Stekauer 1011
Stekauer 1011
Stekauer 1011
PAVOL ŠTEKAUER
FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF
AN ONOMASIOLOGICAL THEORY OF ENGLISH WORD-FORMATION
Abstract
This article presents an outline of the fundamental principles of an onomasiological theory of word-
formation which departs from the existing theories of word-formation in English in a number of essential
points. Word-formation is conceived of as an independent component interconnected with the lexical
component and separated from syntax. Word-formation rules generate fully regular and predictable naming
units The conception of productivity as a cluster of word-formation types makes it possible to consider
word-formation rules as productive as syntactic rules. The idea of the word-formation component that
responds to naming needs of a speech community allows for elimination of the overgeneration principle in
morphology. Introduction of the so-called Form-to-Meaning Assignment Principle makes it possible to put
all the traditional word-formation processes on a unified basis. The advantages of the outlined theory are
illustrated by a series of examples.
Introduction
The theory presented here was inspired by two main sources. First, the work of Miloš
Dokulil (1962, 1966, 1968), a prominent representative of the Prague School of Linguistics.
From him, I took over the idea of an onomasiological structure. While there are a number
of points in which I have deviated from Dokulil’s approach (perhaps due to my reaction to
the generative word-formation of the post-1970 period) I find his 1962 book one of the
most ingenious works on word-formation, and a constant source of valuable ideas.
My next source is my teacher and the most prominent Slovak morphologist, Ján Horecký, in
particular his multilevel conception of the linguistic sign (1983, 1989). Furthermore, the
theory presented here came into existence as a reaction to the predominant formalism of
generative morphology. Having been a student of Josef Vachek, the most prominent
personality of the Prague School of Linguistics in the second half of the 20th century, I find
the form-meaning unity to be a fundamental premise of my onomasiological theory.
Consequently, the conception proposed here differs in many respects from the mainstream
generative theories of word-formation, introduces a new approach to word-formation, and
2
It should be noted, however, that the onomasiological approach is not the only one to
emphasize the necessity to examine both meaning and form of word-formation units and
structures. A most valuable exception to the prevailing tendency in the generative word-
formation is represented by Robert Beard’s Lexeme-Morpheme Base Morphology
(LMBM) elaborated in a series of works, with a comprehensive account being given in
Beard (1995). With Beard I share the view that there exists a universal set of supralinguistic
cognitive categories (Subjective [i.e. Agent], Objective, Instrumental, Locational,
Diminution, Augmentation, etc.) from which the individual languages select, with the core
of these categories appearing in all languages. Beard separates a deep, abstract, semantic
process of the so-called Lexical derivation from affixation. The actual affixes (devoid of
their independent meaning) articulate meaning indirectly, depending on the context, and are
introduced by a separate, extralexical morphological spelling (MS) component.1 While my
OT may also be labelled as a ‘separation hypothesis’, with the cognitive processes preceding
the affixation proper, my treatment of affixes significantly differs from that by Beard. In my
theory, affixes are bilateral, meaning-form units, with their semantics playing an important
role in the matching procedure at the onomatological level (see below for the details). While
Beard “evicted” affixes from the “community” of major classes (N, V, A) by claiming
that—like articles, adpositions, conjunctions, and some pronouns—they “bear no semantic
content but reflect grammatical functions which are managed by other components,
specifically by the lexicon and syntax” (Beard 1995: 20) I find affixes to be on a par with
lexemes (both are form-meaning units). These general differences find their expression in
our respective treatment of a number of more specific issues. 2
Cognitive grammar (CG), in reaction to the formalism of generative grammar, also offered
a highly attractive alternative. Onomasiological theory and cognitive grammar have some
features in common, notably the emphasis on the semantic facet as an indispensable facet of
any unit above the level of phonology. I share the view of the cognitive grammar that all
units above the phonological level are bilateral form-meaning complexes, a view which was
very strongly articulated in the structuralist theories of the Geneva School and the Prague
School. To use the terminology of cognitive grammar, grammar is “symbolic”, and each
symbolic unit has its semantic pole and phonological pole. Both OT and CG maintain that
the overall meaning of complex words is not equivalent to the compositional value of the
constituents. Langacker (1988b: 49) puts it to the very point: “a description of grammatical
structure that makes no reference to meaning is ultimately no more revealing than a
dictionary providing only a list of undefined forms”.
Nevertheless, these common features concern the most general principles. The two theories
differ in their scope, goals pursued, methods employed, and their respective internal
organisation. The scope and goals of cognitive grammar are much more ambitious than
those of my onomasiological theory. While the former covers grammar as a whole the latter
focuses on one part of the grammar, i.e. the word-formation component (and accounts for
its relations to the other components of grammar). The former provides a description of the
system of grammar as it is and as it functions in parole, i.e. how symbolic units come to
mean what they mean. It gives a description of the existing system of symbolic units used
for communication purposes. On the other hand, onomasiological theory gives a dynamic
account of how complex words come into existence. Its scope is thus the generation of new
1
For a moderate version of this approach see Jan Don (1993).
2
For a detailed analysis of Beard’s theory see Štekauer (2000).
3
complex naming units, in accordance with Marchand’s (1960: 2) requirement that “[w]ord-
formation can only treat of composites which are analyzable both formally and
semantically”.
The account of the semantic structures in cognitive grammar is interwoven with pragmatics;
in other words, cognitive grammar does not separate semantics from pragmatics:
“Cognitive grammar explicitly equates meaning with ‘conceptualization’ (or ‘mental
experience’), this term being interpreted quite broadly. It is meant to include not just fixed
concepts, but also novel conceptions and experiences, even as they occur. It includes not just
abstract, ‘intellectual’ conceptions, but also such phenomena as sensory, emotive, and kinesthetic
sensations. It further embraces a person’s awareness of the physical, social, and linguistic context
of speech events” (Langacker 1988a: 6).
Onomasiological theory in its fundamental focus is not concerned with pragmatic aspects,
and concentrates on langue, on the system level of language. The principles of internal
organisation of the two systems differ significantly. Langacker postulates different levels of
abstraction both at the semantic level and phonological level. The higher level structures
function as schemas for more specific symbolic units. Word classes such as Nouns, Verbs,
etc. instantiate more abstract “things”, and “actions”, respectively. Thus, thing and action
are schemas for the respective categories of word class. In OT, the parallel notions
(SUBSTANCE, ACTION, CONCOMITANT CIRCUMSTANCE, QUALITY) represent
the most general conceptual categories which are not instantiated as Nouns, Verbs, etc.;
rather they range over word classes. Thus, for example, ACTION can be expressed by
V and N, QUALITY by N, A, etc. Importantly, however, these conceptual categories
operate in connection with what I call logico-semantic categories (i.e. theta roles,
arguments, etc.) such as Agent, Instrument, Patient, Location, Temporal, Direction,
Factitive, etc. The relation of these conceptual categories to word-classes is (unlike CG)
indirect, mediated, depending on the logical spectrum, the specific onomasiological
structure, and the FMAP principle, i.e. on which morphemes are selected to match the
semes of the onomasiological structure. In other words, they do not function as schemas for
the respective word-classes.
In CG, suffixes do not fall within the schemas like Thing , Action. In the OT, affixes are on
a par with stem morphemes, and can represent respective conceptual categories. In CG, a
compound like pencil-sharpener instantiates a complex schema THING - PROCESS - ER,
which, as a complex symbolic structure, is constituted by a hierarchy of symbolic structures
of ever-increasing complexity. The individual constituents of the individual levels of
complexity reflect the order in which symbolic units are successively combined in formation
of a complex expression. Every node of representation of such a complex symbolic
structure is a symbolic structure per se, incorporating both semantics and phonology.
The OT generation of such a complex word does not rest on several levels of bilateral units
of different level of complexity. Rather, it starts from the conceptual structure, proceeds
through the semantic structure which is then expressed morphematically by matching the
4
semantic primitives occurring in the onomasiological structure with the morphemes of the
corresponding meaning. By implication, the “symbolic nature” is arrived at at the lowest but
one level of the OT.
Before proceeding to an outline of the theory, some terminological remarks are necessary.
The fundamental method applied in my approach is called onomasiological. This term
should be distinguished from the term onomatology. Vilém Mathesius (1975: 16), the
founder of the Prague School of Linguistics distinguishes between functional onomatology
as the study of naming units, i.e. complex words, on the one hand, and functional syntax
defined as the study of the means by which naming units are brought into mutual relation.
The term onomasiology is usually used as an antonym to semasiology. While the latter
concentrates on the analysis of an existing lexis in order to identify any regularities in the
lexicon, the former concentrates on the dynamic aspect of word-formation: it accounts for
the generation of new complex naming units. By implication, like onomatology, it also
refers to the process of naming. Nevertheless, as demonstrated below, it is useful to
distinguish between the level of onomasiology (naming in a more abstract sense) and the
level of onomatology (naming process in a more specific sense).
Another new term which requires explanation is naming unit. This term was first introduced
by Mathesius (1975). In my approach, it substitutes for terms like word, lexeme, lexical
unit, etc., because of their inconsistent use and varying connotations in linguistic literature.
Naming unit refers here to a complex unit generated by the Word-Formation Component.
From this it follows that an onomasiological theory of word-formation deals with coining
new naming units.
not all new product names fall within the scope of the theory of word-formation because,
many times, one encounters names resulting from an irregular process labelled by Marchand
(1960) as word-manufacture.
EXTRA-LINGUISTIC REALITY
SPEECH COMMUNITY
WORD-FORMATION
LEXICAL COMPONENT
COMPONENT
LIST OF NAMING UNITS
(Structured into paradigmat- Conceptual level
ically-based groups) (Logical structure)
LIST OF AFFIXES
(including complete combina- Semantic level
bility information) (Semantic structure)
Onomasiological level
(Onomasiological structure)
Phonological level
(Phonological rules)
Each naming process is preceded by scanning the Lexical Component on the part of a
particular member of a speech community who is going to assign a name to the object to be
named. The scanning operation determines further procedure. Either a completely new
naming unit is coined by taking the path of the Word-Formation Component; or, if a naming
unit is found in the Lexical Component which can serve as a basis for semantic formation, it
is the path of the Lexical Component which is preferred (hence, two downward arrows
from “Speech Community” in Figure 1).
formation and syntax. These two independent components are related through the Lexical
Component. The link to the Syntactic Component is exclusively via the Lexical Component.
The principle of separation of the Word-Formation and the Syntactic Components indicates
that new naming units are not generated from syntactic structures. The rejection of
productive syntactically based word-formation processes follows naturally from my
onomasiological model, which relies on the vocabulary material, on the material of the
system level of language as contained in its Lexicon. The grounds for this claim are closely
related to the assumption that it is the Word-Formation Component (in co-operation with
the Lexical Component) which supplies syntax with material for its sentence structures, and
not vice versa. The process of word-formation is not that of asserting something. It is the
process of naming. Hence, the basic unit of word-formation is the naming unit. It suffices to
add that word-formation is about naming units in isolation, and not about their use (the
latter being the matter of syntax). Word-formation is about naming units coined as signs
and analysed as units existing in paradigmatic relations in the vocabulary. Here, the term
paradigmatic relations refers (a) to structural relations among naming units (synonymy,
homonymy, hyponymy, etc.), and (b) to word-internal relations among word-forms. In the
latter case, the paradigm is conceived as a set of forms provided with morphosyntactic
characteristics; any such form can be retrieved by the Syntactic Component and inserted in
the particular sentence structure.
