social welfare is a
labour services), an important class of 'extra' welfare function only of the utilities to individuals of goods
sources is the non-goods characteristics of individuals and services. The former allows that governments
(like whether they are happy, out of pain, free to (and other 'decision makers') may have other ob-
choose, physically mobile, honest). Extra-welfarism jectives than the making of (actual or potential)
thus transcends traditional welfare: it does not Pareto improvements, which may involve not only
36
A. J. Culyer
rather than merely explained phenomena: the theory on its culture-contingency, I shall say no more on
justifies what is or implies what ought to be, pre- that here. The following sections embrace the usual
scribing rather than predicting. 'list' of factors thatmake health care'different' and
I shall indicate the kind of reasoning that relates to
As a final prefatory remark it is worth pointing out each.
that health economics (in common with many other
fields of application within economics) has by and (i) The Competence of the Consumer
large addressed only a part of the agenda of the
'political economy' of health care, to do with The welfarist approach requires that choices made
finance, public or private. There is very little on the by or for consumers be rational in the particular
normative implications of different forms of sense of that term used by economists. Should
ownership or organisation on the provider side. choices not be founded on axioms that include, for
Indeed, the aforementioned positive theories of the
II. THE WELFARIST APPROACH TO It is common for the consumer, who is almost
HEALTH CARE FINANCE AND invariably incompetent in some degree, to defer
PROVISION some of the judgements involved in clinical choices
to professionals, especially medical doctors, who
It was (and is) common for these issues to be act as agents on his or her behalf: ideally choosing
addressed by considering a set of factors that make in the way the individual would, had he or she been
health care 'different' from other goods or services possessed of the same informational advantages as
and which therefore may constitute a reason for the professional, in a system characterized by what
wanting to allocate it differently from these 'other' Evans (1981) has termed 'incomplete vertical
goods or services (and to evaluate the efficiency of integration' between consumers and producers.
different allocations differently) (Culyer, 1971).
Implicit in this approach is the presumption that The particular technical skill possessed by the
goods and services are in principle best allocated by professional that is relevant here is a better know-
market mechanisms and that departures from that ledge of the effect that health care will have on
mechanism require special warrants. This seems to health. If one supposes that it is health which
be the product of a particular bit of cultural generates utility for individuals, both directly via a
conditioning to which most (Western) economists sense of well-being and indirectly in the sources of
are prone but, since it is my purpose more to outline welfare of which better health enables one to take
an approach than to make sociological comments advantage, then health care is itself only instrumental:
37
OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POLICY, VOL 5, NO. 1
a means to an end. Even if the consumer is able and entry to the profession regulated, and for
rationally to value health, he or she will usually subsidized in-service training systems and other
have much less information about the process of professional activities. The existence of such market
medicine and the risks that different processes failures means that there are inevitably nice balances
imply. Contrary to the usual welfarist assumption, to be struck here between, for example, the self-
the buyer is not the best judge of his or her interests regulating monopoly awarded to doctors in medical
but must rely on the seller's advice. It is quite easy practice and its possible abuse by inhibiting
to imagine circumstances in which the selfish interest innovation (e.g. alleged but not actual quackery,
of the professional can conflict with the best interests inefficiency in doing whatever is done, and the
of the patient. Health itself is not a traded commodity, earning of monopoly rents). While economics is
yet that is what the rational consumer may be helpful in identifying the risks, and in predicting the
expected to seek. The traded commodities are consequences of policies designed to mitigate them,
information and health care, which the consumer its role is mainly qualitative: much judgement is
38
A. J. Culyer
price' to patients; there may be 'excess' 2 demands patient (as is usually the case in general practitioner
at the existing stock and a non-market-clearing services in those medical care systems like the
price, so that increasing utilization following increases UK's that still have GPs), may also come to know
in the stock is simply the meeting of previously a good deal of relevant information about the
unmet 'excess' demand. Doctors may be less patient's values, financial circumstances, working
vulnerable to the effects of consumer detection of life, and family context In such circumstances the
SID in communities with a high doctor/population agency relationship is likely to be as perfect as it
ratio since, given extensive consumer ignorance, probably can be. But even in this situation, the
new patients can always be found to replace any agent too has his or her own values, financial
who leave because of the SID they detect—if so, interests, working relationships, family and social
cross-sectional analysis will produce the observed characteristics which need not be congruent to
correlation between physician stock and utilization. those of the patient (Evans, 1984). In both market
It is unfortunate that this unsatisfactory state of the and non-market systems of health care finance and
2
I put the term in quotation marks as I do not wish to imply that the demands are necessarily in excess of a Parcto optimal
rate of use, merely that they are excess in the (positive economics) sense of demand exceeding price at the going full user-price.
