Justice in Taxation
Justice in Taxation
Justice in Taxation
Tyler A. LeFevre*†
—Aristotle
INTRODUCTION.......................................................................................... 764
A. Discourse in Taxation ...................................................................... 765
B. Complexity and Taxation................................................................. 766
I. CONTEMPORARY DISCOURSE IN TAXATION .......................................... 769
A. Contemporary Criteria of Tax Justice.............................................. 770
B. Critique of Contemporary Criteria of Tax Justice ........................... 771
II. THE MORAL GROUNDS OF POLITICS .................................................... 774
A. Deontological Theories of Justice ................................................... 774
B. Consequentialist Theories of Justice ................................................ 779
III. MORALITY AND TAXATION ................................................................. 781
A. Raising Revenue .............................................................................. 782
B. Redistribution of Wealth .................................................................. 783
C. Influencing Behavior ....................................................................... 784
D. Discourse and the Purposes of Taxation .......................................... 785
IV. SCIENCE AND TAXATION .................................................................... 788
A. Economics ....................................................................................... 788
1. Optimal Taxation Theory ............................................................. 788
2. Tax Incidence ............................................................................... 790
3. On Economic Models and Taxes.................................................. 792
B. Psychology ....................................................................................... 793
C. Sociology ......................................................................................... 793
D. Political Science and Political Economics ....................................... 794
CONCLUSION ............................................................................................. 796
* Associate, Grant Thornton LLP. The views and opinions expressed in this article are those
of the author and do not necessarily reflect the position of Grant Thornton LLP.
† I thank Walter C. White, Jr. for his helpful comments.
1. ARISTOTLE, NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I 3 (W. D. Ross trans. 350 B.C.E).
764 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763
INTRODUCTION
A. Discourse in Taxation
10. JOHN MAYNARD KEYNES, THE GENERAL THEORY OF EMPLOYMENT AND MONEY 383–84
(1936).
11. See Ruth Wodak, What CDA is About – A Summary of its History, Important Concepts and
its Development, in METHODS OF CRITICAL DISCOURSE ANALYSIS 1, 2–3 (Ruth Wodak & Michael
Meyer eds., 2001) (describing language and discourse as the medium through which social inequality is
expressed and legitimized).
12. See id. at 3 (explaining that the historical context of every discourse has a stabilizing and
naturalizing force, which appears to make opposing discourse break convention).
13. Tom Flanagan, The Scientific Method and Why It Matters, C2C JOURNAL (Jan. 21, 2013),
http://www.c2cjournal.ca/2013/01/the-scientific-method-and-why-it-matters.
14. Id.
766 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763
frequent than what it ought to be. Yet, in other cases, the quality and
quantity of discourse is just right, but our only course of action is to wait.
We wait with the expectation that, eventually, we will achieve greater truth
and justice. Patience may be our only recourse.
Third, some economic injustice persists regardless of the quality,
quantity, or duration of our discourse. Justice sometimes fails because of
weaknesses in human nature or the destructive whims of Mother Nature.
Our human tools for pursuing economic justice are modest. Philosophy and
social scientific research are tentative and imperfect.15 Though philosophy
and science may uncover truth relevant to economic justice, there will
nonetheless, be room for reasonable disagreement. Without consensus as to
what economic justice requires, there will always be vacillating competition
between opposing ideas.
In this Article, I examine the first reason for economic injustice: the
quality and structure of our tax discourse in the media, public, academia,
and professional practice. This Article’s purpose is to demonstrate how
different fields of study—philosophy, law, accountancy, economics,
history, psychology, sociology, and the hard sciences—can more efficiently
bring about economic justice through taxation policy and practice. Let me
admit upfront that my discussion in this Article itself is imperfect. Like the
bad shot who is dignified for accepting a dual, I felt impelled to take on the
ambitious topic of this Article because I think it important and necessary. I
decided to write this Article because I perceive that our imperfect
discursive practice in taxation is among the significant impediments to
achieving economic justice. I am unaware of any previous effort to
encapsulate how different fields of study and how experts and lay citizens
do and ought to work together to advance knowledge and justice in
taxation.
15. See THOMAS PIKETTY, CAPITAL IN THE TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY 3 (Arthur Goldhammer
trans., Harvard University Press 2014) (2013) (“Social scientific research is and always will be tentative
and imperfect. It does not claim to transform economics, sociology, and history into exact sciences.
But . . . . [i]t can help to redefine terms of debate, unmask certain preconceived or fraudulent notions,
and subject all positions to constant critical scrutiny.”).
16. Lawrence Zelenak, Maybe Just a Little Bit Special, After All?, 63 DUKE L.J. 1897, 1907
(2014).
2017] Justice in Taxation 767
23. LIAM MURPHY & THOMAS NAGEL, THE MYTH OF OWNERSHIP: TAXES AND JUSTICE 3
(2002).
24. See DANIEL C. DENNETT, INTUITION PUMPS AND OTHER TOOLS FOR THINKING 20 (2013)
(stating that, “[t]here is no such thing as philosophy-free science, just science that has been conducted
without any consideration of its underlying philosophical assumptions.”)
25. Daniel Halliday, Justice and Taxation, 8 PHIL. COMPASS 1111, 1111 (2013).
26. MURPHY & NAGEL, supra note 23, at 3–4.
27. See id. at 4 (describing the disconnect between philosophy, ethics, and public policy).
2017] Justice in Taxation 769
The analytical search for justice in taxation has gone on for centuries,
but modern tax theory can be traced back to Adam Smith and the European
Age of Enlightenment.30 In his groundbreaking work, Wealth of Nations,
Adam Smith advances four maxims of prudent taxation that remain relevant
in tax theory today.31
First, Smith asserts, “[t]he subjects of every state ought to contribute
towards the support of the government, as nearly as possible, in proportion
to their respective abilities; that is, in proportion to the revenue which they
respectively enjoy under the protection of the state.”32 Second, Smith says
that taxes “ought to be certain, and not arbitrary,” and that, “[t]he time of
payment, the manner of payment, the quantity to be paid, ought all to be
clear and plain to the contributor, and to every other person.”33 Third
among Smith’s maxims is that “[e]very tax ought to be levied at the time, or
in the manner, in which it is most likely to be convenient for the contributor
to pay it.”34 Lastly, Adam Smith maintains that taxation should be as
efficient as possible. In his words, taxes “ought to be so contrived as both to
take out and to keep out of the pockets of the people as little as possible
over and above what it brings into the public treasury of the state.”35
40. See Sobel, supra note 37, at 109 (noting that vertical equity does not always take costs of
living into account, but that “wealthier” individuals must pay a larger share of their earnings as taxes
under vertical equity).
41. John Buck, The Equity of a Tax System, ECON. PERSPS. (Dec. 8, 2008),
http://econperspectives.blogspot.com/2008/12/equity-of-tax-system.html.
42. Smith, supra note 31, at 361–62.
43. MURPHY & NAGEL, supra note 23, 12 (lambasting traditional tax policy theorists for
neglecting to account for social values).
44. See id. at 16.
45. Id.
46. See id. at 16–17 (proposing a standard baseline measure without government benefits
included).
47. Id.
48. Id. at 16.
772 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763
49. See id. at 17 (recognizing current human unsustainability without government programs
and direction).
50. See id. at 19 (assuming the pretax baseline is one of the market outcomes untouched by
government).
51. Id. at 18.
52. Id.
53. See Dodge, supra note 38, at 432–33 (arguing that, because the poor benefit from
government expenditures, “it would be difficult for new benefit principle proponents convincingly to
derive a progressive tax system from the principle itself”).
54. Id. at 405.
55. Id. at 406.
56. See DEREK BOK, THE POLITICS OF HAPPINESS: WHAT GOVERNMENT CAN LEARN FROM
THE RESEARCH ON WELL-BEING 139 (2010) (noting that growth in gross domestic product (GDP) has
not resulted in happier Americans); JOSEPH E. STIGLITZ ET AL., MISMEASURING OUR LIVES: WHY GDP
DOESN’T ADD UP 56, 61 (2010) (noting that the “[q]uality of life is a broader concept than economic
production and living standards. It includes a full range of factors that influences what we value in
living, reaching beyond its material side.”).
57. Stephen Utz, Ability to Pay, 23 WHITTIER L. REV. 867, 867–69 (2002).
2017] Justice in Taxation 773
58. Id.
59. See, e.g., David Hasen, Liberalism and Ability Taxation, 85 TEX. L. REV. 1057, 1059
(2007) (explaining endowment tax); MURPHY & NAGEL, supra note 23, at 20 (defining endowment tax).
60. MURPHY & NAGEL, supra note 23, at 21–22.
61. Id. at 20.
62. Id. at 20–21.
63. Id. at 23–26.
64. Id.
65. Id. at 23–24.
66. See id. at 27–28 (arguing that few believe market outcomes are presumptively just).
67. Id.
774 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763
ends. The tax questions having the biggest impact on justice and human
welfare frequently involve conflicts between the benefit-received principle,
the ability-to-pay principle, certainty, convenience, consistency, and
efficiency. How are these conflicts to be rationally settled? How do we
determine the right combination of tradeoffs to maximize justice? Without a
tax theory situated in moral theory, many arguments proceeding from
traditional criteria of good tax policy are incommensurable and
interminable. The traditional criteria are inappropriate proxies for the true
ends of justice. Rather than using shorthand substitutes for what justice
demands of taxation, justice requires a more sophisticated tax dialogue.
68. Judith F. Daar, Selective Reduction of Multiple Pregnancy: Lifeboat Ethics in the Womb,
25 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 773, 823 (1992).
69. Matthias Kettner, Discourse Ethics and Health Care Ethics Committees, in 4 ANNUAL
REVIEW OF LAW AND ETHICS 249, 259 n.24 (B. Sharon Byrd et al. eds., 1996).
70. Other prominent schools of moral thought include virtue ethics and care ethics. Not all
theories fit nicely into these categories and there is a good deal of work that tries to reconcile the
differences between the categories. See Erin Talati, When a Spoonful of Sugar Doesn’t Help the
Medicine Go Down: Informed Consent, Mental Illness, and Moral Agency, 6 IND. HEALTH L. REV. 171,
197–98 (2009) (discussing moral theories beyond deontology and utilitarianism, e.g., communitarian
ethics and the feminist ethic of care theory).
71. Douglas W. Vick, Deontological Dicta, 65 MOD. L. REV. 279, 284 (2002).
72. Chad J. Doellinger, A New Theory of Trademarks, 111 PENN STATE L. REV. 823, 836 n.73
(2007).
73. Germain Grisez, Against Consequentialism, 23 AM. J. JURIS. 21, 22 (1978).
74. Michael W. Austin, Divine Command Theory, INTERNET ENCYCLOPEDIA PHIL.,
http://www.iep.utm.edu/divine-c/ (last visited May 7, 2017).
2017] Justice in Taxation 775
extent that they aligned with God’s will.75 On this theory, a ruler’s
legitimacy rested on the idea that God had elected him or her to be a ruler
through birthright.76 In 1689, John Locke published Two Treatises of
Government to refute this theory of the divine right of kings on religious
and philosophical grounds.77 Locke proposed a deontological theory of
legitimate government based on the concept of a social contract.78
For John Locke, “all men are naturally in” a state of perfect freedom
and “also a state of equality.”79 He wrote:
75. Id.
76. Id.
77. Id.
78. JOHN LOCKE, SECOND TREATISE OF GOVERNMENT ¶ 5 (Jonathan Bennett ed., 2008).
79. Id. ¶ 4.
80. Id. at ¶ 6 (emphasis omitted).
81. Id.
776 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763
rights to all property produced by their labor.91 Instead, “the Marxian idea
of exploitation takes the workmanship ideal, and with it the idea of self-
ownership, for granted.”92
Alternatively, and along the lines of John Locke, libertarians support a
strong deontological right to private property. In Anarchy, State, and
Utopia, Robert Nozick provided perhaps the most prominent justification of
libertarian justice.93 Drawing from Immanuel Kant’s moral philosophy,
Nozick bases his theory on the egalitarian idea that “individuals are ends
and not merely means; they may not be sacrificed or used for the achieving
of other ends without their consent.”94 As a result, Nozick reasons, people
have a moral right to any resources that they acquire through consensual,
market exchanges.95 Libertarianism thus adopts a version of the
workmanship model of property rights: we have a right to validly earned
pretax income or wealth. Consequently, government redistribution of
resources, by taxes or otherwise, represents an unjust taking. The taking is
unjust, except when the government protects against and compensates for
crimes and breaches of contract, e.g., violations of consent. In stark contrast
to Marx, Nozick believes that exchanges are consensual even if “facts of
nature,” like poverty, disability, or other disadvantages, severely limit a
person’s options.96 This philosophy of libertarianism finds no inherent
injustice in a society where people born poor and disadvantaged have to
work for people born wealthy and advantaged in exchange for meager
wages. This is true even if the poor and disadvantaged work harder and are
more talented than the wealthy and advantaged.
It is unclear whether liberal egalitarian theories, which are also
founded on Kantian moral ideas and social contract, are more consistent
with moral ends of equality and liberty than are libertarian conceptions of
justice.97 John Rawls puts forth the most prominent liberal egalitarian moral
theory. Instead of using a historical social contract like Locke, Rawls bases
his theory of justice on a hypothetical social contract.98 For Rawls, an
institution, law, or policy is just if it would be agreed to by hypothetically
reasonable persons behind a hypothetical veil of ignorance. That veil of
99. Id. at 15. See also RAWLS, supra note 5, at 118 (introducing the original position and the
veil of ignorance).
100. RAWLS, supra note 98, at 41.
101. Id. at 42.
102. Id. at 42–43.
103. Id. at 135–36.
104. Henry Richardson, John Rawls (1920-2002), INTERNET ENCYCLOPEDIA PHIL.,
http://www.iep.utm.edu/rawls/ (last visited May 7, 2017).
105. RAWLS, supra note 98, at 42–43.
106. NOZICK, supra note 93, at 183.
107. Id.
2017] Justice in Taxation 779
108. See MICHAEL J. SANDEL, LIBERALISM AND THE LIMITS OF JUSTICE 15–19 (1982)
(explaining why the primacy of justice claim is “intuitively appealing” yet simultaneously
“problematic”).
109. John Harsanyi, Can the Maximin Principle Serve as a Basis for Morality? A Critique of
John Rawls’s Theory, 69 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 594, 595–96 (1975).
110. See id. at 596 (arguing that the maximin principle leads to highly irrational decisions in
everyday life and comparing the maximin principle with utilitarian ethics).
111. See Samuel Freeman, Frontiers of Justice: The Capabilities Approach vs.
Contractarianism, 85 TEX. L. REV. 385, 400 (2006) (reviewing MARTHA C. NUSSBAUM, FRONTIERS OF
JUSTICE: DISABILITIES, NATIONALITY, SPECIES MEMBERSHIP (2006)) (showing that Rawls’s ideal of
moral equality comes in the shape of a well-ordered society); Joan C. Callahan & Dorothy E. Roberts, A
Feminist Social Justice Approach to Reproduction-Assisting Technologies: A Case Study on the Limits
of Liberal Theory, 84 KY. L.J. 1197, 1201 (1996) (citing the Lockean belief that each person has the
right to have “as much as good” as any other).
112. RAWLS, supra note 98, at 20.
113. STEVE MCCARTNEY & RICK PARENT, ETHICS IN LAW ENFORCEMENT 13 (2015),
http://opentextbc.ca/ethicsinlawenforcement (last visited May 7, 2017).
780 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763
114. See Jonathan Glover, Introduction to UTILITARIANISM AND ITS CRITICS 1, 1–3 (Jonathan
Glover & Helen McInnis eds., 1990) (explaining the appeal of utilitarianism).
115. JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION
11–12 (J.H. Burns & H.L.A. Hart eds., 1982).
116. Wesley C. Mitchell, Bentham’s Felicific Calculus, 33 POL. SCI. Q. 161, 163–64 (1918).
117. Id. at 164–65.
118. KYMLICKA, supra note 87, at 14.
119. Id.
120. Id. at 17.
121. Id.
122. See Peter J. Hammond, The Economics of Justice and the Criterion of Wealth
Maximization, 91 YALE L.J. 1493, 1495 (1982) (reviewing RICHARD POSNER, THE ECONOMICS OF
JUSTICE (1981)) (stating that, “wealth maximization often leads to conclusions that many of us would
regard as totally unethical”).
2017] Justice in Taxation 781
123. See id. (identifying one of the criticisms of the utilitarian happiness-maximizing principle
as “the indeterminacy of any measure of utility and the consequent vagueness of its ethical
recommendations”).
124. See e.g., Joseph Grcic, Virtue Theory, Relativism and Survival, 3 INT’L J. SOC. SCI. &
HUMAN. 416, 416 (2013) (grounding moral values in personality structures and intentions); Lawrence A.
Blum, Gilligan & Kohlberg: Implications for Moral Theory, 98 ETHICS 472, 473 (1988) (describing care
and responsibility within interpersonal relationships as a separate element of morality); Gerald J.
Postema, Moral Responsibility in Professional Ethics, 55 N.Y.U. L. REV. 63, 65 (1980) (confining the
moral universe of a decision to the range of practical considerations appropriate for an individual’s
role); Marinus H. van IJzendoorn et al., In Defence of Situational Morality: Genetic, Dispositional and
Situational Determinants of Children’s Donating to Charity, 39 J. MORAL EDUC. 1, 17 (2010) (showing
that cognitive moral judgments take place in situation-specific settings); Paul Ramsey, Kant’s Moral
Theology or A Religious Ethics?, in THE ROOTS OF ETHICS: SCIENCE, RELIGION, & VALUES 139, 154
(Daniel Callahan & H. Tristram Englehardt, Jr. eds., 1981) (separating religious ethics from theories of
natural morality).
782 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763
A. Raising Revenue
B. Redistribution of Wealth
C. Influencing Behavior
they want to do so,” while government is nonetheless permitted “to influence choices in a way that will
make choosers better off, as judged by themselves.” Id. at 5. When it comes to behavior-influencing
taxes, uncertainty is often an issue because it is difficult to predict and measure the effectiveness of such
taxes. The more behavior-influencing taxes there are, the less salient each tax is in the minds of
taxpayers, which may weaken the impact of all behavior-influencing taxes. See Gary M. Lucas, Jr.,
Paternalism and Psychic Taxes: The Government’s Use of Negative Emotions to Save Us from
Ourselves, 22 S. CAL. INTERDISC. L.J. 227, 266 (2013) (providing that a “change in perspective may be
due to a change in the salience of relevant aspects of the decision”).
786 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763
issue: the language of relevant tax law and foreign tax law of partnership
interests lead to one conclusion, while the United States’ general tax policy
preventing asset appreciation from escaping taxation leads to another
conclusion. Without other evidence of legislative intent, a judge may
assume Congress intended whichever policy is more favorable. Presently, it
is often taboo for a technical memorandum, judicial opinion, or tax
authority ruling to deal with issues of justice. Yet, if these practitioners’
conception of the issue as a tug-of-war between internal coherency of the
income tax, on the one hand, and, certainty of taxpayers as to their tax
liability, on the other, is correct, then the only way of prioritizing the two
values—coherency and certainty—may be to dig down into the moral
foundations of taxation. Commonly, the only way to arbitrate between
competing canons of good tax policy is by resorting to moral philosophy
about justice, the good life, and the good society. This is especially true of
the most consequential tax questions.
Reasoning about justice generally––and taxation specifically––takes
the form of analyzing shared, but incomplete, information with the goal of
growing the currently limited consensus about the truth in taxation.156 But
neither laypersons nor tax experts should leave it to professional
philosophers to decide the pressing questions in taxation. Certainly,
philosophers contribute to vetting, elucidating, and proposing moral and
political ideals. However, philosophers have proven largely unwilling or
unable to bridge the gap between moral ideals and real-world tax policy and
law.157 Since accountants, lawyers, and economists understand the complex
tax system best, they have an important role in defining practical tax
applications of normative theories concerning proper conduct and the good
life. In order to promote justice and human well-being, tax experts need to
become morally sophisticated.
interest in a partnership with a United States trade or business “will be sourced in the United States”);
DEP’T OF TREASURY, GENERAL EXPLANATIONS OF THE ADMINISTRATION’S FISCAL YEAR 2016
REVENUE PROPOSALS 26–27 (2015), https://www.treasury.gov/resource-center/tax-policy/Documents/
General-Explanations-FY2016.pdf (suggesting a change in foreign tax credit limitation rules in order to
prevent double taxation on dual capacity taxpayers in regards to foreign levies); N.Y. STATE BAR ASS’N,
TAX SECTION, REPORT ON GUIDANCE IMPLEMENTING REVENUE RULING 91-32, at 1 (2014) (responding
“to a request from the Department of the Treasury . . . for comments relating to the current project at
Treasury and the Internal Revenue Service . . . to issue guidance under Section 864 implementing
Revenue Ruling 91-32”) (footnote omitted).
156. See Lee Smolin, Science and Democracy, TED (Feb. 2003), https://www.ted.com/
talks/lee_smolin_on_science_and_democracy?language=en (describing the scientific method as an
argumentative, consensus-building ethic).
157. See supra Part III.A–III.C (discussing moral differences between philosophies regarding
elements of taxation).
788 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763
A. Economics
lower taxes.163 These people would have preferred windows, but the tax
artificially distorted their decisions.164 Similarly, taxes on labor
disincentivize labor, while consumption taxes disincentivize consumption.
Normatively, optimal taxation theory addresses the question of “how
best to raise revenues in a distorted economy.”165 Optimal tax theory deals
with efficiency rather than equity. Further, optimal tax theory asserts that
tax policies should seek to minimize deadweight loss subject to certain
constraints, such as considerations of justice.166 Optimal tax theory would
recommend a lump-sum tax in a perfectly competitive market without
equity constraints.167 A lump-sum tax is the most efficient tax because it
distorts taxpayers’ choices the least.168
Unfortunately, applying optimal tax theory is more difficult than
simply adopting a lump-sum tax. The real-world market contains
imperfections, including justice and equity constraints.
In a 2009 article, Gregory Mankiw, Matthew Weinzierl, and Danny
Yagan summarized eight high-level conclusions of optimal tax theory:
163. Id.
164. Id.
165. ROBIN BOADWAY, FROM OPTIMAL TAX THEORY TO TAX POLICY: RETROSPECTIVE AND
PROSPECTIVE VIEWS 7 (2012).
166. N. Gregory Mankiw et al., Optimal Taxation in Theory and Practice, 23 J. ECON. PERSPS.
147, 148 (2009).
167. Id. at 149. A lump-sum tax is a uniform tax of a fixed amount. If, for example, a country
imposed a tax of $1,000 on every person once every other year, that would be a lump-sum tax. See id.
(stating that, “this tax falls equally on the rich and poor”).
168. That a lump-sum tax maximizes utility in a perfectly competitive market rests on the
assumption that a perfectly competitive market is maximally efficient. Given a number of stated
assumptions, the First Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Economics posits that a perfectly competitive
market results in the maximum amount of economic output possible. See Kenneth J. Arrow, An
Extension of the Basic Theorems of Classical Welfare Economics, in PROCEEDINGS OF THE SECOND
BERKELEY SYMPOSIUM ON MATHEMATICAL STATISTICS AND PROBABILITY 507, 507–10 (Jerzy Neyman
ed., 1951). See also Mankiw et al., supra note 166, at 149, 158 (demonstrating that lump-sum tax
schedules produce near optimal results while least distorting buyer and worker incentives). In essence,
the theorem is a mathematical confirmation of Adam Smith’s “invisible hand” hypothesis. MASSIMO
FLORIO, APPLIED WELFARE ECONOMICS: COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS OF PROJECTS AND POLICIES 40
(2014).
790 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763
2. Tax Incidence
175. See Presentation, Raj Chetty & Gregory A. Bruich, Harvard University Public Economics
Lectures, Part 2: Incidence of Taxation 7 (Fall 2012), http://rajchetty.com/chettyfiles/public_
economics_lectures.pdf (stating that tax incidence studies analyze the tax change effects on aggregate
groups).
176. See id. at 8–12 (discussing the setup for a partial equilibrium model that focuses on two
goods).
177. Id. at 9.
178. See id. at 89 (stating that the general equilibrium model analyzes all prices to identify the
full incidence of taxes).
179. See id. at 17 (providing a formula for tax incidence that relies on price elasticity).
180. STEPHEN ENTIN, HERITAGE CTR. FOR DATA ANALYSIS, TAX INCIDENCE, TAX BURDEN,
AND TAX SHIFTING: WHO REALLY PAYS THE TAX? 4–5, 22–23 (Nov. 5, 2004), http://www.heritage.org/
taxes/report/tax-incidence-tax-burden-and-tax-shifting-who-really-pays-the-tax.
792 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763
181. Raj Chetty et al., Salience and Taxation: Theory and Evidence, 99 AMER. ECON. REV.
1145, 1145 (2009).
182. See id. at 1165 (explaining why consumers care more about prices than taxes related to
saliency).
183. DANI RODRIK, ECONOMICS RULES: THE RIGHTS AND WRONGS OF THE DISMAL SCIENCE 9
(2015).
184. Id. at 10.
185. Id. at 6.
186. Id. at 12. Mathematics in economics serves two primary purposes. “First, math ensures that
the elements of a model—the assumptions, behavioral mechanisms, and main results—are stated clearly
and are transparent.” Id. at 31. “The second virtue of mathematics is that it ensures the internal
consistency of a model—simply put, that the conclusions follow from the assumptions.” Id. at 32.
2017] Justice in Taxation 793
B. Psychology
C. Sociology
“Sociology is the [scientific] study of social life, social change, and the
social causes and consequences of human behavior.”193 It focuses on social
organization, institutions, and behavior.194 Many moral theories, especially
liberal egalitarian ones, are concerned with economic inequalities drawn
187. See, e.g., BEN R. NEWELL ET AL., STRAIGHT CHOICES: THE PSYCHOLOGY OF DECISION
MAKING 13, 15–16 (2d ed. 2015) (arguing that the way information is provided can influence
decisions); BARRY SCHWARTZ, THE PARADOX OF CHOICE: WHY MORE IS LESS 48–51 (2004)
(explaining how experienced utility, expected utility, and remembered utility shape an individual’s
choices).
188. See DANIEL KAHNEMAN, THINKING FAST AND SLOW 3–5 (2011) (describing systematic
errors as predictably recurring biases).
189. See CHRISTIAN B. MILLER, CHARACTER AND MORAL PSYCHOLOGY, at xi–xii (2014)
(discussing the theory of “Mixed Traits” and how robust character traits can give rise to morally relevant
thoughts).
190. See MARTIN E.P. SELIGMAN, FLOURISH: A VISIONARY NEW UNDERSTANDING OF
HAPPINESS AND WELL-BEING 13–15 (2011) (discussing the inadequacies of authentic happiness theory
and emphasizing the construct of well-being as the focal topic of positive psychology).
191. See MURPHY & NAGEL, supra note 23, at 51–52 (recognizing utilitarianism’s need for a
metric for comparing the total good of policy outcomes).
192. See id. at 51 (defining the utilitarian theory of social justice).
193. JEANNE H. BALLANTINE & KEITH A. ROBERTS, OUR SOCIAL WORLD: INTRODUCTION TO
SOCIOLOGY 6 (3d ed. 2011).
194. Id.
794 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763
195. RAWLS, supra note 98, at 64 (defining personal liberty and the principle of reciprocity as
the only relevant moral concerns).
196. MURPHY & NAGEL, supra note 23, at 54.
197. See id. (explaining Rawls’s view that arbitrary inequalities between individuals are unjust
unless they can be made to serve some non-arbitrary purpose). DÉCLARATION DES DROITS DE
L'HOMME ET DU CITOYEN, ART. I, ASSEMBLÉE NATIONALE CONSTITUANTE 26-08-1789 (Fr.),
translated at The Avalon Proj., Declaration of the Rights of Man, YALE L. SCH. (2008),
http://Avalon.law.yale.edu/18th_century/rightsof.asp.
198. MURPHY & NAGEL, supra note 23, at 23.
199. Elizabeth R. Carter, New Life for the Death Tax Debate, 90 DENV. U. L. REV. 175, 181, 189
(2012).
200. Excise Tax, IRS, https://www.irs.gov/businesses/small-businesses-self-employed/excise-
tax (last updated July 19, 2006). See JOHN. R. SEARLE, MAKING THE SOCIAL WORLD: THE STRUCTURE
OF HUMAN CIVILIZATION 5 (2010) (discussing the philosophy of society and institutions).
201. Carter, supra note 199, at 182.
202. See Amartya Sen, Arrow and the Impossibility Theorem, in THE ARROW IMPOSSIBILITY
THEOREM 21, 21 (Eric Maskin & Amartya Sen eds., 2014) (relating public decisions to individual
preferences).
2017] Justice in Taxation 795
CONCLUSION
211. Arguably, however, the growing global network of tax treaties, most of which conform
closely to the model conventions promulgated by the OECD, is approaching a supranational norm.
Yariv Brauner, What the BEPS?, 16 FLA. TAX. REV. 55, 61–62 (2014). See generally REUVEN S. AVI-
YONAH, INTERNATIONAL TAX AS INTERNATIONAL LAW: AN ANALYSIS OF THE INTERNATIONAL TAX
REGIME 3 (2007) (arguing that international tax law is part of international law even if it differs in some
respects from generally applicable international law).
212. PIKETTY, supra note 15, at 2.
2017] Justice in Taxation 797
213. See Julianne Chiaet, Novel Finding: Reading Literary Fiction Improves Empathy, SCI. AM.
(Oct. 4, 2013), https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/novel-finding-reading-literary-fiction-
improves-empathy/ (discussing research into the value of literary fiction, which expands the capacity for
an individual to empathize).
214. Gwendolyn Brooks, Kitchenette Building, POETRY FOUNDATION,
https://www.poetryfoundation.org/resources/learning/core-poems/detail/43308 (last visited May 7,
2017). Aria means an elaborate song for one voice with orchestral accompaniment, appearing most often
in opera (“aria” means “air” in Italian). Aria, AM. HERITAGE DICTIONARY (3d ed. 1992).
798 Vermont Law Review [Vol. 41:763