Week 11

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 4

DAVAO CENTRAL COLLEGE, INC.

Juan dela Cruz Street, Toril, Davao City


Landline No. (082) 291 1882

Accredited by ACSCU-ACI
GE ETH1

Week 11: Universalizability

Learning Outcomes:
1. Students will be able to evaluate actions using the
universalizability test;
2. Understand Kant’s moral philosophy.

Concept Digest

UNIVERSALIZABILITY

To figure out how the faculty of reason can be use of an


autonomous action, we need to learn a method or a specific
procedure that will demonstrate autonomy of the will. But
first, we need to make a distinction about kinds of moral
theories namely, substantive and formal moral theories.

Substantive moral theory immediately promulgates the specific


actions that comprise that theory. It identifies the particular
duties in straightforward manner that the adherents or
followers of the theory must follow. The specific laws are
articulated mostly in the form of a straightforward moral
command: example, the set of Ten Commandments “Honor your
father and mother”, “You shall not kill” and so forth.

Formal moral theory does not supply the rules or commands


straightaway. It does not tell you what you may or may not do.
Instead, it will give us a set of instructions on how to make a
list of duties or moral commands.

Kant endorses the formal moral theory. The Grundlegung zur


Metaphysik der Sitten (1785), embodies a formal moral theory in
what he calls the categorical imperative, which provides a
procedural way of identifying the rightness or wrongness of an
action. Kant articulates the categorical imperative this way:

Act only according to such a maxim, by which you can at once will that hit become
a universal law.

The four key elements in the formulation of categorical


imperative: action, maxim, will and universal law.

Kant states that we must formulate an action as a maxim, which


he defines as a “subjective principle of action”. In this
context, a maxim consists of a “rule” that we live by in our
day-to-day lives, but it does not have the status of a law or a
moral command that binds us to act in a certain way. Rather,
maxims depict the patterns of our behavior.

Page 1 of 4
DAVAO CENTRAL COLLEGE, INC.
Juan dela Cruz Street, Toril, Davao City
Landline No. (082) 291 1882

Accredited by ACSCU-ACI
Kant pointed out that we should act according to a maxim by
which we can at once will that it become a universal law. But
what does it mean to will a maxim that can become a universal
law? It means that the maxim must be universalizable. In this
formulation, Kant, is telling us to conceive of the maxim as if
it obligated everyone to comply. This mental act of imagining a
universalized maxim leads us to imagine a maxim as a law that
everyone ought to follow.

In Groundwork towards a Metaphysics of Morals, Kant takes up


the issue of making false promises. Consider a man who needs a
money but has no immediate access to obtain it except borrowing
from a friend. This man knows that he cannot pay it back yet he
still borrows the money. This is a specific act under the
general category of acts called false promising.

What does it mean to universalize the maxim of borrowing money


without intending to return it? It is simple. The maxim can
either make sense or not make sense as a universal law. By
“making sense”, we refer to the logical plausibility
(reasonable) of the universalized maxim. The opposite of
logical plausibility is self-contradiction or logical
impossibility.

Let us assess the hypothetical world of borrowing money without


the intention to return it. If this is the case, then, all
lenders would know that they will not be paid and they will
refuse to lend money. The institution of money-borrowing would
lose its meaning of everyone borrow money without intending to
pay it bask. As as universalized maxim, it would self-destruct
because it becomes impossible. This is how Kant assesses it:

Here I see straightaway that it could never be valid as a universal law of nature and
be consistent with itself, but must necessarily contradict itself. For the universality
of a law that each person, when he believes himself to be in need, could promise
whatever he pleases with the intent not to keep it, would make the promise and the
purpose that he may have impossible, since no one would believe what was
promised him but would laugh at such expressions as futile pretense.

In the passage above, Kant distinguishes between being


“consistent with itself” and “contradict itself”. Looking at
the maxim again: “When I am in need of money, I shall borrow it
even when I know I cannot pay it back”. The contradiction is
evident: to borrow (implies returning) but the intention is not
to return. It makes no sense. This is why Kant claims that the
universalized maxim “could never be valid as a universal law of
nature and be consistent with itself, but must necessarily
contradict itself”. Therefore, the act of borrowing money
without intending to pay is irrationally impermissible. Here,
we discover two ways by which Kant rejects maxims. The
universalized maxim becomes either (1) self-contradictory or
(2) the act and its purpose become impossible.

