Download
Download
Download
www.accedoverlag.d
Anissa Castel-Bouchouchi
CPGE Fénelon, Paris, France
(eMail: [email protected])
Abstract: In Plato’s theory of the soul, reason (logos) together with appetite
(epithymiai) and the spirit (thymos), are all three independent sources of
motivation. The contrast between reason and the two other parts of the soul is
not really related to the distinction, derived from Hobbes, between a belief,
an image or plain fact, and a desire, source of motivation. Each part has its
own desires. It is appropriate to present the bad and generally insatiable
desires that tend to lead to dissatisfaction with a double opposition. On the
one hand, there is much to be expected from the thymos in so far as it
demands self-respect and recognition; and on the other, since the desire to
have more (pleonexia) is the main threat to the city, intellect alone cannot
find any final solution to the anthropological, political, and metaphysical
problem that arises from it.
In his famous and often quoted paper, John Cooper has, it would seem,
laid out the complexity and originality of Plato’s theory on human
motivation beyond the established cliché in the history of philosophy,
the famous tripartite theory of the soul (Cooper 2013). Everyone
knows that in the Republic, Plato describes the soul as made up of
three independent parts: reason (logos), the spirited or irascible part
(thymos), and appetite or, in the plural, the lower instincts (epithymiai)
(Renaut 2004: 15-16). The tripartition of the soul is mentioned
explicitly in three dialogues only: Republic, Phaedrus, and Timaeus;
the word thymos appears 4 times in Protagoras, 13 times in Republic,
© 2014 Accedo Verlagsgesellschaft, München.
ISBN 978-3-89265-116-1 ISSN 0943-0180
464 Homo Oeconomicus 31(4)
In the fourth book of the Republic, the nature of desire becomes the
subject of particular analysis. At the outset, desire is acceptation, as
opposed to aversion, which is negation:
For example, will you not agree that the soul of someone who
has a desire always longs for what it desires, or draws it toward
whatever it wishes to possess, or again in so far as it wants
something to be supplied to it, approves this for itself, like
someone making a request, reaching out for its realization?
(Republic IV, 437c).
thoughtless, like affects, or stormy and transitory; rather they take root
and can even co-exist with rationalizing” (Kant 2006 §80, p. 165).
Thus, at least two parts to the soul exist. We can observe
motivating desires that apply independently of any reasoning and,
correlatively, motivations to act in accordance with evaluative beliefs.
It is true that no one would claim, after careful thought, that
champagne alone is sufficiently thirst-quenching and that it would be
better to die of thirst rather than slake it with water. However, if we
substitute sexual desire for thirst the argument that in some cases
abstinence may reasonably be better than the replacement of a lost
love with the first available love object becomes convincing.
The difficulties that trouble the irrational part of the soul come from
the fact that it bundles together the plural impulses that are shared
between the two extremes: personal repletion and enjoyment on the
one hand; love of money and of material goods on the other. This
diversity precludes any amalgamation. Elementary natural needs such
as drinking and eating are not of the same order as those that are
concerned with possession and are not necessary to survival. The
“vehement gang” of terrible desires (see 573e), wild and unbridled,
belong to registers that are sometimes mutually different, including the
imaginary. It wakes up when the rest of the soul is asleep, in our
dreams. Let us say that the epithymetical part is, in this topic of the
soul, the seat of desires that are as irrational as they are abundant and
polymorphous. Hence their heterogeneity is a source of constant
confusion. We may also wonder how devoid of all cognition these
desires actually are. Does not any desire suggest some activity of the
mind: memories of pleasures past, anticipation of forthcoming
pleasures as well as imagination of a state of affairs whose realisation
feels desirable? For that matter, in Philebus (35c-d), Plato asserts that
“there is no desire of the body,” properly speaking, since by virtue of
memory “any effort a living being makes always takes it to the
opposite of the impressions felt by its body” (Philebus, 34d-35e).
