An Introduction To Global Health Ethics
An Introduction To Global Health Ethics
An Introduction To Global Health Ethics
Ross E.G. Upshur is former Director of the University of Toronto Joint Centre
for Bioethics, and a staff physician at Sunnybrook Health Sciences Centre. He is
the Canada Research Chair in Primary Care Research and, at the University of
Toronto, he is a Professor at the Department of Family and Community
Medicine and Dalla Lana School of Public Health, Adjunct Scientist at the
Institute of Clinical Evaluative Sciences, an affiliate of the Institute of the
History and Philosophy of Science and Technology, and a member of the Centre
for Environment.
To Kim, Olivia and Sara with great love for making all
things possible.
– Ross Upshur
Edited by
Andrew D. Pinto
Department of Family and Community Medicine, St. Michael's Hospital,
University of Toronto
Centre for Research on Inner City Health, Li Ka Shing Knowledge Institute, St.
Michael's Hospital
Ross E.G. Upshur
Department of Family and Community Medicine, Sunnybrook Health Sciences
Centre, University of Toronto
Dalla Lana School of Public Health, University of Toronto
Canada Research Chair in Primary Care Research
First published 2013
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
© 2013 selection and editorial material, Andrew D. Pinto and Ross E.G.
Upshur; individual chapters, the contributors
Typeset in Sabon
by Saxon Graphics Ltd, Derby
Contents
List of contributors
Foreword
James Orbinski
PART I: THEORY
A) Introduction
B) Historical roots of global health
C) Global health today
D) Political economy of health
E) Global health ethics and its values
F) Conclusion
A) Introduction
B) Ethical concepts and ethical reasoning
C) Ethical theory and applied ethics
D) Key dimensions of global health ethics
E) Social justice and global health
F) Solidarity and global health
G) Conclusion
A) Introduction
B) The global health learning cycle
C) Conclusion
A) Introduction
B) The right to health
C) Human rights and global health
D) How global health ethics advances human rights
E) How human rights advances global health ethics
F) Conclusion
A) Introduction
B) Genesis of global health governance
C) World Health Organization
D) Zoonoses infection control governance
E) Pandemic management: infection control governance strategies
F) Ethical, human rights and social implications of public health containment
strategies
G) Confinement and social factors
H) Conclusion
A) Introduction
B) The health of Indigenous people globally
C) Colonization and resistance
D) “Decolonizing methodologies”
E) Ethical principles from research involving Indigenous communities
F) Conclusion
A) Introduction
B) Historical background to the ethical oversight of research
C) Principles of research ethics
D) Contextual considerations in research in LMICs
E) A checklist for researchers
F) Conclusion
A) Introduction
B) Benefits of partnerships
C) Challenges of pa
D) Principles for conducting partnerships
E) Conclusion
A) Introduction
B) Guidelines for international collaborations
C) Recommendations
A) Introduction
B) A framework for global health advocacy
C) How students have supported global advocacy to increase access to
antiretroviral therapy
D) Conclusions
Afterword
Solomon Benatar
Index
Contributors
Kaosar Afsana
Health Programme, BRAC, Dhaka, Bangladesh
James P. Grant School of Public Health, BRAC University, Dhaka, Bangladesh
Kelly Anderson
Department of Family and Community Medicine, St. Michael's Hospital,
University of Toronto, Toronto, Canada
Neil Arya
Office of Global Health, Schulich School of Medicine & Dentistry, University of
Western Ontario, London, Canada
Environment and Resource Studies University of Waterloo, Waterloo, Canada
Department of Family Medicine, McMaster University, Hamilton, Canada
Abraham Aseffa
Armauer Hansen Research Institute, Addis Ababa, Ethiopia
Solomon Benatar
Bioethics Centre, Faculty of Health Sciences, University of Cape Town, Cape
Town, South Africa Joint Centre for Bioethics & Dalla Lana School of Public
Health, University of Toronto, Toronto, Canada
Anne-Emanuelle Birn
Social and Behavioural Health Sciences and Global Health Divisions, Dalla
Lana School of Public Health, University of Toronto, Toronto, Canada
Centre for Critical Development Studies, University of Toronto-Scarborough,
Toronto, Canada
Adrienne K. Chan
Division of Infectious Diseases and Institute of Health Policy, Management &
Evaluation, Department of Medicine, University of Toronto, Toronto, Canada
Dignitas International, Toronto, Canada
Global Health Division, Dalla Lana School of Public Health, University of
Toronto, Toronto, Canada
Donald C. Cole
Global Health Division, Dalla Lana School of Public Health, University of
Toronto, Toronto, Canada
Nathan Ford
Médecins Sans Frontières, Cape Town, South Africa
Centre for Infectious Disease Epidemiology and Research, University of Cape
Town, Cape Town, South Africa
Lisa Forman
Global Health Division, Dalla Lana School of Public Health, University of
Toronto, Toronto, Canada Munk School of Global Affairs, University of
Toronto, Toronto, Canada
Demissie Habte
Ethiopian Academy of Sciences, Addis Ababa, Ethiopia
Lori Hanson
Department of Community Health and Epidemiology, College of Medicine,
University of Saskatchewan, Saskatoon, Canada
Jennifer Hatfield
Global Health & International Partnerships, Department of Community Health
Sciences, O'Brien Centre for the Bachelor of Health Sciences, Faculty of
Medicine, University of Calgary, Canada
Ghaiath Hussein
Department of Medical Ethics, Faculty of Medicine, King Fahad Medical City,
Saudi Arabia
Athanase Kiromera
Department of Family and Community Medicine, University of Toronto,
Toronto, Canada
Anant Kumar
Xavier Institute of Social Service, Ranchi, India
Maria de Lourdes Larrea
Universidad Andina Simon Bolivar, Quito, Ecuador
Victor A. López
Trauma and Global Health Program, Universidad de San Carlos de Guatemala,
Guatemala City, Guatemala Centro Integral del INCAP para la Prevención de las
Enfermedades Crónicas, Guatemala City, Guatemala
Sarah Marsh
School of Nursing, University of Texas at Austin, Austin, United States of
America
Jill Murphy
Faculty of Health Sciences, Simon Fraser University, Vancouver, Canada
Victor R. Neufeld
Canadian Coalition for Global Health Research, Ottawa, Canada
Stephanie Nixon
Department of Physical Therapy, Faculty of Medicine, University of Toronto,
Toronto, Canada
Global Health Division, Dalla Lana School of Public Health, University of
Toronto, Toronto, Canada
Director, International Centre for Disability and Rehabilitation, University of
Toronto, Toronto, Canada
James Orbinski
Balsillie School of International Affairs, Wilfrid Laurier University, Waterloo,
Canada
Jane Philpott
Department of Family and Community Medicine, University of Toronto,
Toronto, Canada
Department of Family Medicine, Markham Stouffville Hospital, Markham,
Canada
Andrew D. Pinto
Department of Family and Community Medicine, St. Michael's Hospital,
Toronto, Canada
Centre for Research on Inner City Health, Keenan Research Centre, Li Ka Shing
Knowledge Institute,
St. Michael's Hospital, Toronto, Canada
Kevin Pottie
Centre for Global Health, Institute of Population Health and Bruyere Research
Institute, Departments of Family Medicine and Epidemiology and Community
Medicine, Faculty of Medicine, University of Ottawa, Ottawa, Canada
Katherine D. Rouleau
Global Health Program, Department of Family and Community Medicine,
University of Toronto, Toronto, Canada
Department of Family and Community Medicine, St. Michael's Hospital,
Toronto, Canada
Ana Sanchez
Department of Community Health Sciences, Faculty of Applied Health Sciences,
Brock University, St Catharines, Canada
Malika Sharma
Department of Infectious Diseases, Division of Medicine, University of Toronto,
Toronto, Canada
Janet K. Smylie
Centre for Research on Inner City Health, Keenan Research Centre, Li Ka Shing
Knowledge Institute, St. Michael's Hospital, Toronto, Canada
Department of Family and Community Medicine, St. Michael's Hospital,
Toronto, Canada Dalla Lana School of Public Health, University of Toronto,
Toronto, Canada
References
Rasanathan, K. and Krech, R. (2011) ‘Action on social determinations of health
is essential to tackle noncommunicable diseases’, Bulletin of the World Health
Organization, 89: 775-76. doi: 10.2471/BLT.11.094243
WHO (2008) Closing the Gap in a Generation: Health Equity through Action on
the Social Determinants of Health. Final Report of the Commission on the
Social Determinants of Health. Geneva: World Health Organization.
PART I
Theory
The context of global health
1
ethics
Andrew D. Pinto, Anne-Emanuelle Birn and Ross E.G.
Upshur
Objectives
To present a historical perspective on global health, using a political
economy framework
To discuss past and current definitions of global international health and
relate this discussion to ethics
To develop a rationale for global health ethics
A) Introduction
We live in a radically unequal world in terms of both health and its underlying
determinants. Even the most cursory review of the available data makes this
evident. On average, a person born in 2010 in Afghanistan, Chad or the Central
African Republic can expect to live to approximately 48 years, whereas the
average life expectancy is 80 years in the Republic of Korea, 82 in Iceland, and
83 in Japan (WHO 2011a). Globally, in 2009, approximately 8.1 million
children died before their fifth birthday, deaths occurring almost exclusively in
low- and middle-income countries (LMIC) (WHO 2011b). The vast majority of
these are preventable deaths due to diarrhea, pneumonia and malaria (Jones et al.
2003). It is estimated that in 2008, 358,000 women died in childbirth, with 99
per cent occurring in LMIC. This has remained consistent ‘year after year’ and
again, these deaths were/are almost entirely preventable through existing
knowledge, health services and interventions to improve living conditions
(Campbell et al. 2006).
Stark as these figures are, national averages hide within-country differences
that are even more striking. Evidence cited in the Final Report of the
Commission on the Social Determinants of Health (WHO 2008) demonstrates
that the health of individuals and communities is intricately tied to social factors.
These include income, class, education level, employment relations and
race/ethnicity (Public Health Agency of Canada 2004).To take just one
determinant, in every country, the poor fare worse than the wealthy. In Scotland,
there is a gap of over ten years in healthy life expectancy – years spent in good
health – between residents of the most deprived and least deprived
neighbourhoods (Wood et al. 2006). Similarly, the maternal mortality rate is
three to four times higher among the poor compared with the rich in Indonesia
(Graham et al. 2004), and in Peru infant mortality is almost five times higher in
the poorest quintile of the population compared with the wealthiest (Gwatkin et
al. 2007). Across the world, certain racial and ethnic groups fare worse than
others living in the same country. In an oft-cited example, African-American
men in Harlem, New York were found to be less likely to reach the age of 65
than the average man in Bangladesh (McCord and Freeman 1990). Indigenous
peoples, referring to communities that share a historic link with pre-colonial
societies, have lower life expectancies than their non-indigenous counterparts in
every country where this has been studied (see Chapter 6). For example,
Indigenous Australian men have a life expectancy at birth of 59 years, compared
with 77 years for all Australian men (Australian Government 2009). In Canada,
Aboriginal men live on average eight years less than the male population as a
whole (Anderson et al. 2006). Such disparities between rich and poor nations,
and between privileged elites and marginalized populations within each country,
are expected to worsen with the negative effects of climate change (Costello et
al. 2009) – which is likely to affect LMIC disproportionately – and by the fallout
of the 2008 global financial crisis (Catalano et al. 2011; Stuckler et al. 2011).
None of these realities is new or surprising to health professionals, academics
and policy-makers who are interested in global health. As never before, we have
available an abundance of knowledge about such deplorable health inequities, a
term referring to the differences in levels of health between groups in a society
that are unjust, unfair and avoidable (Whitehead 1992; Starfield 2006). Further,
tackling such health inequities has risen on the political agenda. In October
2011, representatives from 125 governments met at the World Conference on
Social Determinants of Health in Rio de Janeiro, Brazil. The text of the
conference's Political Declaration contains statements such as ‘we need to do
more to accelerate progress in addressing the unequal distribution of health
resources as well as conditions damaging to health at all levels’ (WHO 2011c:
2). Addressing social inequity is even entering the conversation at the 2012
World Economic Forum, where typically the focus is on economic growth and
competitiveness (WEF 2012).
Given the evidence that significant, remediable differences in health exist
globally, and that there is a stated goal to address them, what is being done?
Clearly not enough: inequities in health have persisted – and even increased –
despite enormous resources being channelled into reducing them, despite a rich
body of evidence on effective measures, and despite strongly worded statements
by international bodies that these efforts should be a top priority (WHO 2008).
This book aims to help you explore why this is the case and what can and
should be done. Changing the systems that result in unnecessary death and
suffering is a key goal of global health practitioners. Here we hope to move the
reader from an intuitive sense that something is wrong to a deeper understanding
of how power, access to resources, justice and fairness apply to health –
questions with which global health ethicists are wrestling in an ongoing manner.
This chapter begins by reflecting on what is meant by global health and how the
field and its precursors have evolved over time: before solutions can be proposed
to address inequities, it is essential to understand in what context they have
arisen. Recognizing that there is a multitude of ways to address a problem, we
then argue that ethical perspectives can contribute towards formulating
responses – in terms of both avoiding doing harm and actually improving global
health inequities. Finally, we highlight what the remaining chapters will cover as
an entrée to engaging in global health ethics.
global health is an area for study, research, and practice that places a priority
on improving health and achieving equity in health for all people worldwide.
Global health emphasises transnational health issues, determinants, and
solutions; involves many disciplines within and beyond the health sciences
and promotes interdisciplinary collaboration; and is a synthesis of population
based prevention with individual-level clinical care.
(Koplan et al. 2009: 1995)
F) Conclusion
To summarize, global health is an emerging discipline that traces its origins,
norms and organizational structure to tropical and colonial medicine and
international health, making it highly problematic in that it continues to
reproduce the asymmetries of power extant in its predecessors. Notwithstanding
its enormous growth, global health remains a contested arena. Ethical analysis
creates a space for reflection and deliberation about issues such as social justice,
fairness, our professional duties and the duties of others. It is about asking why,
interrogating power relations and bringing a critical perspective to all such work.
Such analysis must be grounded in the lives of individuals and communities, lest
it become an abstract intellectual exercise that does not truly inform global
health action (Benatar and Upshur 2011). We believe that global health ethics
can assist you in becoming a better practitioner, academic and educator, and that
it is crucial to achieving the goal of collectively improving health for all.
References
Anderson, M. et al. (2006) First Nations, Métis, and Inuit health indicators in
Canada. Background paper for the project ‘Action oriented indicators of
health and health systems development for Indigenous peoples in Australia,
Canada, and New Zealand’.
Arnold, D. (1997) ‘The place of “the tropics” in Western medical ideas since
1750’, Tropical Medicine and International Health, 2(4): 303–13.
Australian Government (2009) Closing the Gap on Indigenous Disadvantage:
The Challenge for Australia. Canberra: Australian Government.
Benatar, S. and Upshur, R.E.G. (2011) ‘What is global health?’, in: Benatar, S.
and Brock, G. (eds), Global Health and Global Health Ethics. Cambridge &
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Berlinguer, G. (1992) ‘The interchange of disease and health between the Old
and New Worlds’, American Journal of Public Health, 82(1): 1407–13.
Birn, A.-E. (2006) Marriage of Convenience: Rockefeller International Health
and Revolutionary Mexico. Rochester: University of Rochester Press.
— (2009) ‘Making it politic(al): Closing the Gap in a Generation: Health
Equity through Action on the Social Determinants of Health’, Social
Medicine, 4(3): 166–82.
— (2011) ‘Remaking international health: refreshing perspectives from Latin
America’, Pan American Journal of Public Health, 30(2): 106–10.
Birn, A.-E., Pillay, Y. and Holtz, T.H. (2009) Textbook of International Health:
Global Health in a Dynamic World, 3rd edn. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Borowy, I. (2009) Coming to Terms with World Health: The League of Nations
Health Organisation 1921–1946. Frankfurt: Peter Lang-International
Academic Publishers.
Bozorgmehr, K. (2010) ‘Rethinking the “global” in global health: a dialectic
approach’, Globalization and Health, 6(19).
Brown, T.M., Cueto, M. and Fee, E. (2006) ‘The World Health Organization and
the transition from “international” to “global” public health’, American
Journal of Public Health, 96(1): 62–72.
Bynum, W. (1993) ‘Policing hearts of darkness: aspects of the International
Sanitary Conferences’, History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 15(3):
421–34.
Campbell, O., Graham, W.J. and Lancet Maternal Survival Series Steering
Group (2006) ‘Strategies for reducing maternal mortality: getting on with
what works’, Lancet, 368(9543): 1284–99.
Catalano, R., Goldman-Mellor, S., Saxton, K., Margerison-Zilko, C.,
Subbaraman, M., LeWinn, K. and Anderson, E. (2011) ‘The health effects of
economic decline’, Annual Review of Public Health, 32: 431–50.
Costello, A., Abbas, M., Allen, A., Ball, S., Bell, S., Bellamy, R. et al. (2009)
‘Managing the effects of climate change’, Lancet, 373(9676): 1693–1733.
Crane, J. (2011) ‘Scrambling for Africa? Universities and global health’, Lancet,
377(9775): 1388–90.
Crump, J.A., Sugarman, J. and Working Group on Ethics Guidelines for Global
Health Training (WEIGHT) (2010) ‘Ethics and best practice guidelines for
training experiences in global health’, American Journal of Tropical Medicine
and Hygiene, 83(6): 1178–82.