2.1. All naming units falling within the scope of the onomasiological theory, that is to say,
all naming units coming into existence in the Word-Formation Component, are coined by
productive and regular Word-Formation Rules (= WF Types). Hence, each immediate
output of a Word-Formation Rule is predictable. In addition, each new naming unit
produced by a Word-Formation Rule is passed to the Lexical Component. This approach
makes it possible to simplify and regularize the Word-Formation Component because any
idiosyncratic changes take place in the Lexicon by way of semantic formation or formal
modification. As a result, Word-Formation Rules are no less productive than Syntactic
Rules or Inflectional Rules. This conclusion is in accordance with Dokulil’s (1962: 223)
view:
“If a naming unit, already existing in the language, is applied to a new concept (on account of a
metaphorical or metonymical connection of the new concept with the one primarily referred to by
the concerned naming unit), this can be denoted as a case of ‘formation’ of a new naming unit
only in a conditional sense. In this case (the so-called semantic formation), that is to say, only the
number of the meanings of a naming unit is increased, not the number of the naming units
themselves. It is true that the resulting polysemy of the concerned naming unit may consequently
lead to dissolution of the naming unit into a number of homonyms, but such dissolution does not
constitute an active process of word-formation. One has to do here with the result of the semantic
development of a polysemous word in specific historical conditions.”
7
2.3. Since each act of naming responds to the immediate naming need of a speech
community, the output of Word-Formation Rules is an actual word, i.e. a naming unit
which was coined to satisfy a linguistic demand, be it the demand of a single member of a
speech community, be it a single-act one-off demand. It should be emphasized that the
frequency of usage, or the “common (general) use”, or “common parlance” as a criterion
for the status of existing (occurring) words is unacceptable not only because of the
vagueness of the notion “common (general) use”, but also because the frequency of usage
can only be applied to words that have already been coined, i.e. to actual (existing) words
(or to nonce-formations). Therefore, for a word to qualify for the status of an actual word,
it must have been coined. Whether its use will be spread over the whole speech community
(implying frequent use), or whether it will be confined to a single use on the part of a single
speaker, is insignificant. What is important is that the respective language has manifested its
productive capacity to provide a new, well-formed linguistic sign by its productive Word-
Formation Rules whenever need arises. By implication, the inclusion in my system of the
extra-linguistic factor (speech community) enables me to eliminate the notion of
overgeneration.
3. Lexicon-Based Theory
3.1. It follows from the above outlined tenets that my theory is built up on the postulate that
all new naming units are coined on the basis of the material available in the system of the
language, notably in the Lexicon, or the Lexical Component. No use is made either of the
speech level (parole) or syntactic constructions (langue) as possible sources of new,
productively coined naming units. It may be added that no naming unit can be generated
8
from units smaller than the morpheme, with the morpheme being defined traditionally as the
minimum bilateral sign, having its own specific form and specific meaning.
3.2. The Lexical Component is not a mere list. Given my paradigm-based approach to the
Lexicon, I prefer to replace the term list with the term component, that is to say, the Lexical
Component. It is subdivided into a number of groups (paradigms) reflecting manifold
morphosyntactic, lexical, and semantic relations. The basic criterion is that of the category
of word-class. In addition, each complex naming unit coined by a productive and regular
Word-Formation Rule brings along the conceptual and the semantic structure and the
phonological features as part of its “outfit”. The monemic part of the Lexical Component is
specified for its features directly in the Lexical Component. And finally, any idiosyncrasies
are, naturally, reflected in the changed location of a particular naming unit within the
paradigmatic structure of the Lexicon.
3.3. Thus, the Lexical Component encompasses all monemes, all productively and regularly
coined naming units, and irregular coinages as well as borrowings, plus a separate list
including all productively used affixes, and finally phrase-based coinages which are
apparently of syntactic origin and are characterized by a high degree of structural
irregularity (see Point 11 for the discussion on these naming units).
3.4. It follows that (a) the Lexical Component contains both the regular naming units
(products of Word-Formation Rules) and idiosyncratic coinages, and (b) a big part of the
Lexicon is represented by all naming units which have been coined by regular and
productive rules of word-formation in response to the naming needs of the particular speech
community. The emphasis on the attributes productive and regular indicates that Word-
Formation Rules do not generate idiosyncratic naming units. Any deviations from the
fundamental regular and productive patterns take place in the Lexicon in connection with
the process of lexicalization. Then, the irregular meanings of naming units such as
transmission (a part of a car), professor, or to use Chomsky’s examples like revolve vs.
revolution as in the French revolution, or construct vs. construction as in the Anglo-Saxon
genitive construction, do not result from Word-Formation Rules. The idiosyncratic
meanings of these and other regularly coined naming units are produced by operations of
semantic formation (i.e., semantic shift—extension of meaning, specialisation of meaning,
metaphor, metonymy, synecdoche, etc.) within the Lexicon. This is also the answer to the
Chomskian claim that words which result from derivational processes often depart from
their “expected meaning”. To sum it up, while the Word-Formation Component generates
new naming units, the Lexical Component is designed for storing all naming units and
affixes. The former are organised in external paradigms (the relationships of polysemy,
hyponymy, synonymy, etc.) and internal paradigms (word classes, case paradigms,
conjugation classes, etc.). This “store” feeds both of the components it is linked to. It feeds
the Word-Formation Component with word-formation bases and affixes for the sake of
generating new naming units, on the one hand, and the Syntactic Component with
morphosyntactically specified word-forms from internal paradigms. In addition, since all
naming units “spend their life” in the Lexical Component and since they are not absolutely
resistant to the influence of linguistic and extra-linguistic factors they may undergo semantic
and/or formal modifications traditionally labelled as lexicalization. This account overcomes
the problem of semantically ‘irregular’ products of productive Word-Formation Rules by
insisting on their absolute regularity, with any modifications and idiosyncratic changes
taking place in the Lexicon.
9
3.5. By the same token, clippings (ad, lab, maths, etc.) cannot be included in the Word-
Formation Component. First, word-formation deals with coining new naming units, new
signs. Clipped words, however, are not new signs. They preserve the same meaning as their
corresponding full forms. Hence, it is the mere process of form-reduction rather than the
naming process which takes place. Wolfgang U. Dressler holds the same position; he does
not include the formation of abbreviations among synchronic WFRs by emphasizing that (a)
these result from diachronic changes and (b) there is no change in word-formation meaning
(Dressler et al. 1987: 106-107). Klaus Hansen refers to them as “bloße Umformungen
bereits vorhandener Lexeme” and “stilistisch markierte Wortvariante” (Hansen et al. 1982:
146).
4.1. This principle follows from de Saussure’s (1989) conception of sign and Ján Horecký’s
(1983, 1989) model of linguistic sign. The basic tenet is that naming units are bilateral
signs, including the meaning and the form. This determines the scope of word-formation:
there are no naming units in the Word-Formation Component that are pure forms
(formemes), i.e., formal elements without any meaning have no place in OT. Words like
perceive, conceive, contain, retain, receive, cranberry, vacant, paucity, possible, Monday,
etc., are treated as synchronically unanalysable units (monemes). “Bound morphemes” such
as per-, con-, re-, -ceive, -tain, pauc-, vac-, cran-, etc., in no way comply with the
traditional sign-based definition of the morpheme as a bilateral unit with two facets: the
form and the meaning. They have form; however, they do not have any meaning that might
take part in constituting the meaning of a new naming unit. Therefore, from the point of
view of word-formation, words like those mentioned above should be conceived of as
word-formation-irrelevant monemes. These segments resemble, in terms of their function,
phonemes: the latter, too, are merely forms without any meaning. Their basic function is to
distinguish the meaning of words. Hence, the function of pauc-, vac-, cran-, Mon-, etc.,
can be reduced to that of a phoneme, i.e., to the meaning-distinctive function, which
cannot be confused with the meaning-forming function. The latter is bound to bilateral
units, i.e., morphemes.
4.2. There is still one group of ambiguous naming units. It can be exemplified by automatic,
hierarchy, mechanism, friction, configuration, etc. The analysis of these and similar naming
units results in a suffix plus “another component” that, though not corresponding to any
other root word, occurs in several formally and semantically related naming units (e.g.
automate - automatic - automation - automaton - automatics - automatism). Obviously, the
“another component” is not limited to single occurrence, and we can associate it with a
distinct meaning. By implication, such a component functions as a word-formation base for
the coining of all the related words. Therefore, it will be useful to consider this component
as a word-formation base. In contrast with the former instances, one can apply the principle
of double analogy (both constituents are bilateral and occur in other naming units, too).
10
5. Speech-community-oriented theory
The theory presented here does not rest on the intuition of a native speaker. Rather, it
attempts to describe word-formation processes resulting from the naming needs of a given
speech community. As a result, the theory takes into account only actual naming units;
therefore, the notion of possible word plays no role in this theory, which makes it possible
to do away with the overgenerating capacity of word-formation rules.
The method outlined below allows for doing away with the traditional notions of
“compounding”, “prefixation”, “suffixation”, “back-formation”, “blending”, etc. As a result,
it is possible to put all naming acts on a common footing, this being a considerable
advantage in discussing the issues of productivity, “bracketing paradoxes”, “back-
formation”, “exocentric compounds”, “blends”, etc. (see below).
8. Scope of Word-Formation
Based on the principles stipulated in 1 through 7, and keeping in mind minor exceptions,
such as phrase-based formations, the scope of word-formation within the onomasiological
theory presented here can be defined as follows: Word-formation deals with productive,
regular, and structurally predictable onomasiological and word-formation types producing
motivated naming units in response to the naming needs of a speech community, by making
use of word-formation bases of bilateral naming units and affixes stored in the Lexicon.
9.1. It follows from Figure 1 that the model of word-formation includes the following
levels:
1. Speech community
2. Extra-linguistic reality
3. Conceptual level
4. Semantic level
5. Onomasiological level
6. Onomatological level
7. Phonological level
11
The primary task to be mastered is to analyze the object (in the broadest sense of the word)
to be named (or better, a class of objects). This is the task of the conceptual level which,
based on the processes of generalization and abstraction, reflects the complexity of the
object in the form of a logical spectrum delimiting the object by means of logical
predicates (noems), and by making use of the most general conceptual categories
(SUBSTANCE, ACTION [with internal subdivision into ACTION PROPER, PROCESS,
and STATE], QUALITY, and CONCOMITANT CIRCUMSTANCE [for example, that of
Place, Time, Manner, etc.]).
Individual logical predicates of this supralinguistic level are captured by semes (the notion
of “seme” is conceived of here in accordance with the notion of “semantic marker” used in
the theory of componential analysis) constituting the semantic structure of the linguistic
sign.
