CEDAW. A Holistic Approach To Womens Equality and Freedom
CEDAW. A Holistic Approach To Womens Equality and Freedom
CEDAW. A Holistic Approach To Womens Equality and Freedom
The abolition of gender norms … would be the abolition of gender and the
radical reformulation – perhaps beyond human recognition – of sexuality. But
their reform could begin to make it less true that our society constructs women
as inferior to men.2
1 Introduction
From its title, it appears that the overall object and purpose of the
Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against
Women (CEDAW, further: the Women’s Convention or the Convention)
is the elimination of all forms of discrimination against women. In this
chapter I will explain that this aim may be divided into three sub-aims: to
ensure full equality of women before the law; to improve the de facto posi-
tion of women; and to modify gender-based stereotypes. In turn, these
sub-aims relate to three possible political and legal methods to enhance
women’s equality and freedom: i.e. through (1) guaranteeing women’s
individual rights, (2) giving social support to women and (3) enhanc-
ing social and cultural change. Most of my attention will go to the third
sub-aim and the corresponding third method and to the provision on
which this sub-aim/method is based, that is to Article 5 CEDAW (further:
This chapter builds on various research projects and derives some texts from earlier publi-
cations that I have written in this area.
1
B. E. Herná ndez-Truyol, ‘Out of the shadows: traversing the imaginary of sameness, diffe-
rence, and relationalism – a human rights proposal ’, Wisconsin Women’s Law Journal 17
(2002) 111–62 at 145.
2
K. Anthony Appiah, ‘Stereotypes and the shaping of identity’, Californian Law Review
88:41 (2000) 41–53 at 52.
95
11
This expresses the fundamental value of the inherent equality of all human beings, which
forms the basis for the principle of formal equality in and before the law. Besides this,
the principle of substantive equality has also received recognition in international law.
In that principle, it is recognised that in fact all human beings are differently situated,
that is, they occupy different social, geographic, economic or other positions. At the core
of the principle of substantive equality is the recognition of these de facto differences,
and the idea of distributive justice, which requires that human beings should have equal
opportunities to make something of their lives.
12
H. Bielefeldt, ‘ “Western” versus “Islamic” human rights conceptions? a critique of cul-
tural essentialism in the discussion on human rights’, Political Theory 28:1 (2000) 90 –121
and M. Winston, ‘Human rights as moral rebellion and social construction’, Journal of
Human Rights 6 (2007) 279–305.
13
Although autonomy and freedom are most often interpreted in an individualistic way, it
must be remembered that human rights protection also includes the protection of family
life and national and cultural rights. The individual, in other words, can only become
a human person within the context of family, culture and nation. See R. Holtmaat and
J. Naber, Women’s Human Rights and Culture: From Deadlock to Dialogue (Antwerp:
Intersentia, 2011) at 96.
14
In Holtmaat and Naber, Women’s Human Rights and Culture and in R. Holtmaat,
‘Article 5’ in M. A. Freeman, C. Chinkin and B. Rudolf (eds.), The Convention on the
Elimination of all forms of Discrimination Against Women: A Commentary [hereinafter
CEDAW Commentary](Oxford University Press, 2012), I discuss the concepts of gender
stereotypes and fi xed parental gender roles (in relation to Article 5 of the CEDAW) in
more detail. See also R. J. Cook and S. Cusack, Gender Stereotyping: Transnational Legal
Perspectives (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2009), and Cusack, this vol-
ume. Men who do not conform to the culturally defi ned male gender role and identity
also encounter discrimination on the grounds of their gender. See, for example, D. S.
Cohen, ‘Keeping men “men” and women down: sex segregation, anti-essentialism and
masculinity’, Harvard Journal of Law and Gender 33 (2010) 509–53.
15
CEDAW Preamble, paras. 1–3.
16
See A. Byrnes, ‘Article 1’ in Freeman et al., CEDAW Commentary.
17
Winston, ‘Human rights as moral rebellion’.
