Autism in Schizophrenia Revisited
Autism in Schizophrenia Revisited
Autism in Schizophrenia Revisited
The concept of autism is reviewed in its historical evolution. It is suggested that the Bleulerian
insistence on the withdrawal component in autism contributed to the decline of its use in adult
psychiatry. Phenomenology offers another approach to grasping the nature of autism as a
relational (subject-outer world) phenomenon. European phenomenological psychiatry in the
field of schizophrenia is introduced and its attempts to reveal the essence of autism are
presented. Autism is here considered as a “loss of vital contact with reality” (Minkowski),
“inconsistency of natural experience” (Binswanger), or “the global crisis of common sense”
(Blankenburg). It is proposed that autism represents dysfunctional perceptual/expressive
attunement to the outer world. The usefulness of this concept is briefly examined in relation to
the diagnosis and etiopathogenesis of schizophrenia.
Copyright 0 1991 by W.B. Saunders Company
consider fulfilled) or occupy themselves with the trials and tribulations of their persecutory ideas;
they have cut themselves off as much as possible from any contact with the external world.
This detachment from reality with the relative and absolute predominance of the inner life. we
term autism.“’ (et. p. 63).*
*References to literature first published in German or French are quoted with the original
publication’s date, in order to facilitate historical apprehension of the concept of autism. When an
English translation is available, it is indicated in the list of references. In that case, pages in the text are
the ones of the English translation (e.f.). Quotations that have not been published in English have been
translated by the present authors.
AUTISM IN SCHIZOPHRENIA 9
Clearly, this conceptualization indicates that Bleuler did not consider autism as
specific to schizophrenia. He even used this term to denounce some forms of
traditional medical thinking,6 which provoked a turmoil in the scientific commu-
nity and, as a byproduct, made psychiatrists feel unsecure about the clinical utility
of the concept of autism. Consequently, Bleuler attempted to attenuate the
psychopathological connotation of the title of his controversial book by (unsuccess-
fully) creating the new term of “dereistic thinking.“7
Even though Bleuler was influenced by Freud and Jung, the term of “autism”
was not in use among psychoanalysts until the post-war analysts became interested
in psychoanalytic psychotherapy of schizophrenia. Basically, autism in psychoan-
alysis is used to denote either a very early, objectless developmental stage of the
infant, or as a defense position due to narcissistic failure and weak ego-
boundaries. In this latter sense, autism in schizophrenia is viewed as withdrawal,
avoidance of object relationships which prevents potential injuries to a fragile
narcissism. In clinical psychiatry, Manfred Bleuler’ considers autism in a similar
way, but in contrast to his father, he views autism as a both fundamental and
primary symptom of schizophrenia. More recently, a term of “aphanisis” was
introduced’ to denote autistic stimulus barrier protecting the individual from the
influx of aversive stimuli. Similar line of thought can be discerned in the learning
theory of schizophrenia which considers the disease as a product of a learning
process in which an autonomically hypersensitive person cumulatively diminishes
his anxiety by deviating attention to nonrelevant issues:
“The thought disorder consists of a set of conditioned avoidance responses which help the
schizophrenic to control his autonomic hyperresponsivity. The avoidant responses (associates or
thoughts) are learned on those occasions when the pre-schizophrenic escapes from some
arousal-producing stimulus by switching to a thought which interrupts this arousal stimulus.“‘0
(P. 86).
“The empiricist argument states, in essence, that the way things are is the way things are and
that human attempts to understand the way things are must take their measure from the reality
that transcends us and exists in itself independently of us. The rejoinder, emanating from the
intellectualist camp, is that all cognition of the way things are is mediated by the finite structures
of human subjectivity: we cannot measure the validity of our cognition from the way things are in
themselves, because we only have access to the way things are for us.“15(p. 87).
“One cannot . . conceive any perceived thing without someone to perceive it. But the fact
remains that the thing presents itself to the person who perceives it as a thing in itself, and thus
poses the problem of a genuine in-itself-for-u.s.“‘~ (e.r. p. 322).
tThe term “phenomenology” can be traced to Kant, who distinguished between noumenon
(thing-in-itself), and phenomenon (appearance), and to Hegel.