Let us now return to the case where reason is in itself a source of
motivating conditions. The best example is obviously not that of
champagne. In order to measure what is at stake in the possibility for
reason to be a place of strong impulses and a mental element “owing
to which we understand” and which “always seeks the knowledge of
truth, wherever it may be” (Republic IX, 581b5-6), the most
economical way is to go to the Phaedo and then Crito.
We can then shed light on one of the core paradoxes of the
Republic, that of the philosopher kings who have to be forced into
being fair. Indeed, the figure of Socrates himself remains the best
example of rational desire. As everyone knows, Socrates decided to
468 Homo Oeconomicus 31(4)
accept his death sentence and not to escape from his prison. In this
way, he raises the question of the inconsistencies in the philosophy of
Anaxagoras who claims to explain the causality of action in a
mechanistic or material manner: “This is what he [Anaxagoras] made
me think of: It was as though one started by saying that all Socrates
does, he does by virtue of his intelligence and then, later, as he
enumerated the causes of every one of my actions, he asserted that I
am sitting here, now, because my body is made up of flesh and bone”
(Phaedo 98c). But, according to Socrates, what accounts for his
presence in prison is the logical relationship that exists between the
fact that he “had judged it better to be sitting in this place” and the
fact that he was actually, intentionally, sitting there (Phaedo 99a).
Thus, can the philosopher maintain: “I act in accordance with my mind
(nôi pratto) considering what seems to be for the best” (Phaedo 99a).
Whatever the secondary and sometimes contradictory motivations
are, in the last resort it is a question of asserting that, for a
philosopher, it is reason that decides. It alone knows the truth and
commands (arkhein, Republic IV, 441c). This directing function is
justified by its synoptic understanding of the soul as a whole. Crito
says just that a very clear formula is enough to show that the
submission of the convicted man to the laws of Athens and his refusal
to escape from his prison have nothing to do with an ordinary
conformism (Crito 46b). This implies that the mere fact of living
somewhere means unconditional submission to the laws as they stand
whatever they may be:
Within me, I listen to one voice alone and that is the voice of
reason (logos) which, after giving the matter some thought,
appears to me to be the best. But those reasonings (logoi) that I
put forward up until now, I cannot set aside merely on account of
what fate has just dealt me; on the contrary, they appear to me to
be noticeably identical; I respect and honour them as I always
have (Crito 46b).
which, at the same time, he both wanted to look at and turn away from
in indignation. He struggled with himself for a while and then allowed
himself to surrender to a desire we would readily call unclean. “This
story shows that passion sometimes does battle with our desires, as
one thing against another” (Republic IV, 440a), but in many other
instances it is the ally of reason. The heart, therefore, is neither an
appetite nor a rational element but a third part of the soul situated
between the other two, metaxy, and which plays a supporting role in
the internal conflicts between irreconcilable desires.
This is why the contradiction that presents such a problem to us in
the return into the Cave seems to originate in the fact that a
philosopher's rational desires are so strong that they need no support
and place no demands on any other sources of motivation, as happened
in the case of Leontios. A philosopher, once he is in the place of truth,
discards his epithymiai. Aristotle speaks of the “autarchy” particular to
theoretical life:
a dominance of the lower instincts of the spirit. As a result, “the truth is
that the city in which those who are to rule are least eager to hold office
must needs be best administered and most free from dissension” (Republic
520d). In ordinary life and in real cities, it is the thymos, with or
without the epithymiai, that reigns supreme. Hence, all of Plato’s merit
would lie in the fact of having established that the desire for
competition and recognition actually constitutes a form of human
motivation distinct from appetites and from reason itself. Morevover,
it is as fundamental to the human nature as the latter two whose
conduct it partly explains (Cooper 2013: 172). Conversely, an ideal
city offers a model, which could be of use as a regulative Ideal, of a
noocracy (Kant 1965 I, III, 1). In short, as stated by Brunschwig, the
lesson of the Republic “is that politics are too important a thing to be
left to people who do not know that there are things that are much
more important” and far more desirable (Brunschwig 1986: 888).