39
OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POLICY, VOL 5, NO. 1
for interference with the market on this ground limited; the mention of things which 'may be' (but
alone was evidently highly limited and the marginal which are not) measured to find out what actually
externality probably falls quite fast as the proportion is.
of immunized individuals rises.
One of the ironies of the period was that these
The subtler kind of externality, direct interdepend- remarks and others in the same genre were being
ence of the form that makes one person's welfare made in societies that had substantially altered the
directly dependent on the consumption of others, terms of financial access to health care, possibly for
was not taken very seriously (e.g. Lees, 1960,1962; reasons (in part) of externality. At least, such a view
Jewkesera/., 1963; Klarman, 1963,1965; Bucha- would imply the possibility that the subsidy
nan, 1965). The view is well-encapsulated by Lees arrangements were a rational response to a real
(1967): situation rather than the irrational constructions of
Even where externalities exist, recent studies have What sort of evidence might settle this issue of the
shown that the scope for government spending to cor- existence and size of what some have called 'car-
rect market imperfections and raise the general level of ing' externalities (e.g. Culyer, 1980)? One is intro-
economic efficiency is less than conventional analysis spective. Are sufficient numbers of introspectors
had led us to believe. The implications of these studies
may be summarized thus: prepared to sacrifice some of their own consump-
tion so that others may have more? If so, they care
(a) many externalities are irrelevant to human action in the externality sense. In particular, invite intro-
and the achievement of optimal solutions; spectors to try to imagine a society in which health
care was supplied entirely by commercial organiza-
(b) many relevant externalities can be, and are, dealt tions without public subsidy or by private charities.
with voluntarily; Ask each, given that they had imagined themselves
into such a society, whether they would be willing
(c) the costs of governmental intervention, even when to sacrifice some of what each has so that others
it is 'perfect', may outweigh the benefits; would receive more. If each would (and they may
want to add the side condition that each would
(d) the imperfections of government as a decision- sacrifice only if others similarly placed also made
making and choice-making process may make an sacrifices) then they would be providing evidence
'imperfect' market situation more imperfect. for the existence of caring externalities of this sort.
Such was the dominant idea at that time: the 'noth- One of the issues that arises in this context is the
ing special' about health argument; the distinction question of whether subsidies should be specific
between philanthropy approved at one level of (e.g. in-kind or directly tied to purchases of specific
collectivity (private charity) but not at a higher goods and services as with voucher schemes) or
(governmental) level; the reference to studies show- general (essentially income support). The basic
ing the scope for corrective government action to be line of argument has tended to be that it seems that
40
A. J. Culyer
generalized support may be appropriate for goods is not easily interpreted, partly because in those
and services that are highly income elastic at low systems which have been most studied—North
levels of household income, where there will be a American—fee-for-service and the possibility of
strong presumption that income supplements will supplier-induced demand can cause supply-side
be spent by most families on basic necessities like contamination of the 'pure' substitution effects of
food (so there is no need for a 'National Food changing user-prices. Beck (1974) estimated that
Service'), but that where this is not the case, or the reduction in use following the introduction of
where people are held to be poor judges of their own charges of $1.50 per surgery visit and $2.00 per
welfare, specific subsidies are a more cost-effective house call in Saskatchewan in 1968 was about 7 per
means of promoting consumption of particular cent for the whole population but 18 per cent for the
goods since they utilize substitution effects as well poor. Early studies of price-elasticity found values
as income effects. It should be clear that the in the range -0.4 to -1.0. Subsequent work by
potential superiority of specific subsidies arises Phelps and Newhouse (1974), Newhouse and Phelps
41
OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POLICY, VOL 5, NO. 1
optimal amounts (assuming price represents mar- tive method of achieving a given level of equality
ginal social cost accurately) are, however, x^ x*, is by a combination of standard subsidy (but not in
and x*. determined by the condition MSC = MV, + general to reduce price to zero) and enforced denial
EMV for all i. This implies a variable subsidy such of access via nonprice rationing (' abstention' in his
that C faces a marginal price of P c , B faces PB, and terminology) to the better off.