AUTISM IN SCHIZOPHRENIA 11
“The world is pregiven to us, the waking, always somehow practically interested subjects, not
occasionally but always and necessarily as the universal field of all actual and possible praxis, as a
horizon. To live is always to live-in-certainty-of-the-world.“’8 (et. p. 142).
According to Merleau-Ponty,
“One can say that we perceive the things themselves, that we are the world that thinks itself--or
that the world is at the heart of our flesh.“19 (e.t. p. 136).
This very obscure formulation attempts to overcome the difficulties created by the
use of language, by which the terms “subject” and “object” deal with the
experience:
“We speak of the perceiving subject and the objects perceived. However, to speak in this
manner is already to have abstracted from perceptual experience. What is given in experience
after all is neither a subject for-itself nor an object in-itself, but rather a perception. The fallacy
inherent in abstraction and analysis lies in our tendency to reify the abstract terms: we speak of
such second-order abstractions as subject and object as though they were given in first-order
experience. Such is our legacy from Descartes that our language is shot through with locutions
which tacitly reify (or realize into first-order existence) the abstractions which should properly be
used for second-order reflection upon experience.“” (p. 48).
“The sick individual, following a classical, descriptive diagnosis, is ‘carrier of the symptom,’ and
the descriptive diagnosing attributes to the individual, as an exclusive property, the characteristics
which it isolates, independently of the present relation with the observer. The word “schizophrenic”
has here the meaning of ‘a predicative characterization of the (assumed) schizophrenic process.’
But its meaning is completely different in the ‘phenomenological diagnosis,’ in which it does not
qualify a pathological process, but Being as globally met by the observer, and as he is met.
Understanding of autism as a phenomenon leads to a shift of emphasis from the schizophrenic
individual to the impression he makes on someone else.“** (p. 42).
Many classic clinicians were aware of such diagnostic process of autism, even
though they were not explicitly influenced by phenomenology, and named it in
different ways. Expressions like “diagnosis through intuition” (Wyrsch),Z” “atmo-
spheric diagnosis” (Tellenbach),24 “Praecox Geftihl” (Rtimke),” “Diagnostic par
penetration” (Minkowski)” occurred regularly in the psychiatric literature.
Riimke postulated that a skilled clinician is able to diagnose schizophrenia very
quickly in the encounter with the patient, and he named this diagnostic feeling on
the part of the psychiatrist as “praecox feeling” [praecox Geftihl]. He was unable
to verbalize the essence of this feeling, but proposed that it had something to do
with the inability to empathize with the patient’s personality as a whole. In his
discussion of the diagnostic value of Kraepelinian fundamental symptoms, he
writes:
“If the symptoms are taken in the literary sense . . ., these criteria are totally insufficient. But
when we add to each of these symptoms the words ‘a very definite,’ it is clear what Kraepelin
meant. It is, however, impossible so far to describe this ‘very definite’ character. Properly
speaking, these words ‘a very definite’ ought to be replaced by ‘a schizophrenic.’ To do so would
seem to be a scientific absurdity. And yet this is not the case, for every examiner with great
experience of genuine schizophrenia knows very precisely what this word ‘schizophrenic’ refers
to.“*’ (et. p. 304).
“Our summaries could not of course provide the data Essen-Moller preferred for assessing
characterological defects such as facial tonicity and emotional accessibility.“28 (p. 219).
“Up to now, Essen-Moller’s clinical assessments represent the most successful attempt ever
made to identify the schizotype or spectrum disorders.“” (p. 220).
“What we have in mind is the faculty of advancing harmoniously with the ambient becoming, in
penetrating it and in feeling one with it. We employ here the term ‘lived synchronism.’ Elements
of the vital contact with reality comprise ‘penetration, ’ ‘contemplation,’ and ‘sympathy.’ It is
because of the penetration that there is no place for the subject/object opposition. There is more
of an equivalence between the two, for if I absorb myself in that I contemplate, the thing
contemplated becomes animated, becomes as alive as I, penetrates to the depth of my being,
becomes the source of my inspiration. . . . Vital contact with reality gives us measure and limits of
our percepts, rendering them infinitely human and nuanced. It is good to have rules of conduct. It
is better to know how to apply them. . . Without being ever able to formulate it, we know what we
have to do; and it is that that makes our activity infinitely malleable and human.“26 (e.t. pp. 66-69).