18
The CEDAW defi nition is very different from the formal equal treatment defi nitions of
discrimination that are dominant in the context of (inter alia) European sex equality
law. See R. Holtmaat, ‘European women and the CEDAW Convention. The way forward’
in L’ égalité entre femmes et hommes et la vie profesionnelle. Le point sur les développe-
ments actuels en Europe (Paris: Dalloz , 2003) 153–74 and R. Holtmaat and C. Tobler,
‘CEDAW and the European Union’s policy in the field of combating gender discrimin-
ation’, Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law 12:4 (2005) 399–425.
19
See Winston, ‘Human rights as moral rebellion’, who states that one should keep in mind
that all human rights law is meant to put an end to the oppression of certain people or
groups of people by their government or by other people.
20
I. M. Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton University Press: 1990) 40ff.
21
See Article 2 and many of the substantive Articles of the Convention.
22
See in particular CEDAW General Recommendations 12 and 19.
23
This means that all laws and legal constructs must be subjected to an in-depth gender ana-
lysis. See R. Holtmaat, ‘The power of legal concepts: the development of a feminist theory
of law’, International Journal of the Sociology of Law 5 (1989) 481–502 and R. Holtmaat,
‘Gender, the Analytical Concept that Tackles the Hidden Structural Bias of Law’ in Recht
Richtung Frauen: Beitrage zur feministischen Rechtswisschenschaft (Lachen/St Gallen:
Dike Verlag 2001) 159–82 . A methodology for such an analysis has been developed in
R. Holtmaat, Towards Different Law and Public Policy: The Significance of Article 5a
CEDAW for the Elimination of Structural Gender Discrimination (Doetinchem: Reed
Business Information, 2004).
24
CEDAW Preamble, paras. 13 and 14.
25
Below in this chapter I will argue that a wide interpretation of Article 5 of the CEDAW
allows us to include men as well as intersexual and LGBT (lesbian, gay, bisexual and
transgender) people who suffer from gender stereotypes and strict masculinity codes,
under the protection against discrimination on the basis of this Convention.
26
Holtmaat, ‘European Women and the CEDAW Convention’, and Holtmaat and Tobler,
‘CEDAW and the European Union’s policy’.
27
K. Crenshaw, ‘Demarginalizing the intersection of race and sex, a black feminist critique
of antidiscrimination doctrine, feminist theory, and antiracist politics’, University of
Chicago Legal Forum (1989) 139–67.
Cohen, ‘Keeping men “men” and women down’ at 523, who distinguishes between ‘hege-
monic masculinity’ and ‘hegemony by men’. ‘Hegemonic masculinity … works to subor-
dinate both women and non-hegemonically masculine men. It subordinates women by
definition, as hegemonic masculinity is associated with characteristics that allow men to
subordinate women; it subordinates other men, non-hegemonically masculine men, by
labelling their expressions of personhood as inferior to “true” manhood.’
33
Sexual harassment very often being part of the culture at the workplace and on that
ground being presented as ‘normal’ behaviour. See for example, A. McKinnon and T. I.
Emerson, Sexual Harassment of Working Women: A Case of Discrimination (New Haven:
Yale University Press, 1979).
34
According to feminist critiques, thereby causing fi nancial and economic crises and
unsustainable economic development. See, for example, J. K. Gibson-Graham, The End
of Capitalism (As We Knew It): A Feminist Critique of Political Economy – 10 Years On
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2006).
35
See, for example, D. Alexander and K. Andersen, ‘Gender as a factor in the attribution of
leadership traits’, Political Research Quarterly 46 (1993) 527.
36
See H. Charlesworth and C. Chinkin, The Boundaries of International Law: A Feminist
Analysis (Manchester University Press, 2000) at 21 See also C. I. Nyamu, ‘How should
human rights and development respond to cultural legitimization of gender hierarchy
in developing countries?’, Harvard International Law Journal 41 (2000) 381–418 at 391.
Nyamu discusses the fact that attempts by human rights activists to fi nd a legal basis for
State responsibility for discrimination against women often fail because many (mainly
Islamic) States have made reservations to Articles 2 and 16 of the Convention.
37
See, for example, A. X. Felmeth, ‘Feminism and international law. Theory, method-
ology and substantive reform’, Human Rights Quarterly 22:3 (2000) 658 –733 at 710 and
H. Charlesworth, C. Chinkin and S. Wright, ‘Feminist approaches to international law’,
The American Journal of International Law (1991) 613–45 at 634.