A pays the full price: the subsidy varies inversely
with ability-to-pay. In practice, of course, fine One set of problems arising from this set of exter-
distinctions between individuals will not be pos- nality models is that, while each provides an ac-
sible and general approximations will have to be count of some of the features of health care subsidy
made—but on this rationale they should clearly (e.g. some selectivity, some 'free' care, some de-
have the selective character shown gree of reduced inequality in access), their practical
implementation (assuming that any one of them
Figure 1
Consumption Externalities and Selective Subsidies
Price and
marginal
value MV A
_MSC
0=x
42
A. J. Culyer
to provide more optimal levels of public goods can public: if B gives to the charity rather than A, A
be seen as a collective solution to the free-rider derives no utility. However, this seems to lead
problem, it is quite clear that there are several types nowhere if one wishes to build a welfarist model of
of activity (most notably private charitable giving) collective health care subsidies, for it is the very
that are not collectivized and that are fully exposed publicness of the external effect that generates the
to the problem of free-riding. Strictly, the free-rider public subsidy argument. Perhaps a mixture of
problem implies that no-one (save one whose what Margolis (1982) calls 'goods altruism' and
marginal value of the external benefit most exceeds •participation altruism' might be developed that
its marginal cost) has an incentive to contribute. helped to account for the simultaneous existence of
Consequently, charities will have either no supporters collective and private acts of altruism.
or only one. Since this is plainly not so, there seems
to be something wrong with the theory. And if each Another problem has been pinpointed by Sugden
43
OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POLICY, VOL. 5, NO. 1
Once again, a theory that has such counter-intuitive and s? Margolis suggests that the higher is g/s the
(and counter-factual) empirical implications has to greater the weight given to s and the higherthe ratio
be regarded as an unusually weak foundation upon G'/S 1 the greater the weight given to g. This he
which to build normative propositions. Yet this is terms the Fair Shares principle (FS). If the weight
the same theory that underpins all these externality given to g relative to s is W, then a stable equilibrium
arguments for public subsidy (of one form or an- occurs at E in Figure 2, with the consequent
other, depending on which of the rival externality equilibrium of g occurring at g*.
theories one is using).
Figure 2
Sugden suggests that it is preferable to invoke
another (extra-welfarist) theory (specifically, of
'duty'). Unfortunately, he does not develop this in
the context of individual charitable behaviour, let
44
A. J. Culyer
The implications of the model have not been devel- literature affords of the concepts of 'altruism',
oped specifically for the health care sector (for a 'selfishness', and 'caring'. As an aid to clarity of
beginning, see Mooney, 1986) but, given the weak- thought, the welfarist literature is valuable; it cannot
ness of other welfarist models, it may be that it be claimed, however, that it has yielded settled
holds out the most promise for a satisfactory such conclusions on those issues I have identified as
model (Margolis himself developed it in a positive requiring judgement. The view that the externality
context, a positive-normative flip is thus required or group concern is derived not from health care
as was noted before in connection with Lindsay, consumption but from 'health' itself is not directly
1969 and Culyer, 19716). addressed in this literature but occurs in what I shall
discuss later in the extra-welfarist sectioa
( v ) . . . and Where Does this Get Us?
(vi) Uncertainty
Figure 3
W(0
income
45
OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POLICY, VOL 5, NO. 1
uncertain prospect if the individual 'self-insures' If an insurance firm offers insurance at an actuari-
by retaining net income in health and by paying ally fair premium pH (the cost of the event times its
medical expenses out-of-pocket if sickness strikes. probability), the welfare of the individual paying
This in turn arises because the m arginal welfare loss the premium is W(Io-pH). The choice confronting
from having to pay an uncertain but large sum is the individual is thus to self-insure or to purchase
greater than that from having to pay a certain but insurance, with payoffs as in Figure 4.
smaller sum, due to the assumption of a diminish-
ing marginal utility of income or wealth. It is It is clear that, with diminishing marginal welfare
usually assumed that the utility of income is inde- from income (risk-aversion), welfare is higher with
pendent of the stochastic states 'healthy' or 'sick'. insurance, at d, than without it, at c. The certain
If it is not, it is not clear what the optimal level of monetary loss pH is preferable to the uncertain loss
insurance is (Shavell, 1978). of H with the same probability. Fair insurance thus
increases welfare.