“This means that within vitally flowing intentionality in which the life of an ego-subject consists,
every other ego is already intentionally implied in advance by way of empathy and empathy-
horizon.“‘* (e.t. p. 255).
Minkowski disagreed with Bleuler on several points. First, he did not consider
“thepredominance of the innerfantay 1ife”as the necessary component of autism. In
fact, he claimed that a typical schizophrenic was characterized by the poverty of
affective-cognitive processes. For such cases he introduced the concept of
“autisme pauvre, “31 i.e., autism characterized by “poverty.” On that point, he
incidentally agreed with Kraepelin, who also criticized Bleuler’s definition of
autism:
“But I very much doubt if it (i.e. autism), as Bleuler thinks, is caused by the withdrawal of the
patient to his own phantasies. . . Stubborn inactivity is often shown by patients, in whom there
can be no thought of special imaginings in which they could lose themselves, and it is lacking in
numerable other delusional diseases (e.g. general paresis), in which the patients dream
themselves into a world of imaginings.“‘j (e.t. p. 51).
14 PARNAS AND BOVET
Minkowski claimed that florid Bleulerian autism [autisme riche] occurred only
when a patient was equipped with an autism-independent propensity towards
affective-cognitive expressivity. Also, he did not consider autism as a withdrawal, but
as a loss of the vital contact with reality In this sense, autism can be viewed as a defect
rather than as a defense mechanism. This defect is discernible not only in the
patient’s expressivity or communication, but also in the activity and attitudes of
the patient. Minkowski coined the term “autistic activity.” What is characteristic
for the autistic activity is not its content, but the way this content is enacted. This
aspect of autistic activity is characterized by its inappropriateness, its friction with
the context of the situation, and its lack of relevant consequences. He mentions as
an example a schizoid father who buys, as a Christmas present for his dying
daughter, a coffin. This act is by objective standards quite rational and logical,
because the coffin is something which the daughter is going to need. At the same
time, this act reveals its total lack of attunement to the daughter’s emotional
needs, and is inappropriate and bizarre by any human standard. It follows from
Minkowski’s conception of autism that loss of the vital contact with reality, that is
lack of attunement with the environment, is discernible both in extraverted and
introverted behavior. This is in contrast with the predominance of a withdrawal
element contained in the Bleulen’an definition, which has led many psychiatrists to
confuse autism with introversion, mutism, or negativism. Last but not least,
Minkowski considered autism as a both primary and fundamental disorder of
schizophrenia, upon which other psychopathological features could be compre-
hended (generating disorder) [trouble gen&ateur].26
L. Binswanger,34235in his existential phenomenology [Daseinsanalyse], arrives at
a similar notion of the schizophrenic way of being as Minkowski, but primarily
from an anthropological (in the European sense of this word) analysis of the
schizophrenic existence.
“The basic concept used in understanding what is called the schizophrenic existential pattern
proves to be the notion of a breakdown in the consistency of natural experience-its inconsis-
tency. Inconsistency implies precisely that inability to ‘let things be’ in the immediate encounter
with them, in other words, to reside serenely among things.“” (p. 250).
The notion of natural experience and natural evidence has been elaborated by
W. Blankenburg.36-3s Natural experience is only possible because it rests on an
anonymous and silent mass of evidences that always and already are present, and
which constitute what has been called the “axioms of everyday life” (Straus).39
Such a formulation refers also to what phenomenology describes as a pre-
linguistic and pre-predicative perceptual ability and attunement (“the allusive
logic of the perceived world”16 e.t. p. 37). On the part of the human being, this
natural experience is given due to the presence of a “common sense” [sensus
comrnunis] (Blankenburg).% According to Blankenburg, common sense is the
ability to see things in the right perspective, provides knowledge of the “rules of
the game” for the human behavior, provides a sense and taste for that which is
adequate and proper, and knowledge of the Other even before his recognition.