Cueto, M. (ed.) (1994) Missionaries of Science: The Rockefeller Foundation and
Latin America. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
DeCamp, M. (2011) ‘Ethical review of global short-term medical volunteerism’,
HEC Forum, 23(2), 91–103.
De Cock, K.M., Lucas, S.B., Mabey, D. and Parry, E. (1995) ‘Tropical medicine
for the 21st century’, British Medical Journal, 311(7009): 860–62.
Farmer, P., Drobac, P. and Agoos, Z. (2009) ‘Colonial roots of global health:
lessons learned for modern humanitarian health’, Harvard College Global
Health Review, 19 September.
Fried, L.P., Bentley, M.E., Buekens, P., Burke, D.S., Frenk, J.J., Klag, M.J. et al.
(2010) ‘Global health is public health’, Lancet, 375: 535–37.
Gow, J. (2002) ‘The HIV/AIDS epidemic in Africa: implications for U.S.
policy’, Health Affairs, 21(3): 57–69.
Graham, W.J., Fitzmaurice, A.E., Bell, J.S. and Cairns, J.A. (2004) ‘The familial
technique for linking maternal death with poverty’, Lancet, 363(9402): 23–7.
Gwatkin, D.R., Rutstein, S., Johnson, K., Suliman, E., Wagstaff, A. and
Amouzou, A. (2007) Socio-economic Differences in Health, Nutrition and
Population within Developing Countries: An Overview. Washington, DC:
World Bank.
Harrison, M. (2006) ‘Disease, diplomacy and international commerce: the
origins of international sanitary regulation in the nineteenth century’, Journal
of Global History, 1: 197–217.
Hutchison, J.F. (1996) Champions of Charity: War and the Rise of the Red
Cross. Boulder: Westview Press.
Institute of Medicine (1997) America's Vital Interest in Global Health:
Protecting our People, Enhancing our Economy, and Advancing our
International Interests. Washington, DC: National Academy of Sciences.
— (2009) The U.S. Commitment to Global Health: Recommendations for the
Public and Private Sectors. Washington, DC: National Academies Press.
Jones, G., Steketee, R.W., Black, R.E., Bhutta, Z.A., Morris, S.S. and the
Bellagio Child Survival Study Group (2003) ‘How many child deaths can we
prevent this year?’, Lancet, 362(9377): 65–71.
Kickbusch, I. (2002) ‘Influence and opportunity: reflections on the US role in
global public health’, Health Affairs, 21: 131–41.
Koplan, J.P., Bond, T.C., Merson, M.H., Reddy, K.S., Rodriguez, M.H.,
Sewankambo, N.K. and Wasserheit, J.N. (2009) ‘Towards a common
definition of global health’, Lancet, 373(9679): 1993–95.
Labonté, R., Mohindra, K. and Schrecker, T. (2011) ‘The growing impact of
globalization for health and public health practice’, Annual Review of Public
Health, 32: 263–83.
Larson, C.P., Haddad, S., Birn, A.-E., Cole, D.C., Labonté, R., Roberts, J.H. et
al. (2011) ‘Grand Challenges Canada: inappropriate emphasis and missed
opportunities in global health research?’, Canadian Journal of Public Health,
102(2): 149–51.
Macfarlane, S.B., Jacobs, M. and Kaaya, E.E. (2008) ‘In the name of global
health: trends in academic institutions’, Journal of Public Health Policy,
29(4): 383–401.
MacLean, S.J. and MacLean, D.R. (2009) ‘A “new scramble for Africa”: the
struggle in sub-Saharan Africa to set the terms of global health’, The Round
Table: The Commonwealth Journal of International Affairs, 98(402): 361–71.
MacLeod, R. and Lewis, M. (eds) (1998) Disease, Medicine and Empire:
Perspectives on Western Medicine and the Experience of European
Expansion. London: Routledge.
McCord, C. and Freeman, H.P. (1990) ‘Excess mortality in Harlem’, New
England Journal of Medicine, 322: 173–77.
McCoy, D., Chand, S. and Sridhar, D. (2009) ‘Global health funding: how much,
where it comes from and where it goes’, Health Policy and Planning, 24:
407–17.
Navarro, V. (ed.) (1981) Imperialism, Health and Medicine, Amityville, NY:
Baywood.
Ollila, E. (2005) ‘Global health priorities – priorities of the wealthy?’,
Globalization and Health, 1(6).
Packard, R.M. (1997) ‘Malaria dreams: postwar visions of health and
development in the third world’, Medical Anthropology: Cross-Cultural
Studies in Health and Illness, 17(3): 279–96.
Pinto, A.D. and Upshur, R.E.G. (2009) ‘Global health ethics for students’,
Developing World Bioethics, 9(1): 1–10.
Public Health Agency of Canada (2004) The Social Determinants of Health: An
Overview of the Implications for Policy and the Role of the Health Sector.
Ottawa: Public Health Agency of Canada.
Said, E.W. (1979) Orientalism. New York: 1st Vintage Books.
Schwartz, L., Sinding, C., Hunt, M., Elit, L., Redwood-Campbell, L., Adelson,
N. et al. (2010) ‘Ethics in conditions of disaster and deprivation: learning from
health workers’ narratives’, American Journal of Bioethics – Primary
Research, 1(3), 45–54.
Starfield, B. (2006) ‘State of the art in research on equity in health’, Journal of
Health Politics, Policy and Law, 31(1): 11–32.
Stuckler, D., Basu, S., Suhrcke, M., Coutts, A. and McKee, M. (2011) ‘Effects
of the 2008 recession on health: a first look at European data’, Lancet,
378(9786): 124–25.
Walt, G. (1993) ‘WHO under stress: implications for health policy’, Health
Policy, 24(2): 125–44.
Whitehead, M. (1992) ‘The concepts and principles of equity and health’,
International Journal of Health Services, 22(3): 429–45.
Wood, R., Sutton, M., Clark, D., McKeon, A. and Bain, M. (2006) ‘Measuring
inequalities in health: the case for healthy life expectancy’, Journal of
Epidemiology and Community Health, 60: 1089–92.
WEF (2012) ‘World Economic Forum Annual Meeting 2012, Davos-Klosters,
Switzerland, 25–29 January’. World Economic Forum.
www.weforum.org/events/world-economic-forum-annual- meeting-2012
WHO (2008) Closing the Gap in a Generation: Health Equity through Action on
the Social Determinants of Health. Final Report of the Commission on Social
Determinants of Health. Geneva: World Health Organization.
— (2011a) World Health Statistics 2011. Geneva: World Health Organization.
— (2011b) ‘Millennium Development Goals: Progress towards the Health-
related Millennium Development Goals’. Geneva: World Health
Organization. www.who.int/mediacentre/factsheets/fs290/en/index.html
— (2011c) ‘Rio Political Declaration on Social Determinants of Health’, in:
World Conference on Social Determinants of Health, 19–21 October 2011.
Geneva: World Health Organization.
— (2012) ‘Commission on Macroeconomics and Health (CMH)’. Geneva:
World Health Organization.
www.who.int/trade/glossary/story008/en/index.html
Ethics and global health
2 Ross E.G. Upshur, Solomon Benatar and Andrew D.
Pinto
Objectives
To introduce the range of ethical concepts and approaches to ethical
analysis required in global health work
To outline frameworks of principles that have been applied within
clinical medicine, public health and global health
To develop the concepts of solidarity and social justice as principles to
guide global health work
A) Introduction
In Chapter 1, the history and origins of global health were outlined.
Consideration of ethical issues at the level of global health requires first a clear
understanding of the early twenty-first-century context in which global health
challenges need to be addressed. Three fundamental issues call for particular
attention: resource disparities and power relationships; the role of
globalized/liberalized trade; and global media and information. These frame our
discussion on ethical principles and ethical reasoning.
Universalist approaches
Schools of thought can be considered universalist when the theory argues that a
universal and objective criterion or test can be applied to human actions to
adjudicate its rightness or wrongness. The Western tradition has been influenced
and shaped by three dominant universalist approaches: deontological,
consequentialist and virtue based.
i) Deontological
Deontological approaches are typified by arguments that focus on the moral
worth of actions, that is, that certain acts are intrinsically right or wrong; and on
rational analysis of such acts. It is important to note that, according to this
approach, ethical acts are appraised largely independently of consciously
calculated potential consequences that follow from them. This is not to deny that
outcomes in general shape what we consider to be right and wrong actions.
The foremost account of a deontological approach is found in the work of the
philosopher Immanuel Kant. Kant's moral theory is based on the requirement
that moral values be stated as universal laws. The abstract and general
formulation of the law-like structure of moral statements is the categorical
imperative. The categorical imperative states that one should act only ‘on that
maxim which you can at the same time will to be a universal law’. These laws
are to command assent by all rational agents capable of acting freely upon them.
The requirements are universal in the sense that they do not depend on anything
in the empirical world for their justification. That is, the entire structure of laws
is established a priori.
Kantianism is influential in that it establishes important conditions for the
treatment of moral agents. They must be treated as ends in themselves and not as
means to an end. This notion is influential in doctrines such as human rights, and
informs standards for human subject protection in global health research. It is the
ethical theory most closely aligned with accounts of human dignity and inherent
worth.
ii) Consequentialist
Consequentialist theories view the rightness or wrongness of actions in terms of
the consequences that result from the action. The classical formulation of
consequentialism is utilitarianism, where the best action is that which creates the
greatest good for the greatest number. Classic utilitarianism is ‘hedonistic’ in
nature, in that it argues that happiness and pleasure are the consequences to be
maximized. There are many variations on consequentialist theories, and they are
prominent in modern health ethics. Consequentialist theories are associated with
economic analyses such as cost-benefit and cost-effectiveness analysis, and with
such tools as disability-adjusted life years (DALYs), quality-adjusted life years
(QALYs) and other outcome measures that are relied on in making public health
policies, as distinct from decisions about individual patients.
i) Relativism
Relativism holds that standards of determining the rightness and wrongness of
actions are related to and hold only for those who participate in a particular
culture and community. They admit to no overarching universal claim that all
humans should follow.
ii) Non-cognitivist
Non-cognitivist accounts hold that ethical statements have no truth-value
whatsoever, and are merely the expression of emotions and personal preferences.
Religion-based approaches
Religious ethics cannot be ignored in considerations of individual or population
health, as many communities in the world base their institutions and practices in
accord with religious principles. In each of the three predominantly monotheistic
religions, Islam, Judaism and Christianity, ethical appraisal consists of the
application of sacred texts and generations of commentary and reflection on the
ethical problem at issue. Casuistry is the term used to describe this ‘looking
back’ to precedents for guidance. Each of these major religions has several
variations of practice and interpretation of sacred texts (indicating significant
within-religion disagreement). In religious ethics, fidelity to the dictates of faith,
as indicated by the sacred texts, is of critical importance. There are many points
of agreement, but also significant areas of disagreement between these religions.
There are numerous other faiths, such as Hinduism and Buddhism, that influence
thinking and popular ideas relevant to health care. It is imperative for
practitioners to be aware of and respectful of religious practices and how certain
health activities may be interpreted in light of revealed religion. While
respecting individuals’ religious beliefs when they are choosing for themselves,
there is a need to be cautious that in the public realm some religious perspectives
are not privileged over others.
Concepts of justice
Justice is a fundamental concept in ethics, and accounts of justice date back to
antiquity. In the most fundamental sense, justice is concerned with issues related
to equality and fairness. As Aristotle noted, justice requires that we treat equal
persons equally and unequal persons unequally. Theories of justice have their
basis in deontological, consequentialist, virtue theory and feminist traditions.
The concept of social justice is discussed in detail later in this chapter.
The most relevant considerations of justice in global health relate to various
theories of distributive justice. Distributive justice consists in the study of the
normative principles guiding how the benefits and burdens of economic activity
are best allocated. Health is included in the scope of these allocative decisions.
There is a range of competing theories of how best to allocate resources.
These theories are rooted in fundamental conceptions of how humans and
societies are ideally to be constituted (Lamont and Favor 2007). The most
commonly held perspectives will be very briefly sketched out. Most of these
theories look at justice from within an established legitimate nation state. There
is an immense volume of literature on this topic, and readers are advised to
consult the suggested reading list at the end of this chapter for further
exploration of the topic. Commonly held views include the following.
The work of John Rawls has been particularly influential in modern theories of
justice (Rawls 1999). For Rawls, justice is fundamentally related to liberty, such
as the right to basic freedoms and equality of opportunity. Differences in terms
of these fundamental liberties, such as inequalities of opportunity, should exist
only insofar as they are of benefit to those with least advantage.
Much writing in global justice seeks to overcome some of the limitations of
the application of theories of justice to within nation states alone. However, this
is contentious and depends on whether there are good arguments for obligations
to others beyond state borders based on considerations of justice. Thomas Pogge
is one of the most influential theorists in this area. He argues that severe poverty
is the most pressing issue of global justice, and that as well as a positive
responsibility to alleviate poverty, there is a ‘negative responsibility to stop
imposing the existing global order and to prevent and mitigate the harms it
continually causes for the world's poorest populations’ (Pogge 2001: 22).
They argue that none of these principles can stand alone to provide an
overarching account of the values of global health ethics, and that solidarity is
the most important value of all.
G) Conclusion
Certainly, global health ethics is in its infancy. Medical ethics has evolved since
the 1970s and transformed the relationship between physicians and patients
through a focus on individuals. The emergence of new infectious diseases, and
the challenges of setting priorities in the face of escalating demands and limited
resources, have stimulated a renewed discourse on public health ethics in which
considerations of the common good require greater attention and justification. In
the face of a ‘complex organic crisis’ characterized by multiple overlapping
crises that threaten the health of all globally, there is now a need for yet another
ambitious discourse on global health ethics. Whether or not we consider this to
be intellectually viable, the need to narrow wide and widening injustices in
health cannot be ignored (Hunter and Dawson 2011). We have attempted to
show here some of the directions in which such thinking needs to advance.
While it can be objected that global health ethics is yet another example of
domination from the North, we contend that there has been increasing evidence
of perspectives from low- and middle-income countries taking similar critical
stances (see Chapter 10). Much more needs to be done to advance a global
dialogue, particularly efforts to minimize obstacles to the dissemination of
views. Some may feel that discussions about ethics do not translate into practical
action to improve health. We argue that any effort within global health rests on
some form of ethical commitment, and that these commitments are often tacit
and under-conceptualized. Attention to the ethical dimensions of interventions
holds the possibility of altering them in fundamental ways. Finally, we have
argued that global health ethics entails more than merely attending to issues in
distributive justice. As noted above, looking towards the transformational
capacity of ethics may help bring about a global state of mind that can lead to
more equitable health outcomes.
References
Bayoumi, A.M. and Guta, A. (2012) ‘Values and social epidemiological
research’, in: O'Campo, P. and Dunn, J.R. (eds), Rethinking Social
Epidemiology. Dordrecht: Springer.
Beauchamp, D.E. (1976) ‘Public health as social justice’, Inquiry, 13(1): 3–14.
Beauchamp, T.L. and Childress, J.F. (2001) Principles of Biomedical Ethics.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Benatar, S.R. (2005) ‘Moral imagination: the missing component in global
health’, PLoS Medicine, 2(12): e400.
Benatar, S.R., Daar, A. and Singer, P.A. (2011a) ‘Global health ethics: the
rationale for mutual caring’, in: Benatar, S.R. and Brock, G. (eds), Global
Health and Global Health Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
129–40.
Benatar, S.R., Gill, S. and Bakker, I. (2011b) ‘Global health and the global
economic crisis’, American Journal of Public Health, 101(4): 646–53.
Braveman, P. (2006) ‘Health disparities and health equity: concepts and
measurement’, Annual Review of Public Health, 27: 167–94.
Brody, H. and Avery, E.N. (2009) ‘Medicine's duty to treat pandemic illness:
solidarity and vulnerability’, Hastings Center Report, 39(1): 40–8.
Brown, P. et al. (2004) ‘Embodied health movements: new approaches to social
movements in health’, Sociology of Health & Illness, 26(1): 50–80.
Dahlgren, G. and Whitehead, M. (2007) Policies and Strategies to Promote
Social Equity in Health: Background Document to WHO – Strategy Paper for
Europe. Stockholm: Institute for Future Studies.
Dawson, A. (2010) ‘Theory and practice in public health ethics: a complex
relationship’, in: Peckham, S. and Hann, A. (eds), Public Health Ethics and
Practice. Bristol: The Policy Press.
Dawson, A. and Verweij, M. (2007) Ethics, Prevention and Public Health. New
York: Oxford University Press.
DeGraw, D. (2010) ‘The economic elite have engineered an extraordinary coup,
threatening the very existence of the middle class’, AlterNet,
www.alternet.org/story/145667
Durkheim, E. (1984) The Division of Labour in Society. New York: Macmillan.
Eyerman, R. (1989) ‘Social movements: between history and sociology’, Theory
and Society, 18(4): 531–45.
Farmer, P. (2003) Pathologies of Power: Health, Human Rights and the New
War on the Poor. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Forman, L. (2008) ‘“Rights” and wrongs: what utility for the right to health in
reforming trade rules on medicines?’, Health and Human Rights, 10(2): 37–
52.
Galeano, E. (1998) Upside Down: A Primer for the Looking-Glass World. New
York: Picador.