46
A. J. Culyer
opportunity costs themselves can be lowered by United States, estimates vary of the numbers who
scale economies and other measures that might be are uninsured or inadequately insured, but seem to
taken to reduce costs, the competitive insurance indicate a total of around 50 million (Farley, 1985;
system itself may thus cause unnecessary welfare Mundinger, 1985). In any event, adverse selection,
losses. unless checked, is likely to cause massive externali-
ties of the sort described earlier and become a major
Loading also leads to a preference for deductibles affront to most principles of equity.
(Arrow, 1963). Suppose, as seems realistic, that the
loading is not simply proportional to the size of the Left to itself, adverse selection would destroy the
premium but is arelativelyhigh proportion of small market entirely. In practice this does not happen,
claims (say, checking for fraud, etc., is equally partly because insurance plans are often based on
costly for probable and less probable events). Then, employee groups in which a condition of employment
as the limit of acceptable (to the consumer) loading may be that each joins the company plan; so opting
47
OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POLICY, VOL. 5, NO. 1
Many, moreover, can be expected to find their risk- hazard is at best fuzzy. The other is that if hospital
aversion insufficient to warrant insurance of any and other services are priced at above marginal cost,
kind. second-best considerations would dictate that the
usual welfarist efficiency condition of P=MV may
(ix) Moral Hazard no longer apply. Consumers may be receiving false
signals about marginal cost from market prices and
Another difficulty with insurance systems is known should probably be encouraged to consume beyond
as moral hazard. One form of this has already been the rate at which P = MV, quite apart from any
met in the shape of supplier-induced demand, which externality considerations, even if this implies even
is a kind of producer's moral hazard, whereby bigger rents for monopoly suppliers of health care,
producers (on a fee for service system of reimburse- as income is redistributed from the insured to the
ment) have an incentive to adjust the client's de- suppliers via the insurers.
mand in pursuit of their personal income objec-
Figure 5
The Welfare Loss of 'Excess' Health Insurance
price
48
A. J. Culyer
While the likely offence to equity principles is reveal their preferences (viz. that the agency rela-
plain, the efficiency implications are less obvious tionship is perfect).
in a welf arist context. With full' first-pound' cover,
and zero marginal (money) user price, the sick Provided that it is not accompanied by compensating
individual may be expected to consume OQ units of X-inefficiencies, a system of compulsory universal
health care in Figure 5, given that he or she is sick, public insurance operated through the general tax
at which point MV = 0. This generates a welfare system may have substantial cost advantages over
loss of abQ: the amount by which the cost of competitive insurance: compulsion avoids adverse
providing Q*Q units exceeds their value to the selection and enables scale economies to be gained
individual (Q*abQ-Q*aQ). This analysis assumes (if they exist), reducing loading and increasing the
that consumer marginal willingness to pay is ade- welfare gains from comprehensive insurance cover.
quately reflected in the demand curve and that OP Universality and tax finance avoid the necessity of
is the marginal social opportunity cost risk assessment and premium setting, billing,
( x ) . . . and Where Does this Get Us? (xi) The Welfarist Approach: an Overview
Insurance is shown plainly to have welfare-increas- The welfarist techniques of analysis have been the
ing properties though it seems clear also that opti- traditional way in which issues of health service
mal insurance may be less than complete insurance: finance have been addressed in the economics
some events should be uninsured and for others less literature. Granted the acceptability of welfarism's
than 100 per cent of the risk will be optimal. This value assumptions, its implications for policy hinge
analysis does not, however, take account of any on judgements about the empirical significance of
contrary indications suggested by externality or consumer rationality, the 'purity' of the agency
equity factors and is entirely dependent on the relationship, the nature of any externalities (physi-
strong assumption that consumer choices adequately cal or utility interdependence or group-concern),
49
OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POLICY, VOL. 5. NO. 1
the extent of adverse selection, moral hazard, sup- 'basic capabilities': a person being able to do
plier induced demand, unnecessary premium load- certain things. It is, he suggests, because a cripple
ing under insurance and the empirical validity of is unable to perform particular activities that he or
the neoclassical behavioural model that, in its nor- she is seen as having special 'needs' that are inde-
mative version, is welfarism's centrepiece. Each pendent of his or her total or marginal utility.
will draw his or her own conclusions based on the Culyer (1989) advocates the more general notion of
(patchy) evidence and more casual experience. 'characteristics of people'—for example, their ge-
netic endowment of health, their relative depriva-
tion independently of the absolute consumption of
III. THE DCTRA-WELFARIST APPROACH commodities or the characteristics of commodities,
theirmoral 'worth' and 'deservingness', whetheror
Whereas welfarism holds that standards of living, not they are in pain, or stigmatized by society.