Common sense enables us to distinguish between what is relevant and irrelevant,
likely and improbable, which is a more elementary ability than to distinguish
between what is true or false. In short, it is the ability to sense the exact weight of
things.
AUTISM IN SCHIZOPHRENIA 15
“It is a logic, not the one of the logicians, but a ‘logic of the world’ [Weltlogik], a ‘natural logic.’
What common sense brings is not whnt is evident, but how it is evident, the ever present and ever
forgotten frame of experience: the most trivial but also the most basic thing, because it forms the
ground of human Presence and Praxis in everyday life, brings historical continuity to the Self, and
constitutes the stream of intersubjectivity.“‘* (pp. 58-59).
“A young patient complains: ‘What is it I really lack? Something so small, but so unique and
important that you cannot live without it. I have the need of support in the most trivial everyday
matters; what I lack really is the natural evidence [Selbstverstandlichkeit]. Every human should
know how to behave and conduct himself. I did not have the requisite premises. There are so many
things which are alien for me. It has simply to do with living, how to behave yourself in order not to
be pushed outside, outside society. But I cannot find the right word for that which is lacking in
me-that is the way I feel it. It is not knowledge; it is something that every child is equipped with.
It is these very simple things a human being has the need for, to carry on life, . . how to act, to be
with other people, to know rules of the game . . . Such a thing as washing for instance, I do not
manage it in a self-evident way. . . . I have to force myself. . that is the case with all the world. I
cannot find a rest in myself, as if I did not have any point of view nor any attitude [Haltung]. I do
not have any solid attitude towards things. Other people see only the relevant questions, natural
problems which do not affect them personally. That is the reason why they can be more relaxed
and more natural. I do not know how I am going to live with this defect.’ Another patient writes to
his friend: ‘I do not know whether you are happy, let us assume that. Whom do you have to thank
for this-let us say-unburdened easiness [Unbeschwertsein]? For your happiness, your easiness
and your security, you can thank ‘a something’ of which you are not even conscious. This
‘something’ is first of all that which makes easiness possible. It provides the first ground’.“3”
Such reports are of course not very frequent. We encounter them in the
complaints of young incipient hebephrenics who still have retained an ability for
self-reflection. This defect in the preintentional attunement makes the preschizo-
phrenic vulnerable to the demands of the outer world, and may result in a
withdrawal from object relations. According to Blankenburg, the lack of natural
evidence facilitates construction of subjective evidences, which leads to the
productive paranoid psychosis. What is typical for such paranoid psychosis is its
universal and stereotyped way of being, which is resilient to any factual
experience.
In the discussion of differences between schizophrenics and depressives,
Blankenburg3’ states that for depressives, the sense for [das Geftihl fur] what they
lack, as evidenced by their guilt or insufficiency feelings, is still present, and
perhaps even intensified as compared to normals, whereas for schizophrenics or
schizoids this sense of experiencing a lack of empathy [das Geftihl fur das Erleben
eines Mange1 an Mitgeftihl] is at least partially lost.
The global crisis of common sense or lack of natural evidence constitutes the autistic
nucleus and leads to the schizophrenic perplexity [Rastlosigkeit14’ or “hyper-
reflexion” [Reflexionskrampf141 where the patient has a feeling that the environ-
ment has lost its elementary meaning and reference. In this sense, the schizo-
phrenic has lost a worldly paradigm for his reflections and activities, and is
compelled to address, for other people, quite elementary and self-evident issues.
16 PARNAS AND BOVET
The global crisis of common sense is well illustrated in the work of K. Conrad,“’
who observed that in the initial stage of schizophrenia [das Trema], judgements,
emotions and behavior are often inappropriate to their social context. Such a
heralding of schizophrenia by isolated, bizarre statements or behaviors was in
classical psychiatry called “paragnomen.”