Gill, S. and Bakker, I.C. (2011) ‘The global crisis and global health’, in: Benatar,
S.R. and Brock, G. (eds), Global Health and Global Health Ethics.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hunter, D. and Dawson, A. (2011) ‘Is there a need for global health ethics? For
and against’, in: Benatar, S.R. and Brock, G. (eds), Global Health and Global
Health Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 77–88.
Ioannes Paulus PP II (1987) ‘Sollicitudo rei socialis’, The Vatican,
www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-
ii_enc_30121987_sollicitudo-rei-socialis_ en.html
Krieger, N. (2001) ‘A glossary for social epidemiology’, Journal of
Epidemiology and Community Health, 55(10): 693–700.
Krieger, N. and Birn, A-E. (1998) ‘A vision of social justice as the foundation of
public health: commemorating 150 years of the Spirit of 1848’, American
Journal of Public Health, 88(11): 1603–6.
Labonté, R. and Schrecker, T. (2011) ‘The state of global health in a radically
unequal world: patterns and prospects’, in: Benatar, S.R. and Brock, G. (eds),
Global Health and Global Health Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Lamont, J. and Favor, C. (2007) ‘Distributive justice’, Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/justice-
distributive
Muntaner, C. et al. (2009) ‘Against unjust global distribution of power and
money: The report of the WHO commission on the social determinants of
health: global inequality and the future of public health policy’, Journal of
Public Health Policy, 30: 163–75.
Nathanson, C.A. (1999) ‘Social movements as catalysts for policy change: the
case of smoking and guns’, Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law, 24(3):
421–88.
Nixon, S.A. et al. (2008) ‘Public health ethics’, in: Bailey, T.M., Caulfield, T.
and Ries, N.M. (eds), Public Health Law & Policy in Canada, 2nd edn.
Toronto: Lexis Nexis Butterworths, 37–59.
Oberschall, A. (1993) Social Movements: Ideologies, Interests and Identities.
London: Transaction.
Pinto, A.D. and Upshur, R.E.G. (2009) ‘Global health ethics for students’,
Developing World Bioethics, 9: 1–10.
Pogge, T. (2001) ‘Priorities of global justice’, Metaphilosophy, 32(1/2): 6–24.
Porta, D. and Diani, M. (2006) Social Movements: An Introduction, 2nd edn.
Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.
Powers, M. and Faden, R. (2006) Social Justice: The Moral Foundations of
Public Health and Health Policy. New York: Oxford University Press.
Rawls, J. (1999) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Richardson, H. (2007) ‘Moral reasoning’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reasoning-moral
Ruger, J.P. (2009) ‘Global health justice’, Public Health Ethics, 2(3): 261–75.
Sachs, J. (2011) The Price of Civilization: Economics & Ethics after the Fall.
Toronto: Random House.
Waitzkin, H. et al. (2001) ‘Social medicine then and now: lessons from Latin
America’, American Journal of Public Health, 91(10): 1592–601.
WHO (1986) ‘Ottawa Charter for Health Promotion’, First International
Conference on Health Promotion, 21 November 1986. Geneva: World Health
Organization.
— (2011) ‘Discussion paper: Closing the gap: policy into practice on social
determinants of health’, World Conference on Social Determinants of Health,
Rio de Janeiro, 19–21 October. Geneva: World Health Organization.
Yamin, A.E. (2011) ‘Our place in the world: conceptualizing obligations beyond
borders in human rights-based approaches to health’, Health and Human
Rights, 12(1): 3–14.
Further resources
Books
Benatar, S.R. and Brock, G. (eds) (2011) Global Health and Global Health
Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Singer, P.A. and Viens, A. (eds) (2008) The Cambridge Book of Bioethics.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Objectives
To articulate questions that bind us together as global health learners
To identify shared elements in the cycle of global health education
To encourage introspection and humility in global health learning
A) Introduction
What are the enduring solutions to creating healthy and resilient communities
(Wheatley and Frieze 2011)? Those asking this question are global health
learners. They are students, trainees, activists, artists, academics, practitioners,
researchers, teachers, policy-makers and politicians. Some are new learners with
varying degrees of interest; others are already experts in their field. Yet all ask
questions such as: Where do we fit within global health? How can the right to
health be achieved for all? What obstacles lie in the way? How do we ensure our
work reflects solidarity and not charity (see Chapter 2)?
This chapter explores these questions and examines how learners go about
finding answers. This process is shaped by an individual's context, motivations
and knowledge, all learners have similar questions and experiences. To
understand the global health learning cycle, we outline four common steps
(Figure 3.1), similar to the model described by Arnold et al. (1991) and
discussed elsewhere (see Chapter 12).
Step 1 is about orientation. Learners start to ask themselves and others
fundamental questions, and are shaped by the answers they find. Step 2 is the
visceral experience, where the learner is put into a global health setting and is
confronted by logistical, moral and ethical questions. Step 3 involves
introspection and honest self-reflection about one's motivations, power and
privilege and the limits of individual efforts. Step 4 entails relearning global
health, where learners begin to appreciate the dynamic nature of global health.
Humility is the hallmark of this stage. A clearer sense of how to engage in global
health as a career is developed through this cycle.
Step 1: Orientation
Learners begin the cycle through hearing about ‘global health’ and becoming
interested in learning more. What is global health (see Chapter 1)? How is it
different from public health, international health or tropical medicine? Where
does global health take place? Who practices global health? Who are leaders in
this field and what do they do? Is engaging in research, education or community-
based field work all forms of global health?
The array of ideas and concepts that fall under the umbrella of global health
can be daunting, but common themes of health equity, human rights and both
individual and population-level interventions emerge (Koplan et al. 2009).
Today, most learners accept that global health is not simply about working in
low- and middle-income countries (LMIC), but can involve working in high-
income countries (HIC) with indigenous communities, the homeless in urban
settings and those without legal status. Indeed, a learner's mentors and personal
learning experiences will continue to reinforce the link between marginalization
and global health (Jarvis-Selinger et al. 2008).
Finally, learners in HIC will begin to contend with the problematic history of
global health (see Chapter 1) and what this means today in terms of an ongoing
connection to foreign policy and ‘corporate colonialism’ (Anonymous 2004). As
learners grow in their political and historical understanding of global health, they
may begin to question whether global health initiatives can lead to deepening
inequalities and further exploitation (Benatar 1998). Unfortunately, many may
ignore such thoughts in order to justify the experiences they want to have.
Step 3: Introspection
It is often the visceral elective experience, and an accompanying sense that
‘something is not quite right’, that pushes the learner to start to identify their
own power and privilege. Learners may also realize that their motivations are
not as altruistic as originally imagined, and may question whether their
experience was potentially harmful to the very population they aimed to serve.
The learner may begin to question the basic premise that those in the global
North are in a position to help those in the South, along with the faulty
assumption that ‘some care is better than none’. This awareness may prevent a
trainee from working above their level of training and causing harm. It may lead
to greater respect for the knowledge and skills of local providers. It may even
lead a trainee to forgo pursuing any further experiences or deferring them until
later in her/his training. This humility may be combined with questions about
entitlement. What are our privileges, and from where do they spring (Pinto and
Upshur 2009)? Do we have the right to travel to another country to study and
work there? Why do internationally trained physicians and trainees face
numerous barriers to practicing, even for brief periods, within HIC? The learner
must recognize that ‘medical training in a developed world context does not
translate to competence in all settings’ (Pinto and Upshur 2009: 7). Humility is
essential to undermining the neocolonialism that can characterize North-South
relationships.
There may also be a re-examination of motivations. Philpott (2010)
categorizes these motivations into those we would rather suppress, those we can
tolerate, and those to which we aspire. A willingness to acknowledge less
palatable or admirable motivations, such as ‘the desire for professional
escapades to punctuate an otherwise dreary career’ (Philpott 2010: 231), does
not make them any less real, but may help cultivate humility and transform our
global health learning journey. Were we influenced by the hero myth? Often,
global health ‘heroes’ share a common story: they were called to adventure,
underwent trials and tribulations in a foreign land, and returned home changed
(Rosenzweig 1996). This myth becomes even more entrenched when we return
home to loved ones, who tell us how proud they are that we want to ‘save the
world’. Dagi (1988) turns the problem of ‘physician as hero’ on its head, using
this paradigm instead to suggest that physicians are called to address the broader
determinants of health and social injustice. Here, the physician is a ‘paragon of
virtue’, willing to assume risks, pursue knowledge and act to improve society as
a whole. However, Dagi (1988) recognizes the dangers inherent in this hero
mythology, which can lead to ‘a savior mentality; a sense of invulnerability; a
sense of entitlement and social mandate; and a highly paternalistic approach to
interactions with patients and with the institutions of society’ (Dagi 1988: 57).
Learners may question why they felt they were called to serve in this hero
role. Certainly, humanitarian celebrities play a role by inspiring us, and at times
demonstrating social justice in action and speaking ‘truth to power’ by virtue of
their position. Does seeking our own heroism build into our motivations around
global health work? How does the quest for awards and accolades fall into our
plans? Learners must question this impulse and be cognizant of the impact it can
have on the people they are aiming to serve, who risk becoming mere subjects in
our hero's tale.
Another danger of the hero myth is the ‘danger of the single story’ (Adichie
2009). When we create and narrate a story to ourselves and others about our
global health experiences, ‘[we] create stereotypes, and the problem with
stereotypes is not that they are untrue, but that they are incomplete. They make
one story become the only story.’ Any singular story can dispossess or
disempower, as it is often impossible to relay a story with objective cultural and
historical context. When using a cultural competency-based approach to
understand their global health experience, trainees may actually further ‘other’
certain communities. By focusing too heavily on ethnocultural characteristics,
rather than an understanding of class, geography and political factors as key
determinants of a patient's health, they may fail to understand the complexities
of identity that involve race, ethnicity, class, gender and sexual orientation.
Rather, this approach simplifies patients or groups into one overarching identity
(e.g. African) (Wear 2003).
Students should reflect on how and whether they are implicitly participating in
this simplification, or telling of ‘a single story’, and whether they are failing to
‘connect the idea of diversity with the underlying core concept of social justice
in health care’ (Wear 2003). Adichie (2009) adds, however, that ‘stories can…be
used to empower and to humanize…stories can break the dignity of a people, but
stories can also repair that broken dignity’. In our examination of our
experiences and their consequences, we must consider how we use our stories
and what unexpected effects telling those stories may have. Does the way we
internally examine and communicate our experience build or break stereotypes,
empower or disempower, expand or contract the ability of those around us to
understand the scope of global health?
Finally, how have we been changed by our global health experience? Learners
may find the immense luxury in the global North unsettling or disturbing after
witnessing extreme poverty in low-income settings. We may find the applause
from family and friends jarring, when recognizing that the task of addressing
health inequities is far larger than anything we could have tackled on our own.
We may return home incensed by the injustice that we have witnessed. We may
feel compelled to enact change in some way, or alternatively may feel defeated
by our seeming inability to change the circumstances in our host communities.
We may feel a sense of discomfort in sharing our experience, sensing that we are
in some ways putting the poverty of others on display. Razack (2007) refers to
this peculiar consumption of the pain and suffering as ‘stealing the pain of
others’, and compels us to recognize our economic, missionary and even moral
complicity, and to question the ways in which we may use other people's
suffering to validate things we believe about ourselves, such as our strong
humanitarian impulses or caring natures. This reflection is even more pressing in
the digital era, where blogs and online photo essays may provide catharsis for
the writer, but may also exploit the grief, suffering and poverty of their patients
(Bhan 2005).
This complex process of introspection is meant to be reflexive as well as
constant. Trainees are encouraged to ask themselves a number of questions
before proceeding on a global health elective (see Box 3.1). However, they will
invariably revisit these questions and ask new ones after their global health
experience. This iterative process allows learners to cultivate global health as a
worldview and, ideally, develop a pattern of lifelong learning.
C) Conclusion
The global health learning cycle (Figure 3.1) is meant to represent the dynamic,
flexible nature of the learner's path. Many learners move from initial questioning
to self-reflection without the need for a visceral experience. By understanding
and articulating these various stages, we have a platform to examine some of the
ethical challenges faced by global health learners from the North.
It is essential to create a space and process for self-reflection as part of this
journey, allowing us to understand the potential risks and benefits associated
with global health experiences in low-resource areas. Our ultimate goal is not to
discourage global health work by trainees, but rather to encourage trainees to
engage in their learning in the most ethical, sustainable and just way possible.
Case resolution 3.1
Ram enjoys his inner-city family medicine residency, but struggles with
the recognition that most of his patients live below the poverty line. He
realizes that his medical training takes him only so far when dealing with
the complex issues many of his patients face. Early in his residency, he
has the opportunity to travel to Tanzania on a short-term medical
elective, but declines, recognizing he is not yet comfortable to work
independently in that type of setting. After completing his residency, he
decides to explore family medicine opportunities in northern Canada,
having realized that global health is about marginalized communities
regardless of location. With the permission of a few of his patients, he
begins writing narrative pieces that highlight the social determinants of
health. He is confident that he can continue to weave global health
concepts into his work locally.
Objectives
To provide an overview of international human rights law, particularly
the right to health
To explore the potential contribution of human rights to the achievement
of global health equity
To explore intersections between human rights and global health ethics
A) Introduction
Despite earlier iterations of rights (including the 1776 US Declaration of
Independence and the 1789 French Declaration of the Rights of Man), the
impetus for the modern development of human rights emerged from the mass
violations of the two world wars (Henkin 1990). In 1945, the United Nations
(UN) was created, in part to reaffirm faith in “fundamental human rights, in the
dignity and worth of the human person, in the equal rights of men and women
and of nations large and small” (United Nations 1945: 2). The 1948 Universal
Declaration of Human Rights was the first explicit human rights instrument of
the contemporary system of international human rights law, articulating a broad
range of rights to be protected in pursuance of the core human rights values of
inherent dignity and equal rights (United Nations 1948). International human
rights law recognizes several categories of rights, including civil and political
rights (including rights to vote, to be free from torture, to have equality before
the law, and to have free expression, movement and association) and economic,
social and cultural rights (including rights to social security, work, education
and participation in cultural life). Despite these categories, within international
human rights law, all human rights are understood to be indivisible, interrelated
and interdependent (United Nations 1993).
Since 1948, these rights have been developed and expanded in multiple
human rights treaties, resolutions and declarations, necessitating the
development of a comprehensive set of international institutions to monitor and
interpret these rights, and prompting the development of regional human rights
systems in Africa, the Americas and Europe. These developments have seen
human rights become the fastest-growing field in international law (Mutua
2001), with international human rights viewed as having become “constitutive
elements of modern and ‘civilized’ statehood” (Risse et al. 1999: 234).
F) Conclusion
Actors within the fields of public health, ethics and human rights can gain
analytic tools by embracing the untapped potential for collaboration inherent in
such a combined approach. As a relatively mature field, human rights offers the
field of global health ethics the benefits of increasingly well-developed notions
of state responsibility with respect to health, and an obligatory legal framework
for action. Conversely, global health ethics offers human rights a strengthened
ethical framework for action, broader justifications for claiming cooperative
action in relation to health, and increased acceptance of collective ethical duties
towards global public health. We argue that the two approaches in tandem offer
a strengthened normative basis for the achievement of global health equity.
In this light, we call for further research to advance understanding and
applications of the intersections of human rights and global health ethics,
including in relation to: (1) limitations of rights in service of global health
interests, (2) responses to new and emerging pandemics, and (3) the legal and
ethical basis for articulating the responsibilities of state and non-state actors
towards global health.
References
African Union (1981) African Charter on Human and People's Rights, 27 June
1981. Nairobi: African Union.
Benatar, S.R., Daar, A.S. and Singer, P.A. (2003) ‘Global health ethics: the
rationale for mutual caring’, International Affairs, 79(1): 107–38.
Beyrer, C. and Pizer, H.F. (eds) (2007) Public Health and Human Rights:
Evidence-Based Approaches. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University
Press.
Callahan, D. and Jennings, B. (2002) ‘Ethics and public health: forging a strong
relationship’, American Journal of Public Health, 92(2): 169–76.
Consortium for Health and Human Rights (1998) ‘A call to action on the 50th
anniversary of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights’, Journal of the
American Medical Association, 280(5): 462–64.
Constitutional Court of South Africa (2002) Minister of Health and Others v
Treatment Action Campaign and Others. Johannesburg: Constitutional Court
of South Africa.
Council of Europe (1961) The European Social Charter, 18 October 1961.
Strasbourg: Council of Europe.
Csete, J., Schleifer, R. and Cohen, J. (2004) ‘“Opt-out” testing for HIV in
Africa: a caution’, Lancet, 363(9407): 493–94.
DeCock, K.M., Mbori-Ngacha, D. and Marum, E. (2002) ‘Shadow on the
continent: public health and HIV/AIDS in Africa in the 21st century’, Lancet,
360(9326): 67–72.
Farmer, P. (2008) ‘Challenging orthodoxies: the road ahead for health and
human rights’, Health and Human Rights, 10(1).
Forman, L. (2012) ‘A Rights-Based Approach to Global Health Policy: What
Contribution can Human Rights Make to Achieving Equity?’, in Brown, G.,
Yarney, G. and Wamala, S. (eds), The Handbook of Global Health Policy.
West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell. Forman, L. (2011) ‘Making the case for
human rights in global health education, research and policy’, Canadian
Journal of Public Health, 102(3): 207–9.
Forman, L. and Bomze, S. (2012) ‘International human rights law and the right
to health: an overview of legal standards and accountability mechanisms’, in:
Blackman, G. et al. (eds), The Right to Health: Theory and Practice. Lund:
Studentlitteratur AB.
Forman, L. and Kohler, J.C. (eds) (2012) Access to Medicines as a Human
Right: What Implications for the Pharmaceutical Industry? Toronto:
University of Toronto Press.
Freedman, L.P. (1999) ‘Censorship and manipulation of family planning
information: an issue of human rights and women's health’, in: Mann, J.,
Gruskin, S., Grodin, M.A. and Annas, G.J. (eds), Health and Human Rights: A
Reader. New York: Routledge.
Gloppen, S. (2008) ‘Litigation as a strategy to hold governments accountable for
implementing the right to health’, Health and Human Rights, 10(2): 21–36.
Gruskin, S. and Loff, B. (2002) ‘Do human rights have a role in public health
work?’, Lancet, 360(9348): 1880.
Gruskin, S., Mills, E.J. and Tarantola, D. (2007) ‘History, principles, and
practice of health and human rights’, Lancet, 370(9585): 449–55.
Harvard School of Public Health (n.d.) ‘Health and Human Rights Database’,
Harvard School of Public Health.
www.hsph.harvard.edu/pihhr/resources_hhrdatabase.html
Henkin, L. (1990) The Age of Rights. New York: Columbia University Press.
Hogerzeil, H.V. et al. (2006) ‘Is access to essential medicines as part of the
fulfillment of the right to health enforceable through the courts?’, Lancet,
368(9532): 305–11.
Hunt, P. (2006) ‘The human right to the highest attainable standard of health:
new opportunities and challenges’, Transactions of the Royal Society of
Tropical Medicine and Hygiene, 100(7): 603–7.
Hunt, P. and MacNaughton, G. (2006) Impact Assessments, Poverty and Human
Rights: A Case Study Using the Right to the Highest Attainable Standard of
Health, Health and Human Rights, Working Paper Series No. 6. Geneva:
World Health Organization and UNESCO.
International Council of Nurses (1998) ‘Position statement on nurses and human
rights’, International Council of Nurses.
www.icn.ch/images/stories/documents/publications/position_statements/E10_Nurses_Huma
ILO (1978) Tripartite Declaration of Principles Concerning Multinational
Enterprises and Social Policy, November 1977. Geneva: International Labour
Organization.
Krieger, N. (1994) ‘Epidemiology and the web of causation: has anyone seen the
spider?’, Social Science and Medicine, 39(7): 887–903.
Mann, J., Gruskin, S., Grodin, M.A. and Annas, G.J. (eds) (1999) Health and
Human Rights: A Reader. New York: Routledge.
Mutua, M.W. (2001) ‘J. Shaund Watson – Theory and Reality in the
International Protection of Human Rights (Book Review)’, American Journal
of International Law, 95(1): 255–56.
Nixon, S. and Forman, L. (2008) ‘Exploring the synergies between human rights
and public health ethics: a whole greater than the sum of its parts?’, BMC
International Health and Human Rights, 8(2).
OHCHR (2010) ‘Special Rapporteur on the right of everyone to the enjoyment
of the highest attainable standard of physical and mental health’, Office of the
United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights.
www.ohchr.org/EN/Issues/Health/Pages/SRRightHealthIndex.aspx
Pogge, T.W. (2003) ‘Responsibilities for poverty-related ill health’, Ethics and
International Affairs, 16(2): 71–79.
Risse, T., Ropp, S.C. and Sikkink, K. (eds) (1999) The Power of Human Rights:
International Norms and Domestic Change. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Rodriguez-Garcia, R. and Akhter, M.N. (2000) ‘Human rights: the foundation of
public health practice’, American Journal of Public Health, 90(5): 693–94.
Singh, J.A., Govender, M. and Mills, E.J. (2007) ‘Health and human rights 2: do
human rights matter to health?’, Lancet, 370(9586): 521–27.
Statistics South Africa (2010) Mid Year Population Estimates 2010. Pretoria:
Statistics South Africa.
Szreter, S. (1998) ‘The importance of social intervention in Britain's mortality
decline’, Society for Social History of Medicine, 1(1): 1–38.
Tesh, S. (1998) Hidden Argument: Political Ideology and Disease Prevention
Policy. New Brunswick: Routledge.
UNCESCR (2000) General Comment No. 14: The Right to the Highest
Attainable Standard of Health, 11 August 2000. New York: United Nations
Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights.
UN ECOSOC (1985) Siracusa Principles on the Limitation and Derogation
Provisions in the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights. New
York: United Nations Economic and Social Council.
UN General Assembly (2007) Convention on the Rights of Persons with
Disabilities, 24 January 2007. New York: United Nations.
United Nations (1945) ‘Preamble’, in: Charter of the United Nations, 26 June
1945. New York: United Nations.
— (1948) Universal Declaration of Human Rights. New York: United Nations.
— (1965) International Convention on the Elimination of Racial Discrimination,
21 December 1965. New York: United Nations.
— (1966) International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights, 16
December 1966. New York: United Nations.
— (1979) Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against
Women, 18 December 1979. New York: United Nations.
— (1988) Additional Protocol to the American Convention on Human Rights in
the Area of Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights (Protocol of San Salvador).
New York: United Nations.
— (1989) International Convention on the Rights of the Child, 20 November
1989. New York: United Nations.
— (1993) Vienna declaration and programme of action. In: World Conference
on Human Rights, Vienna, 25 June 1993. New York: United Nations.
— (2011) Political Declaration of the High-level Meeting of the General
Assembly on the Prevention and Control of Non-communicable Diseases, 16
September 2011. New York: United Nations.
UNHRC (2008) Human Rights Responsibilities for Pharmaceutical Companies
in Relation to Access to Medicines. Report of the Special Rapporteur on the
Right of Everyone to the Enjoyment of Physical and Mental Health. New
York: United Nations Human Rights Council.
WHO (1948) ‘Preamble’, in: Constitution of the World Health Organization, 22
July 1946. Geneva: World Health Organization.
— (1978) ‘Declaration of Alma-Ata’, in: International Conference on Primary
Health Care, 6–12 September 1978. Geneva: World Health Organization.
— (1986) ‘Ottawa Charter for Health Promotion’, in: First International
Conference on Health Promotion, 21 November 1986. Geneva: World Health
Organization.
— (2011) Rio Political Declaration on the Social Determinants of Health, 21
October 2011. Geneva: World Health Organization.
World Medical Association (1999) Resolution on the Inclusion of Medical Ethics
and Human Rights in the Curriculum of Medical Schools Worldwide. Ferney-
Voltaire: World Medical Association.
Yamin, A.E. and Gloppen, S. (eds) (2011) Litigating health rights: Can courts
bring more justice to health? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Global health governance and
5
ethics
Jerome Amir Singh
Objectives
To provide an introduction to governance for global health practitioners
To discuss infection control international governance strategies for
pandemic management
To consider the role of civil society in shaping governance
A) Introduction
Governance structures mediate what the various actors can and cannot do within
global health. Often academics, students and advocates want to see something
changed or something new developed, but are unaware of how things work. This
chapter aims to introduce the global health practitioner to governance.
In broad terms, governance can be defined as the actions and means adopted
by a society to promote collective action and deliver collective solutions in
pursuit of common goals (Dodgson et al. 2002). Governance includes regulation
by states (nation states, intergovernmental organizations); regulation by self-
organization (private sector and civil society); and hybrid forms of regulation,
including cooperation by, and interplay between, states and international
organizations, private sector and civil society (Kohlmorgen 2005). Health
governance concerns the actions and means adopted by a society to organize
itself in the promotion and protection of the health of its population (Dodgson et
al. 2002). For a glossary of terms see Table 5.1.
Global health – aimed at improving health for all people (Institute of Medicine
2009) – is concerned with the role and responsibilities of states and interstate
bodies, such as the United Nations (UN) and its agencies, international financial
institutions such as the World Bank and International Monetary Fund, political
groupings like the G-8 and G-20, private foundations, donors and international
non-governmental organizations (NGOs). It is evident that the nature and scope
of international cooperation has changed dramatically over the past century (see
Chapter 1). The recognition by states that they are no longer effective in
regulating health independently has necessitated a governance system that
encompasses state and non-state actors (Koplan et al. 2009), as well as interstate
bodies and international NGOs. “Global health governance” has been defined as
“the totality of collective regulations to deal with international and transnational
interdependence problems in health” (Hein et al. 2005). It includes the use of
formal and informal institutions, rules, and processes by states,
intergovernmental organizations and non-state actors to deal with challenges to
health that require cross-border collective action (Fidler 2010).
Table 5.1 Glossary of governance terminology
Instrument Example
Charter/Constitution – a set of Charter of the United Nations
foundation principles upon which an
organization or body is governed
Mission statement – comprises a set of Hospital mission statement
fundamental beliefs or guiding
principles that defines what an
organization is, why it exists, its reason
for being
Policy – rules for decision-making and National Department of Health policy
action; not legally enforceable, but on primary health care
usually internally binding within an
organization or body
Resolution – consensus statement of United Nations Security Council
principles which may or may not be Chapter 7 Resolutions (binding) World
binding Health Assembly Resolutions (not
binding)
Code – a set of rules (for example, of Professional association code of
conduct) promulgated by a body or conduct
organization, which is usually binding
on members
Declaration – a set of non-binding World Medical Association
guidance points proposed by an Declaration of Helsinki (2008)
organization or body
Guideline – a set of non-binding WHO guidance documents
recommendations
Regulations – a set of rules, usually International Health Regulations (2005)
with binding effect
Protocol – a set of regulations or Kyoto Protocol to the United Nations
boundaries to operation, recommended Framework Convention on Climate
by a Convention or Commission, in Change
order to comply with the agreement,
convention or treaty; binding on parties
who agree to ratify or accede to it
Treaty – a written agreement between North American Free Trade Agreement
two or more states or Sovereigns,
governed by international law
Convention – an agreement that has Framework Convention on Tobacco
been drafted by or falling under the Control
auspices of an international,
independent organization; binding on
parties who ratify or accede to it
This chapter begins with a brief outline of how global health governance
evolved as a discipline. This is followed by an overview of the World Health
Organization (WHO) and a review of the role the WHO and other interstate
agencies play in global zoonoses governance. This is followed by an overview of
infection-control strategies. The chapter concludes with three case studies.
Abbreviations:
AMCV – Advance Market Commitment for Vaccines
ASEAN – Association of Southeast Asian Nations
GAVI – Global Alliance for Vaccines and Immunisation
IFFIm – International Finance Facility for Immunisation
IGO – international governmental organization
ILO – International Labour Organization
NGO – non-governmental organization
PPP – public–private partnership
TB – tuberculosis
UN – United Nations
UNAIDS – Joint United Nations Programme on HIV/AIDS
UNICEF – United Nations International Children's Emergency Fund
WHO – World Health Organization
WTO – World Trade Organization
Because of its poor record in yielding binding governance instruments, the WHO
has been criticized as being “highly skewed towards recommendations over
treaties and regulations” (Gostin and Mok 2009). Recommendations can take
various forms, but two primary types include resolutions and codes of conduct
(Gostin and Mok 2009). Non-binding instruments of this nature are referred to as
“soft law.” Since its founding, the WHO has also assumed a support role to
governments through a variety of initiatives, including the publication and
dissemination of guidelines and the provision of technical advice.
Pandemic management has emerged as one of the WHO's major concerns in
recent years, with the emergence of diseases that can be transmitted between
animals and humans (zoonoses diseases), such as severe acute respiratory
syndrome (SARS), swine flu and avian flu. It is thus important to briefly
consider global zoonoses infection control governance and related containment
strategies.
[t]he principles and values that help guide actions among public health
system actors, which are designed to promote health and prevent injury and
disease in the population. The principal values of public health ethics include
the salience of population health, safety, and welfare; fairness and equity in
the distribution of services; and respect for the human rights of individuals
and groups.
(Gostin 2003)
Nancy Kass (2001), James Childress (Childress et al. 2002), Ross Upshur (2002)
and Lawrence Gostin (2003), amongst others, have proposed various
frameworks of public health ethics – analytical tools of sorts akin to the four
principles of biomedical ethics – designed to help public health professionals
consider the specific ethical implications of proposed public health interventions,
policy proposals, research projects and health programmes. The following
seven-step framework is a brief attempt to synthesize their respective proposals
(Singh 2007):
What are the public health goals of the proposed project? – the principle
of harm prevention and necessity
How effective is the project known to be in achieving its stated goals? –
the principle of effectiveness
What are the known or potential burdens of the project? – the principle of
burden identification
Can the burdens be minimized? Are there alternative approaches? – the
principle of least infringement/restriction/coercion
Is the project implemented fairly? – the principle of proportionality
Can the benefits and burdens of the project be fairly balanced? – the
principle of public justification and transparency
Individuals who are affected by public health initiatives should be
adequately supported or fairly compensated – the principle of reciprocity
Confinement and human rights
Human rights refers to a set of principles and norms internationally agreed upon
by governments that are contained in treaties, conventions, declarations,
resolutions, guidelines and recommendations at the international and regional
levels. Modern human rights instruments have their source in the 1948 Universal
Declaration of Human Rights (see Chapter 4). Although this instrument is not
legally binding on countries, it carries considerable moral authority. At first
sight, infection control containment strategies appear potentially to violate
several rights in this instrument, including Article 3 (Everyone has the right to
life, liberty, and security of person); Article 5 (No one shall be subjected to
torture or to cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment); Article 9
(No one shall be subjected to arbitrary arrest, detention or exile); Article 12 (No
one shall be subjected to arbitrary interference with his privacy, family,
home…); and Article 25 (Everyone has the right to a standard of living adequate
for the health and well-being of himself and his family, including…medical care
and the necessary social services, and the right to security in the event of…
sickness).
However, human rights doctrine also recognizes the limitation of many rights
in a public health emergency, provided the measures employed are legitimate,
non-arbitrary, publicly rendered and necessary. In this regard, section 25 of the
Siracusa Principles on the Limitation and Derogation of Provisions in the
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights holds: “Public health may
be invoked as a ground for limiting certain rights in order to allow a state to take
measures dealing with a serious threat to the health of the population or
individual members of the population. These measures must be aimed
specifically at preventing disease or injury or providing care for the sick and
injured.” A particular issue from a human rights perspective is whether the
containment strategy in question represents the least restrictive means to achieve
effective infection control and the extent of the belief in the severity of the
threat. The restrictions imposed by authorities should also be of limited duration
and subject to review.
While the curtailment of rights on the grounds of public health is endorsed by
human rights instruments, health workers should also be cognizant of the social
implications of such measures.
XDR-TB
References
Burman, W.J., Cohn, D.L., Rietmeijer, C.A., Judson, F.N., Sbarbaro, J.A. and
Reves, R.R. (1997) ‘Short-term incarceration for the management of
noncompliance with tuberculosis treatment’, Chest, 112(1): 57–62.
Calian, P. and Fidler, D.P. (2007) ‘The New International Health Regulations
and Human Rights’, Global Health Governance, 1(1).
CDC (2004) Isolation and Quarantine Fact Sheet. Atlanta, GA: US Centers for
Disease Control. www.cdc.gov/quarantine/quarantineisolation.html
Childress, J.F., Faden, R.R., Gaare, R.D., Gostin, L.O., Kahn, J., Bonnie, R.J.,
Kass, N.E., Mastroianni, A.C., Moreno, J.D. and Nieburg, P. (2002) ‘Public
health ethics: mapping the terrain’, Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, 30:
170–78.
Davies, S. (2010) ‘Is there an international duty to protect persons in the event of
an epidemic?’, Global Health Governance, 3(2).
www.ghgj.org/Davies_Is%20There%20an%20International%20Duty%20to%20Protect.pdf
Dodgson, R., Lee, K. and Drager, N. (2002) Global Health Governance: A
Conceptual Review. Geneva: World Health Organization and London School
of Hygiene and Tropical Medicine.
http://whqlibdoc.who.int/publications/2002/a85727_eng.pdf
FAO (2003) Veterinary Public Health and Control of Zoonoses in Developing
Countries. www.fao.org/docrep/006/y4962t/y4962t00.htm#Contents
— (2009) Guidelines for Surveillance of Pandemic H1N1/2009 and other
Influenza Viruses in Swine Populations.
www.fao.org/AG/AGAInfo/programmes/en/empres/AH1N1/docs/h1n1_guidelines_fao.pdf
FAO and OIE (2004) The Global Framework for the Progressive Control of
Transboundary Animal Diseases (GF-TADs).
www.oie.int/fileadmin/Home/eng/About_us/docs/pdf/GF-
TADs_approved_version24May2004.pdf
FAO, OIE, WHO, UN System Influenza Coordination, UNICEF and World
Bank (2008) Contributing to One World, One Health. A Strategic Framework
for Reducing Risks of Infectious Diseases at the Animal-Human-Ecosystems
Interface. ftp://ftp.fao.org/docrep/fao/011/aj137e/aj137e00.pdf
Fidler, D.P. (2005) ‘From international sanitary conventions to global health
security: the new international health regulations’, Chinese Journal of
International Law, 4(2): 325–92.
— (2010) The Challenges of Global Health Governance. Council on Foreign
Relations working paper.
http://ec.europa.eu/health/eu_world/docs/ev_20111111_rd01_en.pdf
Gostin, L.O. (2003) ‘Public health ethics: traditions, profession, and values’,
Acta Bioethica, 9(2): 177–88.
Gostin, L.O. and Mok, E.A. (2009) ‘Global health governance report’, in:
Institute of Medicine Committee on the US Commitment to Global Health,
The US Commitment to Global Health: Recommendations for the Public and
Private Sectors. Washington, DC: National Academies Press, 205–248.
www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/books/NBK23801/pdf/TOC.pdf
Hein, W., Bartsch, S. and Kohlmorgen, L. (2005) Global Health Governance:
Institutional Changes in the Poverty-oriented Fight of Diseases. A Short
Introduction to a Research Project.
www.temple.edu/lawschool/phrhcs/salzburg/Salzburg_GHG.pdf
Institute of Medicine (2009) The U.S. Commitment to Global Health:
Recommendations for the Public and Private Sectors. Institute of Medicine
Committee on the US Commitment to Global Health.
www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/books/NBK23801/pdf/TOC.pdf
Kass, N.E. (2001) ‘An ethics framework for public health’, American Journal of
Public Health, 91(11): 1776–82. doi: 10.2105/AJPH.91.11.1776
Kohlmorgen, L. (2005) International Organisations and Global Health
Governance. The Role of the World Health Organization, World Bank, and
UNAIDS. Working paper presented at the Salzburg Seminar on the
Governance of Health, 12/05–12/08/2005.
www.temple.edu/lawschool/phrhcs/salzburg/kohlmorgen_salzburg.pdf
Koplan, J.P., Bond, T.C., Merson, M.H., Reddy, K.S., Rodriguez, M.H. et al.
(2009) ‘Towards a common definition of global health’, Lancet, 373: 1993–
95.
Lakin, A. (1997) ‘The legal powers of the World Health Organization’, Medical
Law International, 3(1): 23–49.
OIE and FAO (2007) Ensuring Good Governance to Address Emerging and Re-
emerging Animal Disease Threats.
www.oie.int/fileadmin/Home/eng/Support_to_OIE_Members/docs/pdf/Good_vet_governan
Singh, J.A. (2007) ‘Epidemiology: ethics, advocacy and human rights’, in:
Joubert, G. and Ehrlich, R.I. (eds), Epidemiology: A Research Manual for
South Africa. Cape Town: Oxford University Press, 30–38.
— (2008) ‘Humanitarian work and infection control: legal, ethical, human
rights, and social considerations’, in: Biquet, J.–M. (ed.), Humanitarian Stakes
No. 1: MSF Switzerland's Review on Humanitarian Stakes and Practices.
Geneva: Médecins Sans Frontières, 12–22.
Taylor, A. (2004) ‘Governing the globalization of public health’, Journal of
Law, Medicine & Ethics, 32(3): 500–8.
United Nations (2004) A More Secure World: Our Shared Responsibility. Report
of the Secretary-General's High-level Panel on Threats, Challenges and
Change, December 2. Fifty-Ninth Session A/59/565, para. 144.
— (2007) Protection of Persons in the Event of Disasters, Memorandum by the
Secretariat, December 11. General Assembly Sixtieth Session, A/CN.4/590.
Upshur, R. (2002) ‘Principles for the justification of public health intervention’,
Canadian Journal of Public Health, 93: 101–3.
WHO (1990) History of the Development of the ICD (International
Classification of Diseases). Geneva: World Health Organization.
www.who.int/classifications/icd/en/HistoryOfICD.pdf
— (2003) Framework Convention on Tobacco Control. Doc. A56/VR/4.
Geneva: World Health Organization.
http://whqlibdoc.who.int/publications/2003/9241591013.pdf
— (2005) Revision of the International Health Regulations 2005. Fifty-Eighth
World Health Assembly. Geneva: World Health Organization.
www.who.int/csr/ihr/IHRWHA58_3-en.pdf
— (2006) Programme on Disease Control in Humanitarian Emergencies
Communicable Diseases Cluster. Pandemic influenza preparedness and
mitigation in refugee and displaced populations. WHO guidelines for
humanitarian agencies. Geneva: World Health Organization.
www.who.int/diseasecontrol_emergencies/training/PI_contents_introduction_jan07.pdf
— (2007) ‘Extensively drug-resistant tuberculosis (XDR-TB) in United States of
America air passenger’. News release, May 30. Geneva: World Health
Organization. www.who.int/csr/don/2007_05_30a/en/index.html
WHO Global XDR-TB Task Force (2007) Control of XDR-TB. Update on
progress since the Global XDR-TB Task Force Meeting, 9–10 October 2006.
Geneva: World Health Organization.
www.stoptb.org/events/world_tb_day/2007/assets/documents/globaltaskforce_update_feb07
Wilson, K., Gardam, K., McDougall, C., Attaran, A. and Upshur, R. (2007)
‘WHO's response to global public health threats: XDR-TB’. PLoS Medicine,
4(7): e246. doi: 10.1371/journal. pmed.0040246;
www.plosmedicine.org/article/info:doi/10.1371/journal.pmed.0040246
Indigenous health and ethics:
6
lessons for global health
Andrew D. Pinto and Janet Smylie
Objectives
To understand the health – and determinants of health – of Indigenous
peoples globally
To examine the historic and contemporary impact of colonization on the
health of Indigenous peoples
To introduce select Indigenous concepts relevant to ethics and global
health
To apply lessons learned from the ethics of working with Indigenous
peoples to other areas of global health
We have survived Canada's assault on our identity and our rights… Our
survival is a testament to our determination and will to survive as a people.
We are prepared to participate in Canada's future – but only on the terms that
we believe to be our rightful heritage.
–Wallace Labillois, Council of Elders, Kingsclear,
New Brunswick (Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples 1996)
A) Introduction
There are over 370 million Indigenous peoples living in over 90 countries
around the world (United Nations 2009). The enormous diversity in language,
beliefs and cultural practices seen across 5000 distinct communities belies the
use of a single term to label them all. Yet these communities share a common
history of colonization and marginalization, as well as of resistance against
dominant sectors of society. Resistance has occurred particularly through a focus
on the preservation of their distinct identities and cultural, economic and
political ways of life (UN Permanent Forum on Indigenous Issues n.d.).
While no universal definition of Indigenous peoples has been accepted (WHO
2007a), it is crucial to be mindful of terminology. Being able to define one's
community on one's own terms is a central part of self-determination. It
preserves the right and power of communities to decide who belongs to them,
rather than have this dictated by outsiders (International Work Group for
Indigenous Affairs n.d.). Self-identification happens through language that a
community has chosen, or through terms it has reclaimed. While it is beyond this
chapter to explore the history of terms used and misused to describe Indigenous
peoples (Bartlett et al. 2007), Table 6.1 lists some examples. Most definitions
will include reference to the relationships of Indigenous peoples to a collective
kin group and a current or historic land base. For example, one definition from
the Indigenous Physicians Association of Canada is:
D) “Decolonizing methodologies”
A crucial aspect of resistance by Indigenous peoples has also been reclaiming
the ability to define and understand their own communities. Research is a site of
this struggle as it is intimately related to protecting and preserving traditional
knowledge (Maina 2003). It is also part of the deeper issue of reframing who is
able to know Indigenous peoples (Said 1979). It should be noted that “aboriginal
knowledge has always been informed by research, the purposeful gathering of
information and the thoughtful distillation of meaning” (Castellano 2004: 98).
As Smith, a Maori scholar, has noted, “Decolonization, however, does not mean
and has not meant a total rejection of all theory or research or Western
knowledge. Rather, it is about centring our concerns and our world views and
then coming to know and understand theory and research from our own
perspectives and for own purposes” (Smith 1999: 39).
Indigenous knowledge that is developed through decolonized methodologies
is a powerful alternative, for both colonizer and colonized. “By animating the
voices and experiences of the cognitive ‘other’ and integrating them into the
educational process, [Indigenous knowledge] creates a new, balanced centre and
a fresh vantage point from which to analyze Eurocentric education and its
pedagogies” (Battiste 2005).
Examples of decolonizing methodologies include a community resisting the
imposition of an externally developed measure of wellbeing and developing a
unique and relevant indicator themselves (Ten Fingers 2005). Another example
is the use of life-course epidemiology to integrate biological and social risk
processes and to conceptualize how socio-economic determinants of health
influence the development of chronic diseases (Estey et al. 2007). A recent
example is community-based participatory research that assesses the health of
urban Aboriginals using respondent-driven sampling (Smylie et al. 2011).
Decolonizing methodologies is also about respecting and upholding
differences in worldviews. Indigenous worldviews place special significance on
the idea of the unification of humans with the natural world, and hence
displacement from the land is particularly traumatic (Matthews 1997). These
worldviews are often centered on the importance of intergenerational
relationships, community wellbeing and a holistic understanding of health (Estey
et al. 2007). They differ from mainstream Western views of health by focusing
not just on the individual, but on the community, the environment (Stephens et
al. 2005) and communal health (United Nations 2009). This is part of the reason
why considering and addressing the social determinants is so essential.
A review of case studies from around the world that discuss ways to address
these social determinants found that successful solutions are holistic – they
address spiritual, physical, mental, emotional, cultural, economic, social and
environmental factors, and address the individual and the context together
(WHO 2007b). The case studies also illustrated the importance of capacity
building (Smylie et al. 2006) better data and supporting community resilience.
Research projects should lead to increases in real financial support for health and
social services and emphasize communal ownership, building strong links with
local community networks.
F) Conclusion
Fanon wrote that colonized societies may be able to “resolve problems to which
Europe has not been able to find answers” (Fanon 1965: 6). Much can be learned
from Indigenous values, which represent a powerful alternative centered on
holism, a focus on community engagement, solidarity and social justice (WHO
2007b). “Values of collectivity, reciprocity, respect and reverence for Mother
Earth, are crucial in the search for a transformed society where justice, equity,
and sustainability will prevail” (Indigenous Peoples’ Caucus 1999).
Global health practitioners can embody these values in their work to reduce
health disparities (Horton 2006), particularly through a focus on addressing the
social determinants of health. This should occur through affirming respect for all
cultures, a focus on ecological renewal and sustainability, political
empowerment, legal and institutional reform, enhancing economic prosperity,
nurturing families and communities, and developing capacity within health and
social systems (WHO 2007b).
References
Alfred, G.T. (2009) ‘Colonialism and state dependency’, Journal of Aboriginal
Health, November: 42–60.
Anderson, I. et al. (2006) ‘Indigenous health in Australia, New Zealand, and the
Pacific’, Lancet, 367(9524): 1775–85.
Australian Government National Health and Medical Research Council (2003)
Values and Ethics – Guidelines for Ethical Conduct in Aboriginal and Torres
Strait Islander Health Research. Canberra: Commonwealth of Australia.
Bartlett, J.G. et al. (2007) ‘Identifying Indigenous peoples for health research in
a global context: a review of perspectives and challenges’, International
Journal of Circumpolar Health, 66(4): 287–307.
Baskin, C. (2007) ‘Aboriginal youth talk about structural determinants as the
causes of their homelessness’, First Peoples Child & Family Review, 3(3):
31–42.
Battiste, M. (2005) Indigenous Knowledge: Foundation for First Nations.
University of Saskatchewan.
www.viu.ca/integratedplanning/documents/IndegenousKnowledgePaperbyMarieBattistecop
Cancer Care Ontario (2008) A Case Study Approach: Lessons Learned in
Ontario: Aboriginal Tobacco Cessation. Toronto: Aboriginal Cancer Care
Unit, Cancer Care Ontario.
Castellano, M.B. (2004) ‘Ethics of Aboriginal research’, Journal of Aboriginal
Health, January: 98–114.
Cunningham, C. and Stanley, F. (2003) ‘Indigenous by definition, experience, or
world view’, British Medical Journal, 327(7412): 403–4.
Dickert, N. and Sugarman, J. (2005) ‘Ethical goals of community consultation in
research’, American Journal of Public Health, 95(7): 1123–27.
Dodson, M. and Williamson, R. (1999) ‘Indigenous peoples and the morality of
the Human Genome Diversity Project’, Journal of Medical Ethics, 25(2):
204–8.
Estey, E.A., Kmetic, A.M. and Reading, J. (2007) ‘Innovative approaches in
public health research: applying life course epidemiology to Aboriginal health
research’, Canadian Journal of Public Health, 98(6): 444–46.
Fanon, F. (1965) The Wretched of the Earth. New York: Grove Press.
Fantus, D. et al. (2009) ‘Injury in First Nations communities in Ontario’,
Canadian Journal of Public Health, 100(4): 258–62.
Government of Canada Panel on Research Ethics (2008) Tri-Council Policy
Statement, Chapter 9: Research Involving Aboriginal Peoples. Government of
Canada Panel on Research Ethics. www.pre.ethics.gc.ca/eng/archives/draft-
preliminaire/chapter9-chapitre9/
Harris, B., Russell, M. and Gockel, A. (2007) ‘The impact of poverty on First
Nations mothers attending a parenting program’, First Peoples Child and
Family Review, 3(3): 21–30.
Health Canada (2005) First Nations Comparable Health Indicators. Ottawa:
Health Canada. www.hc-sc.gc.ca/fniah-spnia/diseases-maladies/2005–
01_health-sante_indicat-eng.php
— (2010) First Nations and Inuit Health: HIV and AIDS. www.hc-
sc.gc.ca/fniah-spnia/diseases-maladies/aids-sida/index-eng.php
Horton, R. (2006) ‘Indigenous peoples: time to act now for equity and health’,
Lancet, 367(9524): 1705–7.
Indigenous Peoples’ Caucus (1999) Indigenous Peoples’ Seattle Declaration on
the Occasion of the Third Ministerial Meeting of the World Trade
Organization, 30 November–3 December 1999. www.ldb.org/indi99.htm
Indigenous Physicians Association of Canada and Association of Faculties of
Medicine of Canada (2008) First Nations, Inuit, Metis Health Core
Competencies: A Curriculum Framework for Undergraduate Medical
Education. Ottawa: Indigenous Physicians Association of Canada and
Association of Faculties of Medicine of Canada.
International Work Group for Indigenous Affairs (n.d.) Identification of
Indigenous Peoples. International Work Group for Indigenous Affairs.
www.iwgia.org/culture-and-identity/identification-of-indigenous-peoples
Lavery, J.V. et al. (2010) ‘Towards a framework for community engagement in
global health research’, Trends in Parasitology, 26(6): 279–83.
Ljunggren, D. (2009) ‘Every G20 nation wants to be Canada, Stephen Harper
insists’, The Calgary Herald, 26 September.
Maina, F. (2003) ‘Indigenous “insider” academics: educational research or
advocacy?’, Canadian Journal of Native Studies, 23(2): 207–26.
Matthews, J.D. (1997) ‘Historical, social and biological understanding is needed
to improve Aboriginal health’, Recent Advances in Microbiology, 5: 257–334.
Michell, H. (2005). ‘“Nîhîthewâk of Reindeer Lake”, Canada: Worldview,
epistemology and relationships with the natural world’, Australian Journal of
Indigenous Education, 34:33–43.
Montenegro, R.A. and Stephens, C. (2006) ‘Indigenous health in Latin America
and the Caribbean’, Lancet, 367(9525): 1859–69.
Nettleton, C., Napolitano, D.A. and Stephens, C. (2007) An Overview of Current
Knowledge of the Social Determinants of Indigenous Health. Geneva: World
Health Organization, Commission on Social Determinants of Health.
Ohenjo, N. et al. (2006) ‘Health of Indigenous people in Africa’, Lancet,
367(9526): 1937–46.
Potvin, L. et al. (2003) ‘Implementing participatory intervention and research in
communities: lessons from the Kahnawake Schools Diabetes Prevention
Project in Canada’, Social Science and Medicine, 56(6): 1295–1305.
Reid, M. (2006) ‘First Nations women works’ speak, write and research back:
child welfare and decolonizing stories’, First Peoples Child and Family
Review, 2(1): 21–40.
Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples (1996) People to People, Nation to
Nation: Highlights from the Report of the Royal Commission on Aboriginal
Peoples. Ottawa: Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples.
Said, E.W. (1979) Orientalism. New York: 1st Vintage Books.
— (1993) Culture and Imperialism. New York: Vintage Books.
Schnarch, B. (2004) ‘Ownership, Control, Access and Possession (OCAP) or
self-determination applied to research’, Journal of Aboriginal Health, 1(1):
80–95.
Silver, J. (2007) Unearthing Resistance: Aboriginal Women in the Lord Selkirk
Housing Developments. Ottawa: Canadian Centre for Policy Alternatives –
Manitoba.
Smith, L.T. (1999) Decolonizing Methodologies: Research and Indigenous
Peoples. New York: Zed Books.
Smylie, J. and Adomako, P. (eds) (2009) Indigenous Children's Health Report:
Health Assessment in Action. Toronto: Center for Research on Inner City
Health.
Smylie, J. and Anderson, M. (2006) ‘Understanding the health of Indigenous
peoples in Canada: key methodological and conceptual challenges’, Canadian
Medical Association Journal, 175(6): 602–5.
Smylie, J. et al. (2006) ‘Indigenous health performance measurement systems in
Canada, Australia, and New Zealand’, Lancet, 367(9527): 2029–31.
Smylie, J. et al. (2011). Our Health Counts: Urban Aboriginal Health Database
Research Project – Community Report First Nations Adults and Children,
City of Hamilton. Hamilton: De Dwa Da Dehs Ney's Aboriginal Health
Centre. www.stmichaelshospital.com/crich/our-health-counts-report.php
Stephens, C. et al. (2005) ‘Indigenous peoples’ health – why are they behind
everyone, everywhere?’, Lancet, 366(9479): 10–13.
— (2006) ‘Disappearing, displaced, and undervalued: a call to action for
Indigenous health worldwide’, Lancet, 367(9527): 2019–28.
Ten Fingers, K. (2005) ‘Rejecting, revitalizing, and reclaiming: First Nations
work to set the direction of research and policy development’, Canadian
Journal of Public Health, 96(Suppl. 1): S60–63.
Tilburt, J.C. and Kaptchuk, T.J. (2008) ‘Herbal medicine research and global
health: an ethical analysis’, Bulletin of the World Health Organization, 86(8):
594–99.
United Nations (2007) United Nations Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous
Peoples, 13 September 2007. New York: United Nations.
— (2009) State of the World's Indigenous Peoples. New York: United Nations.
UN Permanent Forum on Indigenous Issues (n.d.) About Us. Permanent Forum:
Origin and Development. United Nations Permanent Forum on Indigenous
Issues. http://social.un.org/index/IndigenousPeoples/AboutUsMembers.aspx
University of Victoria Center for Aboriginal Health Research (2010) Global
Indigenous Health: An Opportunity for Canadian Leadership. Victoria:
Center for Aboriginal Health Research.
WHO (2007a) Health of Indigenous Peoples Fact Sheet. Geneva: World Health
Organization. www.who.int/mediacentre/factsheets/fs326/en/index.html
— (2007b) ‘Social determinants and Indigenous health: the international
experience and its policy implications’, report on socially prepared
documents, presentations and discussion, in: International Symposium on the
Social Determinants of Indigenous Health, Adelaide, 29–30 April 2007.
Geneva: World Health Organization.
Wilmer, F. (1993) The Indigenous Voice in World Politics: Since Time
Immemorial. Newbury Park: Sage.
PART II
Practice
Ethics and clinical work in
7
global health*
Athanase Kiromera, Jane Philpott, Sarah Marsh and
Adrienne K. Chan
Objectives
To highlight some of the key ethical considerations encountered in global
health when working in a clinical setting
To discuss the challenges clinical trainees face within global health
A) Introduction
Clinical work is perhaps the most common way in which health professionals
engage in global health. This occurs in a variety of ways, including short- and
long-term missions, work within humanitarian non-governmental organizations
(NGOs) as volunteers or through long-term employment, and within public or
private sector institutions as part of training initiatives and through bilateral
exchange programs. Engaging in patient care is often seen as an opportunity to
apply one's skills in a concrete and immediate way and to address the disparity
seen in access to health services. However, concerns exist about the potential for
negative repercussions when professionals from high-income countries (HIC)
perform clinical duties in low- and middle-income countries (LMIC), not just for
the patient, but also for her community, for the practitioner, and for the
organization to which she belongs.
This chapter seeks to explore key ethical issues in global health clinical work
through a series of cases based on our collective experiences as clinicians. We
draw on the principles of the classic bioethics framework of Beauchamp and
Childress (1989): beneficence (do good), nonmaleficence (do no harm), respect
for individual autonomy and a commitment to justice. However, in order to
explore some of the unique aspects of global health work, including cross-
cultural understandings of health and issues of distributive justice within
resource-limited settings, we also incorporate the framework of Pinto and
Upshur (2009) that has been developed throughout this book: humility,
introspection, solidarity and social justice (see Chapters 2 and 3).
Reflective questions
1 How should a clinician respond when they are asked to perform a task that
they do not feel competent doing? What factors would be important to
consider?
2 With the potential for harm regardless of what Melanie does, how should
she decide on what to do?
3 What are the possible long-term consequences for the patient, for Melanie
and for the hospital if she does or does not perform the caesarean? What
would happen if she does perform it, and there is a positive outcome?
4 Considering global health electives such as the one outlined, who
benefits? Who bears the burden?
5 What factors influence the balance between service and learning in a
global health setting?
Cultural conflict
Reflective questions
1 Identify the sources of conflict in this scenario and why each participant
appears to be dissatisfied with how it ended.
2 Why is the visiting fellow angry? What are the underlying assumptions to
his emotions?
3 Could the resident have prepared better for working in this context? How?
4 What are the potential positive and negative consequences of the visiting
fellow's work on the local health care providers?
5 How does decision-making happen in an emergency, and how should
decisions be made about the goals of care?
Reflective questions
1 What are the key ethical principles that one considers when making
decisions about limited resources? How are conflicts between principles
addressed?
2 How would you approach this decision about who receives a potentially
life-saving resource? What would be the factors that you would consider?
3 This scenario occurs in a certain context. Is there a role for health
professionals in addressing the broader issue of social inequity? Is it a
duty?
D) Discussion of Case Study 7.3
This case illustrates a scenario faced by many global health practitioners and the
day-to-day reality of many health systems around the world. When two or more
individuals require a limited resource, who should receive it? Theories may
provide some guidance (see Chapter 2). At first glance, utilitarianism is
intuitively appealing in making health resource allocation choices and seems to
underpin the clinical decisions made by Sangita in this situation. Physicians
make decisions like this every day when they allocate clinical resources or
prioritize patients, whether it is triaging patients in an emergency room, or
deciding on transfers of critically ill patients into intensive care unit beds.
Decisions are made in clinical settings by finding a balance between the greatest
need and also the potential for greatest benefit. The goal of achieving maximum
good, whereby good is equivalent to health for the greatest number of people,
seems to fit with our intuitive notions of justice for all (especially the
marginalized) and our moral obligation. It seems to be a good thing to want
what's best for human beings as a whole and also be concerned with public
health outcomes for overall improvement of wellbeing.
The problem with consequentialism is that there is no moral obligation for the
equal distribution of how interventions to improve public health are shared,
which seems inherently unfair. The only moral obligation for a utilitarian is the
greatest good for the greatest number of people, and as such, a utilitarian is not
concerned at all with equal distribution of resources or how things are shared,
merely with what increases the total good. Sangita's painful choice is a reminder
of the choices that clinicians are forced to make that seem to go against the
principles of justice, and highlights a physician's obligations to his or her
patients that go above the pressing need of the immediate clinical dilemmas that
we face in practice.
Apart from examining consequences, physician advocates should be
concerned with the just and equal distribution of goods, because it is important
that individuals are afforded the same benefit and burden, and fairness is to have
equal treatment of all individuals in a just society, while minimizing in
disparities in health. Sangita's obligations are not simply to following ethical
principles around immediate decisionmaking around the case, but also in going
further to address root causes.
Case study 7.4
Max has worked in Haiti for five years as a program coordinator for a
social justice and health non-governmental organization. For over twenty
years this organization has worked in partnership with the Ministère de la
Santé Publique et de la Population (MSPP) to provide primary health
services to the rural poor of central Haiti.
On January 12, 2010, the country experiences a massive earthquake
near the capital, Port-au-Prince (PaP). At the time, Max is at the NGO's
headquarters, sixty miles north of PaP. Eight days later, Max is sent to a
large public hospital supported by his organization to help with
coordinating the response. Earthquake victims have overwhelmed the
hospital. There are over 200 patients requiring surgery, more than ninety
with compound fractures and crush injuries. Much of the hospital staff is
unaccounted for, assumed to be missing, searching for loved ones or
involved in other emergency response efforts in PaP. A team of volunteer
orthopedic and trauma surgeons, anesthesiologists, nurses and operating
room (OR) technicians from the academic medical system of another
country has been on site for several days with little accompaniment. The
hospital is unaccustomed to foreign surgical teams, and Max has been
sent to facilitate because integration of the short-term expatriate
specialist teams has been a challenge.
The visiting team has reorganized the ORs and post-operative space to
meet their needs, without much involvement of the existing staff. Foreign
volunteers and local staff are working almost entirely independently,
with little interaction or communication. The scene is chaotic and the
hospital staff, expatriate volunteers, patients and family members are
exhausted and increasingly frustrated and angry. Several patients have
refused amputations from the volunteer team and have left the hospital.
Upon arrival, Max is immediately bombarded with complaints from all
parties. The visiting team is working tirelessly, but quickly experiences
both physical and emotional burnout. They are frustrated by the lack of
infrastructure and their inability to communicate with local staff and
patients. They perceive a lack of sense of urgency, difference in work
ethic and lack of organization. They would like to run the OR twenty-
four hours a day, but find no support from the Haitian surgical team and
hospital administration. They are disturbed that patients are leaving the
hospital rather than undergoing what they consider life-saving surgery to
amputate limbs. They are concerned that they are unable to convey the
appropriate information to patients and are therefore failing to do their
job. They are also uncomfortable that the Haitian nurse-anesthetists are
recommending regional versus general anesthetic, claiming that patients
are requesting not to be put to sleep for fear that they will not wake up or
that their limbs will be amputated without their consent.
The Haitian team is also demoralized. Most have lost friends and
family members and many have lost their homes. There is a shortage of
skilled providers to meet patient needs. The frequent explosions of anger
and frustration directed at them by the visitors, and the expectation that
the existing system needs to be changed, upset the local staff. They are
opposed to operating the ORs twenty-four hours a day because of a
severe shortage of skilled nurses to provide post-op care to critical
patients. They voice particular concern around autonomy and informed
consent with respect to amputations of crush-injured limbs. The visiting
medical team seems unaware that rehabilitation services and limb
prostheses are unavailable for most in Haiti. Local staff know that
patients are terrified of amputation and feel that it might give them a life
that they would rather not live as a burden to their community. Patients
and their families express to Haitian staff that they feel that the care
provided by the foreign physicians is substandard.
Max realizes that the conflict is reaching a boiling point which, if not
resolved, will be harmful to patients and their immediate and future
surgical and rehabilitation needs, and to the system, which will need the
support and collaboration of multiple partners in order to provide
services under the immense stress caused by this disaster for years to
come.
Reflective questions
1 Why is conflict on teams with shared goals occurring? What is underlying
these tensions?
2 What is the role of local perspectives? What happens when there is
conflict between the views of the local population and the views of the
outsider clinician?
3 In the setting of a humanitarian disaster, is there a moral obligation to
ensure there is adequate post-operative care available as part of short-term
medical relief?
F) Conclusion
Adopting a critical approach to clinical work both before, during and after
experiences is essential for practitioners to continue to work in resource-limited
settings and in humanitarian crises. Taking the time to think about the complex
ethical dimensions of working in these settings can prevent health workers from
causing unnecessary harm, and also enhance relationships between health
providers and their colleagues in these settings, as well as with patients.
References
Ackerman, L.K. (2010) ‘The ethics of short-term international health electives in
developing countries’, Annals of Behavioral Science and Medical Education,
16(2): 40–43.
Anderson, K.C., Slatnik, M.A., Pereira, I., Cheung, E., Xu, K. and Brewer, T.F.
(2012) ‘Are we there yet? Preparing Canadian medical students for global
health electives’, Academic Medicine, 87(2): 206–9.
Beauchamp, T.L. and Childress, J.F. (1989) Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 3rd
edn. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bjerneld, M., Lindmark, G., Diskett, P. and Garrett, M.J. (2004) ‘Perceptions of
work in humanitarian assistance: interviews with returning Swedish health
professionals’, Disaster Management and Response, 2(4): 101–8.
Chu, K., Stokes, C., Trelles, M. and Ford, N. (2011) ‘Improving effective
surgical delivery in humanitarian disasters: lessons from Haiti’, PLoS
Medicine, 8(4): e1001025. doi: 10.1371/journal.pmed.1001025
Chung, R. (2012) ‘A theoretical framework for a comprehensive approach to
medical humanitarianism’, Public Health Ethics, doi: 10.1093/phe/phs001
Conard, C.J., Kahn, M.J. and DeSalvo, K.B. (2006) ‘Students’ clinical
experience in Africa: who are we helping?’ Virtual Mentor, 8(12): 855–58.
Crump, J.A and Sugarman, J. (2008) ‘Ethical considerations for short-term
experiences by trainees in global health’, JAMA, 300(12): 1456–58.
Dowell, J. and Merrylees, N. (2009) ‘Electives: isn't time for a change?’ Medical
Education, 43(2): 121–26.
Einterz, E.M. (2008) ‘The medical student elective in Africa: advice from the
field’, Canadian Medical Association Journal, 178(11): 1461-63.
Elit, L., Hunt, M., Redwood-Cambpell, L., Ranford, J., Adelson, N. and
Schwartz, L. (2011) ‘Ethical issues encountered by medical students during
international electives’, Medical Education, 45(7): 704–11.
Etienne, M., Powell, C. and Amundson, D. (2011) ‘Healthcare ethics: the
experience after the Haitian earthquake’, American Journal of Disaster
Medicine, 5(3): 141–47.
Federico, S.G., Zachar, P.A., Oravec, C.M., Mandler, T., Goldson, E. and
Brown, J. (2008) ‘A successful international child health elective’, Archives of
Pediatrics & Adolescent Medicine, 160: 191–96.
Greannam, T. (2003) ‘A wolf in sheep's clothing: a closer look at medical
tourism’, Medical Ethics, 1(1): 5054.
Hanson L., Harms, S. and Plamodom, K. (2011) ‘Undergraduate international
electives: some ethical and pedagogical considerations’, Journal of Studies in
International Education, 15(2): 171–85.
Hunt, M.R. (2008) ‘Ethics beyond borders: how health professionals experience
ethics in humanitarian assistance and development work’, Developing World
Bioethics, 8(2): 59–69.
— (2009) ‘Resources and constraints for addressing ethical issues in medical
humanitarian work: experiences of expatriate healthcare professionals’,
American Journal of Disaster Medicine, 4(5): 261–71.
— (2011) ‘Establishing moral bearings: ethics and expatriate health care
professionals in humanitarian work’, Disasters, 35(3): 606–22.
Iezzoni, L.I. and Ronan, L.J. (2010) ‘Disability legacy of the Haitian
earthquake’, Annals of Internal Medicine, 152(12): 812–14.
Knowlton, L.M., Gosney, G.E., Chackungal, S. et al. (2012) ‘Consensus
statements regarding the multidisciplinary care of limb amputation patients in
disasters or humanitarian emergencies: report of the 2011 Humanitarian
Action Summit Surgical Working Group on amputations following disasters
or conflict’, Prehospital and Disaster Medicine, 26(6): 1–10.
Koehn, P.H. (2006) ‘Globalization, migration health, and educational
preparation for transnational medical encounters’, Globalization and Health,
2: 2. doi: 10.1186/17448603-2-2
Lancet (1993) ‘The overseas elective: purpose or picnic?’, Commentary, Lancet,
342(8874): 753–54.
Landry, M.D., O'Connell, C., Tardif, G. and Burns, A. (2010) ‘Post-earthquake
Haiti: the critical role for rehabilitation services following a humanitarian
crisis’, Disability and Rehabilitation, 32(19): 1616–18.
McKinley, D., Williams, S., Norcini, J. et al. (2008) ‘International Exchange
Programs and US Medical Schools’, Academic Medicine, 83: S53–57.
Morgan, M.A. (2007) ‘Another view of “humanitarian ventures” and “fistula
tourism”’, International Urogynecology Journal, 18: 705–7.
Niemantsverdriet, S., van der Vleuten, C.P.M., Majoor, G.D. and Scherpbier,
A.J.J.A. (2005) ‘An explorative study into learning on international
traineeships: experiential learning processes dominate’, Medical Education,
39: 1236–42.
Pinto, A.D. (2010) ‘Denaturalizing “natural” disasters: Haiti's earthquake and the
humanitarian impulse’, Open Medicine, 4(4).
www.openmedicine.ca/article/view/407/364
Pinto, A.D and Upshur, R.E.G. (2009) ‘Global health ethics for students’,
Developing World Bioethics, 9(1): 1–10.
Suchdev, P., Ahrens, K., Click, E., Macklin, L., Evangelista, D. and Graham, E.
(2007) ‘A model for sustainable short-term international medical trips’,
Ambulatory Pediatrics, 7: 317–320.
Torjesen, K., Mandalakas, A., Kahn, R. and Duncan, B. (1999) ‘International
child health electives for paediatric residents’, Archives of Pediatrics &
Adolescent Medicine, 153: 1297–1302.
Wear, D. (2003) ‘Insurgent multiculturalism: rethinking how and why we teach
culture in medical education’, Academic Medicine 78: 549–54.
White, M.T. and Cauley, K.L. (2006) ‘A caution against medical students’
tourism’, American Medical Association Journal of Ethics, 8(12): 851–54.
Wimmers, P.F., Schmidt, H.G. and Splinter, T.A.W. (2006) ‘Influence of
clerkship experiences on clinical competence’, Medical Education, 40: 450–
58.
Further reading
Bhat, S. (2008) ‘Ethical coherency when medical students work abroad’, Lancet,
372: 1133–34.
Crump, J.A., Sugarman, J. and Barry, M. (2010) ‘Ethics and best practice
guidelines for training experiences in global health’, American Journal of
Tropical Medicine and Hygiene, 83(6): 1178–82.
Hardcastle, T.C. (2008) ‘Ethics of surgical training in developing countries’,
World Journal of Surgery, 32: 1562.