Here, the political order writes in broad type what justice is, a
structure of order, an order that is also psychological and that we have
just read written in small letters at the level of the individual soul.
Why do the participants in the Republic take the city as their starting
point rather than the soul? This happens not for axiological but strictly
methodological reasons. A text in large type would be more legible
than a text in small type – that is all. The nature of justice “on a larger
canvas might look bigger and easier to recognize” (Republic II, 369b).
However, the consequences of this mode of exposition are important.
“Rethought along these lines, individual justice ceases to be a
disposition to behave in a certain way with others and becomes a
certain internal structure. Plato and his commentators will have to ask
themselves whether a ‘Platonically just’ person is thus an ‘ordinarily
just’ person and vice-versa” (Brunschwig 1986: 882). In other words,
justice in this case is in no way concerned with the rights individuals
might have within a community or how a man acts in a group and
behaves in relation to others. Defined as an order intrinsic to the
whole, as a relation, it is “justice of” before it is “justice in.”
Indeed, it refers to a balance such that each constituent part of the
whole does all that is necessary and nothing else. Suppose as a
hypothesis that reason exercises, in a noocratic problematic, the
commanding role. The middle part, in well-developed souls, will feel
bound to support a higher authority in order to curb unbridled
appetites. Analogically, philosopher kings in an ideal city, similar to
the rational part of the soul, will have to be backed up by the guardian
A. Castel-Bouchouchi: Plato and the Causes of Excess 473
that gives power its legitimacy. Second, one must admit that erronous
birth control would allow for eugenics that permit the perpetuation of
the elite to crumble and, therefore, “for a state thus constituted to be
shaken and disturbed; but since for everything that has come into being
destruction is appointed, not even such a fabric as this will abide for all
time, but it shall surely be” (Republic VIII, 546a). The inevitable
degenerescence of all that is part of becoming is an opportunity to
sketch a political science in books VIII and IX. They describe the four
forms of imperfect states that correspond to a progression
in corruption when the worst win at the level of the sources of
motivation. Timocracy means government founded on honours where
thymos reigns supreme. Oligarchy is the government by a small
number, usually the rich. Democracy and finally tyranny show the
signs of pathological processes of the epithymiai – limited at first to a
desire for riches, which then become unlimited. Finally, we reach that
total excess that is tyranny where a single individual, himself a victim
of the tyranny of his own impulses, is invested with power to do
absolutely anything.
Timocracy retains an appearance of order because it respects a
number of values that used to be those of the ideal aristocratic
government. Hence, the desire to get rich remains discreet and hidden.
However, oligarchy tips over to the side of the inequality of exchanges
and the disproportion of property and institutes a city where the very
rich and the very poor live at the expense of others without
contributing anything to the common good. Its collapse is inevitable
because the poor, who after a time have nothing to lose, have the
advantage of numbers (Republic VII, 557a).
Democratic man gives way to the polymorphy of desire, hence a
general chaos (Republic VII, 565d-e) where everyone seeks to enjoy
without a thought of saving or producing, leading, in due course, to an
economic and political dead end. Then the future tyrant turns up with
the prospect of the cancellation of debts and the sharing out of land
(Republic VII, 566a). To this self-proclaimed saviour who will, once
in place, govern in no one’s interest but his own, people surrender all
powers in order to escape anarchy and penury.
Such is, broadly described, the spiral of decadence according to the
last books of the Republic. In the end, Plato, more pessimistic than
ever, returns to the very origin of this fall, which leads to the
disappearance of the political as such. He then excludes the possibility
for any man, even a philosopher king or enlightened tyrant, to escape
corruption if he becomes all-powerful. There is no need to invoke
chance or the history of regimes to account for decadence. All that is
needed is to refer to human nature: “Cronos was aware of the fact that no
A. Castel-Bouchouchi: Plato and the Causes of Excess 475
References