At the onomatological level, the onomasiological structure is assigned linguistic units based
on the Form-to-Meaning-Assignment Principle (FMAP). Specifically, individual
members of the onomasiological structure (selected semes) are linguistically expressed by
12
word-formation bases of naming units, or affixes, stored in the Lexicon. The fact that all
naming units are based on assigning linguistic units (word-formation bases and affixes) to
semantic components constituting an onomasiological structure enables me to dispense with
the traditional notions of word-formation processes, including compounding, affixation,
back-formation, or blending. In other words, generation of all naming units is put on a
uniform basis. The advantages of such an approach will be demonstrated below.
9.2. From the point of view of the final form of a naming unit it is important to determine
what kind of onomasiological structure will be employed in the naming act.
9.2.1. The first possibility is that all three constituents are included in the new naming unit
(NU), i.e., the onomasiological base, and the determined and the determining constituents
of the onomasiological mark (language teacher, truckdriver, housekeeping, etc.). Since all
the three fundamental onomasiological constituents are linguistically expressed this
onomasiological type can be labelled as Complete Complex Structure (CCS)
(Onomasiological type I - OT I), and naming units coined according to this onomasiological
type will be labelled as CCS naming units.
Example:
Let us suppose that we want to coin a naming unit denoting a person whose job is to drive a
vehicle designed for transportation of goods.
Conceptual level:
It is SUBSTANCE1.
SUBSTANCE1 is Human.
The Human performs ACTION.
ACTION is the Human’s Profession.
ACTION concerns SUBSTANCE 2.
SUBSTANCE2 is a class of Vehicles.
The Vehicles are designed for Transporting various goods.
Etc.
Semantic level:
[+MATERIAL] [+ANIMATE] [+HUMAN] [+ADULT] [+PROFESSION];
[+MATERIAL] [-ANIMATE] [+VEHICLE] [+TRANSPORTATION], etc.
Onomasiological level:
The below representation indicates that—based on the conceptual analysis of the object to
be named—the coiner identified the actional relation between the two SUBSTANCES as
crucial for his naming intention. Therefore, in the process of naming, SUBSTANCE1 and
SUBSTANCE2 were made the polar members of the onomasiological structure (the
onomasiological base and the leftmost constituent of the onomasiological mark):
SUBSTANCE - SUBSTANCE
In addition, the CCS type (OT I) was selected. The onomasiological connective can be
expressed as follows:
with Ag(ent) standing for SUBSTANCE1 (onomasiological base), Act(ion) for ACTION
(the determined constituent of the onomasiological mark), and Obj(ect) for SUBSTANCE2
(the determining constituent of the onomasiological mark).
Onomatological level:
Based on the Form-to-Meaning-Assignment Principle, the onomasiological structure is
assigned linguistic representation based on the material available in the Lexical Component
(bilateral units included in the Lexicon, either in the form of naming units entering into new
naming units as word-formation bases, or affixes). Here, there are several possibilities.
Thus, Ag(ent) can be expressed by man, -er, -ist, -ant etc.; Act(ion) can be expressed by
word-formation bases of naming units drive, steer, operate, etc., and (logical) Obj(ect) can
be represented by truck or lorry. In general, selecting out of the available options partly
represents the creative aspect within the productive process of coining a new naming unit
and partly is controlled by the limitations of word-formation rules, affix subcategorization,
specific constraints, sociolinguistic factors, etc.. The selected options in our particular case
are as follows:
Obj - Act - Ag
truck drive er
Phonological level:
Here, the new naming unit is assigned its stress pattern and undergoes relevant phonological
rules.
An example of Onomasiological Type I with the specifying and the specified elements is as
follows:
SUBSTANCE - SUBSTANCE
Obj [+PLURAL] - Act - Ag
where computer is the specifying and systems the specified elements of the onomasiological
mark.
9.2.2. Another possible case is that the determining constituent of the onomasiological
structure is left unexpressed. This type is labelled as Incomplete Complex Structure R
(ICSR) (Onomasiological type II - OT II), and the respective naming units will be referred
to as ICSR NUs (writer, teacher, drive shaft). Letter R refers to the expressed right-hand
constituent, i.e., the determined constituent of the onomasiological mark.
Example:
Let us suppose that we want to coin a naming unit denoting a mechanical component used
for securing other components.
Conceptual level:
It is SUBSTANCE1.
SUBSTANCE1 is Inanimate.
The Inanimate SUBSTANCE 1 is Material.
SUBSTANCE1 is designed for ACTION.
14
Semantic level:
[+MATERIAL] [+INANIMATE] [+MECHANICAL COMPONENT]
[+SECURING], etc.
Onomasiological level:
As indicated by the following onomasiological structure, the conceptual analysis led the
coiner to put emphasis on SUBSTANCE1 and ACTION, obviously for the reason that
SUBSTANCE2 cannot be precisely delimited, or its delimitation is insignificant. Hence, the
onomasiological structure is as follows:
ACTION - SUBSTANCE
In addition, the ICSR type (OT II) has been chosen. The onomasiological connective can be
expressed as follows:
Act - Instr(ument)
Onomatological level:
9.2.3. The third type covers those cases in which the determined (actional) element is not
linguistically expressed. What is included is the onomasiological base and the determining
constituent of the onomasiological mark (called “motive” by Miloš Dokulil [1962]). I shall
refer to this onomasiological type as Incomplete Complex Structure L (ICSL)
(Onomasiological type III - OT III), and the respective naming units will be referred to as
ICSL NUs. Letter L refers to the expressed left-hand constituent, i.e., to the determining
constituent of the onomasiological mark. This type roughly corresponds to traditional
“primary” or “root” compounds, but also to some affixation types (policeman, honeybee,
hatter). An important subtype of OT III is that with the determining constituent of the
onomasiological mark structured into the specifying and the specified elements.
Example:
Let us suppose that we want to coin a naming unit denoting a person making hats.
Conceptual level:
It is SUBSTANCE1.
SUBSTANCE1 is Human. The Human performs ACTION.
ACTION is the Human’s Profession.
ACTION produces SUBSTANCE 2.
SUBSTANCE2 is a class of coverings for the head.
Etc.
Semantic level:
[+MATERIAL] [+ANIMATE] [+HUMAN] [+ADULT] [+PROFESSION];
[+MATERIAL] [-ANIMATE] [+COVERING FOR A HEAD], etc.
15
Onomasiological level:
In the process of naming, the coiner decided that the polar members of the onomasiological
structure become SUBSTANCE1 and SUBSTANCE2, supposedly for the same reason as in
the case of truck-driver above:
SUBSTANCE – SUBSTANCE
In addition, the ICSL type (OT III) has been selected. The onomasiological connective can
be expressed as
Fact - (Act) - Ag
with Ag standing for SUBSTANCE1 (onomasiological base), (Act) for formally unexpressed
ACTION (the determined constituent of the onomasiological mark), and Fact for
SUBSTANCE2 (the determining constituent of the onomasiological mark).
Onomatological level:
9.2.4. Moreover, there is also a group of simple structure NUs in which the
onomasiological mark cannot be analysed into the determining and the determined parts
(lionhearted, restart). This onomasiological type will be designated as Simple Structure
type (SS) (Onomasiological type IV - OT IV), and the corresponding naming units as SS
NUs.
Example:
Let us consider, for example, the OT account of coining the word lion-hearted. It is coined
on the basis of the following conceptual analysis:
SUBST - QUALITY
If the onomasiological Type IV is chosen for naming, the onomatological structure after
application of the Form-to-Meaning-Assignment Principle will be as follows:
Pattern - Quality
lion heart ed
16
where lion is the specifying and heart the specified element (not the determining and the
determined constituents!) of the onomasiological mark.
9.2.5. The last type is represented by what is traditionally called conversion or zero-
derivation (OT V), and which is based on the so-called Onomasiological
Recategorization. Since this onomasiological type differs in its nature from the other
onomasiological types, notably by absence of an onomasiological structure, I will briefly
sketch its basic principles. The basic features of conversion in English are as follows:
(a) In my approach to conversion, the first crucial point consists in the fact that each naming
unit results from an intellectual analysis of an extra-linguistic object to be named. Within
this analysis, the object is classed within one of the four above-mentioned conceptual
categories: SUBSTANCE, ACTION (with subcategories ACTION PROPER, PROCESS,
STATE), QUALITY, or CONCOMITANT CIRCUMSTANCE. The individual aspects of
the extra-linguistic reality do not, however, exist in isolation; on the contrary, they can be
conceived of and subsequently linguistically expressed in various relationships, from
different points of view. These different “angles of reflection” of the extra-linguistic reality
can be cognitively brought into a close relation by re-evaluating the already existing logical
spectrum and all the related lower levels. Then, the most striking feature of conversion is
that it always linguistically expresses the conceptual recategorization of the extra-linguistic
reality (see Figure 2). Thus, for example, databank represents a SUBSTANCE. When,
however, conceptually recategorized, it becomes an ACTION; experiment expresses a
PROCESS—after recategorization it refers to an ACTION PROPER; limit is a
CIRCUMSTANCE—after recategorization it obtains as an ACTION; feature is a
QUALITY—its recategorization yields an ACTION; insert is an ACTION—when
recategorized it becomes a SUBSTANCE; stand belongs to a STATE—when recategorized
it becomes a SUBSTANCE; etc.
What is the mechanism of these changes? Individual logical predicates are of different levels
of abstraction and generalisation, thus constituting a hierarchy. When a new, dominating,
logical predicate is added to such a hierarchy or a former dominating logical predicate is
removed, the hierarchy is changed, and becomes dominated by a new logical predicate
which determines the conceptual category of a new extra-linguistic object to be named. The
conceptual re-evaluation of the extra-linguistic reality precedes the linguistic processes
proper. It is the conceptual recategorization which provides us with evidence that
conversion cannot be identified with zero-suffixation: conceptual recategorization is vital
for conversion while only possible for suffixation.
Let us illustrate the point. The naming unit milk belongs to the conceptual category of
SUBSTANCE. It has its typical hierarchy of logical predicates (from the most general to
the most specific one). When the hierarchy within the logical spectrum is changed, the
recategorization from SUBSTANCE to ACTION takes place. Thus, a central position
within the hierarchy of logical predicates in one of the converted meanings of milk (‘to
obtain milk from a female mammal’) is assumed by a predicate focusing on the actional
aspect of the extra-linguistic object (see the scheme above). The changed hierarchy within
the logical spectrum is then reflected in the hierarchy of semes within the semantic structure
of the converted naming unit.
Instr/Purp
switchN – switchV: SUBSTANCE ACTION
(in the meaning of a device for completing or breaking an electric circuit)
Interpretation: Substance as an Instrument of Action
Temp
timeN – timeV: CIRCUMSTANCE ACTION
Interpretation: Action in terms of Temporal dimension
Obj/Dir
magazineN – magazineV: SUBSTANCE ACTION
(the verb is a technical term for placing parts into a magazine)
Interpretation: Substance specifies Object as well as Direction of Action
Fact
driftN – driftV: STATE ACTION
Interpretation: Action results in State
18
Obj
insertV – insertN: ACTION SUBSTANCE
Interpretation: Substance as an Object of Action
Abstr
transportV – transportN: ACTION PROCESS
Interpretation: Abstraction of Action
Fact/Dir
curveV – curveN: ACTION CIRCUMSTANCE
Interpretation: Circumstance of Directional nature as a Result of Action
Hypost/Inh
terminalA – terminalN: CIRCUMSTANCE SUBSTANCE
Interpretation: Hypostasis of Circumstance, which becomes Inherent to Substance
Fact
clearA – clearV: QUALITY ACTION
Interpretation: Action Resulting in a certain Quality
Instr/Purp
switchN - switchV: SUBSTANCE ACTION
(in the meaning of a device for completing or breaking an electric circuit)
Interpretation: Substance as an Instrument of Action
Fact
correctV - correctA: ACTION QUALITY
Interpretation: Action Resulting in a certain Quality
It follows from this account that what was necessarily expressed by the second (zero)
constituent in the zero-derivation theory, governed by the binary-structure principle, is, in
the OT approach, first integrated into the logical spectrum and then correspondingly
reflected at the lower levels of the onomasiological model.
(c) A different word-class of a converted naming unit relative to its motivating counterpart
is another striking feature of English conversion. It also presents another very strong
argument against the zero-derivation theory. While suffixation can be divided into class-
changing and class-maintaining, all new converted coinages—irrespective of considerable
semantic differences—behave equally in this respect: all types of conversion are class-
changing.
(e) Obviously, all previous changes must be reflected in the paradigmatic and syntagmatic
behaviour of new coinages. Thus, for example, the conversion of displayN (meaning ‘a
device for presentation of alphanumeric or graphic information’) to displayV (meaning ‘to
19
present on a display’) changes the position of the new coinage within the sign-external
paradigmatics (different relations of synonymy, homonymy, hyponymy, etc.) and the
internal paradigmatics (of the display, to the display, display (pl.) vs. I display, you display,
he displays, ..., displayed, displaying, ...) as well as different syntagmatic relations
(following from different syntagmatic functions within sentences). The same applies to
conversion in the displayN->A direction. Since this approach to conversion results from the
application of the onomasiological theory, this onomasiological type is labelled as
Onomasiological Recategorization.
9.2.6 Is conversion directional? The issue of directional nature of conversion has been
discussed by a number of authors and would deserve a separate article. Therefore I will only
briefly outline some of the existing proposals and then summarise the OT position as given
in Štekauer (1996). Rochelle Lieber (1981) rejects the zero-morpheme theory of
conversion and argues that no directional rules can account for the facts of conversion in
English. In her view, conversion is a redundancy relation in the permanent lexicon.
Individual items like paintN and paintV should therefore have separate lexical entries.
Importantly, however, Lieber maintains that conversion is another field of word-formation
which lacks isomorphy between the lexical structure and lexical semantics: while the
“syntax” of conversion is non-directional, the semantics of conversion may be governed by
directional rules.
According to this criterion, the verb saw must be derived from the substantive saw. SawN is
defined by Marchand as ‘a cutting instrument with a blade, having a continuous series of
teeth on the edge’. That the instrument may be used for the action of sawing need not be
included, in Marchand’s view, in the definition. SawV is defined by him as ‘use a saw, cut
with a saw’, where the semantic features of the noun are included.
for sawing’ and ‘to cut with a toothed instrument’. These definitions are perfectly
acceptable though they would indicate a reverse ‘derivational’ dependence. Moreover,
Marchand analyzes knifeV as ‘wound with a knife’ and notes that the “substantive knife does
not lean on any content features of the verb knife, which does not exist in the vocabulary of
many speakers who commonly use the noun”. These words indicate that his analysis is
influenced by the frequency of use, a criterion separately mentioned later in his paper. On
the other hand, his analysis of whistle takes the opposite direction in spite of the fact that
both knife and whistle semantically are ‘instruments for performing some action’. In such a
case, it is difficult to see any grounds for unequal semantic analyses of the relations between
the members of the above-mentioned conversion pairs. Moreover, Marchand’s definitions of
whistleV-N ‘forcing the breath through the teeth or compressed lips’ vs. ‘instrument used for
whistling’ do not appear to be more natural or obvious than the following pair: ‘to use a
whistle’ vs. ‘an instrument operated by air expelled from lungs’.
The flaws of Marchand’s criterion were also noticed by Ljung (1977). Ljung (1977: 165)
points out that “when we try to apply Marchand’s criterion [i.e. of semantic dependence,
P.Š.], it immediately becomes clear how elusive it is. The criterion of semantic dependence
rests on the assumption that there are ‘natural’ definitions for the members of the pairs
under consideration here. A case in point is sawN:sawv. Contrary to Marchand’s assumption
(1955: 172) it is possible to ‘saw without a saw’ just as it is possible to hammer without a
hammer”.
Representatives of level-ordering theories (e.g., Allen, Kiparsky) maintain that the direction
of conversion can be determined according to phonological (mostly stress) and
morphological (combinability of affixes) criteria. For illustration, Allen points out the
existence of condition-alA, and the absence of *condition-iveA and other analogical cases.
Both –al and –ive are Level 1 suffixes: -al attaches to nouns, -ive to verbs. The non-
existence of *condition-iveA thus can be accounted for by the fact that conditionV is not
available at Level 1. By implication, the direction of conversion in the case of condition (and
other analogical words) is N V.
In his highly interesting theory of conversion, Don (1993), who rejects zero-based accounts
of conversion, derives the evidence of directionality from the analysis of morphosyntactic
features of conversion pairs in Dutch. Thus, for example, conversion “determines gender if
it is noun-forming, and mode of inflection when verb-forming. Furthermore, several
distributional properties of conversion can only be explained if we assume that it is
directional in nature” (Don 1993: 211).
What then is the OT approach to this issue? First, in view of the theory of onomasiological
recategorization it is necessary to distinguish the word-formation process itself and its
semantic aspect as expressed by the logico-semantic relation between the concepts
interrelated by recategorization. The analysis of conversion pairs in Štekauer (1996)
indicates that the logico-semantic relations between the related concepts do not depend on
the direction of conversion. For example, based on the etymological data, the direction of
conversion for bond is SUBSTANCE → ACTION (Noun → Verb) while that for reject is
ACTION → SUBSTANCE (Verb → Noun). In both cases the concepts are related by the
logical-semantic relation of Factitiveness.
On the other hand, the very fact that OT considers conversion to be the process of word-
formation means that it is a directional process. Here it is worth returning to Marchand’s
21
example of saw. The account of directionality can possibly be based on the extralinguistic
reality, i.e., on the natural subsequence of emergence of the respective phenomena. In this
particular case, first, there must have been an instrument permitting the performance of an
action by means of that particular instrument. With whistle, the direction is reversed. This is
quite obvious, because the primary ‘instrument’ for the given action is our lungs, lips, etc.
They permit the action. Thus from the point of view of the criterion of extralinguistic
subsequence, whistle (instrument) is secondary with regard to the action of our body
organs. It follows that the directionality criterion can in some cases be shifted to the highest
levels (extralinguistic reality) of the word-formation model.
Nevertheless, in the vast majority of cases, this way of determining the “derivational”
relation resembles the familiar “chicken-or-egg” problem: for instance, (computer)
program, interface, link, design. There does not seem to exist any generally applicable
criterion. Therefore, the only way out seems to consist in the complementary effect of a
multiplicity of criteria, including the criterion of extralinguistic subsequence, diachronic
data, formal criteria (like stress pattern), morphosyntactic effects (like in Don’s approach),
structural relations (combinability with affixes), etc.
10.1. In the present model of word-formation, the onomatological level is the place of
determining the category of word-class and the related morphosyntactic features. The
category of word-class is important because, among other things, there are some stress-
assignment rules (phonological level of the model) which are word-class-dependent. For
example, there are some conversion pairs (onomasiological type V) which depend for their
stress upon the word-class of individual conversion pair members, for example, construct,
increase, replay, isolate, abstract, concrete, absent, etc. These differences are not limited
to the instances of the Onomasiological Recategorization type. Therefore, the phonological
component must “know” the category of a naming unit to be assigned a stress.
10.2. A frequently discussed issue is how a new coinage is assigned its category of word-
class and other related morphosyntactic characteristics. The majority of morphologists share
the view that these features are inherited from the head (Marchand’s determinatum). Less
agreement obtains in regard of how the head should be identified. Allen (1978) formulated
her principle under the label of IS A CONDITION, Williams (1981) introduced the Right-
hand Head Rule (RHR) which defined head positionally as the right-hand member of the
word, and Selkirk (1982) proposed a revised RHR because the original RHR appeared to
suffer from many flaws. Williams himself accepted the criticism and, in his joint work with
Di Sciullo (1987), modified the RHR in the form of a relativized head always defined as the
rightmost element of the word marked for the particular feature. In any case, the number of
various approaches to “headedness” indicates the overall uncertainty of morphologists
concerning its identification and overall function. Zwicky criticized those feature percolation
conceptions according to which morphosyntactic features percolate to the complex word
from the head constituent of that word. In his view, “the location of inflectional marks is not
to be managed via percolation, [...] category of determination resides not in constituents but
in rules [my emphasis, P.Š.] performing morphological operations” (Zwicky 1985: 2).
The OT theory presented here takes an approach different from the existing conceptions.
Štekauer (in print) gives arguments in favour of identifying the head with the
onomasiologiocal base. It should be emphasized once more that the latter always refers to a
22
class of objects, a genus, etc. Consequently, rather than identifying head either positionally
or morphologically (a particular morpheme of a naming unit) the proposed approach shifts
the criterion of headedness to the extralinguistic level, in particular, to the conceptual level
of coining new naming units. By implication, head can be a suffix, a prefix, or a word-
formation base. Given this principle, behead, is analysed as follows:
ACTION SUBSTANCE
Act → Obj
be head
where Act is the onomasiological base. It refers to a general class of FACTITIVE Actions
directed at Objects. The Action is more general than the specific Object, in this case head.
Similarly, the meaning of re- (REPETITION of an Action) in restart is more general than
the Action specified. In other words, any particular Action can be repeated or returned to
the original state. Another example, which is treated differently in the literature, concerns
words like greenish (cf. Bauer 1990). Here, -ish is the onomasiological base because its
meaning is much more general (APPROXIMATION) than that of green. Similar
considerations apply to diminutives, such as duckling. -ling (DIMINUTIVE) is more
general than duck. This assessment of evaluative affixes differs from that of Scalise (1988)
who maintains that evaluative affixes violate the Unitary Output Hypothesis3 and, therefore,
cannot function as heads.
