Jasmine Gunkel What Is Intimacy
Jasmine Gunkel What Is Intimacy
Jasmine Gunkel What Is Intimacy
Forthcoming in Journal of Philosophy. Please cite that version of the paper, rather than this final
draft.
What is Intimacy?
Why is it typically more violating to grab someone’s thigh or to stroke their face than it is to
grab their finger? Why is it worse to read someone’s dream journal without permission than it is to
read their bird watching field notes? Intimacy, I argue, is key to understanding these cases, and to
explaining many of our most stringent rights.
I present two ways of thinking about intimacy, Relationship-First Accounts and the Intimate
Zones Account. I argue that only the Intimate Zones Account lets us cohesively understand intimacy’s
importance, and the scope of our intimate rights. I characterize our intimate zones as meeting the
Hiddenness and Importance Conditions, and show how a feature’s meeting these conditions makes it
a locus of special vulnerability by which our persons can be fundamentally altered. This special
vulnerability explains why we must respect the intimate boundaries of others.
1. Introduction:
Intimacy is both one of the most longed for and repulsing facets of human experience. Desired
intimacy with desired persons is essential for our lives as social creatures. Undesired intimacy repels
and unnerves us as little else can. At its worst, it is a tremendous and life-shattering violation. Intimacy
with others shapes our persons, our personalities, and the trajectory of our lives. And yet, intimacy
takes so many different forms. There are intimate conversations, intimate sexual experiences, intimate
friendships, intimate therapy sessions. But it is not obvious what these all share. I argue that a common
thread runs through all these cases and more, and renders us vulnerable. And this vulnerability grounds
our stringent rights against intimate violations. In this paper, I give an account of intimacy that can
account for its multitudinal occurrences, explain why it make us vulnerable, and ground our intimate
rights.
arguments about privacy, sexual rights, abortion, care ethics, cultural appropriation, and humor.1 But
1 Julie Inness, James Rachels, and Jeffrey Reiman talk about intimacy when giving arguments about the nature of privacy
(Inness 1996, Rachels 1975, Reiman 1976). Feminist philosophers such as Maggie Little and Eva Feder Kittay discuss
Gunkel 2
such arguments rarely make clear how they are conceptualizing intimacy, and more rarely still give
arguments for conceptualizing intimacy in this way. This is not a criticism of such arguments. We all,
of course, must take some concepts for granted in our work. Rather, this is an offering. By rationally
reconstructing what has been said about intimacy in the literature and in ordinary life, and making
clear the implications of such views, we are better positioned to investigate its importance.
There are two broad approaches to thinking about intimacy. As Pavel Nitchovski observes
about Julie Inness, she has a “general ‘relationship-first’ approach” (82, 2022). Accordingly, I name
the first class of views, of which Iness’s view is one, ‘Relationship-First Accounts.’ Though they have
not been all grouped together before, nor the view made explicit, many views running through the
background of arguments about privacy, abortion, and care ethics fit share common commitments
and assumptions.2
I will argue that Relationship-First Accounts are not sufficiently unifying, nor informative.
They do not accurately predict which acts are intimate, nor can they adequately explain why some acts
are intimate and others are not. They cannot tell us why sharing a bed with a romantic partner is
intimate, but sharing a garbage disposal is not. Relationship-First Accounts also have trouble capturing
intimacy in the context of pregnancy and care ethics (Little 1999, Feder Kittay 1999, 2011). Thi Nguyen and Matthew
Strohl argue that much cultural appropriation is wrong because it interferes with ‘the intimacy of groups’ (2019). Ted
Cohen discusses the role of intimacy in humor (1978).
2 See Feder Kittay 1999, 2011, Inness 1996, Little 1999, Rachels 1975, and Reiman 1976.
3 Nitchovski (2022) also argues that such approaches cannot capture intimate interactions which occur outside of
relationships.
Gunkel 3
Imagine that Maria has been in a fight with her partner, and posts about it anonymously on
an online forum. She talks about why she fears she is incompatible with her partner, and in doing so
appears to be revealing something intimate. But as she is posting for the first time and is unfamiliar
with the commenters, the relationship she has with them is minimal at best. Relationship-First
Accounts cannot tell us why this forum disclosure seems intimate in a way that posting about one’s
dog’s favorite food is not. Nor can they explain what Maria’s posting on a forum has in common with
Unlike theorists who take intimate relationships to be primary, I argue that the intimacy of
such relationships stems from their exposure of intimate areas of our selves.
Intimate Zones Account: Certain zones of persons are intimate. Intimate acts are
those that expose intimate zones. Intimate relationships are relationships in which
I will argue that intimate zones, not relationships, are most fundamental. This is not to say
that intimacy is identical to our intimate zones. ‘Intimacy’ describes our intimate zones, intimate acts,
and intimate relationships, and the way they relate. Intimacy is the whole phenomenon. Rather, the
claim is that to cohesively understand this phenomenon, and why it is so important to us, we must
build intimacy up from our intimate zones. That intimate areas of the self are primary allows us to see
how intimacy is self-shaping, and why it is imperative we have control over our intimate boundaries.
Having our intimate zones exposed without our consent is not just uncomfortable, but renders us
I have three goals in this paper. The first is to add structure to our thinking about intimacy, a
roadmap to possible unified theories. The second is to show that the Intimate Zones Account is
Gunkel 4
superior to Relationships-First Accounts, that it better captures all the cases it should. And the third
is to defend a substantive account of what these intimate zones are. I argue that our intimate zones
are characterized by two features, their hiddenness and their importance to our conception of our
identity. I call these the ‘Hiddenness Condition’ and the ‘Importance Condition’ and together they
make up the Hidden Importance (HI) Thesis. Together, they show why intimate violations are
2. A Concept of Intimacy
People use ‘intimacy’ and ‘intimate’ in a huge variety of ways. They’re used to describe
relationships, actions, and information. ‘An intimate’ can refer to a confidante. ‘They were intimate’
euphemistically refers to a sexual encounter. In the social sciences ‘intimate labor’ often refers to
sexual, reproductive, domestic, and care labor.4 How could all these cases share some common,
substantive core? We can think of this as the Capture Problem for an account of intimacy.
There is also substantial overlap between ‘privacy’, ‘intimacy’, and ‘closeness’, both in
conception and in usage. A couple whispering to each other might be said to be having ‘an intimate
moment’ by one observer, while another would fairly call it ‘a private moment.’ These sorts of
concepts don’t seem to be natural kinds and it’s reasonable to be skeptical that we can disentangle and
catalogue them. And given that there is a huge literature on privacy, if intimacy is to be a useful
concept, it is particularly important that it is meaningfully different from privacy. We can think of this
as the Distinction Problem for an account of intimacy. I tackle the Distinction Problem in section
6.15, once I have fleshed out part of the picture of intimacy. There, I show that some acts are private
4 See Cohen (2002) and Salazr Parreńas and Boris (2010) for examples.
Gunkel 5
The Capture Problem is, admittedly, more difficult. To begin, exactly capturing the current
extension of ‘intimacy’ is not my goal. Rather, I am interested in a conception of intimacy that can do
important explanatory work.5 I seek an account that can tell us why close and loving relationships,
secret sharing, and sexual acts are all paradigmatically intimate, and why sexual assault is a paradigmatic
intimate violation. It should be close to our common-sense conception of intimacy, so that it can
explain how we use this concept and why we already believe intimacy is so important. It should explain
why intimacy makes us vulnerable and shapes us, and how this gives rise to our stringent rights against
intimate violations.6
Having such an account of intimacy can then help us adjudicate the scope of our legal and
moral rights. It can explain why it is typically so much more violating when a stranger grabs our butt
than when they grab our elbow, and so why we require more robust legal protections against the
former. It also can adjudicate conflicts currently being hashed out in the political realm. Those who
push against mask mandates during the COVID-19 pandemic have co-opted the phrase “my body,
my choice” from the pro-choice movement. The concept of bodily autonomy alone cannot tell us
why forcing someone to continue a pregnancy is so much more violating than requiring someone to
wear a mask or to get a vaccine. Rather, we need to understand why pregnancy is intimate in a way
wearing a mask is not, and why that makes it much more grave to force on someone.