50
A. J. Culyer
more cost-effective) way of realizing it. Since age use of care that contributes to the objective of
inputs are nearly always substitutable, it will not maximizing health. There are also implications for
normally make sense to say that a specific resource rationing care (equalizing marginal products in
in a specific quantity is needed. Since there is no terms of health per unit of resource), selecting
effective treatment for some conditions, it is non- patients from waiting lists, conducting cost-benefit
sensical to say that persons suffering from such analyses in the health service.
conditions need health services (they may need the
fruits of research and they may need love and com- At the core of the extra-welfarist approach is, of
fort, but they cannot need ineffective care, even course, the issue of how the maximand is to be
though they may demand it, and such care may also measured. This has proved to be an issue involving
damage health). Since health services are needed much cross-disciplinary collaboration between (for
only for what they enable to be accomplished, in a example) economists, physicians, psychologists,
world of scarcity judgements must be made about and political scientists which has exposed the
51
OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POLICY, VOL. 5, NO. 1
(1) criteria for selecting characteristics were However, such measures present a potential prob-
usually unspecified lem. The literature frequently characterizes meas-
ures of health as utility measures (e.g. Torrance,
(2) the scaling systems often implied only 1986). Here it is important to distinguish between
order but were subsequently used to con- the welfarist notion of utility as welfare and the
struct a cardinal index extra-welfarist notion. Under Paretianism, for
example, the notion of welfare relates to goods and
(3) the possibility that combinations of char- services and is the utility of the individual affected
acteristics may have higher or lower num- by their consumption. Under extra-welfarism, while
bers than the sum of the separate scores was this notion of utility may still apply, there is the
often excluded further idea that uses utility theory in order to derive
52
A. J. Culyer
As a result, and given the difficulties in defining the cycle relative to others. It is also planned to
relationship between health measures and utility unscramble the life-cycle phases into elements that
measures discussed above, one of the normative are age-, role-, and sex-related.
issues that the extra-welfarist approach identifies
(but does not resolve) concerns who shall decide the If ethical authority is to be accorded these (or
weights to be applied to different health states and similar) results, a departure is implied from the
to the components of health states. Who shall distributive value-judgement normally (if only
decide the categories of functioning, etc. to be provisionally) embodied in measures ofhealth such
considered? Who shall decide who shall decide? as QALYs: that a unit ofhealth' is of equal value
no matter who gets it. It thus seems possible that
The answers may well depend upon the nature of distributive judgements will be able to be built into
the problem under consideration: politicians, civil outcome measures and, via cost-effectiveness analy-
ses, into efficiency analysis (e.g. Culyer, 19886).
53
OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POLICY, VOL 5, NO. 1
includes children being bom who would not other- differences in measure that have been observed as
wise have existed In the welfarist tradition this between rating scales, standard gambles, and time
poses a problem because although it might be trade-offs (e.g. Torrance, 1976, Bombardier etal.,
possible to find out how extra QALYs are valued, 1982). His analysis hinges on a distinction between
it is not possible to find out how the unborn value the utility gained as the result of one's own choice
being born. But this also poses a problem for the and 'choiceless' utility: viz. the utility 'experi-
non-welfarists in so far as they too wish to ascribe enced* as the consequence of a happening gener-
a value to unborn lives—as well as the lives of the ated in any other way. The importance of the
children of the unborn, and so on ad infinitum. distinction lies in the fact that only in the former is
Unfortunately, we have no basis at present for there the possibility that, in an uncertain world, you
valuing population changes, therefore (says Broome) may come to regret or rejoice over a decision you
we have no basis for valuing life or QALYs. have made. The rating method does not involve
54
A. J. Culyer
seek to control producer moral hazard by reimburs- justified by equity arguments but efficient policies
ing providers only for procedures that are demon- justified by heath maximization.