38
Charlesworth and Chinkin, The Boundaries of International Law at 230.
39
Charlesworth et al., ‘Feminist approaches to international law’ at 631.
40
Ibid.
41
Charlesworth and Chinkin, The Boundaries of International Law at 229.
42
Charlesworth et al., ‘Feminist approaches to international law’ at 634.
43
See, for example, L. Lijnzaad, ‘Over rollenpatronen en de rol van het Verdrag’ in A. W.
Heringa, J. Hes and L. Lijnzaad (eds.), Het Vrouwenverdrag. Een beeld van een verdrag
(Antwerp/Apeldoorn: Maklu, 1994) 43–57 and N. Burrows, ‘The 1979 Convention on the
Elimination of all forms of Discrimination Against Women’, Netherlands International
Law Review (1985) 419–60. An extensive discussion of the literature up to 2004 may be
found in Holtmaat, Towards Different Law and Public Policy.
44
See, for example, S. E. Merry, ‘Gender justice and CEDAW: the Convention on the
Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women’, Journal of Women of the
Middle East and the Islamic World 9 (2011) 49–75 at 53 and 58, who argues, for exam-
ple, that the Convention focuses primarily on equalising women’s status with that of
men, and Rosenblum, ‘Unisex CEDAW’, who (inter alia) takes it that the Convention
50
See the CEDAW Committee’s General Recommendations 12, 19, 21 and 24.
51
See L. S. Groenman et al., Het vrouwenverdrag in Nederland anno 1997 (The Hague:
Ministerie van SZW, 1997). The Groenman Commission (named after its chair) was
installed by the Dutch government to write a report about the implementation of the
Convention in the Netherlands. The present author was a member of this Commission.
Their report was submitted to the Second Chamber of Parliament in 1998. A translation
in English of the main chapters of this report is included as an appendix in Holtmaat,
Towards Different Law and Public Policy. The Commission based itself on the historical
background and a textual analysis of the Convention, on the General Recommendations
and Concluding Comments of the Committee, and on the relevant legal literature up to
the year 1996.
52
This position was confirmed in the second and third Country Reports of the Netherlands
to the CEDAW Committee (submitted in 2000, discussed by the CEDAW Committee in
2001).
53
25th Session of the CEDAW Committee, July 2001, A/56/38, CEDAW/C/SR. 512 and 513,
para. 196.
54
CEDAW Committee, General Recommendation 25 on Article 4, para. 1, of the
Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women, on tem-
porary special measures (Thirteenth Session, 2004), paras. 6 and 7.
55
The Article is part of the first section of the Convention, which contains the general obli-
gations for the States Parties. These norms are to be regarded on their own merits, but
they are also indicative for the interpretation of all other Articles of the Convention.
56
See Holtmaat, ‘Article 5’ for a more extensive analysis of the content and scope of this
Article.
57
R. J. Cook, ‘State Accountability under the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms
of Discrimination Against Women’ in R. J. Cook (ed.), Human Rights of Women. National
and International Perspectives (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1994)
228–56, at 239–40.
58
CEDAW Committee, General Recommendation No. 25, para. 7. See also e.g. CEDAW
Committee, Luxembourg (2000), A/55/38, CEDAW/C/SR.446 and 447, para. 404.
71
Like the formal and substantive approach, which have been seen as competing inter-
pretations of (legal) equality by many feminist legal scholars. See Fredman, ‘Beyond the
Dichotomy of Formal and Substantive Equality’.
72
See for example, Groenman et al., Het vrouwenverdrag in Nederland anno 1997, and
Holtmaat, Towards Different Law and Public Policy.
73
See Holtmaat, ‘Preventing Violence Against Women’.
74
The ‘case law’ of the Committee on the issue of VAW has been analysed in great depth in
Chinkin’s contribution to the CEDAW Commentary.
75
Groenman et al., Het vrouwenverdrag in Nederland anno 1997; Holtmaat, Towards
Different Law and Public Policy ; Holtmaat and Tobler, ‘CEDAW and the European
Union’s policy’; and Cook and Cusack, Gender Stereotyping.