5 This could be thought of as a Carnapian explication project. As Georg Brun explains, Carnap’s explication is done to
advance our theorizing. This new concept, the explicatum, must be generally useable in the same circumstances as the
original term, and “should be as fruitful as possible” (Brun 2016). It is not, however, an ameliorative project. As Sally
Haslanger argues, ameliorative analyses “elucidate ‘our’ legitimate purposes and what concept of Fness (if any) would
serve them best. . . Normative input is needed” (2005). My Intimate Zones Account does not require normative input.
Rather, though my account delivers results that I believe will be morally beneficial, its structure is motivated by facts
about human psychology, and does not rest on any moral assumptions. It explains why intimate zones are loci of
vulnerability. That loci of vulnerability are deserving of special protections is normative, though not especially
controversial, but this only explains why intimate zones deserve special protections. It is not required to explain what
they are.
6 I am more concerned with crafting an account of intimacy that can ground our negative rights, our right against
intimate intrusion, than I am with one that can explain positive rights to intimacy (if there are any).
Gunkel 6
This account can also help us better regulate intimate labor. We can acknowledge that sex
work is typically different from much other work without being essentialist about sexuality. We can
see why sex often makes us vulnerable without relying on inaccurate (and often sexist) claims about
sex’s ‘natural role’. However, once we have a measuring stick to test for intimacy, we see that it is not
only sexual and reproductive labor that are intimate, but that work such as nursing, teaching, therapy,
and art are as well. Recognizing these similarities, and being guided by principles of fairness, we can
see that we ought to treat these similar labors similarly. This understanding can guide us to meaningful
social policy reform, informed by the unique way in which intimacy makes us vulnerable.
If some use of ‘intimacy’ appears not to be captured by my account, there are two ways to
respond. First, I can counter that if we correctly understand the case, it does involve revelation of
intimate zones. I’ll demonstrate how this works for less obvious cases in section 10. But of course, for
any potential counterexample I can translate into the language of intimate zones, another awaits in the
wing. And so while I do think anything that can plausibly be called ‘intimate’ is in fact a revelation of
intimate zones, it’s pertinent to address what should be done if some counterexample were to be
found. If there was a case that could not be understood in terms of intimate zones, I would have to
hold it to be a less fundamental sort of intimacy, that it is derivative or even parasitic on genuine
intimacy. And so it would not be protected by the special weight of an intimate right.
There is something intuitively appealing about the idea that intimacy exposes us. Robert Nozick
elegantly captures this when he writes “In intimacy, we let another within the boundaries we normally
maintain around ourselves, boundaries marked by clothing and by full self-control and monitoring”
(1989, 60). Literal nakedness is intimate, but metaphorical nakedness also captures this sense of
vulnerability, of exposure. George Yancy describes “being undone by the intensity of the intimacy”
Gunkel 7
when he watches the film Moonlight. He says that by ‘intimacy’ he means that which “is inmost or
deepest within or farthest from the outside” (Yancy 2019, 66). To understand intimacy, we must
understand this sense of exposure, of a hidden core revealed. Intimate zones help capture this:
Intimate Zone: A feature of a person which renders them vulnerable. These are
features we are disposed to hide, which give insight into how we see ourselves.
Intimate Act: An act that exposes, or relies on the exposure of, at least one intimate
zone.
acts.7
We can think of intimate zones as the building blocks of intimacy, from which intimate acts
and intimate relationships are formed. There are, of course, constraints on how “the building blocks
of intimacy” may be put together. Some of these constraints stem from of the meaning of ‘act’ and
‘relationship’. Some constraints come from the requirements of various act types. Having a
conversation, for instance, requires multiple parties. So for there to be an intimate conversation, at
least two people must be engaged in a conversation in which intimate zones are revealed. Likewise, an
intimate relationship entails the existence of a relationship, which requires there is some interaction
7 Or a series of acts which are not individually intimate, but are intimate when considered as a collective. A single
instance of sitting next to someone at a coffee shop is typically not intimate, but sitting next to someone every day for
years is likely to reveal intimate information through patterns, such as how they look when confused or joyful.
Gunkel 8
4. Cases:
I now introduce some cases that motivate my account. There intuitively seems to be something
intimate happening in each of them, something that an account of intimacy should capture. However,
Dominatrix:
Suzanne is a dominatrix and Lizbeth is her client. She has monthly sessions with Lizbeth for
many years, and in these sessions she learns about Lizbeth’s patterns of sexual response. They talk
about Lizbeth’s desires, Suzanne’s boundaries, the origins of both of these, and they come to
genuinely like each other.8 Lizbeth prefers seeing Suzanne to other dominatrixes, and Lizbeth is one
of Suzanne’s favorite clients, for whom she has some genuine affection. However, though Lizbeth
enjoys their encounters, she would not wish to cultivate an outside friendship with Suzanne, nor
enter into a romantic relationship with her. And should Lizbeth stop paying Suzanne, Suzanne
would stop engaging in sexual activities with her, and would not see her socially.
Support Group:
Valencia is trying to treat her alcohol dependency. When she is craving a drink, she attends a
local AA meeting. She doesn’t agree with all of the group’s methods, doesn’t have a sponsor, and
doesn’t socialize with people before or after the meeting. She quietly enters as they start, and quietly
leaves as they end. However, she listens to other people’s stories during the meetings, and occasionally
8 It is not necessary for the case to be intimate under the Intimate Zones Account that there is some affection between
the parties. Rather, as will become clear in section 5.1, I include this in the description so we can see that even in
versions of Dominatrix where care is involved, the motivation account cannot adequately capture it without becoming
too wide in scope.
Gunkel 9
shares her own struggles. She, like many others there, has opened up about the lowest moments of
her life. In most settings, she would find it too uncomfortable and painful to share these.
Stranger on a Train:
Omar is traveling out of the country by himself for the first time. He is visiting Japan, but does
not read or speak Japanese. After hours on the train, he realizes he is traveling in the wrong direction.
Frustrated and exhausted, he begins to cry. A stranger on the train notices, and tries to help him. After
this stranger gives him directions, Omar opens up to them about how alone he has felt in his travels.
The stranger nods along kindly, and shares an embarrassing travel story of his own. They laugh
together, and spend the next hour of the train ride discussing why they love to see new places, what
they fear traveling alone, and what they have learned from their travels. They do not exchange details,
Memoir:
Author Roxanne Gay writes Hunger: A Memoir of (My) Body. This is the first time she publicly
shares her story of being raped at twelve years old, and the repercussions this has had for her life and
relationship with her body. Though it is easier to “write around what happened” because she doesn’t
“want to have to deal with the horror of such exposure,” she decides to tell her story anyway (2017,
39). The back cover describes the book as an “intimate and searing memoir.”
to explain the intimacy in the above cases. One could reject that these cases contain intimacy despite
the intuitive pull that they do. Just because someone writes that a memoir is “intimate” does not make
Gunkel 10
it so, of course. However, even if what occurs in these cases was not genuine intimacy, we’d want to
say something about why there was pseudo-intimacy in them, about why they appear so similar to
is very easy to see how each of these cases reveals an intimate feature of a person. Granting their
similarity, and that something special is revealed in each, is not only appealing because it conforms to
our intuitions, however. If we can identity something special they share in common, then this special
thing can explain why these exchanges and disclosures deserve robust protections.