Kingham, T.P., Muyco, A. and Kushner, A. (2009) ‘Surgical elective in a
developing country: ethics and utility’, Journal of Surgical Education, 66: 59–
62.
Mutchnick, I.S., Moyer, C.A. and Stern, D.T. (2003) ‘Expanding the boundaries
of medical education: evidence for cross-cultural exchanges’ Academic
Medicine, 78(10): 1–5.
Radstone, S.J.J. (2005) ‘Practicing on the poor? Healthcare workers’ beliefs
about the role of medical students during their electives’, Journal of Medical
Ethics, 31: 109–10.
* The authors wish to acknowledge the contribution of case study content from
Dr. Cheryl Hunchak, Global Health Emergency Medicine, University Health
Network, University of Toronto, Canada.
Ethical challenges in global
8
health research
Ghaiath Hussein and Ross E.G. Upshur
Objectives
To discuss the ethical principles underlying global health research
To discuss the importance of community engagement and respect for
local community process in global health research
A) Introduction
It is well recognized that health research is becoming more “globalized”. While
the large majority of clinical trials are led by teams based in high-income
countries (HIC), health research now takes place in many low- and middle-
income countries (LMIC). For example, health research infrastructure is rapidly
developing in India, South Africa and Brazil. In a recent study, twenty-four of
the twenty-five countries demonstrating the fastest growth in clinical trial sites
were in emerging economies (Thiers et al. 2008). In parallel to the increased
capacity for research, ethical review and oversight of this research is growing,
but has not kept pace. As a report in the British Medical Journal noted:
…of the 100,000 clinical trials carried out around the world each year, some
10 per cent occur in developing countries, where patients are readily
available, regulatory requirements are less strict, and costs are lower. By
2010 European and US drug companies are expected to spend $1.5bn
(#0.8bn; €1.1bn) on trials in India alone. However, many developing
countries, especially in Africa, do not have the logistical support, financial
resources, or trained personnel to establish effective ethical committees or to
supervise the research being carried out among their citizens.
(Watson 2007: 1706).
The emergence of interest in global health research is tied to issues related to the
conduct of certain trials in LMICs. Considerable controversy arose over placebo
controlled trials in Africa, particularly the ACTG 076 trial to prevent mother-to-
child transmission of HIV (Angell 1997). Some argued that using placebos when
an established effective intervention was available, was unethical because it
subordinated the welfare of participants to the goals of science. Others argued
that placebo controlled trials were justified on the basis that participants were
unlikely to be able to access effective preventive therapy in the location where
the studies were being conducted. Furthermore, such trials presented the most
expeditious means of determining whether such therapy was feasible in
comparison with the local standard of care (Lurie and Wolfe 2007).
Global health research also raises issues concerning global justice, what
constitutes fair benefits to individuals and communities participating in research,
individual-level informed consent in communally based societies, and the
importance of community engagement in health research. It has stimulated
efforts to build capacity for ethical oversight in LMICs through training and
educational programs.
The extent of the ethical challenges posed by global health, particularly in
light of the discovery of unethical studies of syphilis transmission in Guatemala,
prompted President Obama to direct the Presidential Advisory Committee to
examine the current status of ethical standards of global health research. The
report, Moral Science, outlines several key challenges that researchers may face
in the conduct of global health research (Presidential Commission for the Study
of Bioethical Issues 2011).
In this chapter, we will provide a brief historical introduction to the evolution
of research ethics, outline its key principles and provide a framework for global
health research, and discuss the importance of securing local review. The
specific focus will be on contextual issues arising from research involving
communities in LMICs that emphasize the importance of community
engagement, particularly on research involving human subjects. Thus we will
not, in this chapter, address ethical issues involved in population-based research.
Also, we will not discuss the particular challenges raised by research in
humanitarian responses.
Researchers need to be clear from the very beginning about what they intend
to do and exactly what “services” they may be able to provide. They should
emphasize that these services are temporary, and that the community may need
to work on making them more sustainable. Whether there is a moral duty on
international researchers to help the studied communities has been debated in the
literature (London 2005; Hawkins and Emanuel 2008). What researchers are
capable of providing should be anticipated in advance, and an agreed-upon
strategy with the community should be negotiated.
Lavery and colleagues have created a series of case studies with commentaries
that illustrate the nuances of the application of ethical principles in actual
research in LMICs (Lavery et al. 2007). It is important to note, as per Chapter 3,
that there will inevitably be disagreement about how the principles should best
be weighed. As noted above, there is still much work to be done to explicate
more fully the extent of duties and obligations of researchers to individuals and
communities involved in research. Judgment will always be required. However,
Table 8.1 provides a framework that articulates the relevant, non-ignorable
ethical considerations. As Emanuel et al. (2004) write:
Prior to the research, the researcher should include the data-sharing plan
and have it approved by the research funders or sponsors. This plan
should be clear about which results will be shared, when, with whom,
and how.
The consent should be clear about the sharing of results, even in cases
where the researcher will not be able to share the results with individual
participants or even community leaders. Participants should be aware of
this, and should approve waiving their right to know the results.
The researcher should collect the contact details of the local health
authorities relevant to the area of research, the leaders of the studied
communities, and the individual participants. The latter should not be
part of the data-collection tool unless needed methodologically.
Researchers do not have to share the results by themselves. This could be
done through local leaders or NGOs working in the studied community.
However, they should ensure the necessary confidentiality of this
information, especially if data are identifiable.
The inclusion of local co-investigators is usually advisable, and
sometimes required by some countries. One of their tasks is to share the
results with their communities in a way that is culturally appropriate.
Informed consent
Informed consent remains an important element of any research involving
human subjects. For consent to participate in research to be ethically valid, it
needs to be obtained from a person who is competent to respond freely and
voluntarily after being fully informed about the relevant information related to
the study in a language that she or he understands. The participant should have
been given the chance to ask questions and have them answered clearly. Usually,
but not necessarily, consent is obtained in writing and signed by the participant.
Implementation of the standards of consent to research by international
researchers in the setting of LMICs is challenged by a number of factors. First,
international researchers frequently have little or no knowledge about the
country in which the research is conducted. This may lead researchers to seek
translation of the consent forms and the data collection tools, especially
questionnaires. The use of translators itself poses a set of ethical issues,
including the extent of precision of the translation – to what extent the
participant was really informed and the confidentiality of the information given
by the participants, especially in smaller, rural communities where most people
are relatives.
Second, the relatively higher rates of illiteracy among vulnerable groups and
in rural areas where there is less access to education, among other basic services,
makes it harder for participants to comprehend the translated consent. Particular
efforts may be required to assure comprehension. Another important cultural
factor that would affect obtaining consent is related to signing forms. Being
asked to place one's signature on papers brought by strangers is treated by
suspicion by many cultures that have suffered from experiences with fraud.
Third, consent may be hard to obtain because of language barriers and the
strong family hierarchy that may be dominated by male members of the family.
Addressing the role of the community leader or head of household in the
decision of a potential participant to participate (or not) should be managed
delicately to avoid unintentional offense to the leader and to ensure the rights of
the participant are respected. If a man tells his wife or daughter to participate in a
research study, you may still ask her in private if she really wants to take part.
The researcher should reassure her that whatever she decides will not be
conveyed to the head of the household.
Fourth, one must be careful and thoughtful about the use of incentives.
Researchers need to avoid direct cash payments, unless justified by
compensation for lost working hours and travel costs. This is not the norm in
many Western countries, where participants are paid at the end of the research.
However, in many LMICs people will volunteer for research and may even feel
offended if they are offered payment for something that is to benefit the
community.
Fifth, access to communities may rely on some form of community consent,
or assent that may be granted only by the community leader(s). Researchers will
need their assistance for official permissions or approvals required for research.
For international researchers, overcoming all these factors when obtaining
consent in the context of LMICs is not easy; however, some practical advice
may include the following.
F) Conclusion
In this chapter we have argued for the importance of researchers in global health
understanding their ethical duties and responsibilities. They must be aware of
international, national and local guidelines and regulations regarding the conduct
of their proposed research. The process of securing appropriate and necessary
approvals is vital for the ethical conduct of research. It is essential that
researchers know as much as possible in advance about the context in which
they will be conducting research. Community engagement and collaborative
partnerships are vital components of the research process, as is discussing and
negotiating benefit-sharing and the return of results. Ethically sound research is
the best research, and is rewarding to both researchers and participants.
References
Angell, M. (1997) ‘The ethics of clinical research in the developing world’, New
England Journal of Medicine, 337: 847–49.
Beecher, H. (1966) ‘Ethics and clinical research’, New England Journal of
Medicine, 274: 1354–60.
Emanuel, E., Wendler, D. and Grady, C. (2000) ‘What makes clinical research
ethical?’, Journal of the American Medical Association, 283(20): 2701–2.
Emanuel, E. et al. (2004) ‘What makes clinical research in developing world
ethical? The benchmarks of ethical research’, Journal of Infectious Disease,
189(5): 930–37.
Glickman, S. et al. (2009) ‘Ethical and scientific implications of the
globalization of clinical research’, New England Journal of Medicine, 360:
816–23.
Hawkins, J. and Emanuel, E.J. (eds) (2008) Exploitation and Developing
Countries: The Ethics of Clinical Research. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Hussein, G. (2009) ‘Democracy: the forgotten challenge for bioethics in the
developing countries’, BMC Medical Ethics, 10(3).
Lavery, J.V. et al. (2007) Ethical Issues in International Biomedical Research: A
Casebook. New York: Oxford University Press.
London, A. (2005) ‘Justice and the human development approach to
international research’, Hastings Centre Report, 34: 24–37.
Lurie, P. and Wolfe, S. (1997) ‘Unethical trials of interventions to reduce
perinatal transmission of the human immunodeficiency virus in developing
countries’, New England Journal of Medicine, 337: 853–56.
National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and
Behavioral Research (1979) The Belmont Report: Ethical Principles and
Guidelines for the Protection of Human Subjects of Research. Bethesda, MD:
National Institutes of Health. http://ohsr.od.nih.gov/guidelines/belmont.html
Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues (2011) Moral
Science: Protecting Participants in Human Subjects Research.
http://bioethics.gov/cms/sites/default/files/Moral%20Science%20%28Updated%202012%2
Schopper, D. et al. (2009) ‘Research ethics review in humanitarian contexts: the
experience of the independent ethics review board of Médecins Sans
Frontières’, PLoS Medicine, 6(7).
Thiers, F.A. et al. (2008) ‘Trends in the globalization of clinical trials’, Nature
Reviews Drug Discovery, 7: 13–14.
Tindana, P.O. et al. (2007) ‘Grand challenges in global health: community
engagement in research in developing countries’, PLoS Medicine, 4(9).
Watson, R. (2007) ‘Developing world needs stronger research guidelines’,
British Medical Journal, 334(7603): 1076.
World Medical Association (1964) WMA Declaration of Helsinki – Ethical
Principles for Medical Research involving Human Subjects. World Medical
Association. www.wma.net/en/30publications/10policies/b3/
Resources
General guidelines
Canada – Tricouncil Policy Statement – Ethical Conduct for Research Involving
Humans: www.pre.ethics.gc.ca/eng/policy-politique/initiatives/tcps2-
eptc2/Default/
Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences:
www.cioms.ch/publications/guidelines/guidelines_nov_2002_blurb.htm
Declaration of Helsinki: www.wma.net/en/30publications/10policies/b3/
India Council for Medical Research, Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research
on Human Participants: http://icmr.nic.in/ethical_guidelines.pdf
Nuffield Council on Bioethics – Research in Developing Countries:
www.nuffieldbioethics.org/research-developing-countries-follow
South Africa – Medical Research Council: www.mrc.ac.za/ethics/ethics.htm
World Health Organization – WHO Research Ethics:
www.who.int/ethics/research/en
Ethical considerations of global
9
health partnerships*
Jill Murphy, Victor R. Neufeld, Demissie Habte,
Abraham Aseffa, Kaosar Afsana, Anant Kumar, Maria
de Lourdes Larrea and Jennifer Hatfield
Objectives
To review the importance of collaboration and partnership for global
health
To develop an understanding of the challenges and opportunities related
to fostering global health collaborations and partnerships
To foster an understanding of “partnership ethics” through examples
A) Introduction
Partnerships are central to global health. In this field, academics, practitioners
and activists are constantly meeting and working with a variety of colleagues
and patients from diverse communities. When approached with care, these
relationships can be rich and beneficial (Royal Society 2011). Nurturing these
relationships, and fostering strong and successful collaborations and
partnerships, requires deliberate thought and action based on ethical conduct.
We define partnership as strategies that facilitate building, consolidating and
sharing knowledge and expertise that contributes to promoting the goals of
global health and building capacity (Canadian Coalition for Global Health
Research (CCGHR) 2009). Partnerships can describe the way large-scale global
health initiatives are funded, including public–private partnerships (e.g. Roll
Back Malaria, Stop TB Partnership) and donor-country partnerships where
governments of high-income countries (HICs) fund health programs in low- and
middle-income countries (LMICs). Partnership may also refer to a way of
working together with communities as an alternative to top-down initiatives. In
the context of global health research, researchers from HICs and LMICs may
collaborate to study complex challenges related to global health.
Much of the literature in this area pertains to research partnerships. Of equal
importance are educational partnerships, which commonly take the form of joint
degree programs between institutions in HICs and LMICs (Sewankambo 2011).
These partnerships can be beneficial to each institution, and can help to fill a
critical gap in training to support human resource capacity development in
LMICs. Other types of partnership include those involving the actual delivery of
clinical services and study placements, where a trainee is placed at another
institution.
Understanding these different relationships is essential for ethical global
health work. It helps in building trust between researchers, communities and
institutions. This chapter provides examples of collaboration and partnership for
global health, and of how principles such as social justice and solidarity (see
Chapter 2) are realized through such relationships.
B) Benefits of partnerships
Partnerships are the result of a variety of motivations (Katz and Martin 1997)
and benefits (Oldham 2005), which results in diverse impacts (Association of
Universities and Colleges of Canada 2006).
Knowledge production
Research partnerships and collaborations may lead to the critical analysis of
existing systems, the sharing of resources and the development of innovative
interventions. According to Oldham (2005), scientists in LMICs often want to
access the knowledge and expertise of their counterparts in HICs, in order to
apply this knowledge to address local challenges. Importantly, knowledge
sharing is certainly not a “one-way street.” Partners from HICs and LMICs learn
from one another, leading to broadened perspectives and new solutions to key
challenges (Association of Universities and Colleges of Canada 2006).
Researchers in HICs have a significant amount to learn from their colleagues in
LMICs, for example about topics such as the control of diseases such as
HIV/AIDS, malaria and TB and how to effectively use research findings to
influence policymakers. For example in Cameroon, researchers have used policy
briefs and stakeholder engagement to promote access to artemisinin-based
combination therapies for malaria (Ongolo-Zogo and Bonono 2010).
Capacity development
Partnerships lead to strengthened capacity among individuals, institutions and
systems in both HICs and in LMICs (Association of Universities and Colleges of
Canada 2006; Bradley 2007). Strong, equitable and mutually beneficial research
partnerships can lead to better health and health system outcomes (Bradley
2007). Again, researchers from HICs learn as much, if not more, from their
LMIC colleagues, including increased knowledge of different cultural contexts
and the adaptation of methodologies to various research contexts (Bradley
2007).
Access to resources
Access to both scientific (laboratories, equipment) and financial (grant money,
institutional research budgets) resources is a benefit of collaboration (Oldham
2005). For example, research funding by organizations such as Canada's
International Development Research Centre (IDRC) and the Swedish
International Development Agency (SIDA) specifically promote collaboration as
a key outcome of research initiatives.
Policy influence
Research partnerships between HICs and LMICs may often lead to new
perspectives that inform or influence policy and subsequently address health
challenges (Oldham 2005; Association of Universities and Colleges of Canada
2006).
C) Challenges of partnerships
Priority setting
Many LMICs have weak national health research systems and limited local
sources available for research funding. This means that initiatives are generally
funded by foreign donors, who often control the project's priorities (Forti 2005).
Costello and Zumla (2000) state that: “[f]oreign domination in setting research
priorities and project management may have negative consequences which
outweigh the apparent benefits of the research findings” (Costello and Zumla
2000: 827).Therefore a lack of control of the research agenda by partners from
LMICs might result in an imbalance of benefits in the favour of partners from
HICs (Forti 2005; Oldham 2005.)
Exploitation
All too often, a pattern is seen whereby the academic partner from the LMIC
will be employed as a data collector or research assistant, while their HIC
counterpart takes on a leadership position (Oldham 2005). Partners from HICs
may also fail to ensure that results from research are properly owned and
controlled by local stakeholders. This, in turn, may lead to the research
partnership being of great benefit to partners from HICs, while in fact being
detrimental to their partners in LMICs. This may diminish the positive potential
of the partnership to develop capacity, as described above. In order to avoid the
exploitation of colleagues from LMICs, investment in long-term capacity
development is needed to “level the playing field” and to balance power. In other
words, where benefits exist as outlined above, risks are also present if
partnerships are not properly designed and conducted.
Such challenges are reflective of the ‘10/90 Gap’, where only 10 per cent of
research funding is directed to health challenges that 90 per cent of the world's
populations face (Commission on Health Research for Development 1990).
Research funding is heavily weighted in favour of HICs, causing challenges to
equity in health research. This can be seen throughout global health policy and
practice.
