Department of The Classics, Harvard University
Department of The Classics, Harvard University
Department of The Classics, Harvard University
Studies in Xenophanes
Author(s): Aryeh Finkelberg
Source: Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, Vol. 93 (1990), pp. 103-167
Published by: Department of the Classics, Harvard University
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/311284 .
Accessed: 26/12/2014 05:58
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Department of the Classics, Harvard University is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Harvard Studies in Classical Philology.
http://www.jstor.org
ARYEH FINKELBERG
3 Metaph. 986b27 (here and elsewhere Aristotle is quoted in the Oxford translation
with occasional minor changes); cf. Cael. 298b15. Renderingntot as 'in places,' 'else-
where' seems to me preferableto the reading 'with somewhat more insight': the former
construalseems to be suggested both by the fact that Aristotlerefershere to the Doxa and
by t•adtvat 986b33.
4 Cf. Aristotle's discussion in Ph. 184b15-187a10.
5 Metaph.984b2.
6 Cf. H. Bonitz, Aristotelis Metaphysica. Commentarius (Bonn 1849, repr. Hil-
desheim 1960) 72, 84; A. E. Taylor, Aristotle on His Predecessors (repr., Chicago-
London 1949) 49; Ross (above, n. 2) 1.153, ad 986b19; K. Deichgraiber,"Xenophanes
nrepi(poeco;," RhM 87 (1938) 14. H. Cherniss,Aristotle's Criticism of Presocratic Phi-
losophy (Baltimore 1935) 220 n. 15, is therefore wrong in assuming that Aristotle
deduces the formal characterof Parmenides'and the materialcharacterof Melissus' One
only from the finitudeof the formerand the infinity of the latter.
Now why could Aristotle not determine which kind of unity was
posited by Xenophanes? To answer this question we should recall that
in forming his judgment concerning the respective natures of Par-
menides' and Melissus' One, Aristotle was relying on two criteria,the
spatial characteristicsof the One and its compatibilitywith "more than
one accordingto our sensations." The lack of clear statementon Xeno-
phanes' part must therefore mean the lack of unambiguousdetermina-
tion of God in precisely these two respects. This is to say that in Xeno-
phanes Aristotle found neitherdirect statementsnor indirectindications
as to whether he assumed that God, though one entity, nevertheless
allowed internaldiversity and whetherhe conceived of God as finite or
infinite.14The former obscurity is surprising. Melissus consistently
denied the sensible manifold, but Parmenides"in places" spoke "with
more insight,"that is, supplementedhis doctrineof the One with that of
"two causes and two principles";on Aristotle's account, Xenophanes
seems to have done neither. Aristotle, however, knew that, beside the
doctrine of the One, Xenophanes, like Parmenides, advanced cosmo-
gonical and cosmological doctrines one of which, namely, that earth
stretches indefinitely dawnwards, he discusses in De Caelo;15 yet
strangely enough, Aristotle does not take Xenophanes' cosmology as
an indicationof the formal characterof his One, as he does in the case
of Parmenides. Below, in examining Theophrastus'account of Xeno-
phanes, Aristotle's reasons will become clear; here we must content
ourselves with the mere statementof this fact.
But without toil he shakes all things by the will of his mind.22
n. 6) 220 n. 15: "Xenophanesdoes not say anything which can show in which way he
meant the unity he championed to be understood [viz. whether it is formal or material],
and Aristotle decides that it was with a view to the whole universe that he said that the
One is God." Does Cherniss mean that the unity declared "with a view to the whole
universe"need not be either formal or material?
19Notably by H. Frankel, Dichtung und Philosophie des friihen Griechentums(New
York 1951) 428.
20 Cf. von Fritz (above, n. 14) 1546-1547; Guthrie(above, n. 8) 1. 382; Babut (above,
n. 8) 430, and some others.
21 See Guthrie (above, n. 8) 1. 382 (cf. F. M. Cornford,Principium Sapientiae [Cam-
bridge 1952] 147), who asserts that &civrlroqin Metaph. 986b14 must mean "ungen-
erated." But does not Aristotle say: ". .. some at least of those who maintainit to be one
... say the one and natureas a whole is unchangeablenot only in respect of generation
and destrucilton(for this is a primitive belief, and all agreed in it), but also of all other
change; and this view is peculiarto them"(Metaph.984a29)? This equally applies to the
suggestion of F. M. Cleve, The Giants of the Pre-Socratic Greek Philosophy (The Hague
1965) 24, that God is unchangeableonly in respect of his size.
22On v6oi cppEvisee: K. von Fritz, "NOYX,NOEIN and Their Derivatives in Preso-
cratic Philosophy 'excluding Anaxagoras)," CP 40 (1945) 229-230; see also S. M.
Darcus,"The Phren of the Noos in Xenophanes' God,"SO 53 (1978) 25-39.
bance. Xenophanes' God thus always remainsin the same place and in
the same state, which is tantamountto freedom from all kinds of move-
ment includingchange.23
God's identity with the entire universe is not only implied by group-
ing God with Eleatic Being but is also explicitly and unambiguously
pointed out by Aristotle: "with his sight on the whole of the world he
says that the One is, viz. God." Still, some critics challenge this
report.24How, we are asked, can God, if unmoved and indentical with
the world, be said, as infr. 25, to move all things? Does this not rather
suggest that unchangeableGod is distinct from the changeable inivta,
the totality of things, which he sets in motion?25To examine the vali-
dity of this objection we must consider the question from three points
of view, doxographic,logical, and historical.
In equating Xenophanes' God with the whole of existence Aristotle
concurs with Plato who, relating Xenophanes to the "Eleatic tribe,"
specifies their-and hence also Xenophanes'-teaching as the unity of
"what we call all things."26Theophrastus,as we shall see later, and the
Sceptic Timon who, being an admirer and imitator of Xenophanes'
poetry, was necessarily well acquaintedwith it,27adheredto the same
23 Xenophanes' criticism of the
popularbelief that the gods are born (fr. 14) implies
that God is also ungeneratedand a fortiori everlasting (cf. Xenophanes' apophthegms
collected in Diels-Kranz [above, n. 9] under 21 A 12). Babut (above, n. 8) 434, thinks
that "l'immobilit6de Dieu n'est en d6finitiveque la cons6quenceimm&diatede son apti-
tude A r6alisersa volont6 Adistance." Yet God's immobility is but a particularaspect of
his unchangeability(which Babut is not ready to accept in Xenophanes),the explanation
of which should be looked for in the ontological purportof the concept of God.
24On various grounds, see K. Reinhardt, Parmenides und die Geschichte der
griechischen Philosophie (Bonn 1916) 116, 122, 125, 152; Cherniss (above, n. 6) 201
n. 228; O. Gigon, Der Ursprung der griechischen Philosophie (Basel 1945) 184; Jaeger
(above, n. 8) 43; Lumpe (above, n. 8) 22-26; J. Kerschensteiner,Kosmos (Miinchen
1962) 90-93; Kirk,Raven, Schofield (above, n. 7) 171-172.
25Frainkel(above, n. 19) 428, 431-432; cf. Lumpe (above, n. 8) 23; Kirk, Raven,
Schofield (above, n. 7) 171-172.