76
Fredman, ‘Beyond the Dichotomy of Formal and Substantive Equality’ at 116.
77
Cusack and Cook, ‘Combating Discrimination on Sex and Gender’ at 207. See also Cook
and Cusack, Gender Stereotyping at 5.
78
Fredman, ‘Beyond the Dichotomy of Formal and Substantive Equality’ at 116.
79
Van Maarseveen, ‘Internationaal vrouwenrecht’ at 75.
80
Ibid.; Groenman et al., Het vrouwenverdrag in Nederland anno 1997.
81
Groenman et al., Het vrouwenverdrag in Nederland anno 1997.
82
Ibid. at 27. After the publication of the Groenman report, the Dutch government ordered
a follow-up study in which the content and scope of Article 5(a) of the CEDAW was inves-
tigated in more depth. See Holtmaat, Towards Different Law and Public Policy.
83
Th is methodology is further developed in Holtmaat, Towards Different Law and Public
Policy, Chapters 15 and 16.
84
Groenman et al., Het vrouwenverdrag in Nederland anno 1997 at 27.
85
Ibid. Italics in original. See also Holtmaat, ‘The power of legal concepts’.
86
General Recommendation No. 25, para. 10.
87
The fact that the Preambles of the main Human Rights Covenants all mention equality
and dignity in one breath already indicates that equality is not the sole foundational prin-
ciple of human rights.
88
Gendered categories are often presented as ‘natural’, ‘essential’ or ‘God-given’, that is, as
eternal and unchangeable. I have discussed the role of gender-essentialism in Holtmaat
and Naber, Women’s Human Rights and Culture.
89
M. Nussbaum, Women and Human Development. The Capabilities Approach (Cambridge
University Press, 2000). See also Kang, ‘The burdens of manliness’ at 478, who argues
that guaranteeing the right to self-defi nition is the main objective of (USA) constitu-
tional equality clauses: ‘By the right to self defi nition, I mean the right not to be overly
dominated by government in how I structure and give meaning to my identity.’ The right
to be free from gender stereotypes, in that sense, should also stretch to men, according to
Kang.
For all women and men this ‘diversity principle’ is as important as the prin-
ciple of equality per se. But it is important first and foremost for women
and men who do not conform to dominant legal, social and cultural
standards about what it means to be a female or male person. Women’s
90
Cook and Cusack, Gender Stereotyping at 68.
91
CEDAW Committee, Concluding Observations: Suriname (2002), A/57/38 (part II),
CEDAW/C/SR. 557, 558 and 566, para. 48. See also CEDAW Committee, Concluding
Observations: Uzbekistan (2001), A/56/38, CEDAW/C/SR.500, 501 and 507, para. 169.
92
Lijnzaad, ‘Over rollenpatronen’ at 57.
93
Judgment in National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v. Ministry of Justice,
South African Supreme Court 1999 1 SA 6 (CC), para. 143, as quoted by E. Bonthuys and
C. Albertyn (eds.), Gender, Law and Justice (Cape Town: Juta, 2007) at 28.
94
See J. Butler, Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity, 1st edn (London/
New York : Routledge, 1990) at 1–34 and 110–28 and J. Butler, ‘Imitation and Gender
Subordination’ in D. Fuss (ed.), Inside/Out: Lesbian Theories, Gay Theories (New York :
Routledge, 1991) at 13. See A. M. Gross, ‘Sex, love, and marriage: questioning gender and
sexuality rights in international law’, Leiden Journal of International Law 21 (2008) 235 –
53. At 251, Gross summarises Butler’s position as follows: ‘the division in two genders as
part of the institution of compulsory heterosexuality, (which) requires a binary polarised
gender system since patriarchy and compulsory heterosexuality are only possible in a
world built on such a hierarchised division.’ Real liberation or emancipation of women
and gay and lesbian people, according to this author, requires ‘undoing gender’, instead
of accepting the thus pre-fi xed gender categories and identities (as either being male/
female or heterosexual/homosexual). Another way of expressing the same principle is
saying that a transformation of gender and sexuality needs to take place. See also Gross,
‘Sex, love, and marriage’ at 252.