As illustrated, these three concepts of autism in phenomenological psychiatry,
i.e., “loss of vital contact with reality” (Minkowski), “inconsistency of natural
experience” (Binswanger), and “global crisis of common sense” (Blankenburg),
overlap each other considerably.
These descriptions indicate that autism comprises both affective and cognitive
components. This may imply that the primary dialogue between the Self and the
outer world [Mitweltbezogenheit] is an intertwining of affect, cognition and will,
which become semantically separated by the application of language.
The diagnostic value of autistic tendencies for milder forms of schizophrenia or
schizoid personality was noted by all classic schizophrenia researchers. Already
Kahlbaum4’ spoke about “heboid states” (heboidophrenias), which he noted
occurred frequently among relatives of hebephrenics, and which were character-
ized by subtle formal thought disorder, and disturbances in social feelings, tact,
and conduct. Later, expressions like simple form of Dementia praecox,43 latent
schizophrenia,’ or schizoid personality44 were introduced to describe behavioral
features which were identifiable in preschizophrenics, relatives of schizophrenics,
and attenuated forms of schizophrenia. These observations were in our time
confirmed by the adoption studies in schizophrenia45,46 and premorbid study of
schizophrenics and schizotypes.47-4y Basically, all these studies indicate that
peculiar expressivity is the hallmark of the schizophrenic phenotype. In the
DSM-III-R’ definition of schizotypal personality, there are at least four criteria
that are connected to the concept of autism: excentricity, restricted and/or
inappropriate rapport, odd communication, and social isolation. It is interesting
to note that the interviewer in the Danish-American adoption studies was always
employing the concept of autism in his diagnostic work (Jacobsen, personal
communication).
“All perception, and all action which presupposes it, in short, every human use of the body, is
already primordial expression. This means that perception is . , the primary operation which first
constitutes signs as signs. Perception makes what is expressed dwell in signs, not through some
previous convention, but through the eloquence of their very arrangement and configuration.“‘”
(et. p. 78).
Molecular level
.___________________------------ __________________
(pre-phenomenal level)
I. khizolaxia
(prephenomenal,
Neurwintegrative deficit physiological
,~ r,,
”
REFERENCES
1. American Psychiatric Association: Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (ed 3,
revised). Washington, DC, APA, 1987
2. Bleuler E: Dementia Praecox oder Gruppe der Schizophrenien, in Aschaffenburg G (ed):
Handbuch der Psychiatric. Leipzig, Germany, Deuticke, 1911. Translation by Zinkin J, Lewis NDC:
Dementia Praecox or the Group of Schizophrenias. New York, NY, International University Press,
1950
3. Landmark J: A manual for the assessment of schizophrenia. Acta Psychiatr Stand Suppl65,1982
4. Freud S: Drei Abhandlungen zur Sexualtheorie. Wien, Austria, Deuticke, 1905
5. Janet P: Les Obsessions et la Psychasthenic. Paris, France, Alcan, 1903
6. Bleuler E: Das autistisch-undisziplinierte Denken in der Medizin und seine Ueberwindung.
Berlin, Germany, Springer, 1919. Translation by Rapaport D, in Rapaport D (ed): Organization and
Pathology of Thought. New York, NY, Columbia University, 1951, pp 399-437
7. Stromgren E: Autism. Eur J Psychiatry 1:45-54,1987
8. Bleuler M: Die schizophrenen Geistesstorungen im Lichte langjahriger Kranken- und Familienge-
schichten. Stuttgart, Germany, Thieme, 1972. Translation by Clemens SM: The Schizophrenic
Disorders. Long-term Patient and Family Studies. New Haven, CT, Yale University, 1978