A question may be raised concerning the identification of head in structures containing both
prefix and suffix. The onomasiological model of word-formation does not (advantageously)
generate naming units by means of concatenation of the individual word-formation
processes (binary principle), for example, (de + ((centreN + alA)A+ izeV)V)V; rather new
naming units are formed by the so-called FMAP principle which matches the morphemes
stored in the Lexicon with the individual constituents of the onomasiological structure
within a single act of assignment. Consequently, this theory may appear to be in a tight
situation if it is required to determine which of the affixes stands for the onomasiological
base (head) in words like decentralize, ungrammatical and a number of other similar prefix-
suffix structures; that is to say, which of the affixes represents a more general class. The
problem follows from the fact that it is hardly possible to classify various affixes in terms of
more or less general semantic classes.
The OT model postulates that if a speech community needs a new naming unit, the object of
the extra-linguistic reality is intellectually analyzed at the conceptual level by means of
logical predicates. Thus the process of analysis which underlies, for example, the naming
unit decentralise, is roughly ‘ACTION1 of making something central which is Negated by
ACTION2’. Clearly, the ‘Action of Negation’ is logically superordinate to ACTION1. This
conceptual analysis is born out at the onomatological level. The FMAP principle must
observe the subcategorization of affixes stored in the Lexicon. Therefore, the operation of
the FMAP principle is both vertical and horizontal. Vertically, the semantic facet of the
morphemes must match the meaning of the semes of the onomasiological structure (in our
example, de- stands for Negating Action; central corresponds to the specific Qual; and -ize
3
The Unitary Output Hypothesis assumes that the “output of a rule of suffixation is always the same
independent of the base (1988: 232)“, which means, for example, that the form of a rule such as
[[ ]X +hood]N, <+abstract>,<-count><+common><...>
will have the same form irrespective of the content of X, that is, no matter whether X is a Noun or an
Adjective (wifehood/livelihood) or whether X is a proper Noun or a common Noun
(Christhood/sisterhood).
23
to the specific Act); horizontally, the individual morphemes must be mutually compatible.
Thus, de- requires verbal category on the right-hand side (no matter what the right-hand
constituent’s internal structure is, i.e., whether it is a single morpheme or a combination of
morphemes); on the other hand, ize- subcategorizes for both adjectival and substantival
partners on its left-hand side, and is thus semantically less coherent (see Aronoff 1976). In
addition, it does not combine with negated adjectives or nouns. The onomasiological
structure delimited by its polar members
ACTION – ACTION
will thus be
The FMAP principle assigns the specific word-formation base and affixes. In addition, the
FMAP evaluates the respective compatibilities of de- and -ize, and permits the combination:
Since it is the Negating Action which dominates the conceptual and onomatological level
analyses, the head is represented by the prefix de.
Štekauer (in print) demonstrates that all heads identified as onomasiological bases are in a
position to transfer their features to the respective naming units. The morphosyntactic
information need not, however, percolate directly from the head. Prefixes are envisaged to
have a decision-making capacity—they either determine the category directly (class-
changing prefixes) or indirectly (class-maintaining affixes); in the latter case, they
acknowledge the category of the particular naming unit. While suffixes seemingly fulfil the
same function, as it were, straightforwardly (inflectional morphemes as indicators of
morphosyntactic features are simply attached to them), prefixes seem to do it as mediators.
10.3. Thus, the onomasiological base is postulated to determine the word-class category
and the related morphosyntactic features of a new naming unit. Furnished with this
information, each coined naming unit is passed to the phonological level where it can be
specified in terms of stress, and other rules determining the phonological form of naming
units, for instance, the Trisyllabic Laxing Rule. The phonological aspects of word-formation
have been much discussed in literature under various labels (for example, Siegel’s Level
Ordering Hypothesis, Allen’s Extended Ordering Hypothesis, Kiparsky’s Cyclic Phonology,
etc.), and a number of rules were aptly formulated.
10.4 These issues are closely related to the relation between the Word-Formation
Component and the Lexical Component in terms of restrictions imposed on the
combinability of individual word-formation constituents. It is generally known that not all
combinations of morphemes are permissible. Generally, the permissibility is governed by
specific properties of an affix, and can be expressed in its subcategorization frame. In my
model, it is supposed that affixes represent a separate list in the Lexicon, with each affix
(just like any other naming unit in the Lexicon) having its specific entry. While
morphosyntactic properties of naming units, necessary for combining them to form
sentences, follow from their membership in the respective paradigm (to which each naming
unit is automatically integrated according to the features of the onomasiological base in
24
10.4.1. Kiparsky (1982a) mentions the suffix -al which is only added to verbs stressed on
the last syllable, e.g. arríval, revérsal vs. *depósital, *recóveral. In his view, the cyclic rule
of stress assigning to verbs must precede the suffixation by -al, which is predicted by
Kiparsky’s scheme of lexical phonology. In my model, this condition would be specified in
the entry of the suffix -al. Since the phonological level of the model has access both to the
list of affixes and to the paradigmatically classified naming units in the Lexical Component,
the condition (restriction) is simply applied by checking both the affix for the respective
condition, and the naming unit (whose word-formation base is assigned to the respective
logical-semantic unit by the FMAP) for its stress.
10.4.2. The frequently adduced (e.g. Halle 1973) example of restrictions imposed by the
inchoative suffix -en can be explained in a similar way. It means that the condition according
to which the affix attaches only to monosyllabic stems and, moreover, only if they end in an
obstruent, optionally preceded by a sonorant (blacken, whiten, toughen, dampen, harden,
*dryen, *dimmen, *greenen, *laxen) will be stated as a specification of the affix. Moreover,
there are also examples in which this restriction appears to have been violated, for -en has
attached to a stem ending in two obstruents /ft/ or /st/: soften, fasten, moisten. These
examples illustrate an operation of the phonological rule which deletes the /t/. Then the -en
is attached to a stem which complies with the phonological condition, namely sof-, mois-, or
fas-. This form-adjusting rule is included in the phonological level of my model, and
operates in close “co-operation” with the suffix because, thanks to the direct
interconnection of the phonological level and the list of affixes, it can “see” the restriction
specified in the affixal entry.
10.4.3. The entry for the suffix -able must contain the information that this suffix combines
only with transitive verbs. In other words, the onomatological level has access to the
Lexicon. In this particular case, it has access to the paradigm containing the respective verb
whose word-formation base is to be combined with the suffix -able by means of the FMAP.
Logically, the onomatological level does not “scan” all the verbs in the Lexicon. Its task is
simplified by all transitive verbs being grouped in the “Transitive Verb Paradigm ”.
10.4.4. The suffix un- will be specified for stress assignment. In particular, it is provided
with information that it carries a secondary stress when occurring in adjectives containing
the suffix -able. As mentioned above, the word-class category of a naming unit being coined
is specified at the onomatological level. Therefore, the phonological level at which stress
changes occur can act based on the word-class specifications imposed by the
onomatological level plus the stress condition specified for the suffix in its entry. Certainly,
the entry of un- contains another condition, notably that it can be combined with word-
formation bases of adjectives, and that the meaning of such adjectives should be positive.
Therefore, the onomatological level automatically “retrieves” the “Adjectives with Positive
Meaning Paradigm”.
25
10.4.5. The example of the ‘truncation rule’ (nominate - nominee, evacuate - evacuee)
mentioned by Aronoff (1976) fits my scheme, too. The entry of the suffix -ee contains a
condition stating that if the immediately preceding constituent (word-formation base of a
verb) assigned by the FMAP ends in the -ate cluster, the latter will be deleted. The
operation of form adjustment takes place at the onomatological level based on the
information from the affixal entry. The same principle applies to Aronoff’s examples of
allomorphy rules (electrify - electrification).
10.4.6. Certainly, selectional restrictions apply to word-formation bases, too. It is assumed
that selectional restrictions are not changed by application of Word-Formation Rules.
Therefore, if the verb refuse requires an animate subject, this restriction is also transferred
to the noun refusal coined by employing the word-formation base of the naming unit refuse.
As a result, refusal automatically takes over this feature in the Lexicon, and is classed in the
paradigm containing all similar nouns. Any deviations are reflected in the changed place of
the respective naming unit within the system of paradigms of the Lexical Component.
10.5. Let us illustrate the way the individual naming units are represented in the Lexicon. As
already mentioned the Word-Formation Component forms new naming units by means of
word-formation bases of naming units stored in the Lexicon, and it supplies the Lexicon
with new naming units. Each new naming unit comes to the Lexical Component with its
specific categorial features. Thus, for example, a new-coined noun is allocated to the
respective class of regular or irregular nouns based on the nature of the naming unit/affix
which enters into a new naming unit as its onomasiological base. Based on these features,
the new naming unit is classed with a large group of naming units, each of them having the
same paradigm (in inflectional languages, for example, identical noun case endings, or
verbal person endings, etc.). Each such paradigm-based group can be further subdivided, for
example, in terms of the transitive-intransitive opposition, etc. This approach can best be
illustrated by inflectional languages like Slovak. Here, for example, agent nouns can be
formed by the suffix -el’ added to verbal stems: riadit’-el’ (manage-er), ucit’-el’ (teach-er).
Individual case-morphemes, specific for the seven cases of declension both in singular and
plural, depend on the category of word-class (noun, in this particular case), gender
(masculine), gender declension pattern (each formal gender (masculine, feminine, neuter -
the latter is of formal nature in Slovak; therefore, for example, dievca (girl) is a neuter
gender noun) distinguishes four patterns depending on a feature like [Animate], the
vowel/consonant opposition with regard to the final phoneme, the nature of the immediately
preceding phoneme, etc.). Syntax, then, has access to the individual paradigm -based groups,
and retrieves those word-forms which correspond to its particular sentence-generation
needs. The same principles can be applied to English in a fairly simplified way owing to the
lack of inflectional morphemes in English. Moreover, the same principle holds for the
argument structure of verbs. The constituent underlying the onomasiological base assigns a
new naming unit the respective word-class and subcategory (e.g. intransitive/transitive).
Based on this criterion, or any other criterion defining the argument structure, a new
coinage is identified with a particular argument structure subcategory in the Lexical
Component, and is taken from the Lexicon when syntax requires it.
It was already mentioned above that not all naming units neatly fit the ideal onomasiological
model (actually, is there any model without exceptions?!) of word-formation according to
which all naming units are formed by productive WFRs and the linguistic material is taken
by FMAP from the Lexical Component. An obvious exception to the rule is a group of
syntax-based formations like sit-around-and-do-nothing-ish, leave-it-where-it-is-er, son-in-
26
A question may be raised at this place: Do these naming units comply with one of the basic
tenets of the theory presented here, i.e., the premise that new naming units are coined by
productive and regular WFRs? The answer cannot be unambiguous. OT distinguishes
between the onomasiological level and the onomatological level. The former generates a
structure constituted by semes which come to be represented by morphemes. By
implication, any WFR results from an interaction between the two levels. As indicated
above, no problems concern either onomasiological structure or the application of FMAP to
the onomasiological base. The pitfall concerns the application of FMAP to the
onomasiological mark. Given these circumstances, it may be concluded that the basic
27
principle is partly complied with: these naming units might be said to be generated by
productive rules which result in a partly irregular structure.
12. Nonce-Formations
(a) It goes without saying that from the point of view of a speaker (or better, a coiner),
every nonce-formation is accurately delimited and well defined. Consequently, context-
dependence is the matter of the listener/reader, and it takes the nature of degree:
monosemous naming units are less context-dependent than polysemous naming units;
morphologically transparent naming units are less context-dependent than the
morphologically vague ones (compare the lower dependence of words with unambiguous
word-class compared to converted naming units, or the context-dependence of lexicalized
naming units [in Bauer’s sense of this term] vs. fully transparent naming units); naming units
of the core part of the lexicon are less context-dependent than those at the periphery
(compare the words of everyday use and those of any scientific terminology, or commonly
known words vs. slang or argot expressions).
Context-dependence is a vague notion at least for the following reasons: (i) each naming
unit, no matter how well it is integrated in the system, is used in its typical “context”, unless
certain stylistic objectives require its use in the “context” of a different register; (ii) context-
dependence is always the matter of speech (parole) and never that of system (langue): at
the system level, every naming unit is accurately defined and has its distinct meaning and
function; (iii) a closely related issue is the meaning of “context” based on which a naming
unit may be context-free for a specific subset of a speech community (for those in the know,
e.g. experts in a particular field of science) and fully context-dependent for another subset
of a speech community; (iv) and finally, context-dependence (again at the speech level) may
also result from the analytic nature of English (for example, the identical external form of
conversion pairs; but the same holds of word-forms—because of the lack of inflectional
morphemes it is only the specific context which determines the function of the respective
form in a sentence—this is, however, not to say that such word-forms are not distinctly
defined by their fixed place in the paradigmatic system!).
(c) Since nonce-formations are, in Hohenhaus’ view, not listed, they must be interpreted “in
a constructive way”. The interpretation of nonce-formations cannot rely on “genericness”
considered by Hohenhaus to be a crucial factor conditioning the listing of a naming unit. In
28
his view, genericness means “keeping a word in order to have it at hand ready-made for
future use, which must be worth it. Listing something which is highly unlikely ever to be
usable again would not make much sense” (Hohenhaus 1998: 263).
This account necessarily raises doubts. What does it mean “to be worth listing” and “highly
unlikely to be usable again”? How can anybody know whether or not a particular new
coinage is worth storing in the Lexicon? By exaggerating a little bit: should these decisions
be taken by a special-purpose linguistic institution? And furthermore, how can we foretell
the fate of the apple-juice seat type words, or any other “nonce-formation” types? How can
one be sure about apple-juice seat not becoming one of the central items of household
architecture or restaurant organisation sometimes in future (for example, conditioned by a
new trend in nutrition, architecture, etc.)?
When coined each naming unit is an attempt, a very real word-formation attempt, i.e. an
actual naming unit. It comes into existence as a response to a specific demand of (a
certain number of members, or only one member of) a speech community, and it is this
demand which justifies the existence of such a coinage. As such, it becomes an offer for the
remaining part of the particular speech community. If accepted by (a specific group, i.e.
subset of) the speech community, it becomes integrated for (possibly) long-term use, if not,
it drops out of the system. In any way, however, the worthiness and the likeliness of use
are terms upon which no theory of word-formation can be built.
In addition, it should be noted that the frequency of usage, or the “common (general) use”,
or “common parlance” as a criterion for the status of existing (occurring) words is
unacceptable not only because of the vagueness of the notion “common (general) use”, but
also because the frequency of usage can only be applied to words that have already been
coined, i.e. to actual (existing) words (or, to nonce-formations conceived of as the first
stage in the “life” of any new naming unit).
This issue, however, is not so unproblematic. There is a hitch in it. It concerns some syntax-
based formations. The majority of “shorter” syntax-based formations fit well the conception
of nonce-formations outlined above. They are productively coined (though feature partial
structural irregularity) and some of them even survive the test of time (for example, matter-
of-factness, out-of-the way, son-in-law, lady-in-waiting, milk-and-water, save-the-whales
campaign, etc.) and become integrated in the system of language; some “longer” units are
no doubt disposable coinages. A case in point is Jerome K. Jerome’s “pearl” from his Three
Men in a Boat: There is a sort of Oh-what-a-wicked-world-this-is-and-how-I-wish-I-could-
do-something-to-make-it-better-and-nobler expression about Montmorency... It goes
29
without saying that such a coinage has no chance to survive in the Lexicon. In principle,
there is no structural difference from the other syntax-based units. It differs from the
storable ones in extreme length which is obviously the main obstacle to memorizing and,
therefore, to keeping this unit in the Lexical Component. Thus, rather than the structural
factor, or the factor of context-dependence (this naming unit can be perfectly understood
out of context) it is an utmost pragmatic factor of human memory capacity which makes
this naming unit an ad-hoc coinage. A similar view is presented by Dressler (1982: 174): “If
we take one of the (universally accepted) functions of WFRs, i.e. that of enlarging the
lexicon [...] by the labelling of concepts, then clearly there is less pragmatic need to label
concepts of such complexity that phrasal or even sentential bases must be used [...] Here the
semiotic principle of the optimal size and sign may be invoked: Too big a sign(ans) is
difficult to perceive for the hearer and to store for the speaker and hearer”. A question is
whether, how, and to what degree this kind of factors should be incorporated (is
incorporateable) in any theory of word-formation. For the time being, I must leave this
question open.
[[transformational][grammarian]],
[[transformational grammar][ian]],
in terms of morphology because the comparative affix -er only attaches to monosyllabic and
some disyllabic words; however, the meaning of unhappier is ‘more unhappy’ rather than
‘not happier’. Therefore, semantically it must be bracketed as
This kind of paradox follows from the generally applied binary principle. Since the
onomasiological theory with its FMAP does not rely on a binary word-formation structure,
the problem of bracketing paradoxes is meaningless. Moreover, the proposed approach is
based on the principle that the relations in question are not hierarchical. The members of the
onomasiological structure (the base, the determining and determined constituents of the
mark, and the specifying and specified elements of the determining constituent) function at
the same level of description (onomasiological level) Thus, transformational grammarian
can be analysed as follows:
30
Conceptual level:
‘a person dealing (professionally) with transformational grammar’
(where transformational is the specifying element and grammar the specified element of the
onomasiological mark).
Conceptual level:
‘a state of not being happy; this state is characterised by a higher degree relative to the
original state’
13.2.1. One of the traditional divisions of compounds in English is that into endocentric and
exocentric compounds. While the former are characterised by the binary structure of
determinant - determinatum with the compound being a hyponym of its determinatum
(head), the latter (redskin, pickpocket, hunchback, paleface, five-finger, scatterbrain, etc).
are said to have zero determinatum, i.e., one lying outside the compound (Marchand 1960:
11); therefore, the compound cannot be a hyponym of the determinatum. In this section, I
will present a different approach and argue that these compounds are generated in the same
way as endocentric compounds. The reasons for this assumption are as follows:
(i) The psychological reasons for this approach can be found in both classical structuralist
and onomasiological approaches. Marchand (1960: 11) points out the general tendency of
speakers “to see a thing identical with another already existing and at the same time
different from it”. This principle, labelled by Kastovsky (1982: 152) as an “identification-
specification scheme” is a key to one of the fundamental principles of Marchand’s and
Kastovsky’s theories based on the binary, syntagmatic, structure of motivated words. Each
word-formation syntagma is based on the determinant/determinatum relation, where the
latter “identifies” and the former “specifies”. The same principle underlies the
onomasiological conception. Dokulil (1962: 29) maintains the following:
“The phenomenon to be named is usually identified with a specific conceptual class having its
categorial expression in the particular language and subsequently, within the limits of this class,
it is determined by a mark. The conceptual class enters the onomasiological structure as a
determined constituent—the onomasiological base, the mark as a determining constituent—the
onomasiological mark. The onomasiological base may stand for a conceptual genus or a more
general conceptual class”.
31
Finally, natural morphology claims the same, though in a different way. The most “natural”
are those coinages which are most diagrammatic (a new meaning is accompanied by a new
form), for instance, read-er where there is “a diagrammatic analogy between semantic and
morphotactic compositionality (or transparency)” (Dressler et al. 1987: 102).
(ii) There is no reason to surmise that there is any other cognitive process underlying a small
group of “exocentric compounds” deviating from the identification-specification scheme
because this way of conceptual analysis is the essence of naming in general.
13.2.3. An important piece of evidence supporting the approach outlined here is the
irregular plural. It is generally known that compound nouns are not pluralised by attaching a
plural ending to the compound as a whole; rather, they take over its plural form from the
right-hand constituent. Therefore, the plural of milktooth is not *milktooths, but milkteeth,
the plural of postman is not *postmans, but postmen, etc. Now, taking the example
mentioned by Sproat (1988: 349), the expected plural of the “exocentric” sabertooth is
*
saberteeth, which is not the case. Implicitly, tooth is not the right-hand member. Since
I—as opposed to Kiparsky (1982a) or Sproat (1988) (who accounts for exocentric
compounds by applying the so-called Mapping Principle primarily used in his approach to
“Bracketing Paradoxes”)—reject the notion of zero-morpheme in word-formation, a
solution must be sought elsewhere. The “elsewhere” is provided by the above-given
approach. Based on a conceptual analysis we can identify the onomasiological base as a
SUBSTANCE representing a class of animals (or more specifically, a class of tigers). The
onomasiological mark identifies its subclass. The FMAP then yields an auxiliary naming unit
saber-tooth tiger, or more generally, saber-tooth animal (both the more general and the
more specific forms fit our purpose; in other words, what matters here is the
onomasiological structure, and not the onomatological structure). In any event, the actual
onomasiological base, and—at the same time—the right-hand constituent of the naming unit
forms its plural in a regular way (i.e., tigers, animals). Since it is the plural of the right-hand
member (onomasiological base) of a complex naming unit, the plural of sabertooth is
sabertooths.
13.2.4. Let us illustrate this theory by presenting some more examples. The naming unit
redskin has been traditionally identified as an “exocentric compound” because (as opposed
to “endocentric compounds”) redskin is not a kind of skin. By applying the onomasiological
model of word-formation we arrive at the following abridged analysis of redskin:
SUBST - SUBST
Stative - Patient
Stative - Patient
redskin person
The auxiliary naming unit obtained is an “endocentric compound”. The second step consists
in elliptical shortening, which is reflected in the notation by bracketing the base member of
the structure. As with all clippings, the lexical and grammatical features of a full naming unit
are passed over to its clipped version (in this particular case, it is the word-class of Noun,
and lexical class of Human Beings). This is indicated by an arrow:
Similarly:
killjoy is ‘a person who usually kills joy’ (killjoy person);
wagtail is ‘a bird that characteristically wags its tail’ (wagtail bird);
turnstone is ‘a bird that typically turns stones’ (turnstone bird);
catchfly is ‘a plant that typically catches flies’ (catchfly plant); etc.
To sum it up, this account rests upon the principles of Marchandian structuralist theory, the
onomasiological principles of the functional Prague School tradition, and on the principles
of Natural Morphology. It should be stressed that the facts of naturalness should not be
confined to the processing stage of language use, i.e. to parole. Naturalness is an
indispensable feature of dynamic processes shaping the langue. Therefore, we may assess
word-formation units in terms of what is the most natural way of their coming into
existence.