95
Lesbian women being gang raped in order ‘to cure them’ from their outrageous ‘abnor-
mal’ sexual preference, is an example of this kind of ‘correction’. See for example, Report
of the UN Special Rapporteur on the question of torture and other cruel, inhuman or
degrading treatment or punishment, Commission on Human Rights, March 2006, UN
Doc. E/CN.4/2006/6/Add.1, paras. 180 and 183.
96
See text in footnotes 14 and 32.
97
That is, different from the heterosexual norm and other than the binary male–female
scheme.
98
Cook and Cusack, Gender Stereotyping at 2.
99
It is therefore not necessary to ‘unisex’ CEDAW, as is argued by Rosenblum in ‘Unisex
CEDAW’. Th is author does discuss Article 5 of the CEDAW, but does not give much
attention to its relevance for intersex and LGBT people.
100
In 2009 the Committee recognised that women may be discriminated against on the
grounds of their sexuality, thereby possibly including their homosexuality. However,
it seems to be hesitant to use that word or to use the word lesbianism. See, for exam-
ple, CEDAW Committee, Concluding Observations: Guatemala, CEDAW/C/GUA/
CO7 (2009) para. 19, where it speaks of sexuality in general. It has mentioned sexual
orientation and gender identity in CEDAW Committee, Concluding Observations:
Panama, CEDAW/C/PAN/CO/7 (2010) para. 22. In its General Recommendations on
older women (GR27) and on Article 2 (GR 28), adopted in October 2010, the CEDAW
Committee has explicitly mentioned sexual orientation and gender identity. See www.
iglhrc.org/cgi-bin/iowa/article/takeaction/resourcecenter/1235.html (last accessed 11
January 2012).
101
In the following, I will capture all of these phenomena under the word ‘culture’ or ‘cul-
tural’ (without the quotation marks).
102
See Holtmaat and Naber, Women’s Human Rights and Culture, Chapter 3 for the descrip-
tion of various stakeholders.
103
There is extensive international legal and academic debate about the ‘clash’ between
women’s human rights and the right to culture. See Holtmaat and Naber, Women’s
Human Rights and Culture, Chapter 3 para. 2.5. It is especially contested whether the
right to culture prevails over women’s human rights or vice versa.
104
UN Special Rapporteur on Violence Against Women (VAW), Report on ‘Intersections
between culture and violence against women’, 17 January 2007, UN Doc. A/HRC/4/34,
para. 68.
105
Quote by Farida Shaheed, Independent United Nations Expert in the field of Cultural
Rights, in her fi rst press Statement on 23 November 2009. See: www.ohchr.org/en/
NewsEvents/Pages/DisplayNews.aspx?NewsID=9619&LangID=e (last accessed 20 July
2010).
106
As becomes apparent from the work of Ann Hellum, State resistance to women’s
equality does not only come from the side of (religious) dictatorships in the South. See
Hellum’s chapter in this volume and A. Hellum, ‘The Global Equality Standard Meets
Norwegian Sameness’ in A. Hellum, S. Ali and A. Griffiths (eds.), From Transnational
Relations to Transnational Laws: Northern European Laws at the Crossroads (London:
Ashgate, 2010). An example of the ambivalent responses of States (and their organs) to
the CEDAW is given in Ali’s chapter in this volume.
107
Gross, ‘Sex, love and marriage’.
108
Most famous in this respect are two crucial symbols of cultural unity in France, consist-
ing of the positive symbolic images of two women: Jeanne D’Arc and ‘Marianne’.
109
L. Vollp, ‘Blaming culture for bad behaviour’, Yale Journal of the Humanities 12 (2000)
89–115 at 90.
114
CEDAW Committee, Concluding Observations: Ecuador, UN Doc.A/49/38, 13th
Session (1994) para. 524.
115
See C. Packer, Using Human Rights to Change Tradition (Antwerp/Oxford/New York :
Intersentia, 2002) at 15.
116
States Parties are obliged to implement international norms in good faith, and so on. See
Cook, ‘State Accountability under the CEDAW’ at 229ff. See also CEDAW Committee,
Concluding Observations: Portugal, CEDAW/C/PRT/CO/7 (2008) para. 29.