26Sophist 242D (Diels-Kranz[above, n. 9] 21 A 29). Stokes (above, n. 8) 84, says that
"Aristotleis clearly ... EleaticizingXenophanes. But his involuntaryEleaticizationdoes
not proceed so far as to credit Xenophanes explicitly with the view ... that all things
(meaning the world) are one." Does Stokes mean that Aristotle did not count Xeno-
phanes with the "partisansof the One" or that he did not say that the "partisansof the
One" spoke of the universe"as if it were one entity"?
27Fr. 59. On Timon as an independentsource on Xenophanes see: Steinmetz (above,
n. 13) 35-37; cf. Barnes(above, n. 17) 98.
cal with the world? Obviously not, provided that God is conceived as
an intelligible essence unifying the sensible manifold,-in Aristotle's
terms, the One in definition. Now it seems thatfr. 25 suggests just this
idea of unity. From the more general point of view, this understanding
of God is requiredby the fact that, beside the concept of the unchange-
able One, Xenophanes posited a cosmological doctrine which in its
very essence assumes plurality and change. If in trying to understand
Xenophanes' position we wish to spare ourselves the difficulties which
generationsof Parmenideanscholars have experienced in adopting the
formal approach to Parmenides' system, with the inevitable result of
viewing his mind as split between the real and the fantasy world,29we
will have to grantXenophanes a more or less unified outlook, that is, to
assume the "formal"characterof his One. I am aware of the objection
that logically necessary is not the same as historically true or even
plausible, and I shall thereforeturn now to the historical aspect of the
issue.
Do we indeed possess historical evidence that allows us to credit
Xenophanes with such a sophisticatedidea of unity? Fortunately,we
do. The idea in fact antedatesXenophanes, being attested, at least in a
rudimentaryform, in Anaximander. I mean Diogenes' report that,
according to Anaximander, "the parts change, while the whole is
unchangeable."30"The whole" referredto here can hardly be anything
other than the Apeiron which is therefore said to remain unchangeable
notwithstandingthe changes of its "parts,"i.e., the various components
of the developed world. If my interpretationis correct, the Apeiron
appearshere as a selfsame intelligible essence unifying the changeable
manifold.31I do not intend to claim that this concept of the Apeiron is
predominantin Anaximander;all I wish to show is that Anaximander
29 "A doctrine
which, taken literally, might seem to be either madness or sheer sophis-
try" (C. Kahn, "The Thesis of Parmenides,"Review of Metaphysics 22 [1969] 715); "As
to whetherParmenideshimself accepted these conclusions ... we can merely guess ...
perhapshe believed it all the time, and was mad"(M. Furth,"Elementsof Eleatic Ontol-
ogy," in A. P. D. Mourelatos ed., The Pre-Socratics [New York 1974] 296). There is
something decidedly wrong with the interpretationof a philosophic doctrinethat requires
one to assume the insanity of its author.
30 Diog. 2. 1 (= Diels-Kranz[above, n. 9] 12 A 1).
31It is not impossible that it was Anaximander,and precisely for this reason, whom
Plato primarily had in mind when he said that the "Eleatic tribe" started even before
Xenophanes(cf. above, n. 28).
occasionally touches upon the idea of the intelligible unity of the mani-
fold. But occasional as it may be, the idea is not incidental: it arose, as
I argue elsewhere, in response to the inadequacy of the material form
of monism.32Consequently, if truly understood, the idea had to pro-
duce a profoundeffect on the monistic thinkeraware, as alreadyAnax-
imanderevidently was, of the failure of material monism to provide a
consistently monistic picture. Now who is a better candidate for the
role of such a thinker than Ionian-born and Ionian-educated Xeno-
phanes who in his youth, as Theophrastus tells us, was personally
acquaintedwith Anaximander33and who, as Aristotle puts it, was the
first of the "partisansof the One," that is, the champions of the new
kind of monism?34
I conclude that the Xenophaneanconcept of God as the single and
unchangeable, intelligible essence unifying the manifold, an essence
endowed with divine powers and causing and controlling all that goes
on in the world, must be the development of one of the facets of the
Anaximandreannotion of the Apeiron, the divine substanceunderlying
the entire universe and governing it.35
Jaeger ... [cf. above, n. 37]) that Xenophaneswas not a physiologos; ratherhe said that
Xenophanes' alleged monism was not a 'physical opinion."' Yet Barnes believes that
Theophrastusrelates the Xenophaneanmonistic doctrine to theology (cf. above, n. 38)
and in consequence misinterpretsthe intendedmeaningof Theophrastus'remark: "Xeno-
phanes' theological monism was lightheartedlyconstruedby Plato as an ontological mon-
ism; Theophrastussolemnly indicatesthatPlato is romancing." Setting aside the assump-
tion thatPlato misconstruedXenophanes'doctrine,Theophrastusmeans nothing like this;
he, like Aristotle, sharesPlato's notion of Xenophanes'God as an ontological concept.
44Steinmetz (above, n. 13) 37 and n. 69, 47-48, assesses the paraphraseon the strength
of the resemblance between Aristotle's and Timon's wordings; as does also Barnes
(above, n. 17) 99. Stokes (above, n. 8) 71, in his turn,observes the resemblancein word-
ing between Aristotle and the doxographies stemming from Theophrastusbut makes no
constructiveconclusions.
Table 1
Hippol. Ps.-Plut. Simpl. Cic. Ps.-Galen
Haer. 1.14 Strom.4 Phys. 22.22 Acad. 2.118 Hist. Phil. 7
t oiTe y~veatv
oMboy
o& yive•~ ov?s
0peiperat Topiav
o-V&KtVEdat aLtLt,
arO
,
2 KaiiOn Ev a ETvat gav &Miv unumesse Tvat
T6
siRv ontv fYVttr6 n&v Ev omnia ndzvEa
Tv
ap•rv
Toov Katirav.
rIlot
3 i( neque id
LeTaxo•i;. daE
8iiotov" esse mutabile
4 TplTYoip y p Fv et id Kal oo
Kat ?Tv iai
Tou3To esse deum ot
IOnpX•etv
OEOov
y•EOv
dvat In&vOv
OEv 'AeyEv,
10
11 oute
UE
vov oIUre ;OYtKov,
gLEVOVOUtFE
'tvoV-
lpegofvV...
13 Kaizirdvra
voiv 5U
prlotv "&zaX'
X~Myov aabxb
... •Kpacat-
vet" [B 25].
14
Table 1 (continued)
Sext. Emp. Theodoret. Diogenes Alexander Nicolaus
Pyr. 1.224 4.5 9.19 ap. Simpl. ap. Simpl.
2 v Evat v dvat
7b L&v, 7r L&v
iE~pioe
3
4 mKa v olaitv
Oebvo•upvfi Oeoe
rot; naotv,
7 navraXdOeV
o8otov
8 edvat8o'zttpoet&- i,
opatpoetm nEnepaogpvov
ompatpoetL8 Ka) Kat •ratpov
Kat
nEnEpacLovOV, octpatpOetm
9 ptyuiv 4otov
EXo-oav
10 0o YEVtIo)V
aXStov
11 m
tnaOfi mti d tvar7ov
ri
Kat an•av
artvtrlov.
Xl9Trov
12 Ka'i 8Pov 8E
oyLKdv. Opav Kati
0 Kov duoiEtV,
g11
~lEVTOt
dvvatvoi3v
pcp6vlvotv
13
14 Kati itov.
AristotleMetaph.986b24 Theophrastus
tbvOE6v. icairouro060E6;
cott.
50 Some critics (see Burnet [above, n. 10] 125 n. 1; Deichgriiber [above, n. 6] 27 and
n. 44; Barnes [above, n. 17] 98-99) take Timon's fr. 60 (... OEbv... Toov &ncvrT
(d&rpefii)d&acr0i voespotepovin as an evidence of God's homogeneity. Here,
vorl•ta)
however, as distinct fromfr. 59, Timon obviously goes far beyond Xenophanes' wording
and even Xenophanes' very idea, for it is of course needless to argue that Xenophanes
could neither speak nor conceive of God as voep•kepog;i v6rlLa. Timon here accom-
modates Xenophanes' notion to later conceptual patterns, so that we need not, while
rejecting i7v6rlega, take Toov &nainv as more authentic, and the fact that
Aristotle voeptrepov
did not know about God's homogeneity indeed proves that it is not authentic.
This, however, is not to say that the word i8goto; did not occur in Xenophanes: Table 2
shows that Deichgrdiber(above, n. 6) is correct in suggesting that the word can be traced
back to Xenophanes. But we must distinguish between gLoto; without qualificationor
qualified with &eli(as in Ps.-Plut. Strom.4 = Diels-Kranz[above, n. 9] 21 A 32; cf. Timon
fr. 59.6: 6pion;6jooir) which gives 'the same,' 'selfsame,' and ~igoto; qualified with
adverbialslike or riavral (Hippol. Haer. 1.14; Simpl. Phys. 22.22;
Timonfr. 60 =ixcvrl,, cavax~•68Ev,n. 21 A
Diels-Kranz [above, 9] 33, 31, 35) which means 'everywherethe
same,' viz. 'homogeneous.' The appearanceof 'homogeneous' in some doxographersis
thus easily explicable, especially in view of Parmenides'use of i"Lotov.
51Diels (above, n. 13) 111 and n. 3, 112 and n. 2, 113; cf. Burnet (above, n. 10) 125;
McDiarmid(above, n. 2) 117; Steinmetz (above, n. 13) 54.
52Diels (above, n. 13) 110 n. 1, quoting with approvalSusemihl's (wrong, see above,
n. 13) exegesis of Metaph. 986b22, does not explain why Theophrastusallegedly goes
against his master's opinion here. The fact that Aristotle unambiguously testifies that
Xenophanes did not provide God with spatial characteristicsdoes not prevent many
Xenophanean scholars from asserting the sphericity of God, a temptation their ancient
colleagues also could not resist, see, e.g., Reinhardt(above, n. 24) 115-116; DeichgrAiber
(above, n. 6) 27 and n. 45; Gigon (above, n. 24) 183; B. Snell, The Discovery of the Mind,
trans. T. G. Rosenmeyer (New York 1982) 142; Kahn (above, n. 28) 80; Guthrie(above,
n. 8) 1.376-379; Cleve (above, n. 21) 10-11, 14; Barnes (above, n. 17) 98-99; Darcus
(above, n. 22) esp. 30-31.
54Cf. Jaeger (above, n. 8) 43 n. 23; Lumpe (above, n. 8) 29; cf. also Untersteiner's
arguments(above, n. 38) lxx-lxxvi.
55 As Stokes (above, n. 8) 75, puts it, "It would not have been difficult for a historianto
deduce the sphericity of the god from his being the same everywhere,and his being the
same everywherefrom his ability to see, hear,and perceive as a whole."
ascribed to Xenophanes. On the other hand, Cicero's (in Nat. D.) and
Nicolaus' (as reported by Simplicius) attributionof infinity to God
seems evidence of the existence of, in a sense, the contrary doxo-
graphic tendency, namely, the assimilationof God to Melissus' Being.
The third group is represented by Simplicius alone who ascribes to
Xenophanes the surprisingidea that God is neither finite nor infinite
and neither moved nor unmoved. As distinct from the two previously
described deviations from Theophrastus' account, that of Simplicius
has no rationalexplanationand is, in all probability,the result of some
doxographic corruptionof the original text. We must therefore try to
determinewhat exactly in Theophrastus'account could have given rise
to such a misrepresentation.
Let us repeat: Xenophanesdid not provide God with spatial charac-
teristics, nor did Theophrastusever attempt to do so. This, however,
does not necessarily mean that Theophrastuspassed the issue over in
silence. On the contrary, there is every reason to believe that Theo-
phrastussomehow had to refer to the question, for, apartfrom its gen-
eral interest, the spatial characteristicsof the One was precisely the
controversialissue among the Eleatics, and it would hardly be possible
to speak of the "firstof these partisansof the One" without mentioning
his position concerning this problem. It may be added that in his dis-
cussion of the "partisansof the One" Aristotle took the spatial charac-
teristics of the One as one of the two criteriaof whether the One was
conceived as formal or materialunity; true, Theophrastusseems not to
follow these distinctions, preferringhis master's more usual and gen-
eralized view of the Eleatics, but it seems improbablethat he merely
ignored a point to which Aristotle drew attention. Now to state Xeno-
phanes' position in the Eleatic controversyregardingthe spatialcharac-
teristicsof the One is precisely to say thathe had none, that he said nei-
ther that God is finite nor that he is infinite. We may assume thus that
it was some such Theophrasteanstatementthat was misinterpretedas
the "neitherfinite nor infinite"which we find in Simplicius.56Advanc-
ing this explanationof Simplicius' "neitherfinite nor infinite,"we must
apply the same kind of explanation to his "neither moved nor
unmoved"as well.57Let us consider whether some such explanationis
56 Cf. Jaeger(above, n. 8) 53 n. 64; McDiarmid(above, n. 2) 117-118; Guthrie(above,
n. 8) 1.369; cf. also Stokes (above, n. 8) 72 n. 15.
57To say, as Guthrie (above, n. 8) 1.369, does, that "Aristotle's negative verdict that
Xenophanes did not distinguish between material and non-material,nor (as is implied)
between finite and infinite, is absurdlytwisted by the later writers into a positive state-
ment that the divine unity of Xenophaneswas both moved and unmoved, both finite and
infinite" is hardly to explain the emergence of the "neithermoved nor unmoved." It is
clear what was twisted into "neitherfinite nor infinite,"but what was twisted into "neither
moved nor unmoved"?
58 Steinmetz (above, n. 13) 53, is correctin saying that Theophrastusdid not apply the
notions "finite"and "infinite"to God, but is mistakenin adding (because of assuming that
the MXG closely reflects Theophrastus' account) that he did not apply the notions
"moved"and "unmoved"either.
59Cf. Stokes (above, n. 8) 72.
60My argumentproceeds from the assumptionthat Simplicius' reportis not a mechani-
cal compilation, see below in the text.
Evavdtav EXEetprlaEv
aToadav. [i.e., both adheringto Xenophanesand
diverging from him].
di8tov giv yTp O xR&v
Kci d~ivrltov KcayYap ; da6t6v oxttr6tn&v
anorcpaiveTat caxt tliv t(ov ov KcaiyVEatv
Rpaywtr &rnopawivatat
&?'ijOetavelvat yXpar6%[B &ano8t6vat netp&XatTcxiv 6vtxov,oij
8.4]"
6ooio; repiagPoTepowy
og0moV,
&U&6 gv iT
rcaT'&XijAetav
CV t6 v Kct
xyEv7jTov Kati a patpoEt8&;-j;o`aMo43civov,
i
Yti UTv Kcva'
yvEaEtv Kaj
v eu8fji
?1`MNnXtv a
0tX&av &•TxvvRoXXv E?it6
E
8ol'ovTOv dvat. yeveoiv adoIo8Ovat T-v watvo0vPov
io notuov ; ApcXdq,
x5RIp Ki%yiyv KtX.
Kattra aiatija&7
eK(kXXXcp
S ELC
eK
aXr1OEta;.ei'st
9p71o b'et rnap"T6 8v i•dppXEt, Theophr.fr. 7 (ap. Simpl.):
toUto olKcatv vT8EJO LROv Lv TOnapa Toov tv olcKOvo6iiv
6v" Toov. o•lKov"
t; ot; oIcK otxt.
To• Ot4TO0 tv ovpa v
oitv3vT%
aVyvrltov knoxdieit KcX.
of fr. 34 and 35, which, as we now know, refer to the physical province
only and which are precisely the lines most probably quoted by Theo-
phrastushimself, give us an idea as to what Theophrastus'qualification
might have looked like: "the other way, that of accounting for
coming-to-be of existing things, he dismissed, declaring such accounts
to be no more than opinions deprivedof any certainty,saying thus (fr.
34); nevertheless he proposes some such opinion which he seems to
have adjudgedlooking plausible, as he says himself (fr. 35)."72
We can see now why Aristotle was reluctantto take Xenophanes'
cosmology as evidence of the formal characterof his One: it seems
that he was not certain of the precise purportof Xenophanes' scepti-
cism, whether it was restricted to explanations of the structureof the
sensible manifold or extended to its very existence. The status of
cosmology not being altogetherclear to him, Aristotle preferrednot to
base on it his conclusions regarding the kind of unity postulated by
Xenophanes; he thus neither referred to Xenophanes' cosmological
doctrine as evidence of the "formal"character of God, nor took the
sceptical qualificationof its validity as evidence of the contraryview.
The conclusion that Xenophanes' scepticism applies to natural
explanationsonly, not extending to the "theology,"naturallyraises the
question why the doctrine of the One is immune to it. To find the
answer we should first determinethe reasons for Xenophanes' physical
scepticism, i.e., his labelling naturalexplanationsas no more than more
or less plausible opinions. The main statementof Xenophanes' scepti-
cism isfr. 34:73
Certain truth no man has seen nor will be anyone who knows
about the gods and concerningeverythingI speakof; for even if he
should happen to say what is true, he himself however does not
know [this];opinion is wroughtover all [men].74
To begin with, the two last lines of fr. 34 can hardlymean that precise
knowledge in the physical realm (for as we know now it is this realm
that constitutes the scope of the sceptical pronouncementof 34.1) is
unattainablebecause the objects of this knowledge are illusory, lacking
in reality, or the like. On the contrary,34.3 seems to imply that they
are perfectly knowable in themselves75(and are actually known by
God)76yet to the human being this kind of knowledge is nevertheless
unattainable. Why so? The answer that first suggests itself is that this
is due to the relativity,invalidity,or the like of our sense-perceptions.77
On a closer examination of the problem, however, we see we must
abandonthis approach. Quite apartfrom the question whether Xeno-
phanes indeed discredited sense-perceptions,we should ask ourselves,
is it because of the relativity, deceptiveness, or the like of our senses
that we lack certain knowledge in such mattersas to whether the rain-
bow is the goddess Iris or a cloud of a certain kind, whetheror not the
earth indefinitely stretches downwards, or whether the moon is
somehow useful to the world?78But let us consider the method to
which Xenophanesresortedin his physical theory:
... Xenophanes thinks that mingling of earth with sea takes place
and that in course of time earth is dissolved by the wet element,
claiming as proofs that shells are found in the midst of the land and
on mountains;and in the quarriesat Syracuse, he says, the impres-
sions of a fish and of seaweed have been found, on Paros the
impressions of a bay-leaf in the depth of the stone, and on Malta
flattened shapes of all sea-creatures. These, he says, were formed
when everything, long ago, was covered in mud, and the impres-
sion dried out in the mud. All men are destroyed when the earthis
carried down to the sea and turns to mud, then a new generation
begins.. .79
Wissen ... werde es fiir den Menschennicht geben." Yet it is artificialto limit the expli-
cative force of the yd'pin fr. 34.3, and there is no justificationfor importingthe grounds
for the sceptical pronouncementof 34.1-2 from elsewhere.
82Cf. Plato, Meno 80D; Sext. Emp. Math. 7.46-52. Sextus' interpretationis therefore
generallycorrect,cf. U. von Wilamowitz,"Lesefriichte,"Hermes 61 (1926) 280; Kranzin
Diels-Kranz (above, n. 9) ad loc. pace Fr'inkel(above, n. 73) 124-125, followed by von
Fritz (above, n. 14) 1557-1558; Guthrie(above, n. 8) 1.395 n. 5; J. Lesher, "Xenophanes'
Scepticism," Phronesis 23 (1978) 2, and some others. Von Fritz (ibid.) objects that
Xenophanescould not say that he happenedto touch the truthin his criticism of anthro-
pomorphismbut did not know this himself; this is quite correct,but the objection is mis-
directed:Xenophanes'scepticism does not apply to the "theological"domain.
83AMt.2.20, 3; Ps.-Plut. Strom.4 and Hippol. Haer. 1.14.3; Hippol. Haer. 1.14.6; Hip-
pol. Haer. 1.14.4 (= Diels-Kranz [above, n. 9] 21 A 40, 32, 33). Nobody can know such
matters but God whose knowledge is free from the spatial and temporal limitations to
which humancondition is subject. It is here, if anywhere,that the traditionalopposition
between divine omniscience and human ignorance may be supposed to exercise an
influenceon Xenophanes. Deichgraiber,however, without any justification,specifies this
opposition as that between the Muse and the poet, for which he is correctly rebukedby
J. Mansfeld, Die Offenbarungdes Parmenides und die menschliche Welt (Assen 1964) 8
n. 1; Deichgr~iber'sapproachhas gained favor among Xenophanean scholars some of
whom go as far as to assume that this is all that Xenophanes wanted to stress (see esp.,
Steinmetz [above, n. 13] 40; Snell [above, n. 52] 139-141).
84This is, in fact, the well known demandby the Ionian ioroptrl (cf. Frfinkel[above,
n. 73] 131; Deichgraber [above, n. 6] 24, cf. 20; see also Heitsch [above, n. 73] esp.
194-205) of awto~ia as the prerequisite of reliable knowledge which Xenophanes
applied universally, i.e., also to the province of cosmological speculation where it is
impracticable. Frtinkel (ibid., cf. Jaeger [above, n. 8] 43 n. 2; Barnes [above, n. 17)
139-140) comparesthe HippocratictreatiseOn AncientMedicine, 1:
If a man were to learn and declare the state of these [things in the sky or below the
earth], neitherto the speakerhimself nor to his audiencewould be clear whetherthe
statementswere true or not. For there is no test the applicationof which would give
certainty(o16yap oti, rpbqOTt Xpil &AvEviyKavTaE•i&vaitT •ocpq).
[Hippocrates,W. H. S. Jones, trans.(London-NewYork 1923) 1.15.]
Frankel (and Jaeger), misinterpretingXenophanes' position, fails to draw the true paral-
lels between it and the position of the Hippocraticwriter. Barnes (ibid.) points out the
continuity between Xenophanes' approachand that of the authorof the treatise. In fact
the quoted passage merely repeats what Xenophanes says in fr. 34 and about the same
things-it is precisely the knowledge of "heavenly and undergroundthings," the subject
of physical speculation, that is lacking certainty because it cannot be verified. To the
uncertaintyof the knowledge in the cosmological province the Hippocraticwriteropposes
medicine, where the empirical verification of assumptions is fairly possible and hence
precise knowledge is attainable. Barnes (ibid.), arguing from the treatiseto Xenophanes,
concludes that he "advocates a limited, not a general scepticism: it is theology and
naturalscience, not knowledge in general, that must elude our human grasp"(cf. Lumpe
[above, n. 8] 33-34). Barnes is correct,except for the "theology"which, as we shall soon
see, is quite a differentmatter.
It may be noted in this connection that the idea of the advance of mankind, which
seems to be the purportof fr. 18, is thereforesituated on a different plane, pace Heitsch
(above, n. 73) esp. 227. (Apropos: in 18.2 cannot mean more certain
ttetvov
knowledge, as notably Snell [above, n. 52] 139-140, claims, but betterconditions of life.)
If Xenophaneshere anticipateslatertheories,these are the Sophistic doctrinesof material,
social, and cultural advance rather than the idea of infinite scientific progress, as
K. Popper,"Back to the Presocratics,"in Studies in Presocratic Philosophy, D. J. Furley
and R. E. Allen, eds. (London 1970) 1.152, would have us believe. This advance in the
search for betterconditions of life involves, of course, the progress of knowledge, but of
practical knowledge whose attainabilityXenophanesnever denied. When we realize this,
the position of the Hippocraticauthorproves to be entirely identical with that of Xeno-
phanes.
the most certain truth? This seems highly implausible, if not to say
altogether paradoxical. At any rate, to saddle a thinker with incon-
sistencies and contradictions is not the best exegetical method, and
before resorting to it, it is always advisable to investigate other possi-
bilities. We should therefore explore the alternative, namely, that
Xenophanes drew an epistemic distinction between cosmological and
"theological"speculation,consideringthe latteras certainin itself. The
assumptionamountsto saying that in his monistic doctrineXenophanes
widely used apodeictic inference and, what is not less important,was
aware of its character. Theoretically speaking, this is not historically
impossible, for the distinction between apodeictic and non-apodeictic
knowledge is found in Parmenides.85
There is nothing inherently improbable in assuming Xenophanes'
use of logical proofs which, it seems, were alreadyemployed by Anax-
imander,86whose associate Xenophanes is reportedto have been. The
real question then is not whether Xenophanes could have used logical
argumentsbut ratherwhat extent and quality of argumentationcan be
admitted without transcendingthe limits of historical plausibility. It
may be stated at the outset that such an "upper limit" hardly exists:
Parmenides with his purely deductive doctrine of Being was, even if
much younger, a contemporaryof Xenophanes,87and nobody, I ima-
gine, would contend that had Parmenides been born some thirty or
forty years earlier, his doctrine could not have taken the inferential
form. Xenophanes thus could have resorted to logical proofs, and the
possibilities range between sporadic and rudimentaryuse and a con-
tinuous discourse like Parmenides'. The first question, therefore, is
what evidence we have to prove that Xenophanesresortedto argumen-
tation and what kind of argument,if any, did he use.
The allegedly Xenophaneanargumentationis amply presentedin the
relevant section of the pseudo-Aristotelian treatise De Melisso
tion and that of the earth's magnitude, leaves no doubt that there is
something wrong with our passage, for on no account can this be its
proper place. Moreover, not only does the passage prove to be mis-
placed, its content also betrays confusion. Indeed, &ico~etv•E icai
6pav KaO6ko ai ai•l icarX&gepo;, predicated here of the gods, is
associated in other sources with One God (see Table 1, line 12), and
this is undoubtedlycorrect, as is shown by the singularinfr. 24, olo;
6p0, oi~Xo8;&8voEt, 6~ ' &icoEt, to which this descriptioncan
olX)o;
be traced back.92But perhaps Xenophanes admitted the existence of
other, lesser gods who, he maintained,are also thoroughlyperceiving?
This suggestion does not save the situation: in Theophrastusthe phrase
was related to One God; whatever Xenophanes might have said about
the supposed "lesser gods," Theophrastuswas speaking of One God.
Two possibilities thereforeexist: eitherPs.-Plutarchor his source read-
dressed Theophrastus'reportabout God's perceiving as a whole to the
gods or he was mistaken about the true subject of Theophrastus'predi-
cation. The latter solution is clearly preferable:mistaking God for the
gods, in itself quite a possible doxographicerror, easily explains both
the surprisinglocation of the passage and the fact that in Ps.-Plutarch's
account of Xenophanes' monistic doctrinenot a word is said aboutGod
and his identity with "the whole," which in Theophrastuswas conse-
quent upon the statementof the Xenophaneanconcept of the "eternally
selfsame whole"; it is thus quite probablethat this Theophrasteanpas-
sage, not found in Ps.-Plutarch,was, as a result of doxographicconfu-
0tEv and then, being detached from the account
sion, altered into nrEpi
of the One, naturally relocated into a more appropriatecontext, the
cosmological part of Xenophanes' teaching. Now let us perform an
experiment. We shall take the nEpi O'Eov reportas the direct continua-
tion of the account of the "eternallyselfsame whole" and present the
entire passage as a column in synoptic table, while two other columns
will presentthe texts of the MXGand Simplicius (see below).
The parallels between the MXG and Simplicius, on the one hand,
and Ps.-Plutarch,on the other, are undeniable.93The argumentwhich
comes first in the Stromateis, though in itself differing from the first
92Cf. von Fritz (above, n. 14), 1555.
93This shows beyond any doubt that the nEpi Oestvreport in the Stromateis did not
come from the antianthropomorphicpolemics of the Silloi, as Reinhardt(above, n. 24)
94-95, suggests.
94The whole report tEpi ~iOov being the misinterpretedaccount of One God, this argu-
ment must originally have been the proof of God's oneness. Cf. von Fritz (above, n. 14)
1554; Barnes (above, n. 17) 91-92.
95See R. Kiihner and B. Gerth, Ausfiihrliche Grammatikder griechischen Sprache4,
Satzlehre (Leverkusen 1955) 1.581-588; E. Schwyzer, Griechische Grammatik,A. De-
brunnered. (Munich 1950), 2.20-24.
98Rh. 1399b5; 1400b5. See also Deichgriber (above, n. 6) 28-29; 0. Dreyer, Unter-
suchungen zum Begriff des Gottgeziemendenin der Antike (Hildesheim 1970) 21 n. 59;
Babut (above, n. 8) 431-434; Barnes (above, n. 17) 85-86. Babut is right as opposed to
Jaeger (above, n. 8) 49-51, who regards the prepon-category in Xenophanes as the
expression of a religious feeling; it also seems wrong to interpretthis category as purely
ethical, as in Gigon (above, n. 24) 191. For the meaning and development of the
prepon-category see M. Pohlenz, "TO HPEHON. Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte der
griechischen Geistes," in his Kleine Schriften (Hildesheim 1965) 1.100-139. Reiche
(above, n. 77) 93-95, objects that the understandingof the prepon-category in Xeno-
phanes as a purely aprioristic norm specifying the logically necessary connection of
God's essence with certain predicates, as Deichgriiber (above, n. 6) 29, interprets it,
causes the break between the "theology" and the cosmology in Xenophanes; yet this is
precisely what is alreadyproducedby Xenophanes' exclusion of the "theology"from the
scope of the sceptical attitude.
tion of the ideas necessarily implied in the notion of the divine, in the
presentcase, freedom from deficiency.
Having examined and assessed severally the argumentsretrievable
from the Stromateiswe should now appraisethe reliabilityof this infor-
mation in general. Our synopsis demonstratesthat all three accounts of
Xenophanes' arguments, those of the MXG, Simplicius, and Ps.-
Plutarch,can be traced back to one common source, and since the ulti-
mate source of the Stromateis is Theophrastus,he must be also the
source of the two other accounts. Theophrastus,it would then appear,
reported certain Xenophanean arguments, and this report has come
down to us in three versions. Two of them, those of the MXG and Sim-
plicius, preserved very little from their ultimate source while adding
much that is non-authentic;in consequence, these reports provide no
evidence for Theophrastus'account of Xenophanes' argumentsand a
fortiori of these argumentsthemselves." But have we reason to assume
that the informationconcerningXenophanes' argumentswhich we find
in the Stromateisfaithfully representsTheophrastus'account?
As we have seen, the Stromateis, certainly in their section on Par-
menides and in all probabilityalso in that on Xenophanes' God, closely
follow i~ of Theophrastus'Physical Opinions, which lends great relia-
bility to Ps.-Plutarch'saccount in general and the informationconcern-
ing the Xenophanean argumentationin particular. It is importantin
this connection that Ps.-Plutarchis the only doxographic writer (for
Simplicius, strictly speaking, is not such) who reportsthe Parmenidean
argumentand moreover, in its Theophrasteansetting;100 the authorof
the intermediarysource to whom the Stromateisgo back seems to have
had a taste for such things.
Now the orderin which the Xenophaneanargumentsare reportedin
the Stromateis (after restoring the original place and purport of the
99Reinhardt(above, n. 24) 91-93, was the first to assess the MXG's stemming from
Theophrastus'account (see also O. Regenbogen, "Theophrastusvon Eresos,"RE, Suppl.
7 [1940] 1544-1545), but was wrong in taking this as sufficient basis for using the MXG
as historicalevidence on Xenophanes,a mistake in which he is followed by Gigon, Stein-
metz, von Fritz, and Barnes. Those guided by the method recommendedby von Fritz
(above, n. 14) 1459, namely, to distinguish between the form and content of the MXG,
inevitably find themselves producing,as Barnesconfesses, accounts"of a somewhat arbi-
traryair."
'10 Two settings, Theophrastus'and Eudemus', are reportedby Simplicius, Phys. 115.
11 (Dieis-Kranz[above, n. 9] 28 A 28).
Table 4
Theophrastus Ps.-Plutarch Simplicius MXG
1 1. ungenerated: 1. ungenerated:
argument argument
la 2. ungenerated: 1. ungenerated:
argument(non- argument(non-
Theophrastean) Theophrastean)
2 2. one: argument 2. one: argument 1. one: argument 2. one: argument
3 3. it is not said
whether finite or
infinite
3a 3. homogeneous:
argument
3b 4. spherical,
argument
3c 3. neither finite 5. neither finite
nor infinite: nor infinite:
argument argument
4 4. it is not said
whethermoved
or unmoved
4a 4. neither moved 6. neither moved
nor unmoved: nor unmoved:
argument argument
5 5. actually
unmoved
6 6. thoroughly 3. thoroughly
perceiving: perceiving:
argument argument
7 7. governing all 5. governing all
things by his things by his
mind mind
that is, a short summaryof the "On the Principles,"the first book of
Theophrastus' Physical Opinions. Formally, Simplicius' account of
Xenophanes does not constitute an exception; here too he refers his
informationto Theophrastus,paraphrasingor even quoting his words
verbatim.103 It appears,however, thata considerablepartof the account
has nothing to do with Theophrastusand closely resembles the picture
presented in the MXG. This has made critics believe that in reporting
about Xenophanes Simplicius conflates Theophrastus' account with
that of the MXG,104 an assumption which leads to insuperable
difficulties.105Fortunately,it is quite unnecessary to assume that Sim-
plicius resorted to the MXG to explain the emergence in his reportof
the false propositions (3c) and (4a): these did not come into Theo-
phrastus' account from elsewhere but originated within it, being a
103See Diels (above, n. 13) 111-113, 480-481; cf. McDiarmid(above, n. 2) 116.
104This is the view of Diels (above, n. 13) 109-112, which has become standardin
Xenophaneanscholarship.
105It is quite inconceivable how Simplicius could have combined two such incompati-
ble reports(explanationslike McDiarmid's [above, n. 2] 118, are hardlyrealistic). Diels
himself (above, n. 13) 112, is at a loss to explain this-"nolo argutariqua ratione haec
cum priore sententia secundum metaphysica confirmataconciliaverit, utrum ambiguita-
tem illam allatis Xenophanisversibus demonstraveritan alia in capite de principioalia in
c. de deo attulerit";he then suggests (ibid.) that Simplicius had no access to Theo-
phrastus'work but drew his informationfrom Alexander(cf. Uberweg-Praechter[above,
n. 8] 74; Burnet [above, n. 10] 126; McDiarmid[above, n. 2] 116). This suggestion how-
ever is unwarranted-see Reinhardt(above, n. 24) 92 n. 1; Regenbogen (above, n. 99)
1536; Kahn (above, n. 28) 14 n. 1; but if abandoned,the hypothesis of the conflation
becomes altogether impracticable. Further,Simplicius nowhere indicates that he uses
some other account beside Theophrastus;we therefore have to allow that he takes the
MXG to be also by Theophrastus. But this suggestion makes Simplicius hold that Theo-
phrastusproducedtwo incompatible accounts of Xenophanes. Could he have believed
this? Could he, at the very least, not even have mentioned this extraordinaryfact?
Finally, we are told (Kahn,loc. cit) that Simplicius' presumablereliance on the MXGor a
similar source proves that "he was perfectly capable of ignoring the Phys. Opin." Let
alone that the isolated and doubtful example of such a practice on Simplicius' part can
prove hardlyanything,what Simplicius is admittedto be doing on this explanationcannot
properlybe called "ignoringthe Phys. Opin.";the only appropriatename is deliberatefor-
gery: Simplicius would then not merely have preferredanothersource to Theophrastus,
he would have combined Theophrastus'account with what he knew was not by Theo-
phrastusand moreover was entirely incompatiblewith him and proceededto ascribe this
amalgamto Theophrastus. Can one credit Simplicius with such conscious (and purpose-
less) falsification? (For the quality of Simplicius' scholarship see Diels [above, n. 13]
112).
106 That the version of Theophrastus'work Simplicius used was mutilatedin more than
one respect seems to me obvious. First of all, this was very probablynot the whole of
Theophrastus'work but only the first book, "On the Principles": Simplicius' commen-
tary offers no evidence that he possessed something more. Further,it has been observed
that his reliance on Theophrastusis sometimes mediated by Alexander. This suggests
that he had no access to these pieces of the Theophrasteaninformation,i.e., they were
missing in his version of the "On the Principles." Diels (above, n. 13) 113, lists three
cases where Simplicius, as he maintains, clearly resorts to Alexander's reproductionof
Theophrastus: Phys. 38.20 (= Theophr. fr. 6), 115.11 (=fr. 7), and 700.18 (=fr. 15).