Page 2 of 4
DAVAO CENTRAL COLLEGE, INC.
Juan dela Cruz Street, Toril, Davao City
Landline No. (082) 291 1882

Accredited by ACSCU-ACI

What is the result of all these? We reveal the rational


permissibility of actions insofar as they cannot be rejected as
universalizable maxims. In contrast, those universalized maxims
that are rejected are shown impermissible, that is, they are
irrational and thus, in Kant’s mind, immoral. But what does
rational permissibility mean? Simply put, it refers to the
intrinsic quality of action that is objectively and necessarily
rational. Therefore, we have demonstrated that borrowing money
without intending to pay, as kind of false promise, is
objectively and necessarily wrong, insofar as it encounters a
self-contradiction and logical impossibility when it is
universalized as maxim.

SUMMARY

Kant’s categorical imperative is formal, not substantive,


moral philosophy. We have shown how an action is permissible or
not. Instead of given list of substantive moral commands, we
now have a sort of tool, like a measuring instrument, that
tells us whether an action is morally permissible or not.
Hence, we have the capacity to make our own list of moral
commands. Instead of receiving them from other, we use our
rational faulty to produce our own list of moral duties.

Returning to Reggie and the suitcase that was left in his


cab, he can now test on his own moral permissibility of the
formulated maxim: “When a suitcase that does not belong to me
is left in my can, I shall take its contents and sell the for
my own benefit”. Does the universalized maxim encounter a self-
contradiction, or does it remain self-consistent? The
universalized maxim of Reggie becomes contradictory, for the
meaning of ownership is contradicted. How is it that everyone
is obligated to take a suitcase and sell its contents, despite
the fact that they do not have the rights to possess, use, and
dispose of that suitcase?
Now, imagine applying this procedure to other scenarios in
which a person encounters moral problems, such as lying,
cheating in exam, murder and adultery, among others. Can the
maxims in the specific actions under those moral issues be
universalized without encountering self-contradiction?

In summary, this procedure is properly used when one


wishes to determine the moral permissibility of an action.
Indeed, we are often already told which actions are right or
wrong, but this knowledge is usually based on what authority
figure say like our parents, priests, school rules and
regulations, and government ordinances already prescribe
clearly determined moral commands. So what is the categorical
imperative for? If we already know whether or not an action is
right?

Page 3 of 4
DAVAO CENTRAL COLLEGE, INC.
Juan dela Cruz Street, Toril, Davao City
Landline No. (082) 291 1882

Accredited by ACSCU-ACI
The categorical imperative is precisely for the rational
will that is autonomous. Recall that autonomy implies a self-
legislating will. The test for universalizability makes
possible for self-legislation, for the result of the
categorical imperative, is nothing other than the capacity to
distinguish between permissible and impermissible moral acts.
Any rational will can then begin the work of producing a list
of duties, what a rational and autonomous will believes to be
right and wrong actions.

In conclusion, what can deontology contribute to our


lives, specifically to our moral reflection? The answer lies in
one concept: enlightenment morality. This kind of morality is
opposed to paternalism, which evokes the metaphor of father. In
this metaphor, the father makes decisions on behalf of and in
the interest of the children, as long as the children are
dependent and may nit know yet what is best for them. The
children are expected to comply and obey because they are still
unfit to make good decisions on their own. But what happens
when children grow and become mature adults? When they move on
to develop their minds and live their own lives? Certainly,
paternalism has to give way to a more mature and rational will
when the children are no longer children, when they mature, and
can begin to navigate the complex world.

This is therefore, the place of deontology in the spirit


of enlightenment morality. Deontology is based on the “light”
of one’s own reason when maturity and rational capacity take
hold of a person’s decision-making. With deontology,
particularly the method of universalizability, we can validate
and adopt those rules and laws that are right and reject those
that are irrational, thus impermissible because they are self-
contradictory. This is the practical value of deontology in our
moral reflection: we are encouraged to have courage to think on
our own, to use our rational will against external authorities
as well as internal base impulses that tend to undermine our
autonomy and self-determination.

Page 4 of 4

You might also like