5. Relationship-First Accounts:
very natural about using relationships as the starting point in explorations of intimacy. Intimate
relationships very obviously impact us. We decide to share a living space with a partner, move across
country to be closer to our children, develop hobbies our friends share with us. They are often where
we feel intimacy’s force, how it changes us. And so it is easy to take for granted that we should begin
our investigation of intimacy here. But that intimacy is most apparent to us in intimate relationships
I separate these Relationship-First Views into two broad camps, the Motivation Account and
the Intertwinement Account. I argue that they cannot stand on their own if they are to capture all and
only intimacy, nor all and only intimate relationships. Rather, they must be supplemented with a
preexisting account of intimacy, and that is what I offer with Intimate Zones Account.
In Privacy, Intimacy, and Isolation, Julie Inness explicitly defines and defends an account of
intimacy. She lays out a model Relationship-First View, one she believes will provide a unified
Gunkel 11
justification of privacy law. She is clear and careful, and though I believe intimacy and privacy come
apart, I take inspiration from her ambitious goals for an account of intimacy.
Inness sees two possible forms an account of intimacy could take. The first she calls
“behaviorist.” This is the view that “we might find some characteristic of the behavior constituting
intimate acts and activities that could identify them as intimate” (1996, 74). She rejects this view
because she thinks any particular behavior we might identify, such as a kiss, is only intimate in some
cultural and historical contexts. This is an insightful line of critique. Given the diversity of human
psychology, I am very skeptical there are any act types that are always intimate for everyone.
Inness argues we should instead embrace a motivational account of intimacy. She argues that
intimacy is that which draws its motivation, “meaning, and value from . . . love, liking, or care” (75).
As she puts it, “when I claim that an act, such as kissing another, is intimate, I am not discussing the
nature of the behavior; I am referring to the fact that the kiss expresses my affection for another” (10).
However, a dilemma is revealed when we explore the notion of care and affection required here. If
it’s too thin, she’ll have to say that anything done out of a mild sense of care is intimate. But if it is any
thicker, it will leave out cases like Dominatrix, Support Group, Stranger on a Train, and Memoir. I
begin by discussing the non-intimate acts her account lets in, and proceed by proposing and rejecting
Not all acts that express affection and draw their meaning from this are intimate. I might like
my coworkers, and want to express my affection in the form of bringing in a box of donuts. And this
is valuable not only because donuts taste good, but because it expresses my care. However, bringing
donuts into the office is not intimate.9 So if the account is to avoid being absurdly wide, the kind of
9 There are variations on this case which could be intimate, however. If one of your coworker has confided in you that
they love chocolate old-fashion donuts because they used to get them with their beloved grandmother, then bringing in a
chocolate-old fashioned for them could be an intimate act. But the adjustment to the case which makes it intimate is not
Gunkel 12
It is helpful here to look to what others have said about the emotional component of intimacy.
Jeffrey Reiman, in “Privacy, Intimacy, and Personhood,” offers an account that seeks to capture the
sort of feeling which must ‘animate’ intimacy. He says it consists of a “reciprocal desire to share
present and future intense and important experiences” (Reiman 1976, 34). My bringing donuts is not
motivated by a desire to share intense experiences with my coworkers. And so defining care this way
However, this definition would preclude the existence of intimacy in the cases discussed
above. In Stranger on a Train, Omar knows he’ll probably never see the stranger again, and is fine
with that. In fact, the fleetingness of the encounter could be what makes it so intimate. Because they’re
confident they’ll never see each other again, they don’t worry about the repercussions of what they
reveal. And certainly at least some casual, one-time sexual encounters are intimate. So desiring future
shared experiences is not necessary. Additionally, we can be motivated by a desire for shared future
slightly ajar, and I worry they might leave me over this, I can be motivated by a desire for a shared
future to develop a habit of better closing lids. But closing the lids of condiments is not intimate. The
reciprocity component will also leave out one-sided intimate disclosures, such as Memoir. 10 So the
What does that leave us with? Let’s try to shore up Inness’ Account with the pieces of Reiman’s
account of care that remain. Might intimacy be that which is motivated by care, where care is
‘reciprocal desire to share present and future intense and important experiences’?
adding more care, but that it relies on some special knowledge about the coworker, the previous exposure of an intimate
zone.
10 The reciprocity requirement also gives the verdict that pregnancy cannot be intimate, contrary to the experiences of
many pregnant people, because fetuses can’t desire shared future experiences. We then could not ground the wrongness
of forced pregnancy in its forced intimacy, as Maggie Little (1999) does.
Gunkel 13
Such a definition would still leave out most intimate labor, and many other intimate
agreements. Because they would not continue to engage if Lisbeth were not paying Suzanne, neither
of them is sufficiently motivated by a desire to share an intense experience with the other. This is also
a problem for many familiar cases of personal intimate exchange. A person might agree to give their
partner a massage only on the condition that they’ll receive one in return. What’s genuinely motivating
them here is not the desire for a shared intense experience, but to get the knots out of their own neck.
To see why there is a problem with drawing a tight connection between intimacy and care, let
us look to two final cases. Imagine that your sister has had a baby during the COVID-19 pandemic,
but due to lockdowns you’ve been unable to meet him. You’ve been unable to form a relationship
with him, unable to hold or feed him, unable to establish trust. But knowing that he is your sister’s
son, you can care deeply for him. This love could motivate you to do small things, like watch long
videos of him sent by your sister. It could also motivate you to sacrifice significantly, to run into a
burning building to save him. Love and care can be found where there is not intimacy, and intimacy
And it is not only that there can be intimacy where there is no care, but even where there is
malice and disregard. Torture illustrates this saliently. As David Sussman puts it, “the most intimate
and private parts of a victim’s life and body become publicly available tools for the torturer to exploit
as he will . . .the victim is in a position of complete vulnerability and exposure” (2005, 7). One could,
of course, deny that there is any intimacy in torture. But by recognizing it as intimate, we are better
positioned to understand its great wrongness, wrongness that is not grounded in pain and fear alone. 11
11Though Sussman focuses on the wrong of one’s agency being turned against oneself, of being made to be complicit in
one’s own violation, he gestures at the intimacy of this being an important wrong making feature of torture. He says “in
the most intimate aspects of his agency, the sufferer is made to experience himself not just as a passive victim, but as an
active accomplice in his own debasement” (2005, 23).
Gunkel 14
I believe we only understand the importance of our intimate rights when the intimacy of egregious
violations, like torture and sexual assault, is recognized.12 That these are acts of forced intimacy is part of
Inness is right that we can’t look to particular act types to identify the intimate, but must
instead look to psychological states. However, being motivated by care and affection is not the right
state to look to. Rather, I will argue that we must instead look to Hiddenness and Importance to
There is something very natural about thinking of intimacy as a kind of merging, a coming
together, an intertwinement. People often speak about romantic love this way, and romantic love is
paradigmatically intimate. It is also apt to describe pregnancy this way. In “Abortion, Intimacy, and
the Duty to Gestate,” Maggie Little argues that forcing someone to carry a pregnancy is gravely wrong
not just because of the health or financial risks imposed, but because forced intimacy is so violating
think Little is right to emphasize the role of intimacy in justifying abortion rights. But for her argument
to helpfully generalize to cover other intimate arenas, we must have a better understanding of the
I live in a thin-walled apartment, and so there are many ways my life is intertwined with the
lives of my neighbors. Some of these ways are intimate. I might overhear a couple’s unsparing late
12 Nitchovski astutely observes that Inness’s account makes it hard to understand why abusive relationships count as
intimate. However, while his own proposed alternative account of intimacy does a good job capturing both good
intimacy and much of the bad, as well as intimate one-offs, it does not seem able to explain intimate violations. He
argues that intimacy requires taking the ‘intimate stance. As he puts it, “to take the intimate stance is to treat the other
(person, object, or thing) as though they are engaged in the cooperative activity of joint authorship over the narrative
one uses to make sense of oneself. In other words, to take the intimate stance is to treat the other as co-author in
answering the question ‘who am I?’” (iii, 2020). We very well may not treat those who violate us as if they are engaged in
cooperative activity.