9. McGlashan TH: Aphanisis: The syndrome of pseudo-depression in chronic schizophrenia.
Schizophr Bull 8:118-134,1982
10. Mednick SA, Schulsinger F: Factors related to breakdown in children at high risk for
schizophrenia, in Roff M, Ricks DF (eds): Life History Research in Psychopathology. Minneapolis,
MN, University of Minnesota, 1970, pp 51-93
11. Kanner L: Autistic disturbances of affective contact. Nets Child 2:217-250,1943
20 PARNAS AND BOVET
38. Blankenburg W: Autismus, in Muller C (ed): Lexicon der Psychiatric. Gesammelte Abhandlun-
gen der gebriuchlisten psychiatrischen Begriffe (ed 2). Berlin, Germany, Springer, 1986, pp 83-89
39. Straus E: Die Aesthesiologie und ihre Bedeutung fur das Verstandnis der Halluzinationen, in
Straus E: Psychologie der menschlichen Welt. Gesammelte Schriften. Berlin, Germany, Springer,
1949, pp 236-269. Translation by the editors: Aesthesiology and Hallucinations, in May R, Angel E,
Ellenberger HF (eds): Existence. New York, NY, Basic Books, 1958, pp 139-169
40. Starring GE: Wesen und Bedeutung des Symptoms der Rastlosigkeit bei psychischen Erkrankun-
gen. Leipzig, Germany, Thieme, 1939
41. Conrad K: Die beginnende Schizophrenic. Versuch einer Gestaltanalyse des Wahns. Stuttgart,
Germany, Thieme, 1958
42. Kahlbaum KL: Ueber Heboidophrenie. Allgem Zschr Psychiatr 46:461-480,189O
43. Diem 0: Die einfach demente Form der Dementia praecox (Dementia simplex). Arch Psychiatr
Nervenkrank 37:11-187,1903
44. Kretschmer E: Korperbau und Charakter. Untersuchungen zum Konstitutionsproblem und zur
Lehre von den Temperamenten. Berlin, Germany, Springer, 1921. Translation by Sprott WJH:
Physique and Character; an Investigation of the Nature of Constitution and of the Theory of
Temperament. London, England, Kegan Paul, 1925
45. Kety SS, Rosenthal D, Wender PH, et al: The biological and adoptive families of adopted
individuals who later became schizophrenic: Prevalence of mental illness and other characteristics, in
Wynne LC, Cromwell RL, Matthysse S (eds): The Nature of Schizophrenia. New York, NY, Wiley,
1978, pp 25-37
46. Gunderson JG, Siever LJ, Spaulding E: The search for a schizotype. Arch Gen Psychiatry
40:15-22, 1983
47. Parnas J, Schulsinger F, Schulsinger H, et al: Behavioral precursors of the schizophrenia
spectrum. Arch Gen Psychiatry 39:658-664, 1982
48. Parnas J, Schulsinger H: Continuity of formal thought disorder from childhood to adulthood in a
high risk sample. Acta Psychiatr Stand 74:246-251, 1986
49. Parnas J, Jorgensen A: Pre-morbid psychopathology in schizophrenia spectrum. Br J Psychiatry
155:623-627,1989
50. Merleau-Ponty M: La Prose du Monde. Paris, France, Gallimard, 1969. Translation by O’Neill
J: The Prose of the World. Evanston, IL, Northwestern University, 1973
51. Stern DN: The Interpersonal World of the Infant. A View From Psychoanalysis and
Developmental Psychology. New York, NY, Basic Books, 1985
52. Meehl PE: Schizotaxia, schizotypy, schizophrenia. Am Psycho1 17:827-838, 1962
53. Meehl PE: Schizotaxia revisited. Arch Gen Psychiatry 46:935-944,1989
54. Klosterkotter J: Basissymptome und Endphinomene der Schizophrenic. Heidelberg, Germany,
Springer, 1988
55. Maher BA: Anomalous experience and delusional thinking: The logic of explanations, in
Oltmanns TF, Maher BA (eds): Delusional Beliefs. New York, NY, Wiley, 1988, pp 15-33
56. Ciompi L, Miiller C: Lebensweg und Alter der Schizophrenen. Eine katamnestische Langzeit-
studie bis ins Senium. Berlin, Germany, Springer, 1976
57. Huber G, Gross G, Schuttler R: Schizophrenic. Verlaufs- und sozialpsychiatrische Langzeitunter-
suchung an den 1945-1959 in Bonn hospitalisierten schizophrenen Kranken. Berlin, Germany,
Springer, 1979