117
Herná ndez-Truyol, ‘Out of the shadows’148ff.
118
See the recommendations made by the CEDAW Committee in its Concluding
Observations, as cited below in notes 123 and 124.
119
For example, A. Shachar, Multicultural Jurisdictions: Cultural Differences and Women’s
Rights (Cambridge University Press, 2001); A. Phillips, Multiculturalism without Culture,
(Princeton University Press, 2007); Nyamu, ‘How should human rights and develop-
ment respond to cultural legitimization’; and A. A. An-Na’im, ‘Problems of Universal
Cultural Legitimacy’ in A. A. An-Na’im and Francis M. Deng (eds.), Human Rights in
Africa. Cross Cultural Perspectives (New York : Brookings Institution, 1990) 331–67.
120
Nyamu, ‘How should human rights and development respond to cultural legitimization’
at 393.
121
Currently, this strategy is attracting more and more political and scholarly attention in
all areas of legal pluralism or multilayered jurisdictions. See, for example, F. Fontanelli,
G. Martinico and P. Carrozza, Shaping Rule of Law Through Dialogue. International and
Supranational Experiences (Groningen: European Law Publishing, 2009).
122
CEDAW Committee, Concluding Observations: Nigeria, CEDAW/C/NGA/6 (2008)
para. 323.
123
CEDAW Committee, Concluding Observations: Nicaragua, CEDAW/C/NIC/CO/6
(2007) para. 12.
124
UN CESCR General Comment 21, 20 November 2009, UN DOC. E/C. 12/GC/21,
para. 11.
125
Here again I disagree with Merry (‘Gender justice and CEDAW’), who states that the
Convention and the Committee adhere to a static and essentialist view of culture and
also use culture to describe other worlds, not their own. For a more detailed discussion
on this issue, see Holtmaat and Naber, Women’s Human Rights and Culture at para. 3.1.
12 Concluding remarks
Th is chapter argues that the Women’s Convention contains a holistic
understanding of equality and that it includes the principle of freedom
or diversity. On this basis, the Convention aims at eliminating all forms
of discrimination against women by means of various strategies of legal,
social and cultural reform. Especially in the last part of the chapter, it
becomes clear that such reform meets with a lot of (often silent) resist-
ance, and sometimes even with a vehement call upon other values and
rights, such as the right to sustain and support cultures, traditions and
religions, however oppressive these may be for women. It is not enough
that Article 5 offers the legal legitimacy for the necessary changes in this
respect; it is also required that States Parties and other stakeholders find
the roads to broaden and strengthen the necessary cultural legitimisation
for the process of modifying gender stereotypes and fi xed parental gen-
der roles. Thanks to the existence of Article 5, the Women’s Convention
is a revolutionary instrument that addresses the root causes of discrimi-
nation against women. However, in order for this instrument to become
126
CEDAW Committee, Concluding Observations: Jordan (2007), CEDAW/C/EST/JOR/
CO/4, para. 20. See also CEDAW Committee, Concluding Observations: Mozambique
(2007), CEDAW/C/MOZ/CO/2, paras. 20 and 21 and CEDAW Committee, Concluding
Observations: Cook Islands (2007), CEDAW/C/COK/CO/1, para. 23. We found a simi-
lar consideration for the fi rst time in CEDAW Committee, Concluding Observations:
Angola (2004), A/59/38/CEDAW/C/SR. 655 and 661, para. 147. Th e Committee
in its earlier days at some points went rather far in suggesting that a particular cul-
ture or religious practice or conviction can and should be changed. See, for exam-
ple, CEDAW Committee, Concluding Observations: Libyan Arab Jamahiriya (1974),
A/49/38, CEDAW/C/SR.237 and 240, para. 130 and CEDAW Committee, Concluding
Observations: Pakistan (2007), CEDAW/C/PAK/CO/3, para. 29. In the latter
Concluding Observation the Committee ‘calls on the State party to take prompt action
to counteract the influence of non-State actors, which, through the misinterpretation
of Islam and the use of intimidation and violence, are undermining the enjoyment by
women and girls of their human rights’.