Gunkel 15
night arguments. But there are also non-intimate ways my life might be intertwined with theirs.
Imagine that, because of faulty wiring, every time my neighbor turns on their air conditioner, my
kitchen lights go out. Any time I’d like to cook a meal or eat a snack, I’ll have to think about how hot
it is outside, how hot they might be in their apartment, and decide if they’re likely to be turning on
their AC. They might think about typical meal times before they turn on their air conditioner. Our
lives are intertwined, especially if we’re both spending all day in our homes, but this is not a particularly
intimate ways. So while Little’s notion of intertwinement is very helpful for understanding how
intimate relationships work, to use it we must have a prior conception of the intimate parts of people
and their lives. That is, we must know what intimate zones are.
And as I’ve argued, there can be intimacy without an intimate relationship, and Little’s
Account does not capture such cases. Someone can expose their intimate zones, and be made
vulnerable, without there being any intertwinement. Though there is some mutuality between Omar
and the stranger on the train because they laugh together and listen kindly, it is a stretch to describe
this fleeting mutuality as ‘intertwinement’. And there is even more obviously no ‘intertwinement’
between Roxanne Gay and the reader of her memoir. The reader might take some lessons from the
book and apply them to their life, identify with Gay, and even find that the memoir changed them in
ways that are perceptible years later. And so Gay could be woven into their life. But unless the reader
reaches out and successfully makes significant contact with her, Gay will not weave them into her life.
There is an intimate exposure without any intertwinement. So though intertwinement is helpful for
understanding the richness of intimate relationships, even when it’s filled out with prior
Now that I have argued that the Intimate Zones Account is better positioned to cohesively
explain intimacy, and capture its scope so as to explain our intimate rights, I develop my particular
theory of intimate zones. Though I hope to convince the reader this theory is right, someone could
accept the Intimate Zones Account without thinking I have correctly circumscribed these zones. I will
now argue that for a zone to be intimate, the Hiddenness Condition and the Importance Condition
must be met. I call this the Hidden Importance Thesis (HI Thesis).
6.1 Hiddenness
The first condition is Hiddenness. That there is some connection between intimacy and
hiddenness is intuitive. Prime examples of intimacy are secrets whispered under the cover of darkness
and sex had behind closed doors. Intimate decisions are those made with a partner or doctor, those
which we typically have a right to make away from prying eyes. There is a tension between something’s
being intimate and its being shouted from rooftops. But of course, sometimes the intimate is made
public. A blackmailer night expose a secret, a woman might share her abortion story in a speech about
the necessity of abortion access. So the tricky piece is not establishing that there is a Hiddenness
is disposed to hide X, and would feel psychological discomfort at X’s being exposed
to a general audience.
It is not that intimate features must always be hidden, nor be hidden most of the time, nor
around most people. Rather, we must be generally disposed to hide this feature of ourselves. This
disposition can manifest in many ways. I might steer conversations away from this feature of myself.
Gunkel 17
I might avoid activities which will reveal this feature. Importantly, a disposition to hide a feature X is
distinct from a disposition not to mention feature X. These dispositions will often come apart because
of norms of politeness. Cindy might be happy to talk about an award she won if asked about it, but
not be disposed to mention it without prompting because she does not wish to brag.
What we have a disposition to hide is different for different people. Imagine Malcom is
embarrassed about his love of Pokémon. He hides his collection of Pokémon cards when casual
friends visit his apartment, and when something reminds him of something that happened in an
episode of Pokémon, he keeps it to himself. In contrast, Lexie is very open about her love of Pokémon.
She has a Bulbasaur sticker on her laptop, and loves to tell people which Pokémon they remind her
of. For Malcom loving Pokémon is a Hidden feature, while for Lexie it is not. This means Malcom
Because of this individuality, many kinds of ‘intimate labor’ do not actually reveal the intimate
zones of all who participate in them. Sex will not be intimate for all those who do sex work, for
instance. Importantly, however, this does mean we may not grant special protections to practices
which, for biological or sociocultural reasons, will commonly be intimate. We can likewise legally
protect ‘intimate rights’ even though these legal protections will not perfectly conform to everyone’s
intimate zones.
and familial environments. Perhaps Malcom was teased by his middle school friends for liking
Pokémon, while at Lexie’s school everyone played the card game at lunch. Lexie could be more
Gunkel 18
comfortable talking about Pokémon in professional contexts because she remembers the 2016
Democratic Presidential candidate, Hillary Clinton, telling young people to “Pokemon GO to the
polls.” It is not just our dispositions regarding revealing our hobbies which are affected by our cultural
environments, of course. How much of our bodies we feel comfortable showing when we go to the
grocery store and to the beach is affected by cultural norms. Whether we think it appropriate for a
casual acquittance to kiss us on the cheek, or give us a hug, or even shake our hand, will be affected
This is not to say, however, that X is a Hidden feature if and only if X is typically hidden in
our culture. Though our culture influences what about ourselves we hide, it is not the determinate
influence, nor is it explanatory. We may be very open about something which most of our fellows
hide. Most people in the contemporary United States are disposed to hide their nude bodies, and this
is so culturally salient that we have the term ‘private parts.’ Despite this, some nudists have no
disposition to hide their naked bodies. Though most nudists typically hide their naked bodies due to
legal concerns, or knowledge that they won’t be hired if they show up naked to an interview, exposure
does not make them feel the requisite psychological discomfort. This discomfort happens when we
do not want others’ eyes or thoughts on this part of us. We are fearful not just of the downstream
It’s not that having some fear of the legal consequences of exposure means the feature of
yourself is not Hidden. People who are disposed to hide their naked body because they think it private
will also typically want to avoid the legal consequences of public nudity. Rather, for it to be intimate,
they must be disposed to hide it even if they knew no legal trouble, economic recourse, or external
consequences would ensue. To meet the Hiddenness Condition, we must adopt the internal point of
Gunkel 19
view in relation to the norm in question, and so be liable to feel shame about the norm-violating
feature itself.13 We can then be altered not only via a rational choice to change ourselves, but via shame.
Our Hidden features need not be static. A bisexual man’s coming out could make his sexual
orientation a non-Hidden feature of himself. Where his bisexuality was once something he only talked
about with his closest friends, as he becomes more inclined to mention that he is bisexual to
acquaintances or hold his boyfriend’s hand around town, this feature of himself becomes un-Hidden.
This can also go the other direction. After an openly trans* teenager faces transphobic abuse from her
family, she might decide to temporarily present as male again to avoid their derogatory comments,
One might worry that the Hiddenness Condition will rule out public displays of our intimate
features. That is, if we are sharing a feature X publicly, does that mean we are not disposed to hide X,
entailing X is not intimate? This objection rests on a misunderstanding of what it means to be disposed
to hide a feature of ourselves.14 Amy might be disposed to keep hidden the fact she was sexually
assaulted. The incident was deeply harmful to her, she considers its details very personal, and it is
painful to talk about. And yet, as the #MeToo movement unfolded, Amy came to believe that sharing
her story would help change a culture which enables sexual assault. So, despite her discomfort, Amy
shared her story on social media. Amy’s sharing this despite discomfort does not mean this is not a
Hidden feature of herself. Rather, the discomfort indicates it is a Hidden feature. Discomfort is
common when we are disposed to keep something Hidden, and yet choose to reveal it. This is the
“horror of exposure” Roxanne Gay identified in deciding to speak publicly about being sexually
13I am here thinking of the internal point of view as described by H.L.A. Hart (1961).
14Though there is significant disagreement about the nature of dispositions, there is wide agreement that being disposed
to X under Y conditions does not require always Xing under Y. A glass, because of its fragility, is disposed to break
when dropped even if it does not break many times it is dropped (Choi and Fara 2018).
Gunkel 20
assaulted. When we reveal something we are disposed to keep Hidden, it feels as if we are overcoming
This does not mean that Amy’s being sexually assaulted will always be a Hidden feature of her.
Amy might be inspired to become an activist, to speak often about her sexual assault in order to effect
policy change. After doing this for some time, she might come to feel comfortable with sharing. Her
A second concern one might have about the Hiddenness Condition is that it can’t capture the
intimacy of interacting with a person’s public features in very familiar ways. For instance, though faces
are very public, touching someone’s face is usually an intimate gesture. If a person is not disposed to
hide their face, how can we say someone’s touching it exposes a hidden feature? This problem only
arises when our features are carved up in sloppy ways. Though it is true that the look of our face is
not hidden, the feel of our face is. We would be uncomfortable at the exposure of the feel of our face.
And it is not only that we would be uncomfortable with someone being close enough to touch it, or
feeling entitled to put their hands on us, though violations of these relationship-building norms explain
part of the discomfort. We can know this because many of us would be uncomfortable if a scan was
used to make a 3-D printed model of our face, which was then available for anyone to touch.
Likewise, though what our face looks like at some time T 1 might be public, what our face looks
like through time is not. The public does not have access to the patterns of my facial expressions or
physicality. A pattern can be hidden even though a single instance of my instantiating the pattern is
not. Jenna’s touching her eyebrows once might be public, but her pattern of rubbing them when
stressed can remain hidden even so. That one of our features can be a pattern we engage in is a very
important detail. A 70 year old man who doesn’t much talk may still be known very intimately by a
spouse who has seen his intimate features revealed through 50 years of daily patterns.
Gunkel 21
We also monitor our facial expressions more closely in public. Though my neutral expression
might be public, my expression of intense anguish is not. I, like most people, feel deeply uncomfortable
crying in public. When we describe features in adequate detail, we can see that it is too simple and too
There is, I grant, something strange about speaking of intimacy so informationally. It does feel
a bit unnatural to describe the intimacy of having one’s face touched as someone getting information
about the feel of one’s face. However, we often speak of intimacy in terms of special knowledge. We
talk of “really knowing” someone. So though speaking of intimate information seems a bit awkward,
Meeting the Hiddenness Condition alone is not sufficient for intimacy. There are some
features of ourselves which we are disposed to hide, which would make us uncomfortable if exposed,
and yet are not intimate. How we cut our toe nails is usually one such feature. We are disposed not to
cut our toenails in public, or even with friends. We would find it very uncomfortable should someone
make public a secret recording of us cutting our toenails. However, for most of us, we do not think
our toenail cutting technique reveals anything intensely personal about us. A secret recording of this
would not be nearly as violating as a secret recording of us engaged in an intimate act, such as having
sex or telling a secret to our partner. Acts like cutting our toenails, while being private, are not typically
intimate. Seeing that intimacy and privacy come apart helps us see one way accounts of intimacy can
go wrong. Features of ourselves that are Hidden, but not intimate, reveal the need for a second
6.2 Importance
Gunkel 22
What this second condition should be is less obvious. We can begin our search from the case
that revealed the Hiddenness Condition alone to be inadequate. We saw that though cutting one’s
toenails is something one is typically disposed to hide, there is something about this act that seems
too trivial, too inconsequential, to play the role that intimacy place in our lives. And remembering that
we are seeking to describe why intimate violations are so serious, it is natural to posit an Importance
Condition. Figuring how to spell out this Importance Condition is the challenge. What features are so
central to our lives, that they are in need of special protection? I posit that they are the ones which are
related to how we see ourselves, which are related to our self-conception. This colors how we move
in the world, and our ability to act autonomously (Oshana 2005), a central feature of personhood.
Important features are those we think make us who we are. This is a subjective condition. Our
This is not to say that we are always right about what features are part of our identity. Someone can
be a racist even if they do not themselves think of themselves as a racist. A man’s being a father could
be an objectively important part of his identity even if he neglects his child and does not think his
being a father defines him. We are not the sole authority on who we are. However, only aspects of
our identity which we think are important can make us uniquely vulnerable in the way intimacy does.15
15 Because how we see ourselves is what is important for vulnerability, the account side-steps many worries about the
nature of identity. Even if there is no fact of the matter about which parts of us are central (see Mogensen 2020), we are
vulnerable merely when we think some parts of ourselves are central. This is true even of Mogensen, who does not
believe there is a fact of the matter about which parts of him are central to his identity. The ‘identity’ concept I’m using
here would instead match onto some concept such as ‘personality’ for him, and will still lead to vulnerability in the
relevant manner.
Gunkel 23
Intimacy makes us uniquely vulnerable because it makes us liable to shame. Where emotions like guilt
are felt about our actions, shame is felt about our person, our self (Lindsay-Hartz 1984; Niedenthal,
Price Tangney, and Gavanski 1994). We feel shame about characteristics we believe, fear, or worry are
The Importance Condition alone is not sufficient for intimacy. We believe many public
features our ourselves reveal a facet of our identity. But though my being a philosopher is Important,
However, Hiddenness and Importance together are able to capture the cases Relationship-
First Views could not. They explain why there is intimacy in Dominatrix, Support Group, Stranger on
a Train, and Memoir. Someone’s sexual desires, their alcohol dependency, their fear of being alone in
a new country, the assault which shaped their relationship to their body, these are all zones many will
be disposed to hide, and will see as part of who they are. It is not only such obviously significant
features that can be intimate zones. And the HI Thesis can explain this. A birthmark may come to
take on outsized importance in a person’s psychology and sense of self, and be kept hidden. What one
threw in the trash this week can even be an intimate zone. This sentiment is captured amusingly by
comedic documentarian John Wilson when he muses about his trash removal: “on Tuesday and Friday
every week, all the evidence of my shameful lifestyle is removed without any question.”16
Some might worry that the Importance Condition fails to capture the intimacy of the body.
We often feel as if our bodies are very private. We go to the bathroom and groom ourselves behind
closed doors. Some go to great lengths to hide their body’s “indecencies” from even romantic partners.
Midge, in The Marvelous Mrs. Maisel, wakes up before her husband every morning and sneaks out of
16 This is from How to With John Wilson, “How to Throw out Your Batteries.”
Gunkel 24
bed to put on her makeup and do her hair, returning to bed before he wakes up so he never sees her
bedhead or bare face. However, the way one excretes waste or how one’s hair looks in the morning
Though it is right that many of these particular bodily functions are not connected to our
personality, having a body itself is an important feature about us. We live our lives as embodied
creatures and this is tremendously connected to our identity, to our concerns. We feed ourselves
multiple times a day, seek out bathrooms on extended trips away from our homes, fear disease, know
others will make judgments about us based on the way we style our bodies, and know our existence
will be over when our body dies. And so even if our bed head is not specifically an important part of
us, it is a manifestation of something important about us: that we are embodied, that our bodies are
unruly and can communicate things about us that we cannot control. And so any uncontrollable
feature of our body can come to take on outsized importance in our self-conception.
