Whomens Humans Rights.
Whomens Humans Rights.
Whomens Humans Rights.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
Yale University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Wollstonecraft, Mill, and Women's Human Rights
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
WOMENS HUMAN RIGHTS AS INTEGRAL
TO UNIVERSAL HUMAN RIGHTS
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
nism was a negative yet apt epithet for the tradition, as exemplified
by Wollstonecrafts Rights of Woman. From both the right and the
left, the pejorative use of the term liberal feminist neatly captured
the despised individualistic, rationalistic, and bourgeois aspects of
Wollstonecrafts and Mills political thought.13
Such critiques have assumed, however, that Wollstonecraft, Mill,
and their followers are primarily liberals and secondarily femi-
nists. Paying attention to their defining contributions to the idea of
womens human rights allows us to develop a counterinterpretation of
their legacies for feminism today. Wollstonecraft and Mill exercised
a critical style of feminist inquiry into the value of liberal ideas for
women, which ultimately put feminism first and liberalism second.
Liberalism had to meet certain feminist standards of justicesuch
as the actual guarantee of equal human rights for the sexesin order
to realize its own basic moral principles. In Nussbaums formulation,
these liberal principles could be stated most generally as (1) recog-
nizing the equal dignity of persons, (2) respecting the power of
moral choice within each person, and (3) ensuring the consequent
right of each person to fair treatment by society at large. Nussbaum
further argued that feminist criticism had the potential to transform
liberalism in a way that made it more deeply consistent with its own
most foundational ideas.14
Fundamentally, I also share Okins feminist liberal conception of
the integral place of womens rights within a universal and egalitar-
ian conception of human rights. As Okin wrote in 1998, five years
after the Vienna Declaration, The male bias of human rights think-
ing and its priorities had to change in order for womens rights to
be fully recognized as human rights. By male bias, she meant the
historic tendency for male-dominated societies to perpetuate legal
and cultural norms that discriminate in favor of men against women.
Similarly to Mill in chapter 1 of his Subjection of Women, she acknowl-
edged the practical necessity of confronting the fact of male bias in
public opinion about womens rights. As Mill conceded in the open-
ing pages of his argument, I am willing to accept the unfavorable
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
10
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
11
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
12
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
13
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
14
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
15
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
16
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
17
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
18
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
19
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
20
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
21
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
would make men and society happier, Wollstonecraft and Mill rein-
forced the prevalent gender stereotype of women as passive or self-
less servants of their fathers, husbands, and children. Ironically, their
consequentialist arguments for the public benefits of UPE did not
escape gender bias so much as perpetuate it, despite their philosophi-
cal intentions to the contrary. To avoid such a pernicious feedback
loop, reformers ought to balance or even counteract appeals to the
public utility of UPE with regular reminders of its intrinsic value for
individual girls and women.
Chapter 4 confronts the place of Western prejudices within Woll-
stonecrafts and Mills narratives of womens progress. Despite their
repeated defenses of a common human nature that united the sexes,
Wollstonecraft and Mill in their adaptations of Enlightenment phi-
losophies of history made their theories of womens human rights
less universalistic because of their Eurocentric biases. Following
philosophers such as Voltaire and Adam Smith, Wollstonecraft
and Mill assumed a Western European model of human economic
and cultural development. Like Lord Kames and Antoine-Leonard
Thomas, they condemned the low status of women in non-Western,
non-Christian cultures and argued for the advancement of women
based on such prejudiced Eurocentric comparisons with supposedly
backward Muslims and Hindus. Although Wollstonecraft and Mill
put strong feminist twists on these Western Eurocentric theories of
human progress, they did not escape their cultural biases.27
The critical examination of the place of cultural bias in their polit-
ical theories leads us to a more general ethical question: May one ad-
vocate a global standard of human rights without an imperial mind-
set that imposes ones own cultural biases upon others? Through an
international genealogy of the reception of Wollstonecraft and Mill
in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, I reveal that some
of their earliest interlocutors also faced the problem of cultural bias.
Some replicated an Orientalist idiom for feminism and liberalism,
while others confronted, challenged, and ultimately subverted this
trend. Three nineteenth-century nonWestern European feminist
liberalsMaria Tsebrikova of Russia, Martina Barros Borgoo of
22
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
23
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
24
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION
25
This content downloaded from 69.140.153.215 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 03:05:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms