Applied Critical Theory Reader
Applied Critical Theory Reader
Applied Critical Theory Reader
III HERMENEUTICS 45
IV LINGUISTIC CRITICISM 70
VI POST-STRUCTURALISM
Jacques Derrida: 'Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of the Human
Sciences' 1
Roland Barthes: 'The Death of the Author'
XIII POSTMODERNISM
Reprinted from Russian Formalist Criticism: Four Essays, trans. and ed.
Lee T. Lemon and Marion]. Reis (Lincoln, Nebraska, 1965), pp. 5-22.
consciously automatic; if one remembers the sensations of
holding a pen or of speaking in a foreign language for the first
time and compares that with his feeling at performing the action
for the ten thousandth time, he will agree with us....
Just why precisely this stupid, savage means of causing pain and not any
other -why not prick the shoulders or any part of the body with needles,
In brief, the imaginative life is its own justification; and this fact
must be faced, although sometimes -by a lover, for example -it
may be very difficult to accept. When it is faced, it is apparent that
all the attitudes to other human beings and to the world in all its
aspects, which have been serviceable to humanity, remain as they
were, as valuable as ever. Hesitation felt in admitting this is a
measure of the strength of the evil habit I have been describing.
But many of these attitudes, valuable as ever, are, now that they
are being set free, more difficult to maintain, because we still
hunger after a basis in belief.
CLEANTH BROOKS: 'THE FORMALIST CRITIC'
In the first place, to make the poem or the novel the central
concern of criticism has appeared to mean cutting it loose from
its author and from his life as a man, with his own particular
hopes, fears, interests, conflicts, etc. A criticism so limited may
seem bloodless and hollow...
III HERMENEUTICS
The difficulty -it initiated my research in the first place -is this:
there is no general hermeneutics, no universal canon for exegesis,
but only disparate and opposed theories concerning the rules of
interpretation. The hermeneutic field, whose outer contours we
have traced, is internally at variance with itself.
All three clear the horizon for a more authentic word, for a new
reign of Truth, not only by means of a 'destructive' critique, but
by the invention of an art of interpreting. Descartes triumphed over
the doubt as to things by the evidence of consciousness; they
triumph over the doubt as to consciousness by an exegesis of
meaning. Beginning with them, understanding is hermeneutics:
henceforward, to seek meaning is no longer to spell out the consciousness
of meaning, but to decipher its expressions. What must be
faced, therefore, is not only a threefold guile. If consciousness is
not what it thinks it is, a new relation must be instituted between
the patent and the latent; this new relation would correspond to
the one that consciousness had instituted between appearances
and the reality of things. For Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud, the
fundamental
category of consciousness is the relation hidden-shown
or, if you prefer, simulated-manifested.... What is essential is that
all three create with the means at hand, with and against the
prejudices of their times, a mediate science of meaning, irreducible
to the immediate consciousness of meaning. What all three
attempted, in different ways, was to make their 'conscious'
methods of deciphering coincide with the 'unconscious' work of
ciphering which they attributed to the will to power, to social
being, to the unconscious psychism. Guile will be met by double guile.
I have been asked for summary remarks about poetics in its relation
to linguistics. Poetics deals primarily with the question, What
makes a verbal message a work of art? Because the main subject of
poetics is the differentia specifica of verbal art in relation to other
arts and in relation to other kinds of verbal behavior, poetics is
entitled to the leading place in literary studies.
be schematized as follows:
CONTEXT
ADDRESSER MESSAGE ADDRESSEE
CONTACT
CODE
REFERENTIAL
METALINGUAL
Let us begin with a few words about the first attitude, for which
the literary work is the ultimate and unique object, and which we
shall here and henceforth call interpretation. Interpretation, which
is sometimes also called exegesis, commentary, explication de texte,
close
reading, analysis, or even just criticism (such a list does not mean we
cannot distinguish or even set in opposition some of the terms), is
defined, in the sense we give it here, by its aim, which is to name
the meaning of the text examined. This aim forthwith determines the
ideal of this attitude -which is to make the text itself speak; i.e., it
is a fidelity to the object, to the other, and consequently an effacement
of the subject -as well as its drama, which is to be forever incapable
of realizing the meaning, but only a meaning subject to
historical and psychological contingencies. This ideal, this drama
will be modulated down through the history of commentary, itself
coextensive with the history of humanity.
It is not the literary work itself that is the object of poetics: what
poetics questions are the properties of that particular discourse
that is literary discourse. Each work is therefore regarded only as
the manifestation of an abstract and general structure, of which
it is but one of the possible realizations. Whereby this science
is no longer concerned with actual literature, but with a possible
literature, in other words with that abstract property that constitutes
the singularity of the literary phenomenon: literariness.
The goal of this study is no longer to articulate a paraphrase, a
descriptive resume of the concrete work, but to propose a theory
of the structure and functioning of literary discourse, a theory
that affords a list of literary possibilities, so that existing literary
works appear as achieved particular cases. The work will then be
projected upon something other than itself, as in the case of
psychological or sociological criticism; this something other will no
longer be a heterogeneous structure, however, but the structure
of literary discourse itself. The particular text will be only an
instance that allows us to describe the properties of literature....
The fact that this essay was originally intended for a series of
structuralist studies raises a new question: what is structuralism's
relation to poetics? The difficulty of answering is proportional to
the polysemy of the term 'structuralism'.
Taking this word in its broad acceptation, all poetics, and not
merely one or another of its versions, is structural: since the
object of poetics is not the sum of empirical phenomena (literary
works) but an abstract structure (literature). But then, the introduction
of a scientific point of view into any realm is always and
already structural.
Only writing, again, and this is a first step towards defining it,
can practise language in its totality. To resort to scientific discourse
as if to an instrument of thought is to postulate that there
exists a neutral state of language, from which a certain number of
specialized languages, the literary or poetic languages for
example, have derived, as so many deviants or embellishments. It
is held that this neutral state would be the referential code for all
the 'excentric' languages, which themselves would be merely its
sub-codes. By identifying itself with this referential code, as the
basis of all normality, scientific discourse is arrogating to itself a
right which it is writing's duty precisely to contest. The notion of
'writing' implies indeed that language is a vast system, none of
whose codes is privileged or, if one prefers, central, and whose
various departments are related in a 'fluctuating hierarchy'.
Scientific discourse believes itself to be a superior code; writing
aims at being a total code, including its own forces of destruction.
It follows that writing alone can smash the theological idol set up
by a paternalistic science, refuse to be terror-stricken by what is
wrongly thought of as the 'truth' ofthe content and of reasoning,
and open up all three dimensions of language to research, with its
subversions of logic, its mixing of codes, its shifts of meaning,
dialogues and parodies....
VI POST-STRUCTURALISM
JACQUES DERRIDA: 'STRUCTURE, SIGN, AND PLAY IN THE DISCOURSE OF THE HUMAN
SCIENCES'
(I use this word deliberately). Thus it has always been thought that
the center, which is by definition unique, constitutes that very thing
within a structure which governs the structure, while escaping
structurality.
This is why classical thought concerning structure could
say that the center is, paradoxically, within the structure and outside
it. The center is at the center of the totality, and yet, since the
center does not belong to the totality (is not part of the totality),
the totality has its center elsewhere. The center is not the center. The
concept of centered structure -although it represents coherence
itself, the condition of the ipisteme as philosophy or science -is
contradictorily
coherent. And, as always, coherence in contradiction
expresses the force of a desire. The concept of centered structure is
in fact the concept of a freeplay based on a fundamental ground, a
freeplay which is constituted upon a fundamental immobility and a
reassuring certitude, which is itself beyond the reach of the
freeplay. With this certitude anxiety can be mastered, for anxiety is
invariably the result of a certain mode of being implicated in the
game, of being caught by the game, of being as it were from the
very beginning at stake in the game....
Though the sway of the Author remains powerful (the new criticism2
has often done no more than consolidate it), it goes without
saying that certain writers have long since attempted to loosen it.
In France, Mallarme was doubtless the first to see and to foresee
in its full extent the necessity to substitute language itself for the
person who until then had been supposed to be its owner. For
him, for us too, it is language which speaks, not the author; to
write is, through a prerequisite impersonality (not at all to be confused
with the castrating objectivity of the realist novelist), to
reach that point where only language acts, 'performs', and not
'me'. Mallarme's entire poetics consists in suppressing the author
in the interests of writing (which is, as will be seen, to restore the
place of the reader) .... Linguistically, the author is never more
than the instance writing, just as I is nothing other than the instance
saying l: language knows a 'subject', not a 'person', and
this subject, empty outside of the very enunciation which defines
it, suffices to make language 'hold together', suffices, that is to
say, to exhaust it.
The removal of the Author (one could talk here with Brecht
of a veritable 'distancing', the Author diminishing like a figurine
at the far end of the literary stage) is not merely an historical
fact or an act of writing; it utterly transforms the modern text
(or -which is the same thing -the text is henceforth made and
read in such a way that at all its levels the author is absent). The
temporality is different. The Author, when believed in, is always
conceived of as the past of his own book: book and author stand
automatically on a single line divided into a before and an after.
The Author is thought to nourish the book, which is to say that he
exists before it, thinks, suffers, lives for it, is in the same relation
of antecedence to his work as a father to his child. In complete
contrast, the modern scriptor is born simultaneously with the
text, is in no way equipped with a being preceding or exceeding
the writing, is not the subject with the book as predicate; there
is no other time than that of the enunciation and every text
is eternally written here and now. The fact is (or, it follows)
that writing can no longer designate an operation of recording,
notation, representation, 'depiction' (as the Classics would say);
rather, it designates exactly what linguists, referring to Oxford
For instance, these three read this clause in Faulkner's 'A Rose
for Emily' describing Colonel Sartoris: 'he who fathered the edict
that no Negro woman should appear on the streets without an
apron.' Sandra adjusted the phrase to just the amount of strength
she could identify with ... Sebastian discovered an aristocratic,
sexualized master-slave relationship ... Saul, however, had to
reduce the force and cruelty of the original. ...
... Ego, id, superego, reality, and the compulsion to repeat all
exist as functions of identity. Hence, instead of structures, they
can be better understood as questions about a total transaction
by a self with an identity. One can ask, What in this transaction
looks like an integrating, synthesizing activity? What looks like an
incorporated parental voice? These questions will lead to a
picture of the whole person acting, rather than five 'agencies'.
The strong word and stance issue only from a strict will, a will
that dares the error of reading all of reality as a text, and all
prior texts as opening for its own totalizing and unique interpretations.
Strong poets present themselves as looking for truth in
the world, searching in reality and in tradition, but such a stance,
as Nietzsche said, remains under the mastery of desire, of instinctual
drives. So, in effect, the strong poet wants pleasure and
not truth: he wants what Nietzsche named as 'the belief in truth
and the pleasurable effects of this belief'. No strong poet can
admit that Nietzsche was accurate in this insight, and no critic
need fear that any strong poet will accept and so be hurt by
demystification....
... A strong poem does not formulate poetic facts any more than
strong reading or criticism formulates them, for a strong reading
is the only poetic fact, the only revenge against time that endures,
that is successful in canonizing one text as opposed to a rival text.
...To say that a poem's true subject is its repression of the precursor
poem is not to say that the later poem reduces to the
process of that repression. On a strict Freudian view, a good poem
is a sublimation, and not a repression. Like any work of substitution
that replaces the gratification of prohibited instincts, the
poem, as viewed by the Freudians, may contain antithetical effects
but not unintended or counterintended effects. In the Freudian
valorization of sublimation, the survival of those effects would be
flaws in the poem. But poems are actually stronger when their
counterintended effects battle most incessantly against their overt
intentions.
You will remember how Plato, in his project for a Republic, deals
with writers. In the interests of the community, he denies them
the right to dwell therein. Plato had a high opinion of the power
of literature. But he thought it harmful and superfluous -in a
perfect community, be it understood. Since Plato, the question of
the writer's right to exist has not often been raised with the same
emphasis; today, however, it arises once more. Of course it only
seldom arises in this form. But all of you are more or less conversant
with it in a different form, that of the question of the writer's
autonomy: his freedom to write just what he pleases. You are not
inclined to grant him this autonomy. You believe that the present
social situation forces him to decide in whose service he wishes to
place his activity. The bourgeois author of entertainment literature
does not acknowledge this choice. You prove to him that,
without admitting it, he is working in the service of certain class
interests. A progressive type of writer does acknowledge this
choice. His decision is made upon the basis of the class struggle:
he places himself on the side of the proletariat. And that's the
end of his autonomy. He directs his activity towards what will be
useful to the proletariat in the class struggle. This is usually called
pursuing a tendency, or 'commitment'....
... If, then, we were entitled earlier on to say that the correct
political tendency of a work includes its literary quality because it
includes its literary tendency, we can now affirm more precisely
that this literary tendency may consist in a progressive development
ofliterary technique, or in a regressive one....
... Here I should like to confine myself to pointing out the decisive
difference between merely supplying a production apparatus
and changing it. I should like to preface my remarks on the
New Objectivio/ with the proposition that to supply a production
apparatus without trying, within the limits of the possible, to
change it, is a highly disputable activity even when the material
supplied appears to be of a revolutionary nature. For we are confronted
with the fact -of which there has been no shortage of
proof in Germany over the last decade -that the bourgeois apparatus
of production and publication is capable of assimilating,
indeed of propagating, an astonishing amount of revolutionary
themes without ever seriously putting into question its own continued
existence or that of the class which owns it. In any case
this remains true so long as it is supplied by hacks, albeit
revolutionary
hacks. And I define a hack as a man who refuses as a
matter of principle to improve the production apparatus and so
prise it away from the ruling class for the benefit of Socialism. I
further maintain that an appreciable part of so-called left-wing
literature had no other social function than that of continually
extracting new effects or sensations from this situation for the
public's entertainment. Which brings me to the New Objectivity.
It launched the fashion for reportage. Let us ask ourselves whose
interests were advanced by this technique.
History, then, certainly 'enters' the text, not least the 'historical'
text; but it enters it precisely as ideology, as a presence determined
and distorted by its measurable absences. This is not to say
that real history is present in the text but in disguised form, so
that the task of the critic is then to wrench the mask from its face.
It is rather that history is 'present' in the text in the form <?f a
double-absence. The text takes as its object, not the real, but certain
significations by which the real lives itself -significations which
are themselves the product of its partial abolition. Within the text
itself, then, ideology becomes a dominant structure, determining
the character and disposition of certain 'pseudo-real' constituents.
This inversion, as it were, of the real historical process,
whereby in the text itself ideology seems to determine the historically
real rather than vice versa, is itself naturally determined in
the last instance by history itself. History, one might say, is the
ultimate
signifier of literature, as it is the ultimate signified. For what
else in the end could be the source and object of any signitying
practice but the real social formation which provides its material
matrix? The problem is not that such a claim is false, but that it
leaves everything exactly as it was. For the text presents itself to us
less as historical than as a sportive flight from history, a reversal
and resistance of history, a momentarily liberated zone in which
the exigencies of the real seem to evaporate, an enclave of
It is true that some texts seem to approach the real more closely
than others. The level of the 'textual real' in Bleak House is
considerably
more predominant than it is in, say, Burns's lyric, My love is
like a red, red rose. The former seeks to illuminate, among other
things, a highly localised history; the latter has an extremely
abstract referent. Yet whereas it is obvious that Burns's poem refers
us to certain modes of ideological signification rather than to a
'real' object, so that whether he had a lover at all is, of course,
entirely
irrelevant (and is intimated to be so by the poem's very form),
the same is true, if not so obviously, of Dickens's novel. It is simply
that Dickens deploys particular modes of signification (realism)
which entail a greater foregrounding of the 'pseudo-real'; but we
should not be led by this to make direct comparisons between the
imaginary London of his novel and the real London. The imaginary
London of Bleak House exists as the product of a representational
process which signifies, not 'Victorian England' as such,
but certain ofVictorian England's ways of signifYing itself. ...
TEXT ----s~gn~fier-sIgmfied
} signification
IDEOLOGY --signified
---------signifierI
HISTORY
...Ideology pre-exists the text; but the ideology of the text defines,
operates and constitutes that ideology in ways unpremeditated, so
to speak, by ideology itself. The particular production of ideology
which we may term the 'ideology of the text' has no pre-existence:
it is identical with the text itself. What is in question here, indeed,
is a double relation -not only the objectively determinable relation
between text and ideology, but also (and simultaneously)
that relation as 'subjectively' flaunted, concealed, intimated or
mystified by the text itself. ...
This is not to say that a text is not an object; the words can be
counted and catalogued, their definitions can be traced. But
such activity does not qualify as literary experience, nor does it
qualify as 'criticism'. It is only the organization of perceptual
data; it is counting, as distinct from naming. The major activities
in the history of literary study are acts of naming, that is, of
identifying values and making judgments of value. A judgment
of meaning is a special form of a valuejudgment, since it
depends on the selective perception of the judge, which in turn
is determined by the set of values which govern his life. These
values are forces whose behaviors are determined by the rules
of personality functioning and by the constraints of social
existence. They are, to be brief, subjective. If a literary text is to
be anything beyond a piece of 'sense data' it must come under
the control of a subjectivity; either an individual's subjectivity or
the collective subjectivity of a group. The only way a work of
literature has consequential meaning is as a function of the
mind of the reader. ...
With regard to the first area the view urges us to abandon the
critical attitude of Northrop Frye, who conceived his task as trying
to confer upon criticism the authority of the scientist ....
... For the author, the work ofliterature is a response to his life
experience. For the reader, the interpretation is the response to his
reading experience. This understanding of the literary transaction
creates a new scale of values for the serious study of literature and
literary experience. The personalities involved in the literary
transaction
are of primary importance; the properties of the work of art,
while necessary, are insufficient and of secondary importance....
Ultimately, I accept Frye's view that criticism is a 'science', in the
sense that it is the systematic study of aesthetic experience which
produces new knowledge. But it is a science that began almost at the
moment when the assumption of objectivity had proved no longer
adequate. Close examination of the aesthetic experience has shown
that the assumption in fact is not viable in our efforts to learn about
this experience. Instead, our recognition of the subjective character
of critical interpretation yields satisfying new understanding.
It seems then that the price one pays for denying the priority of
either forms or intentions is an inability to say how it is that one
ever begins. Yet we do begin, and we continue, and because we do
there arises an immediate counter-objection to the preceding
pages. If interpretive acts are the source of forms rather than the
other way around, why isn't it the case that readers are always
performing
the same acts or a random succession of forms? How, in
short, does one explain these two random successions of forms?
How, in short, does one explain these two 'facts' of reading?: (1)
the same reader will perform differently when reading two 'different'
(the word is in quotation marks because its status is precisely
what is at issue) texts; and (2) different readers will perform similarly
when reading the 'same' (in quotes for the same reason)
text. That is to say, both the stability of interpretation among
readers and the variety of interpretation in the career of a single
reader would seem to argue for the existence of something independent
of and prior to interpretive acts, something which produces
them. I will answer this challenge by asserting that both the
stability and the variety are functions of interpretive strategies
rather than of texts. '
The large conclusion that follows from these four smaller ones
is that the notions of the 'same' or 'different' texts are fictions. If!
read Lycidas and The Waste Land differently (in fact I do not), it
will not be because the formal structures of the two poems (to
term them such is also an interpretive decision) call forth different
interpretive strategies but because my predisposition to
execute different interpretive strategies will produce different
formal structures. That is, the two poems are different because I
have decided that they will be. The proof of this is the possibility
of doing the reverse (that is why point 2 is so important). That is
to say, the answer to the question 'why do different texts give rise
to different sequences of interpretive acts?' is that they don't have
to, an answer which implies strongly that 'they' don't exist. Indeed
it has always been possible to put into action interpretive strategies
designed to make all texts one, or to put it more accurately,
to be forever making the same text. Augustine urges just such a
strategy, for example, in On Christian Doctrine where he delivers
the 'rule of faith' which is of course a rule of interpretation. It is
dazzlingly simple: everything in the Scriptures, and indeed in the
world when it is properly read, points to (bears the meaning of)
God's love for us and our answering responsibility to love our
fellow creatures for His sake. If only you should come upon something
which does not at first seem to bear this meaning, that 'does
not literally pertain to virtuous behavior or to the truth of faith',
you are then to take it 'to be figurative' and proceed to scrutinize
it 'until an interpretation contributing to the reign of charity is
produced'. . .. Whatever one may think of this interpretive
program, its success and ease of execution are attested to by
centuries of Christian exegesis. It is my contention that any
interpretive program, any set of interpretive strategies, can have a
similar success, although few have been as spectacularly successful
as this one....
But why should this ever happen? Why should two or more
readers ever agree, and why should regular, that is, habitual,
Reception Theory and Reader-Response Criticism 207
spiritual material
spirit/soul body
virginal ideal sex object
Mary Eve
inspiration seductress
good evil
The real question is not whether a woman can identify with the
subjective consciousness or the self if it is male, but whether she
should, given her own political and social environment. In other
words, isn't it morally misleading to encourage a person who is
barred from action to identify with an individual whose dilemma
(in the case of Hamlet) is simply whether to act? Action, .taking
charge, is a choice that historically has been denied women and
still is unavailable to them in many areas. Until, however, ideological
socialization ceases, we as female readers cannot authentically
transcend our sex. Such literature as treated in this article must
remain alien. This does not mean that we should throw out or
refuse to read these works, but that they should be read with
perspective that recognizes the sexism inherent in their moral
VlSlOn....
Feminist criticism can be divided into two distinct varieties. The first
type is concerned with woman as reader -with woman as the consumer
of male-produced literature, and with the way in which the
hypothesis of a female reader changes our apprehension of a given
text, awakening us to the significance of its sexual codes. I shall call
this kind of analysis the feminist critique, and like other kinds of
critique it is a historically grounded inquiry which probes the
ideological
assumptions of literary phenomena. Its subjects include the
images and stereotypes of women in literature, the omissions and
misconceptions about women in criticism, and the fissures in
maleconstructed
literary history. It is also concerned with the exploitation
and manipulation of the female audience, especially in popular
culture and film; and with the analysis ofwoman-as-sign in semiotic
systems. The second type of feminist criticism is concerned with
woman as writer -with woman as the producer of textual meaning,
with the history, themes, genres and structures of literature by
women. Its subjects include the psychodynamics offemale creativity;
linguistics and the problem of a female language; the trajectory of
the individual or collective female literary career; literary history;
and, of course, studies of particular writers and works. No term
exists in English for such a specialised discourse, and so I have
adapted the French term la gynocritique: 'gynocritics' (although the
significance of the male pseudonym in the history of women's
writing also suggested the term 'georgics').
In the Female phase, ongoing since 1920, women reject both imitation
and protest -two forms ofdependency -and turn instead to
female experience as the source of an autonomous art, extending
the feminist analysis of culture to the forms and techniques of
literature. Representatives of the formal Female Aesthetic, such as
Dorothy Richardson and Virginia Woolf, begin to think in terms of
male and female sentences, and divide their work into 'masculine'
journalism and 'feminine' fictions, redefining and sexualising
external and internal experience....
Such errors are. avoidable if, while retaining the epochal hypothesis,
we can find terms which recognize not only 'stages' and 'variations'
but the internal dynamic relations of any actual process. We
have certainly still to speak of the 'dominant' and the 'effective',
and in these senses of the hegemonic. But we find that we have also
to speak, and indeed with further differentiation of each, of the
'residual' and the'emergent', which in any real process, and at any
moment in the process, are significant both in themselves and in
what they reveal of the characteristics of the 'dominant'.
We have argued that what a text means and what its author
intends it to mean are identical and that their identity robs intention
of any theoretical interest. A similar account of the relation
between meaning and intention has recently been advanced by
[a] rock' or 'a computer poem'), Juhl points out that there is
'something odd about interpreting [such a] "text.'" However one
might understand this text, one could not understand it as a
representation
of 'the meaning of a particular utterance.' We agree with
this -if it implies that the random marks mean nothing, are not
language, and therefore cannot be interpreted at all.... Our point
is that marks produced by chance are not words at all but only resemble
them. For Juhl, the marks remain words, but words detached
from the intentions that would make them utterances....
Juhl is right of course to claim that marks without intention are
not speech acts, since the essence of a speech act is its intentional
character. But we have demonstrated that marks without intention
are not language either. Only by failing to see that linguistic
meaning is always identical to expressed intention can Juhl
imagine language without speech acts. To recognize the identity
oflanguage and speech acts is to realize thatJuhl's prescription when
confronted with language, read it as a speech act -can
mean nothing more than: when confronted with language, read it
as language.
XIII POSTMODERNISM
From long before World War Two until the early 1970s, the main
tradition of comparative-literature studies in Europe and the
United States was heavily dominated by a style of scholarship that
has now almost disappeared. The main feature of this older style
was that it was scholarship principally, and not what we have come
to call criticism. No one today is trained as were Erich Auerbach
and Leo Spitzer, two of the great German comparatists who found
refuge in the United States as a result of fascism: this is as much a
quantitative as a qualitative fact ....
root with them. Mimesis, for example, written while Auerbach was
in exile from Nazi Europe in Istanbul, was not simply an exercise
in textual explication, but ... an act of civilizational survival. It had
seemed to him that his mission as a comparatist was to present,
perhaps for the last time, the complex evolution of European literature
in all its variety from Homer to Virginia Woolf. Curtius's
book on the Latin Middle Ages was composed out of the same
driven fear. ...
What to read and what to do with that reading, that is the full
form of the question. All the energies poured into critical theory,
into novel and demystifying theoretical praxes like the new historicism
and deconstruction and Marxism have avoided the
major, I would say determining, political horizon 0f modern
Western culture, namely imperialism. This massive avoidance has
sustained a canonical inclusion and exclusion: you include the
Rousseaus, the Nietzsches, the Wordsworths, the Dickenses,
Flauberts, and so on, and at the same time you exclude their
relationships
with the protracted, complex, and striated work of
empire. But why is this a matter of what to read and about where?
Very simply, because critical discourse has taken no cognizance
of the enormously exciting, varied post-colonial literature produced
in resistance to the imperialist expansion of Europe and
the United States in the past two centuries. To read Austen
without also reading Fanon and Cabral -and so on and on -is to
disaffiliate modern culture from its engagements and attachments.
That is a process that should be reversed.