strably relatively cost-effective in restoring health
and in any clinical research with a similar objective. There is a danger in extra-welfarism of becoming
In this territory, extra-welfarists have been more too fixed on the' bottom line'. The great advantage
active empirically than welfarists typically have the approach can claim in issues like outcome
beea measurement is rather like the claim made earlier
on behalf of welfarism: it provides a conceptual
As a matter of necessity, the literature has focused framework for handling extremely complex issues
on the difficult issues of measuring health itself (or in a systematic fashion and that exposes each aspect
changes in it) in order to improve the ability of the of an argument clearly. It is less important what the
system to produce health cost-effectively. It is cost-per-QALY is, than that individuals with re-
quite possible for these efforts also to serve the sponsibility for resource allocation in health care
55
OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POLICY, VOL. 5, NO. 1
REFERENCES
Arrow, K. J. (1963), 'Uncertainty and the Welfare Economics of Medical Care', American Economic Review,
53,941-73.
Auster, R. D. and Oaxaca, R. L. (1981), 'Identification of Supplier Induced Demand in the Health Care Sector',
Journal of Human Resources, 16,327-42.
Beck, R. G. (1974), 'The Effects of Co-payments on the Poor1, Journal of Human Resources, 9,129-42.
Bergson, A. (1938), 'A Reformulation of Certain Aspects of Welfare Economies', Quarterly Journal of
Economics, 52,310-34.
Bombardier, C , Wolfson, A. D., Sinclair, A, J. and McGreer, A. (1982), 'Comparison of Three Preference
Measurement Methodologies in the Evaluation of a Functional Stratus Index', in Deber, R. and Thompson,
G. (eds.). Choices in HealthCare: DecisionMakingandEvaluationofEjfectiveness,ToTontQ,\JniveTsily
56
A. J. Culyer
Farley, P. J. (1985), 'Who are the Underinsured?', Milbank Memorial Fund Quarterly, 63,476-503.
Fuchs, V. (1978), 'The Supply of Surgeons and the Demand for Surgical Operations' Journal of Human Resources,
13, 35-56.
Green, J. R. (1978), 'Physician-Induced Demand for Medical Care', Journal of Human Resources, 13,21-34.
Grogono, A. W. and Woodgate, D. J. (1971), 'Index for Measuring Health', Lancet, 1024-6.
Harris, A. et al. (1971), Handicapped and Impaired in Great Britain, London, HMSO.
Harsanyi, J. (1955), 'Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparsions of Utility', Journal
of Political Economy, 63,4, 309-21.
Jewkes, J.,Jewkes,S., Lees, D.S.andKemp, A. (1963), 'Ethics and the Economics of Medical Care—Discussion',
Medical Care, 1,234-44.
Kant, I. (1930), Lectures on Ethics, London, Macmurray.
Klarman, H. E. (1963), "The Distinctive Economic Characteristics of Health Services', Journal of Health and
Human Behaviour, 4,44—9.
— (1965), 'The Case for Public Intervention in Financing Health and Medical Services', Medical Care, 3,
57
OXFORD REVIEW OF ECONOMIC POLICY, VOL. 5, NO. 1
Rice, T. H. (1983), 'The Impact of Changing Medicare Reimbursement Rates on Physician Induced Demand',
Medical Care, 21, 803-15.
— (1987), 'Comment on "Induced Demand—Can we Ever Know its Extent?" By Charles E. Phelps', Journal
of Health Economics, 6,375-6.
Rosser, R. (1983), 'Issues of Measurement in the Design of Health Indicators', in Culyer (1983).
Schoemaker, P. J. H. (1982), "The Expected Utility Model: Its Variants, Purposes, Evidence, and Limitations',
Journal of Economic Literature, 20,529-63.
Sen, A. K. (1977), 'Social Choice Theory: A Re-examination', Econometrica, 45,53-90.
— (1979), 'Personal Utilities and Public Judgements: or What's Wrong with Welfare Economics', Economic
Journal, 89, 537-58.
— (1980), 'Equality of What?', in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press.
Shavell, S. (1978), 'Theoretical Issues in Medical Malpractice', in Rottenberg, S. (ed.). The Economics of Medical
58