Moreover, even if we don’t consciously believe that some bodily feature reveals an important
part of ourselves, we often worry it will be interpreted in such a way, and that perhaps such
interpretations might be right. We might worry that our leg hair or smell after a run will make people
think they’ve gotten insight into our personality, and have judged us to be fundamentally unhygienic
or gross. We might, knowing stereotypes people apply to fat bodies, worry that people will think our
fatness gives them insight into our personality traits; that they’ll conclude we’re lazy or uncaring. We
worry that a cancer or IBS diagnosis could inspire some to think that we should have taken better care
of ourselves, or are disgusting. We feel shame not only about what we believe is true, but what we fear
or worry might be true about us. Therefore, it is unsurprising that bodily features often meet the
As comes through the discussion of the Importance of bodily features, other people’s beliefs
influence which of our features meet the Importance Condition. And through this mechanism, our
Stigma and social oppression clearly affect what beliefs, worries, and fears we have. Stigma
can make seemingly minor features of ourselves into something that, as Erving Goffman argues,
‘spoils’ our identity. Others see a stigmatized feature as connected to, and ruining in some way, our
whole person. The characteristic takes on outsized social importance, and possessing it can mean we
are “disqualified from full social acceptance” (Goffman 1963). When the people around us respond
to a feature of our persons in such a way, it is nearly inevitable that it will meet the Importance
Condition, at least sometimes. Even if we steel ourselves, and do not believe the feature negatively
reflects on who we are, it is exceedingly difficult to never worry or fear that it does. And so for those
of us with more stigmatized features, fear and worry will tend to play a bigger role in determining
Others can also influence which features are Important in less socially systematic ways. So it
is not only our broader culture, but individual relationships and interactions, that can alter our intimate
zones. Imagine that you are having an online Zoom meeting from your home. Some of what is visible
in your background does feel intimate, such as a piece of art a friend made you for. However, right as
you’re logging onto Zoom, your dog knocks a pile of clothes onto the floor. You are disposed to keep
messes in your home Hidden, but don’t have another room from which to work. The mess in the
background is not itself intimate, at least initially, because you don’t think it reveals something
Important about you. After all, your dog just coincidentally knocked over the clothes and you had no
17 That stigmatized individuals are pushed into interpreting themselves through the lens society applies to their
stigmatized identities is similar to what W.E.B Du Bois gets at with his notion of ‘double-consciousness’ (1903).
Gunkel 26
chance to clean it up. However, as the meeting drags on, you notice your colleague’s eyes dart across
the screen. It looks like they might have landed on the piles of clothes. You might initially be confident
that they would be wrong in accessing that the mess reveals anything substantial about you. However,
contemplating what they might be thinking could induce a change in you that makes the pile of clothes
intimate. You could start to fear that it does reveal something about you, that you could have picked
it up if only you had better time management, for instance. Our awareness of what others take to be
Important then, can affect what about us is Important through this mechanism.18 And so our intimate
zones are influenced by others through both the Hiddenness and Importance Conditions.
enough to capture all genuine intimacy, to protect all of our intimate rights. But there is some
intimacy that might seem like it’s unable to be captured by the account, where it’s not obvious that
any intimate zones are being revealed. These are cases in which something is paradigmatically shared
only in intimate relationships, and yet doesn’t seem especially revealing. If the intimate zones
account couldn’t make sense of why these cases seem intimate to us, this would be a reason to doubt
Pet names are used as a example of “interpersonal intimacy” by Thi Nguyen and Matthew
Strohl.19 They share that Nguyen and his spouse call each other by “odd pet names” (2019, 988).
And there is something seemingly intimate about having a goofy pet name for someone. Though not
confined to romantic contexts, we nearly invariably give pet names only to people we’re very close
with. A dear friend of mine calls me “Jamblies,” a term she invented accidently, when she misspoke
18 This is reminiscent of Charles Cooley’s influential concept of the ‘looking glass self’ (1902). This is one mechanism by
which others’ imagined perceptions of us can influence our self.
19 I thank an anonymous reviewer for encouraging me to think about this case.
Gunkel 27
while meaning to affectionately insult my “rambley voice.” This pet name encapsulates so much of
our friendship: our comfort and security and knowledge of each other, that I can poke fun at her
tendency to misspeak and she can do the same at my tendency to prattle on. Can the Hidden
Importance Thesis give us insight into the phenomenon of pet names, and why they strike us as so
intimate? Let’s take a look at five cases. Only one showcases what I call an ‘intimate violation.’ Three
showcase wrongs having to do with intimacy, wrongs that the account gives us the ingredients to
1. Pet Name Alex calls their wife, Beatrice, “smooshie.” Alex calls her this in public,
It’s not obvious what could be Hidden here, given their public usage of the nickname. And
it’s not obvious how ‘smooshie’, let alone more common pet names like ‘honey’, captures anything
someone would see as related to their identity. So how might the HI Thesis make sense of the
Alex might call Beatrice ‘smooshie’ because the term sounds soft and squishy, and they
know a soft and squishy side of Beatrice. This side might be Important to Beatrice’s identity, and
also Hidden from the general view. Because dubbing Beatrice ‘smooshie’ is the result of an intimate
exposure of this softer side, giving her the nickname can be recognized as an intimate act.
2. Spying A stranger secretly puts a camera into Alex and Beatrice’s home, and
witnesses the softer side of Beatrice that way. The stranger calls Beatrice “smooshie”
Beatrice’s intimate zones.. The Intimate Zones Account helps us identify exactly where the intimate
rights-violations occur. It also allows us to distinguish this sort of case from nearby cases which,
while sometimes wrong for other reasons, do not violate intimate rights. Let’s take a look at three of
them.
3. Catcaller: Beatrice is walking alone at night. She is on the phone with Alex, who
uses her nickname when they say goodbye. A man overhears. He wolf whistles and
In Catcaller, the usage of the nickname isn’t responsive to Beatrice’s intimate features.
Rather, because pet names are a common marker of intimacy, they can be used to pretend some
intimacy already exists between the parties, communicate that intimacy is desired, or even to assert
power. It is tempting to think that the wrong committed in Catcaller is an intimate one. But it is
better to understand it as a threat of intimate wrongs. Alone at night, Beatrice might very well be
afraid that the catcalling might escalate. Catcalling is sometimes succeeded by being followed down
the street, or even sexual assault, and women are well-aware of this. Someone who catcalls a woman
alone at night demonstrates that they either don’t care if a women is made afraid, or like causing that
fear. This makes it eminently reasonable, and prudent for staying safe, to find them threatening. The
threat of intimate violence is a grave wrong, and so we can strongly condemn this even though an
‘intimate violation’ does not occur. In parallel, the reasons physical violence is wrong make the
Gunkel 29
threat of physical violence wrong, but we wouldn’t call a threat to hit someone an act of physical
violence.
4. Crush: Alex develops a crush on a friend and starts to call her “smooshie”.
Beatrice is wronged in Crush, but there is no violation of her intimate rights. It is our own
intimate zones that make us uniquely vulnerable, and give rise to the special protection of intimate
rights. Our intimate rights are rights over ourselves, not rights over how people behave with others.
Alex would wrong Beatrice if he slept with someone else without Beatrice’s consent. But she doesn’t
have an intimate right against him doing this, as she does have an intimate right to refuse to
continue to have sex with him. Alex wrongs Beatrice, and does so in a way that has to do with
intimacy. He takes a nickname that made her feel special and taints it. In doing so, he can undermine
her trust in him. And as I argue in “Shame, Self-Shaping, and Intimate Rights” (redacted,
manuscript), because intimacy makes us vulnerable, we typically only choose to expose our intimate
zones when we trust, at least in the domain of exposure, those to whom we expose ourselves. So
when Alex undermines Beatrice’s trust, he’s likely to undermine her comfort revealing her intimate
5. Overstepping Friends: After overhearing Alex use the nickname, Alex and
Beatrice friends’ begin to call Beatrice “smooshie.” They occasionally persist even
Gunkel 30
after she reminds them she only likes it when Alex calls her that. The friends have
As Nguyen and Strohl put it when talking about what Nguyen shares with his wife: “Are
their friends allowed to witness, use and transmit those pet names and that funny dance? There is no
independently grounded fact of the matter; it simply depends on where the couple decides the
boundary should be” (988). Beatrice’s asking her friends not to use the pet name makes it wrong for
them to use it. But their usage isn’t wrong only because of the request to avoid it. Rather, their usage
can also undermine the symbolism of the pet name. The non-intimate utterances can have a
swamping effect on the intimate ones. Others might not realize that when Alex uses the pet name, it
is different, and an intimate act. And so others’ perception of the intimacy shared between Alex and
Beatrice can be undermined. And for Alex and Beatrice too, the association with intimate exposure
might weaken. They might instead come to more heavily associate it with feelings of annoyance, as
their friends overstep bounds, or even use it to make fun of the couple.
Though I’ve focused here on pet names, this pattern applies broadly. Many things that are
shared paradigmatically in intimate relationships, from inside jokes to mannerisms to a couch, are
not intrinsically intimate. But even when there is no revelation of anyone’s intimate zones, my
Intimate Zones Account and exploration of how intimacy builds can help us better understand why
they’re associated with intimacy, and why they can make people vulnerable to special sorts of harms.
Now that we can see how Hiddenness and Importance make for an intimate zone, let’s turn
our attention to how these zones can make us vulnerable. Recall that I have defined an intimate act
as “an act that exposes, or relies on the exposure of, at least one intimate zone.” And recall in
“Support Group,” Valencia attends a meeting of Alcoholic Anonymous. Given that “Anonymous”
Gunkel 31
is in the name of the group, and members do not share their last names with each other to partially
conceal their identities, in what sense are Valencia’s intimate zones ‘exposed’?20 And what if Valencia
introduced herself with a fake name, and wore a disguise to the meeting? Understanding why these
count as exposures is helpful for seeing why intimate exposure makes us vulnerable, and thus why
Valencia’s intimate zones can be exposed even if they are not revealed to be Valencia’s
intimate zones. In parallel, imagine that a tornado rips the wall off of Valencia’s room, leaving the
room visible to passersby. A passing stranger might be unaware the room belongs to her as they
peer inside. Her room is exposed even though its being her room is not.
Recall that when we discussed Hiddenness and Importance, shame came up in relation to
both conditions. And as I argue elsewhere (redacted, manuscript), shame can warp us. Though I
don’t have space here to fully develop and defend the view, I’ll sketch it enough that the reader can
see how shame could be the sort of thing to, in conjunction with Hiddenness and Importance,
explain why intimate violations are so serious. Shame can subvert our rational decision making
processes about how we’d like to change, instead making us feel so badly that we can become
desperate to change the feature we see as responsible for the feeling. And shame about our intimate
features, because they meet the Importance Condition, threatens to alter us not only in some
incidental way, but along axes we see as important to who we are. I call this the ‘shame-warping
thesis’.
Even when we don’t share our real name or show our face to someone, their reactions still
have the power to induce shame in us. If Valencia shares her rock bottom moment in an AA
meeting, and someone reacts with “you’re a disgusting human being!”, she might feel shame even if
20I’m grateful to an anonymous referee for encouraging me to explore what “exposure” requires, particular in light of
this example.
Gunkel 32
she’s wearing a disguise and introduced herself as ‘Veronica’. Others’ interactions with our intimate
zones can be tremendously affecting even if they don’t know who we are. We can be exposed and
altered even when our name and face are concealed. As long as we feel others’ eyes on our intimate
The reader might be suspicious that there is an additional condition (or conditions) necessary
for a zone to be intimate. Though I cannot present a counterexample to every possible additional
Psychologists Karen Prager and Linda Roberts stipulate that intimate interactions require
(2004, 45). Though Prager and Roberts reject a requirement of positive affect, this is reminiscent of
Inness’s Motivation Account. Does intimacy require, if not positive feelings, some kind of positive
Intimate violations typically preclude positive involvement, and so an account of intimacy that
is to capture them cannot have this condition. Sexual assault, reading someone’s diary without consent,
torture: the performances of these actions display a total lack of regard for the violated. The violated
is not seen as a collaborator. The assault can certainly distancing and alienating. Yet they intimately
expose the victim and leave them uniquely vulnerable, and this makes them gravely wrong. To add a
Positive Regard Condition would undermine the goal of giving an account that can explain the unique
To take an example that is less theoretically loaded, we can look to fights between loved ones.
Surely a couple can have an intimate fight in which both parties become defensive. Someone might
Gunkel 33
even be prone to becoming defensive when their intimate zones are being discussed. Because our
intimate zones are loci of vulnerability, it is unsurprising that discussion of them might breed
defensiveness. However, though positive regard is not necessary for an act to be intimate, this does
not mean it is unimportant to intimacy. Rather than characterizing what is intimate, positive regard
Though we are disposed to hide our intimate features, we are not always entitled to hide them.
To see why someone might think there is an Entitlement Condition on intimate zones, consider the
following case.
Karl the Kidnapper: Karl has kidnapped someone and is keeping them trapped in his
basement. Unlike some other kidnappers who only worry about the legal consequences
According to the Intimate Zones Account, Karl’s having someone in his basement is intimate.
This understandably will strike many as odd, and as reason to add an additional condition. Because
kidnapping someone is obviously wrong, and keeping this fact hidden interferes with the victim’s
rescue, one is not entitled to hide this fact. That someone is trapped in one’s basement is simply not
the kind of thing one is allowed to keep to oneself. By adding that one must be entitled to keep a
feature hidden for the feature to be intimate, such cases would be ruled out.
It is a bit awkward to call having a person in one’s basement ‘intimate information,’ but that
is in part because of the conversational implications of calling something ‘intimate.’ When you assert
Gunkel 34
that something is “intimate,” you’re often communicating “mind your own business.” And this would
be clearly inappropriate to utter if someone was inquiring into your having a kidnapping victim. But
that this would be an inappropriate conversational move does not mean that the fact isn’t intimate.
Similarly, we have an obligation to reveal a shameful secret if a villain will otherwise murder a
crowd. And there are many non-fictional examples of our being obligated to reveal intimate features.
Though we are prima facie entitled to hide our health conditions, there are some jobs which legally
and morally obligate us to disclose them, such as being a commercial airline pilot. That they are
intimate, even though we must disclose them, explains why such disclosure requirements can be so
discomforting. Leaving off an Entitlement Condition helps us see that requiring such employment
disclosures makes people vulnerable, and is a pro tanto wrong. It is more accurate to see that this
vulnerability is outweighed by other considerations, rather than to think that there is nothing to
outweigh.
Finally, adding an Entitlement Condition passes the buck. Rather than our intimate features
being loci of vulnerability because of our psychology, and this vulnerability grounding our intimate
rights, the story would be much less informative. To say we have intimate rights because we are entitled
to keep our intimate zones hidden would leave us wondering: but why are we entitled to keep these
features hidden? Rather than claiming that we are entitled to keep the intimate hidden, we should seek
to understand why the nature of our intimate features make us vulnerable, and so typically entitled to
control them.
There is something a little strange, I grant, about building intimacy up from exposure of the
self. This concern is helpfully developed by Candace Vogler. In “Sex and Talk,” she states that her
purpose is “not to argue against the thought that intimacy is sometimes a matter of reciprocal self-
Gunkel 35
expression and self-scrutiny . . . but to contend, first, that not all intimacies are affairs of the self”
(1998, 328-9). Vogler parodies Nozick’s views about the self-expressive nature of intimacy. She quips
that “Nozickian romance is made of autobiographies” (1998, 361). Such an intimate encounter is quite
silly to imagine: each party listing facts about themselves and their history. However, our intimate
zones are not revealed only by our listing facts. Someone’s shyness, for instance, tends to be revealed
by their seldom speaking rather than by an utterance of “I am shy.” Our self is often revealed through
our actions and patterns. And so our selves are often revealed more naturally, and not solely by
But there is something deeper to this line of criticism. It is not only that autobiographical
revelations would be comedic and strange, but that there is something morally objectionable about
approaching intimate interactions this way. It seems too self-centered. It seems to risk encouraging
what Mark Johnston calls the ‘pornographic attitude’ in our intimate interactions. Johnston defines
the ‘pornographic attitude’ as “the change of attentive focus from the appeal of other things and other
people to their agreeable effect on us” (2001, 201). It’s right that there is something morally troubling
about exclusively focusing on ourselves during intimate exchanges. But this again tells us about how
to do intimacy well, not what intimacy is. Though intimacy reveals our intimate zones, we should not
spend all our time being intimate with others thinking about our own zones. Not only does this take
us out of the moment, but it can distract us to the point we don’t give uptake to the intimate exposures
of others. This disrupts intimacy building. Deeply intimate relationships require two people get to
know each other’s intimate zones, not solely spout off about their own.
12. Conclusion
In this paper, I have developed the landscape of possible views about intimacy. It is my hope
that adding this structure will make investigations into intimacy easier, more fruitful, and more
Gunkel 36
common. Whether or not the reader is persuaded by the Intimate Zones Account, I hope the reader
is persuaded that we think clearly and systematically about intimacy, and that it requires our attention.
Intimacy is powerful. It’s vital for human flourishing. It can be powerfully transformative or
deeply violating. But without a philosophical account of intimacy’s nature, how this is possible is
obscured. That intimacy makes us vulnerable helps us understand this valence. Being vulnerable to
others is required if they are to really know us, if we are to build loving relationships. But being
vulnerable to others also risks the worst sorts of abuses. Not only might we be subject to violence, or
to our secrets being used to exploit us, but we also risk others’ judgments about the deepest and most
Relationship-First Accounts describe something important. They tell us about some kinds of
intimate relationships, close and loving ones. And they do give us important insight into why these
are worthy of protection. However, there is intimacy outside of such relationships, and we need to
understand the full nature of intimacy if we are going to understand how it makes us vulnerable and
what policies are appropriate to govern intimate interactions in our personal and professional lives.
What is so deserving of protection in loving relationships can be found elsewhere, and must be
protected there as well. The Intimate Zones Account lets us see this. Intimacy, whether in loving
relationships or in encounters between strangers, reveals Hidden and Important features of persons.
It is my conviction that the Intimate Zones Account can explain the stringency of our intimate
rights, and settle disputes about their scope. Perhaps, I grant, I have been too ambitious in claiming
that it is a complete theory of intimacy, that intimate zones are at bottom of it all. Maybe my
conception of intimacy is so far from our everyday conception that it is only fit to be called intimacy*.
Whether the Intimate Zones Account describes intimacy or intimacy* does not matter as much to me
Intimacy lets others deeply know us, and so makes us vulnerable to being shaped by them.
Given this, we must have control over how and when we reveal our intimate zones, and not just with
whom we are in loving relationships. This ought to guide us in our investigations not only of abortion,
surrogacy, and sex work, but also of therapy, teaching, and art. Intimacy’s importance has been
gestured at in many of these arenas, but a theory of intimacy in hand can help us make new progress
with them.
Intimacy is very risky. But many tremendously rewarding activities are risky. It would be a
grave mistake to always run from such risks, or to prohibit others from accepting them. But these
risks must guide us in our pursuits. And we must remember that others can reasonably weight these
risks and their rewards differently from us. In such deeply personal and risky matters, we must abide
Works Cited
Boris, Eileen, and Rhacel Salazr Parreńas (eds.). (2010). Intimate Labors: Cultures, Technologies, and the
Politics of Care. Stanford University Press.
Brun, George. (2016). “Explication as a Method of Conceptual Re-engineering.” Erkenntnis, 81:
1211-1241.
Choi, Sungho and Michael Fara. (2018). “Dispositions”. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Cohen, Jean L. (2002). “Regulating Intimacy: A New Legal Paradigm.” Princeton University Press.
Cohen, Ted. (1978). “Metaphor and the Cultivation of Intimacy.” Critical Inquiry 5(1): 3-12.
Cooley, Charles. (1902). Human Nature and Social Order. Charles Scribner’s Sons.
De Bois, W.E.B. (1903). The Souls of Black Folk. A.C. McClurg & Co.
Feder Kittay, Eva. (1999.) Love’s Labor. Routledge.
Feder Kittay, Eva. (2011). “The Ethics of Care, Dependence, and Disability.” Ratio Juris 24(1): 49-58.
Gay, Roxanne. (2017). Hunger: A Memoir of (My) Body. HarperCollins Publishers.
Goffman, Erving. (1963). Stigma: Notes on the Management of Spoiled Identity. Simon & Schuster.
Hart, H.L.A. (1961). The Concept of Law. Clarendon Press.
Haslanger, Sally. (2005). “What Are We Talking About? The Semantics and Politics of Social
Kinds.” Hypatia, 20(4): 10-26.
Inness, Julie C. (1996). Privacy, Intimacy, and Isolation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Johnston, Mark. (2001). “The Authority of Affect.” International Phenomenological Society 63(2): 181-214.
Lindsay-Hartz, Janice. (1984). Contrasting experiences of shame and guilt. American Behavioral Scientist
27: 689-704.
Little, Margaret Olivia. (1999). “Abortion, Intimacy, and the Duty to Gestate.” Ethical Theory and
Moral Practice 2(3): 295-312.
Mogensen, Andreas L. (2021). “Is Identity Illusory?” European Journal of Philosophy 29(1): 55-73.
Niedenthal, Paula M., June Price Tangney, and Igor Gavanski. (1994). “’If Only I Weren’t’ Versus ‘If
Only I Hadn’t’: Distinguishing Shame and Guilt In Counterfactual Thinking.” Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 67(4): 585-595.
Nozick, Robert. (1989). The Examined Life: Philosophical Meditations. Simon and Schuster.
Nitchovski, Pavel. (2022). On Intimacy. Doctoral Dissertation, Chapel Hill.
Oshana, Marina. (2005). “Autonomy and Self-identity.” In Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism,
ed. John Chistman and Joel Anderson. Cambridge University Press.
Prager, Karen J., and Linda J. Roberts. (2004). “Deep Intimate Connection: Self and Intimacy in
Couple Relationships.” In Handbook of Closeness and Intimacy, ed. Debra J. Mashek and Arthur
Aron.
Rachels, James. (1975) “Why Privacy is Important.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 4(4): 323-333.
Reiman, Jeffrey H. (1976). “Privacy, Intimacy, and Personhood.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 6(1): 26-
44.
Strohl, Matthew and C. Thi Nguyen. (2019). “Cultural Appropriation and the Intimacy of Groups.”
Philosophical Studies 176(4): 981-1002.
Sussman, David. (2005). “What’s Wrong with Torture?” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33(1): 1-33.
Vogler, Candace (Winter 1998). “Sex and Talk.” Critical Inquiry 24(2): 328-365.
Yancy, George. (2019). “Moonlight: The Weight of ‘Intimacy’.” Western Journal of Black Studies
43(3/4): 65-69.