13.3. Back-formation
separately, fully consistent with the onomasiological model and the Form-to-Meaning-
Assignment Principle. This can be exemplified by stage-manager and stage-manage:
SUBSTANCE - SUBSTANCE
Obj ← Act - Ag
stage manage er
Obj ← Act
stage manage
13.3.2. In the case of naming units of the peddler type only the “longer” word falls within
the scope of word-formation: As indicated above, peddler must have come into existence in
some way. Therefore, an auxiliary naming unit peddle is postulated for the sake of coining
the “longer” word. Later on, it became “actualised” based on the demand of a speech
community. However, being a moneme, it became actualised directly in the Lexicon.
13.4. Blending
The process of “blending” can also be treated as a two-step process. The first step consists
in coining an auxiliary “full version” naming unit consistent with the onomasiological model
of word-formation. Such a naming unit is then formally reduced in an unpredictable (and
hence, irregular) way which cannot be captured by a regular Word-Formation Type. Such a
change then necessarily takes place in the Lexical Component.
14. Iconicity
14.1. In the following paragraphs I will attempt at outlining the OT approach to the much-
discussed problem of iconicity (for example, Mayerthaler 1977, 1981, Dressler 1977, 1981,
1982, Dressler et al. 1987). An ideal case of constructional iconicity in word-formation is
one in which a new meaning is represented by a specific morpheme: “An icon is established
as in the sign read-er. There is a diagrammatic analogy between semantic and morphotactic
compositionality (or transparency). Let us denote semantic compositionality with (A+B)
and morphotactic compositionality with (a+b) [...] Then we can say that A, the meaning of
read, is represented symbolically/conventionally by a = E[nglish] read-, B, the meaning of
agency, by b = suffix –er” (Dressler et al. 1987: 102). This account is based on the binary
principle in describing complex naming units. Here, as already indicated above, one can see
a substantial difference between the OT and the generative approaches. A complex word,
such as structuralization has been traditionally generated in three steps, each including two
constituents, which may be represented by labelled bracketing in:
All of the structural constituents are bilateral signs, thus representing an ideal case of
constructional iconicity in word-formation. On the other hand, OT forms this naming unit in
a different way. It proceeds from conceptual representation through semantic one towards
34
formal representation, and the bilateral units are introduced by the FMAP principle at the
onomatological level. By implication, unlike the generative treatment, structuralization is
formed within a single step by matching the morphemes (stored in the Lexicon) with the
semes of the onomasiological structure. From this point of view, an ideal case of iconicity
(diagramaticity) is one in which all constituents of the onomasiological structure are
matched with corresponding morphemes. It is Onomasiological Types I and IV which meet
this requirement. For convenience, let us reintroduce the examples:
Obj - Act - Ag
truck drive er
Obj ← Act
stage manage
Onomasiological Types II and III are less iconic because either the determining or the
determined constituent is left unexpressed. No iconicity can be found in OT V, i.e.,
onomasiological recategorization (conversion). Interesting cases in terms of iconicity are
represented by the so-called exocentric compounds, blends, and back-formations.
14.2. As envisaged above, exocentric compounds are generated in two steps, with the first
step postulating the morphematic representation of the onomasiological base. From this
point of view, these naming units mostly fall within Onomasiological Type III. What,
however, one encounters in a language is a significantly curtailed naming unit stored in the
Lexicon, with no morphemes representing the onomasiological base and the determined
constituent of the onomasiological mark. Similar considerations apply to blends. While
iconicity is fairly high at the word-formation stage, it disappears in the subsequent stage.
The plural of nouns will be used here as a case in point. The regular plural has three
allomorphs /-s/, /-z/, and /- z/. There are also other means of forming plural nouns, including
-en (oxen), stem vowel alternation (goose – geese, mouse – mice), and identical forms for
sg. and pl. (sheep, fish). The first group does not require any comments. The plural meaning
is based on the contrast based on the absence of a formal element in sg. and its presence in
pl. The second case does not pose any problems either if accounted for as internal
35
modification, or vowel alternation. Which zero-based options are available to the case of
sheep-sheep?
The first one is based on the contrast between sg. and pl. In this particular case it is the
contrast between sg. without any morpheme expressing this grammatical meaning, on the
one hand, and pl. which also lacks any overt representation. If we wish to contrast these
two grammatical meanings, we can do it in the following way:
(i) We can assume that sg. has no inflectional morpheme while pl. is represented by zero,
which would introduce a contrast between the absence of any inflectional morpheme and
the presence of a zero form of an inflectional morpheme. This introduces a theoretical
contrast between the presence and the absence of an abstract component. This option poses
the question of the adequacy of introducing zero to basic forms I do not think this to be an
appropriate approach simply because the basic form (nominative sg. (N), present tense (V),
positive (Adj), etc.) serves as a reference form, as a contrast-establishing form. It is the
unmarked member of any contrastive relation. It embodies the grammatical meaning via
its status of being a fundamental form. Hence, zero would be redundant, superfluous with
respect both to the grammatical meaning (sg) and form (unmarked member). A similar
position is taken by Haas (1974: 47) who emphasizes that the pl. suffix contrasts with its
absence, and not with zero in sg.. Moreover, Haas maintains that “while an overt element
may have its distinctive value established by contrasting either with overt elements or with
zero, zero itself can contrast only with an overt element, never with acoustic zero. To
suppose this would make nonsense of the notion of contrast”.
(ii) We can assume that sg. is represented by a zero morpheme. By implication, the contrast
can be achieved by introducing another zero with the meaning of plurality. Or, possibly, we
can postulate that sg. zero is replaced by the plural one.
Obviously, this theorizing, in effect a double zero morpheme, develops the binary structure
principle to absurdity.
(iii) There is one more possibility to establish a contrast of zero plural, in particular, if pl.
zero is contrasted with overt plural morphs /-s/, /-z/, /- z/, /- n/ rather than with the sg.
form. This approach follows from the premise that zero is justified by its functional identity
(synonymy) and formal contrast with other plural morphs or stem alternations. In fact, this
conception is based on the double-contrast principle involving the contrast between sg. and
pl. forms and that between synonymous formal elements expressing the meaning of
plurality. This principle complies with two basic postulates set out by Bloch (1947) and
Haas (1974), respectively:
(a) one of the alternants of a given morpheme may be zero but no morpheme has
zero as its only alternant;
(b) zero itself can contrast with an overt element, never with acoustic zero.
{umlaut} – {zero morpheme} establish the same functional contrast as {-s, -z, - z} – { n} –
{umlaut} – {absence of an inflectional morpheme}. Thus, this way of introducing zero does
not seem to be acceptable either. It is not the contrast between functionally identical forms
36
which is significant. Rather we need a contrastive relation between the basic form and
other forms of the respective paradigm. One can draw an important conclusion from
these considerations: In a two-member system, in which the basic element is unmarked, zero
morpheme has no justification.
Another important implication is that this issue should be treated at the system level of a
respective grammatical category. It cannot be reduced to the subsystem level (e.g., the
relations between allomorphs, or synonymous grammatical morphemes expressing the
particular category). Contrast is one of the universals of language: the articulatory-acoustic
contrast between phonemes, the contrast between both formal and semantic facets of signs,
the contrast between naming units, the contrast between various intonations, etc. Contrast
delimits mutual positions of the individual elements in the structural relations within a
system. Grammatical categories are also built up on contrast: sg. vs. pl., present tense vs.
past tense, positive vs. comparative/superlative, case contrasts in synthetic languages, etc.
Various possibilities of expressing a grammatical meaning, plural in our example, are—in
regard to the fundamental contrast—irrelevant, or secondary. For illustration, let us take
phonemes. The contrast between, for example, /p/ and /b/ is primary, the relations between
various allophones of /p/ and /b/, respectively, are secondary in view of the basic function of
phonemes—their capacity to distinguish the meaning of words. While the contrast between
sg. and pl. can be called categorial contrast (the category of number) the relations between
the individual synonymous morphemes within one and the same category can be labeled as
allocategorial contrast. It follows from the previous account that the latter is not relevant
for our purpose.
(2) The method dispenses with the traditional word-formation processes (prefixation,
suffixation, compounding, conversion, back-formation, and blending) by putting the
generation of all naming units on a uniform basis. This makes it possible to avoid a number
of serious problems connected with various versions of the Level Ordering Hypothesis
(Siegel 1979, Kiparsky 1982a, 1982b, 1983, 1985, Mohanan 1982, Kaisse / Shaw 1985,
etc.).
(3) Morpheme is uniformly and consistently treated as a bilateral unit, as opposed to some
other approaches in which it is an ambiguous unit of language: sometimes a pure form,
sometimes a meaningful unit. This fact allows me to maintain the hierarchical structure of
37
linguistic planes, with smaller units representing building blocks out of which higher level
units are formed.
(4) The theory refers to the pragmatic naming needs of a speech community within the
theory of word-formation itself, which makes it possible to do without the principle of
overgenerating morphology, and its related notions, like possible naming units, lexical gap,
etc.
(5) Word-Formation Rules (called Word-Formation Types here) are—unlike the previous
linguistic tradition—considered to be as productive as the rules of syntax and inflection.
They are regular and predictable.
(8) The theory offers a new explanation of the so-called “exocentric compounds”,
bracketing paradoxes, and other issues of word-formation.
I am far from pretending that the theory outlined here is a panacea for all the problems that
have emerged in word-formation since 1960. Rather, the onomasiological theory should be
envisaged as a viable alternative to the prevailing mainstream generative theories.
Moreover, I hope that this article will give rise to a fruitful discussion regarding various
aspects of onomasiological theory, because discussion remains the main driving force in any
field of research.
Pavol Štekauer
ul. 17. novembra 1
Katedra anglistisky a amerikanistiky
Prešovská Univerzita
08116 Prešov, Slovakia
[email protected]
Anderson, Stephen R. (1993), “Morphological Theory”, in: Newmeyer, F.J. (ed.), Linguistics: The
Cambridge Survey, Vol. 1: Linguistic Theory: Foundations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; p.
146-191.
Aronoff, Mark (1976), Word Formation in Generative Grammar, [Linguistic Inquiry Monograph 1],
Cambridge (Mass.): MIT.
38
Bauer, Laurie (1979), “Against word-based morphology”, Linguistic Inquiry 10: 508-509.
Bauer, Laurie (1990), “Be-heading the Word”, Journal of Linguistics 26: 1-31.
Beard, Robert (1987a) , “Morpheme Order in a Lexeme/Morpheme Based Morphology”, Lingua 72: 1-44.
Beard, Robert (1987b), “Lexical Stock Expansion”, in: Gussmann, E. (ed.), Rules and the Lexicon: Studies
in Word Formation, Lublin: Catholic University Press; p. 24.
Beard, Robert (1988), “On the Separation of Derivation from Morphology: Toward a Lexeme/Morpheme-
Based Morphology”, Quaderni di Semantica 9,1: 3-59.