As to fr. 15, the mere mention of Alexander's name after Theophrastus'is not sufficient
testimony to reliance on Alexander;butfr. 6 and 7 are undeniable. In both cases the sub-
ject is Parmenides'doctrine,and Simplicius' knowledge of Theophrastus'account of Par-
menides seems not to go beyond this information. The conclusion that the section on
Parmenideswas missing in Simplicius' manuscriptof the "Onthe Principles"seems una-
voidable. Now in Theophrastus,the accountof Parmenidesfollowed that of Xenophanes
which, in turn,was precededby the account of the Milesians; in Simplicius, the confused
account of Xenophanesappearsat the very beginning, before the Milesians. It would fol-
low that not only did Simplicius possess only one detachedbook of Theophrastus'work,
but that the text of this book was damagedin the partdealing with Xenophanes and Par-
menides: the account of Parmenides dropped out entirely, while the report on Xeno-
phanes, fundamentallygarbled,was relocatedat the beginning of the book.
107Cf. von Fritz
(above, n. 14) 1552.
doretus, Diogenes, Sextus, and Ps.-Galen, which stem from the "Par-
menidized" version of the Abridged Summary, only Hippolytus des-
cends directly from it, for, while droppingthe arguments,as in all other
sources of this group, he reportsall the theses presumablycontainedin
it and in the same order (only (5) is relocated, being given earlier, see
Table 1). The rest of the accounts stemming from the "Parmenidized"
version report only some of the theses, in various combinations and
orders;what, however, is more significantis that all of them lack thesis
(3a). Such consistency can hardlybe incidental;ratherit suggests their
derivation from a common source differing from the "Parmenidized"
version in that it lacks (3a). In determining the mutual relationship
between these two sources we should take into account that the doxo-
graphic idea that Xenophanes conceived of God as finite and spherical
had to be, and actually was, as Alexander's reportshows, the result of
inference by the analogy with Parmenides from God's homogeneity
which, in turn,was easily suggested by God's perceiving as a whole.Ito
It is thereforenot very plausible that homogeneity and finitudeentered
the transmission separately, and at any rate homogeneity must have
come before finitude, not vice versa. It follows that the account in
which finitude and/or sphericity is reportedwhile the homogeneity is
lacking should be assumed to derive from a text in which both attri-
butes are present, being, in all probability, its abridged form. We
should therefore postulate the existence of an abridged form of the
"Parmenidized"version as a common source to which the accounts of
Cicero (Acad.), Theodoretus,Diogenes, Sextus, and Ps.-Galen can be
traced.
Beside the "Parmenidized"version, yet another expansion of the
Abridged Summary seems to have existed where Xenophanes' God
was described as infinitepresumablyby analogy with Melissus' Being.
The existence of this version, termed "Melissized" (see Table 3), is
suggested by the coincidence of the reportsof Cicero (in Nat. D.) and
Nicolaus Damascenus (ap. Simpl.). Finally, Ps.-Plutarch's account
most probablyis in direct descent from the Abridged Summary,being
mediatedneitherby the "Parmenidized"nor "Melissized"versions.
It remainsto consider the origins of the Xenophaneansection of the
MXG. This is obviously the productof the combinationof two sources,
the "Parmenidized" version of the Abridged Summary and the
110 Cf. Stokes (above, n. 8) 75.
THE CORRUPTEDVERSIONOF T
THE 'ON THE PRINCIPLES': O
(1) withoutits argument;(2); (3) and (1
(4) corrupted;(5) and (6) missed; (7)
THE ABRIDG
THE 'PARME
VERSION:
(1),(2); (3a) dr
(3b),(5),(6)
[35] 0o ya'pa&veU
Toi 6vTo;,9v fr. 24:
oaytv, voe' , o~o; &
oieo 6p , oi~Xo&5
n•~paqctoievov
b voEIv...
[36]eFiprijaet; I' a&couet.
[42] au6,rxp~ineinieipa;q n~iatov,
C0aTi
teTeXehRTLevov
[43] ni&vroOev, etGmrickou aq(paiprI
EvalyKtov icyK(p,
[44]geCaa60evivaoinag idv'rn'T6 "
ytp orTe Rt Ciei ov
[45] oTrEe It 1pai6repoviteXvat
1i
pe6v a'tt'tf7
[46] o rzeyazpoKEcov'tf7.gaoUt,x6 cev
aotaIoi1viiceio0at
[47] ei; 6Og6v,oj ' byvagrtyviuno;
ei'rcev d6vro;
[48] 'i &Xhovti 8' 8 faooov, nEi%
Rnavanttv~atoukov
[49]of yapiauvroOev•Tov, v
RneipautKicpet. 6.ilo;
113Cf. fr. 23.2: "[God]is not like mortalseither in body or in thought." Barnes(above,
n. 17) 94 and n. 20, rightly equates God's being free from any want with his perfection,
adducing as the parallels Eur. HF 1345 (cf. Guthrie [above, n. 8] 1.373), Antiphon'sfr.
10, Xen. Mem. 1.6.10, and Diogenes the Cynic ap. Diog. 6.105.
114Cf. Reinhardt(above, n. 24) 112-114; Stokes (above, n. 8) 83 n. 53.
115Cf. Diels (above, n. 13) 111 n. 2: "Xenophanisrationemrepresentarilicet ex Par-
menid. v. 66 St." (Diels quotesfr. 8.5-8 and 12-13).
major inclusive piece. At the same time,fr. 34 presupposesas its context a more or less
extensive passage concerned with philosophic topics (cf. Deichgraiber[above, n. 6] 19;
Gigon, Untersuchungenzu Heraklit [Leipzig 1935] 151; Untersteiner [above, n. 38]
c-cxiv; Barnes [above, n. 17] 83-84), specifically, as we have seen, with naturalexplana-
tions. There are therefore two possibilities: either the monistic deductions and the
naturalexplanationsconstituted two parts of a unified philosophic composition, or they
were two separatepoems, on God and on the world (whetheror not combined with other
topics such as criticism of popularbeliefs, etc.). Now there are three reasons for prefer-
ring the former option. First, the ancients knew only one Xenophanean philosophic
piece, which is thrice referredto in our sources as lepi P•0ioe;,-by the grammarians
Crates of Mallos and Pollux (Diels-Kranz [above, n. 9] 21 B 30, 39) and presumablyby
AMtius(Diels-Kranz [above, n. 9] A 36, the second text, wrongly assessed by Diels as
"aus d. homerischenAllegorien,"-see J. Mansfeld, "Aristotleand Others on Thales, or
The Beginning of NaturalPhilosophy,"Mnemosyne38 [1985] 127 n. 64); cf. also Diog.
8.56 (= Diels-Kranz [above, n. 9] 21 A 5). The title by no means indicates that the con-
tent of the piece was restrictedto cosmological speculationalone; HEptipoEoS is usual
in ancient references to the early philosophic compositions, and even the Parmenidean
poem was referredto as HEpi ple o; (Suda s.v.; Diog. 8.55; Simpl. De Caelo 556, 25 =
Diels-Kranz [above, n. 9] 28 A 2, 9, 14). Secondly, the combinationof the monistic and
cosmological doctrinesas two formallydistinct partsof the same poem is attestedfor Par-
menides, which, in view of the overt influence, may be taken as suggesting the unified
composition in Xenophanes as well. Thirdly, in the absence of contraryevidence, we
should admit the unified poem in orderto meet the requirementof the most economical
solution. We may thus assume that Xenophaneswrote a poem known in antiquityunder
the conventional title Hepi <piamo;, which formally fell into two parts, on God and on
"the gods and all other such things," that is, cosmology (cf. above, n. 101). It is quite a
different question whether the piece was a didactic epic or a Sillos, i.e., whether it also
included criticism and polemics, and whether it was in hexametersor in mixed meters,
questions which, it seems, can hardlybe solved.