Beard, Robert (1995), Lexeme-Morpheme Base Morphology, New York: State University of New York
Press.
Brekle, Herbert E. (1970), Generative Satzsemantik und transformationelle Syntax im System der
englischen Nominalkomposition, München: Fink.
Brekle, Herbert E. / Kastovsky, Dieter (eds) (1977), Perspektiven der Wortbildungsforschung, Bonn:
Bouvier Verlag Herbert Grundmann.
Bresnan, Joan W. (ed.) (1982), The Mental Representation of Grammatical Relations, Cambridge (Mass.):
MIT.
Bybee, Joan L. (1985), Morphology: A Study of the Relation between Meaning and Form, Amsterdam /
Philadephia: Benjamins.
Carroll, John M. / Tanenhaus, Michael K. (1975), “Prolegomena to a Functional Theory of Word-
Formation”, in: Papers from the parasession on functionalism, Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society; p.
47-62.
Chomsky, Noam (1970), “Remarks on Nominalization”, in: Jacobs, R. / Rosenbaum, P. (eds.), Readings in
English Transformational Grammar, Waltham (Mass.): Ginn; p. 184-221.
Chomsky, Noam / Halle, Morris (1968), The Sound Pattern of English, New York: Harper & Row.
Clark, Eve V. / Clark, Herbert H. (1979), “When Nouns Surface as Verbs”, Language 55,4: 767-811.
Di Sciullo, Anna M. / Williams, Edwin (1987), On the Definition of Word, Cambridge (Mass.): MIT.
Dokulil, Miloš (1962), Tvorení slov v c eštine I. Teorie odvozování slov, Praha: AV.
Dokulil, Miloš (1966), “Zum wechselseitigen Verhältnis zwischen Wortbildung und Syntax”, Travaux
linguistiques de Prague 1: 215-224.
Dokulil, Miloš (1968), “Zur Frage der Konversion und verwandter Wortbildungsvorgänge und
–beziehungen”, Travaux linguistiques de Prague 3: 215-239.
Don, Jan (1993), Morphological Conversion, [OTS Dissertation Series], Utrecht: Reserarch Institute for
Language and Speech.
Dressler, Wolfgang U. (1981), “On Word Formation in Natural Morphology”, Wiener Linguistische
Gazette 26: 3-33.
Dressler, Wolfgang U. (1982), “On Word Formation in Natural Morphology”, in: PICL 13: 172-182.
Dressler, Wolfgang U. et al. (eds.) (1987), Leitmotifs in Natural Morphology, Amsterdam / Philadelphia:
Benjamins.
Evaraert, Martin; Evers, Arnold; Huybregts, Riny and Trommelen, Mieke (eds.) (1988), Morphology and
Modularity, Dordrecht: Foris.
Guerssel, Mohand (1983), “A Lexical Approach to Word Formation in English”, Linguistic Analysis 12:
183-243.
Haas, W. (1974), “Zero in Linguistic Description”, in: Studies in Linguistic Analysis. Special Volume of the
Philological Society, 33-54. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Halle, Morris (1973), “Prolegomena to a Theory of Word Formation”, Linguistic Inquiry 4,1: 3-16.
Hansen, Barbara et al. (1982), Englische Lexikologie. Einführung in Wortbildung und lexikalische
Semantik, Leipzig: VEB Verlag Enzyklopädie.
Horecký, Ján (1960), “Vzt’ah pojmu a termínu”, Jazykovedný casopis 11: 97-102.
Horecký, Ján et al. (1989), Dynamika slovnej zásoby súcasnej slovenciny, Bratislava: SAV.
Jackendoff, Ray S. (1975), “Morphological and Semantic Regularities in the Lexicon”, Language 51: 639-
671.
Jensen, John T. (1990), Morphology. Word Structure in Generative Grammar, Amsterdam / Philadelphia:
Benjamins.
Kaisse, Ellen and Shaw, Patricia (1985), “On the theory of lexical phonology”, Phonology Yearbook 2: 1-
30.
Kastovsky, Dieter (1977), “Word-formation, or: At the Crossroads of Morphology, Syntax, Semantics, and
the Lexicon”, Folia Linguistica 10: 1-33.
Kastovsky, Dieter (1995a), “Wortbildungssemantik: Ein historischer Lagebericht”, in: Hoinkes, U. (ed.),
Panorama der Lexikalischen Semantik. Thematische Festschrift aus Anlaß des 60. Geburtstags von
Horst Geckeler, Tübingen: Narr; p. 385-398.
Kastovsky, Dieter (1995b), “The Syntactic Aspects of Word-Formation: Where Are We Today?”, in:
Melchers, G. / Warren, B. (eds.), Studies in Anglistics, [Acta Universitatis Stockolmiensis 85],
Stockholm: Univ.; p. 157-169.
40
Kiparsky, Paul (1982a), “Lexical Morphology and Phonology”. in: Linguistics in the Morning Calm, Seoul:
Hanshin.
Kiparsky, Paul (1982b), “From Cyclic Phonology to Lexical Phonology”, in: van der Hulst, H. / Smith, N.
(eds.), The Structure of Phonological Representations, Part I, Dordrecht: Foris; p. 131-175.
Kiparsky, Paul (1983), “Word Formation and the Lexicon”, in: Ingemann, F. (ed.), Proceedings of the
1982 Mid-America Linguistics Conference, Lawrence: University of Kansas; p. 3-22.
Kiparsky, Paul (1985), “Some consequences of Lexical Phonology”, Phonology Yearbook 2: 85-136.
Langacker. Ronald W. (1988a), “An Overview of Cognitive Grammar”, in: Rudzka-Ostyn, Barbare (ed.),
Topics in Cognitive Linguistics. Current Issues in Linguistic Theory 50, Amsterdam / Philadelphia:
Benjamins; p. 3-48.
Langacker. Ronald W. (1988b), “A View of Linguistic Semantics”, in: Rudzka-Ostyn, Barbara (ed.), Topics
in Cognitive Linguistics. Current Issues in Linguistic Theory 50, Amsterdam / Philadelphia:
Benjamins; 49-69.
Lees, Robert B. (1960), The Grammar of English Nominalizations, Bloomington (Indiana): Indiana
University Press.
Lees, Robert. B. (1966), “On a Transformational Analysis of Compounds: A Reply to Hans Marchand”,
Indogermanische Forschungen 71: 1-13.
Lees, Robert. B. (1970), “Problems in the Grammatical Analysis of English Nominal Compounds”, in:
Bierwisch, Manfred / Heidolph, K. E. Progress in Linguistics, The Hague: Mouton; p. 174-186.
Lieber, Rochelle (1983), “Argument Linking and Compounding in English”, Linguistic Inquiry 14: 251-86.
Lieber, Rochelle (1992), Deconstructing Morphology. Word formation in Syntactic Theory, Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press.
Ljung, Magnus (1977), “Problems in the Derivation of Instrumental Verbs”, in: Brekle Herbert E. /
Kastovsky Dieter (eds.), Perspektiven der Wortbildungs-forschung, Bonn: Bouvier Verlag Herbert
Grundmann; p. 165-179.
Marchand, Hans (1955), “Synchronic Analysis and Word-formation”, Cahiers Ferdinand de Saussure 13:
7-18.
Marchand, Hans (1960), The Categories and Types of Present-Day English Word-Formation. Wiesbaden:
Harrassowitz.
Marchand, Hans (1963a), “On a Question of Contrary Analysis with Derivationally Connected But
Morphologically Uncharacterized Words”, English Studies 44,3: 176-187.
Marchand, Hans (1963b), “On Content as a Criterion of Derivational Relationship with Backderived
Words”, Indogermanische Forschungen 68: 170-175.
Marchand, Hans (1964), “A Set of Criteria for the Establishing of Derivational Relationship between Words
Unmarked by Derivational Morphemes”, Indogermanische Forschungen 69: 10-19.
Marchand, Hans (1965a), “The Analysis of Verbal Nexus Substantives”, Indogermanische Forschungen 70:
51-71.
Marchand, Hans (1965b), “On the Analysis of Substantive Compounds and Suffixal Derivatives not
Containing a Verbal Element”, Indogermanische Forschungen 70: 117-145.
41
Marchand, Hans (1969), The Categories and Types of Present-Day English Word-Formation, 2nd revised
edition. München: C. H. Beck.
Marchand, Hans (1974), Studies in Syntax and Word-Formation, edited by D. Kastovsky. München: Fink.
Mathesius, Vilém (1975), A Functional Analysis of Present Day English, The Hague: Mouton.
Mayerthaler, Willi (1977), Studien zur theoretischen und französischen Morphologie, Tübingen: Niemeyer.
Newmeyer, Frederick (ed.) (1988), Linguistics: The Cambridge Survey, Vol. 1: Linguistic Theory:
Foundations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pennanen, Esko V. (1966), Contributions to the Study of Back-formation in English, [Acta Academiae
Socialis ser. A 4], Tampere: Yhteiskunnallinen korkeakoulu.
Pennanen, Esko V. (1971), Conversion and Zero-Derivation in English, [Acta Universitatis Tamperensis
ser. A 40], Tampere: Univ.
Pennanen, Esko V. (1972), “Current Views of Word-formation”, Neuphilologische Mitteilungen 73: 292-
308.
Pesetsky, David (1985), “Morphology and Logical Form”, Linguistic Inquiry 16: 193-246.
Roeper, Thomas (1988), “Compound Syntax and Head Movement”, Yearbook of Morphology 1: 187-228.
Roeper, Thomas and Siegel, Muffy. E. A (1978), “A Lexical Transformation for Verbal Compounds”,
Linguistic Inquiry 9: 199-260.
Selkirk, Elisabeth O. (1986), The Syntax of Words, 3rd printing, Cambridge (Mass.): MIT.
Sproat, Richard W. (1988), “Bracketing Paradoxes, Cliticization and Other Topics: The Mapping between
Syntactic and Phonological Structure”, in: Everaert 1988: 339 - 360.
Štekauer, Pavol (1992), “On Some Issues of Zero Morpheme in English”, Linguistica Pragensia 2: 73-87.
Štekauer, Pavol (1994b), “Hapax Legomena and Word-Formation”, ASA Journal 1: 6-9.
Štekauer, Pavol (1996), A Theory of Conversion in English , Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.
Štekauer, Pavol (in print), “Beheading the Word? Please, Stop the Execution”, Folia Linguistica.
Štekauer, Pavol et al. (1997), “Getting Beyond the Rules of Language”, Acta Facultatis Philosophicae
Universitatis Safarikanae 83], Prešov: Univ.
Strauss, Stephen L. (1982), Lexicalist Phonology of English and German, Dordrecht: Foris Publications.
Williams, Edwin (1981a), “On the Notions ‘Lexically Related’ and ‘Head of a Word’”, Linguistic Inquiry
12: 245-274.
Williams, Edwin (1981b), “Argument Structure and Morphology”, Linguistic Review 1: 81-114.
Zimmer, Karl E. (1964), Affixal Negation in English and Other Languages: An Investigation of Restricted
Productivity, [Word Supplement Monograph 5], New York: Linguistic Circle.