118See Diog. 9.18 (= Diels-Kranz [above, n. 9] 21 A 1): A&k& icKaacrgT6 et
ppa•4
119Cf. above, n. 96; see also Reinhardt(above, n. 24) 122-125.
sibly and what is not true," (c) "he speaks implausibly but what is
true." Of these only (c) is a true witticism capable of sticking in the
memory and worth recalling and at the same time providing Aristotle's
"plausibly but what is not true" with the best contrast.120The next
question is, what was Epicharmus' point of reference? As we have
seen, Xenophanes declared that his cosmology was not true but only
plausible, using, it must be noted, a similar expression,,otico6Ta toi
T6CIotat(fr. 35). Now if it was the Xenophaneancosmology that was
Epicharmus' intended target, i.e., if he simply derided Xenophanes'
sceptical qualification of natural accounts, the joke appears to be an
idle mockery which could hardly appeal to Aristotle and be described
by him as what "Epicharmusput against (or 'in regardto'-eiq) Xeno-
phanes." It seems therefore much more probable that the target was
Xenophanes' "theology." Now it is perfectly understandablethat one
can call the concept of a thoroughlyperceiving and totally immovable
cosmic god implausible, but it is not immediately obvious why one
should at the same time assent, though ironically, to the truth of this
idea. This, however, is easily explained if we bear in mind that Xeno-
phanes' implausible doctrine was supportedby "irrefutable"proofs. It
seems, therefore, that Epicharmus ironically alludes to Xenophanes'
own qualification of his natural explanations: they are, as he himself
confesses, plausible yet hardly true; his account of the divine is, of
course, true, yet, regrettably,implausible. The situation, amply illus-
trated in Plato, is quite puzzling for anyone inexperienced in logical
discourse as all Xenophanes' hearerscertainly were: the starting-point
seems undeniably true but the conclusions are surprising and hardly
acceptable. It was precisely this paradox, I believe, that made Epi-
charmus call Xenophanes' "theology" "implausible truth." Such was
its effect on contemporaryhearers and such witticisms were current
among them.121
120 See Th. Gomperz in Diels-Kranz (above, n. 9) ad loc.; Ross' note ad loc. in the
Oxfordtranslation,and Ross (above, n. 2) 1. 276, ad 1010a6.
121We can now appraise the extent of
Jaeger's misinterpretationof Xenophanes'
thought when he writes: "It is nothing that rests on logical proof, nor is it really philo-
sophical at all, but springs from an immediate sense of awe at the sublime of the Divine"
([above, n. 8] 49). Von Fritz (above, n. 14) 1547, correctly warnsthat "das logische Ele-
ment in X.s theologischem Denken ... sollte ... nicht Uibersehenwerden"(cf. Reinhardt
[above, n. 24] 100; Deichgriiber[above, n. 6] 28-30; Barnes [above, n. 17] 94). Yet the
very controversy as to whether Xenophanes was a religious mystic, as Nietzche first
claimed (Die Philosophie im tragischenZeitalterder Griechen in Werke,ed. K. Schlechta
Nevertheless Lumpe is much closer to the truth than those critics who, as Frinkel and
Reiche, try to reduce Xenophanes' approachto a "rigorousempiricism"(Frinkel [above,
n. 73] 130).
126Pace Barnes (above, n. 17) 137, who ranges Ps.-Plutarch'sreportwith Sotion's (cf.
also Lumpe [above, n. 8] 32),-compare Sotion's wording (ap. Diog. 9.20 = Diels-Kranz
[above, n. 9] 21 A 1, above n. 70) echoed in Hippol. Haer. 1.14.1 (= Diels-Kranz [above,
n. 9] 21 A 33).
parallel with Hippolytus finally proves this. Aristocles, that is, here
draws on the Theophrasteandoxographyof Xenophanes (in all proba-
bility, on the "Parmenidized"version, as the parallel with Hippolytus
suggests-see Table 5) applying what is said with reference to Xeno-
phanes to a whole group of thinkers.
We can thus conclude that Theophrastusdid define Xenophanes'
epistemological approach and that his definition was exactly as we
would expect it to be-"he throws out aistheseis, while trusting logos
alone." The definition is loose and misleading, for it implies that, in
contrast to the "theology," the "physics" is "accordingto aistheseis";
yet the actual contrast is not that between two kinds of cognition,
purely intellectual and that based on the senses but that between two
kinds of inferences, a priori demonstrationlabelled certain knowledge
and a posteriori inferences which, when unverifiable, are but fallible
guesses. 129
Hereour reconstruction
of Theophrastus'
accountcan be regarded
as completed: we have determinedhis generalapproachto Xeno-
129 We can now see whether, as is usually believed, Xenophanes held that the sense-
perceptionsare unreliable. Comparingthe reportin the Stromateiswith thatof Aristocles
we observe that Ps.-Plutarchnot only completely misrepresentsthe second partof Theo-
phrastus' statement,but also glosses its first part as "senses lie," and thereforewe must
not take these words as suggesting that TheophrastusreportedXenophanes'distrustof the
reliability of sense-perceptions. Theophrastus'"throwingout aistheseis, while trusting
logos alone" must also be Aetius' reason for listing Xenophanes together with ten other
philosophers under the title "the senses lie"; and indeed, the names listed (AMt.4.9.1 =
Diels [above, n. 13] 396; cf. Diels-Kranz[above, n. 9] 21 A 49) suggest this interpretation
ratherthan the unreliabilityof sense-perceptions. The doxographicmaterialat our dispo-
sal thus provides no evidence that Theophrastusever said that Xenophanes claimed the
unreliability of our sense-perceptions, and the fact that the Sceptics did not explicitly
ascribe this view to Xenophanes furtherproves our conclusions. We are left with Xeno-
phanes' fr. 38 which is usually interpretedas stressing the relativity of our perceptions
and our empiricaljudgments (e.g., Frinkel [above, n. 19] 430; G. Rudberg,"Xenophanes,
Satirikerund Polemiker,"SO 26 [1948] 133; Guthrie [above, n. 8] 1.401). This is the
possible purportof the lines, but in the absence of the broader context it is not clear
whetherthis was the intendedone. At any rate, it is evident that the idea of the unreliabil-
ity of the senses, if articulatedby Xenophanes at all, was casual and peripheric in his
thought.
phanes' twofold teaching and dwelt on the main points of his reporton
Xenophanes' monistic doctrine; the examination of Xenophanes'
cosmological conception, however interesting and desirable, is a
separatetask which should be left for anotheropportunity. After such
a lengthy discussion one should perhapsbriefly recapitulatethe results
arrivedat, and the best way to do this seems to be to presentthe Theo-
phrasteanaccount in the form of the orderedseries of statementsrecon-
structedabove. In this list the sources from which a given statementis
excerpted or on the basis of which it is formulatedare referredto by
the name of the authorand the page and line(s) of the Diels-Kranzedi-
tion; statements and parts of statements which are purely conjectural
are italicized.