The report also calls for a paradigm shift in research, so that the “culture of the
science system” better acknowledges socially relevant research, thus opening
new channels for collaborative research (ibid.).
In 2000, Costello and Zumla advanced four broad principles for a partnership
model to improve the practice of research in LMICs. They based their principles
on a criticism of the practice of “annexed research” whereby researchers from
HICs create research sites that are managed by expatriate staff, and often employ
local people at inflated salaries. They argued that these “annexed” sites are
damaging in that they attract local researchers away from national institutions
and rarely involve sufficient local ownership to lead effective or appropriate
policy influence (Costello and Zumla 2000). The principles are:
E) Conclusion
Ethics and equity must be at the heart of partnerships in order for them to be
successful. Partnering is not just a way in which to get things done – it is about
people and relationships, and therefore must be approached with care, thought
and consideration. Students engaging in partnerships must also recognize the
bigger picture of global health, grounded in the desire to improve health
outcomes and health equity on a global scale. Successful partnerships depend on
ethical conduct. Not only that, successful partnerships are also more likely to
lead to results that influence health policy, practice and outcomes to have a real
impact. In the course of their careers, students might be faced with situations in
which they recognize unethical conduct in partnerships.
This chapter draws on the experiences of its authors. Some key additional
recommendations are as follows.
References
Association of Universities and Colleges of Canada (2006) Highlighting the
Impacts of North-South Research Collaboration among Canadian and
Southern Higher Education Partners. Ottawa: Association of Universities and
Colleges of Canada.
Bradley, M. (2007) North-South Research Partnerships: Challenges, Responses
and Trends; a Literature Review and Annotated Bibliography. Canadian
Partnerships Working Paper #1. Ottawa: International Development Research
Centre.
CCGHR (2009) Partnership Assessment Tool. Ottawa: Canadian Coalition for
Global Health Research.
www.ccghr.ca/Resources/Documents/Resources/PAT_Interactive_e.pdf
— (2011) About Us. www.ccghr.ca/about_us
Commission on Health Research for Development (1990) Health Research:
Essential Link to Equity in Development. New York: Oxford University Press.
Costello, A. and Zumla, A. (2000) ‘Moving to research partnerships in
developing countries’, British Medical Journal, 321: 827–29.
Forti, S. (2005) Building Partnerships for Research in Global Health: Analytical
Framework. Ottawa: Canadian Coalition for Global Health Research.
Katz, J.S. and Martin, B.R. (1997) ‘What is research collaboration?’, Research
Policy, 26(1): 1–18.
KFPE (1998) Guidelines for Research in Partnership with Developing
Countries: 11 Principles. Swiss Commission for Research Partnership with
Developing Countries.
www.kfpe.ch/key_activities/publications/guidelines/guidelines_e.php
Oldham, G. (2005) International Scientific Collaboration: A Quick Guide.
Science and Development Network. www.scidev.net/en/policy-
briefs/international-scientific-collaboration-a-quick-gui.html
Ongolo-Zogo, P. and Bonono, R.-C. (2010) ‘Policy brief on improving access to
artemisinin-based combination therapies for malaria in Cameroon’,
International Journal of Technology Assessment in Health Care, 26: 237–41.
RAWOO (2001) North-South Research Partnerships: Issues and Challenges.
Trivandrum Expert Meeting Report, 1999. The Hague: RAWOO.
Royal Society (2011) Knowledge, Networks and Nations: Global Scientific
Collaboration in the 21st Century, RS Policy Document 03/11. London: The
Royal Society.
Sewankambo, N. (2011) ‘The value and challenges of institutional partnerships
in global health: a view from the South’, in: Building Institutions Through
Equitable Partnerships in Global Health Conference, Royal College of
Physicians, London, 14–15 April. www.rcplondon.ac.uk/policy/reducing-
health-harms/global-health/global-partnerships-2011
Speigel, J. et al. (2011) ‘Establishing a community of practice of researchers,
practitioners, policy-makers and communities to sustainably manage
environmental health risks in Ecuador’, BMC International Health and
Human Rights, 11(Suppl. 2).
ZAMFOHR (n.d.) About ZAMFOHR. Lusaka: Zambia Forum for Health
Research. www.zamfohr.org/aboutus.html
Zarowsky, C. (2011) ‘Global health research, partnership, and equity: no more
business-as-usual’, BMC International Health and Human Rights, 11(Suppl.
2).
* The KFPE revised the 11 principles in 2012. The revised principles can be
accessed at: http://kfpe.ch/11_Principles/
Perspectives on global health
10
from the South
Ana Sanchez and Victor A. López
Objectives
To discuss reasons for the under-representation in the literature on global
health from Southern authors based in the South, despite collaboration
with Northern partners
To consider guidelines and recommendations for ethical conduct being
developed for students, researchers and countries in the North
collaborating with LMICs
A) Introduction
The existing body of literature on global health – its evolving definitions, scope
and, very importantly, the values and competencies required for ethical practice
– reveals a troubling imbalance: there is little contribution from Southern authors
based in the South. This under-representation is even more striking when
considering the enormous growth in global health activity, particularly the
hosting of Northern partners as part of the myriad of research and training
opportunities taking place in low- and middle-income countries (LMICs).
Undoubtedly such opportunities are beneficial for the arriving guests (Crump
and Sugarman 2008; Fennell 2009; Plugge and Cole 2011), but are they
beneficial to the hosts? Laabes et al. (2011) suggest that while some African
schools receive much needed funding from an ever-increasing number of
European and American graduate programs, these collaborations often
perpetuate “post-colonial syndrome,” a legacy of reckless, exploitative and
unequal interactions (Laabes et al. 2011). Conversely, Glew (2008) argues that
not all Western investigators are necessarily cultural imperialists, and prefers to
believe his American students and colleagues when they express noble motives
for undertaking research or studies in Africa (Glew 2008). An examination of
the impact of study-abroad students in Chilean institutions and society concludes
that these opportunities can contribute greatly to world peace through a better
understanding of different values and cultures in both the sojourner and the host
(Stephenson 1999).
“We have always wanted to help find a solution for a health condition
affecting livestock and people in our country, so we approached a group
of researchers from a developed country that had produced and was
testing a treatment for the disease in animals. They were happy to
entertain our ideas and accepted our country as a research site. With our
own funding, we tested the treatment using a very expensive, rigorous
and ethical experimental protocol. The one-year trial was a success and
we were interested in doing a larger study. We sent samples to the
foreign researchers’ lab for some additional testing, but a year passed
without feedback. Every so often we would ask for results, but our emails
went unanswered. One day we were finally told that our findings didn't
show anything new as they already had proof of the treatment's efficacy;
they were also busy testing the treatment at a larger scale elsewhere so
could not continue working with us. This was extremely disappointing
and made us regret having spent our resources and time on this study.
Finally, in an attempt to rescue something, we asked if at least we could
publish the results, but they said that the study didn't prove anything new
and was now too old to be published. That was the last time we heard
from them.” (Source: a biomedical researcher from the South.)
Even though proficient researchers in less developed countries are
indeed capable of initiating collaboration with researchers in the North,
an equitable and lasting partnership can develop only when both parties
perceive the association as mutually beneficial and synergizing. There is
also a need to establish a written agreement that explicitly outlines each
partner's expectations and obligations at the outset.
C) Recommendations
It is imperative that scientific collaboration between researchers, institutions and
countries – whether for training, research, or both – operates under the guiding
principles of reciprocity, solidarity and social justice. This is particularly
important where one of the partners may be more vulnerable due to historic,
economic or political reasons. To this extent, it is commendable that guidelines
and recommendations for ethical conduct are being developed for students,
researchers and countries in the North. Of equal importance, LMIC stakeholders
should endeavor to develop similar regulations based on their own insights and
perspectives, thus bringing their essential voices to the dynamic conversation
about the ethics of global health – one that continues to be dominated by
Northern voices.
References
Bates, I., Taegtmeyer, M., Squire, S.B., Ansong, D., Nhlema-Simwaka, B.,
Baba, A. and Theobald, S. (2011) ‘Indicators of sustainable capacity building
for health research: analysis of four African case studies’, Health Research
Policy and Systems, 9: 14.
Chandiwana, S. and Ornbjerg, N. (2003) ‘Review of North–South and South–
South cooperation and conditions necessary to sustain research capability in
developing countries’, Journal of Health, Population, and Nutrition, 21: 288–
97.
Corbin, J.H., Mittelmark, M.B. and Lie, G.T. (2011) ‘Mapping synergy and
antagony in North–South partnerships for health: a case study of the
Tanzanian women's NGO KIWAKKUKI’, Health Promotion International,
15 December.
Costello, A. and Zumla, A. (2000) ‘Moving to research partnerships in
developing countries’, British Medical Journal, 321: 827–29.
Crump, J.A. and Sugarman, J. (2008) ‘Ethical considerations for short-term
experiences by trainees in global health’, JAMA, 300: 1456–58.
— (2010) ‘Ethics and best practice guidelines for training experiences in global
health’, American Journal of Tropical Medicine and Hygiene, 83: 1178–82.
Fennell, R. (2009) ‘The impact of an international health study abroad program
on university students from the United States’, Global Health Promotion, 16:
17–23.
Glew, R.H. (2008) ‘Promoting collaborations between biomedical scholars in the
U.S. and sub-Saharan Africa’, Experimental Bioogy and Medicine
(Maywood), 233: 277–85.
Ijsselmuiden, C.B., Kass, N.E., Sewankambo, K.N. and Lavery, J.V. (2010)
‘Evolving values in ethics and global health research’, Global Public Health,
5: 154–63.
Kickbusch, I., Novotny, T.E., Drager, N., Silberschmidt, G. and Alcazar, S.
(2007) ‘Global health diplomacy: training across disciplines’, Bulletin of the
World Health Organization, 85: 971–73.
Laabes, E.P., Desai, R., Zawedde, S.M. and Glew, R.H. (2011) ‘How much
longer will Africa have to depend on western nations for support of its
capacity-building efforts for biomedical research?’, Tropical Medicine
& International Health, 16: 258–62.
Moreno, E., Gutierrez, J.M. and Chaves-Olarte, E. (2011) ‘The struggle of
neglected scientific groups: ten years of NeTropica efforts to promote research
in tropical diseases in Central America’, PLoS Neglected Tropical Diseases,
5: e1055.
Muula, A.S. (2010) ‘We are not just a “tiny, landlocked, impoverished sub-
Saharan country with HIV burden”’, Croatian Medical Journal, 51: 560–62.
Plugge, E. and Cole, D. (2011) ‘Oxford graduates’ perceptions of a global health
master's degree: a case study’, Human Resources for Health, 9: 26.
Redwood-Campbell, L., Pakes, B., Rouleau, K., Macdonald, C.J., Arya, N.,
Purkey, E., Schultz, K., Dhatt, R., Wilson, B., Hadi, A. and Pottie, K. (2011)
‘Developing a curriculum framework for global health in family medicine:
emerging principles, competencies, and educational approaches’, BMC
Medical Education, 11: 46.
Reisch, R.A. (2011) ‘International service learning programs: ethical issues and
recommendations’, Developing World Bioethics, 11: 93–98.
Sauer, S. and Arrison, T. (2011) Examining Core Elements of International
Research Collaboration: Summary of a Workshop. Washington, DC: National
Academies Press.
Stephenson, S. (1999) ‘Study abroad as a transformational experience and its
effect upon study abroad students and host nationals in Santiago, Chile’,
Frontiers: The Interdisciplinary Journal of Study Abroad, 5: 1–38.
The political context of global
11
health and advocacy
Nathan Ford
Objectives
To offer an overview of global health advocacy
To introduce a framework for global health advocacy that draws on
policy analysis
A) Introduction
The practice of health advocacy has existed for hundreds of years. Rudolf
Virchow's (1840) often-cited claim that “Medicine is a social science, and
politics is nothing else but medicine on a large scale” (cited in Sigerist 1941: 93)
may be seen as recognition of intensive health activism taking place at that time.
In the United Kingdom, for example, campaigning by pressure groups to
promote the sanitary reform brought about the 1848 Public Health Act (Berridge
2007).
Global health advocacy – which could be defined as people in one part of the
world advocating for the improved health of people in another part of the world -
also has a long history. Recent advocacy efforts to draw attention to the lack of
drug development for neglected tropical diseases of the developing world (Barry
2003) are the latest in a 100-year-long struggle to control these diseases
(Janssens et al. 1992).
In a world driven by humanitarian concerns alone, funding would be
prioritized according to medical and public health need, with particular attention
to factors such as marginalization and discrimination that deliberately promote
poor health among certain groups, or exclude them from accessing care.
Unfortunately, such a global health utopia does not exist. In reality, national
interests play a substantial role in donors’ decisions to respond to major health
challenges. Just as colonial interests drove the United Kingdom's tropical disease
research in the first half of the twentieth century (see Chapter 1), more recent
international efforts to fight diseases such as HIV, tuberculosis and malaria have,
in part, been driven by diplomacy and national security considerations
(Feldbaum et al. 2010). This can have mixed or even contradictory
consequences. For example, national security concerns formed part of the US
government's decisions to invest in global funding for HIV (Feldbaum et al.
2006), resulting in the largest international funding effort against a single disease
(Ford et al. 2011). At the same time, however, domestic trade interests led the
US government to lobby for trade rules that protected the patents of
pharmaceutical companies and limited access to the most affordable treatments
for HIV.
This chapter provides an overview of global health advocacy, introducing the
reader to a useful framework that draws on policy analysis. Advocacy efforts to
increase access to HIV treatment will be illustrated as a key example.
Championing a solution
Up until 2000, the high cost of antiretroviral medicines excluded widespread
access to treatment in Africa. Although there had been calls in the past for
reducing the prices charged by pharmaceutical companies, these were by and
large comfortably ignored (Altman 2006).
The potential for antiretroviral drugs to be manufactured at substantially lower
prices was being explored by two middle-income countries with a high burden of
people living with HIV – Brazil and Thailand (Ford et al. 2007). However, such
initiatives were focused mainly on developing affordable medicines for their
own populations, with no major ambition to produce medicines for export to
other countries.
A major breakthrough came in 2001, when the Indian generics company Cipla
announced that it could manufacture triple therapy for US$350 per person per
year (Hoen et al. 2011). It rapidly became clear that the global patent rules that
permitted or hindered the international movement of medicines, as determined
by the World Trade Agreements, had a major influence over the ability of
developing countries to be able to access generic drugs at the price being offered
by the Indian manufacturers.
The availability of affordable generic antiretrovirals in India represented a
solution that could help drive an advocacy strategy both to pressure other
companies to lower the prices of their medicines and, at the same time, to
encourage governments and intergovernmental agencies to support the export of
Indian generic drugs to Africa.
Building alliances
In order to build the case that increased access to antiretroviral therapy should be
a priority, expertise and experience from a range of fields was required.
Intellectual property experts provided an analysis of the legal aspects of
international and national laws that determined the possibility of overriding
patents in order to manufacture and export generic medicines. Clinicians gave
advice about which drugs were most urgently required and, through treating
patients as soon as medicines were available, provided evidence that treating
HIV in resource-limited settings was feasible. In order to address concerns about
poor adherence and the risk of drug resistance, researchers gathered and
synthesized data that showed that adherence to treatment in Africa was as good
as, if not better than, adherence in North America (Mills et al. 2006). Health
economists modelled data to show that treating HIV was cost-effective. NGOs
launched public campaigns to challenge pharmaceutical patents and support
access to medicines in trade laws. Pharmacists advised on the quality of generic
versions of patent drugs. And, perhaps most importantly, the voices of patients
themselves articulated the urgency of the need.
One of the landmark cases illustrating the strength of such collaborative
efforts was a court case that took place in South Africa. Between 1997 and 2001,
a consortium of thirty-nine pharmaceutical companies litigated against the
government of South Africa, which at the time was trying to pass a Medicines
Act that would allow for the import of medicines being sold at a lower price in
neighbouring countries. At that time (and still today), South Africa was the
country with the largest number of people living with HIV, estimated at around
5.6 million. A dedicated advocacy campaign was mounted against the court case,
bringing together a coalition of lawyers, doctors, NGOs and local and
international activist groups. A local activist group, the Treatment Action
Campaign, challenged the court case on the grounds that it was a violation of the
human right to health. MSF co-ordinated a petition that collected over 250,000
signatures. These and other actions led to such forceful international public
pressure that the pharmaceutical industry was forced to drop the case (Forman
2008; Hoen et al. 2011).
Challenging the status quo
By definition, advocacy is confrontational because it involves, at least in the
early stages, challenging the status quo. The proposal that the needs of patients
in developing countries should be prioritized over the patents of pharmaceutical
companies and that affordable generic medicines should be purchased in order to
scale-up treatment was, in 2000, a radical idea that met with strong opposition
from Western governments. The pharmaceutical industry tried to deflect
attention, arguing that the price of medicines was not the most important issue,
and that efforts should first address poverty rather than medical patents
(GlaxoSmithKline 2011). UN officials who conducted investigations into
pharmaceutical pricing policies were threatened, sometimes violently (Vidal
2001). Western governments, protecting the interests of their domestic
pharmaceutical industries, threatened trade sanctions against developing
countries that attempted to override medical patents (Wilson et al. 1999). The
establishment of broad coalitions was essential to help overcome these pressures
and provide political support to groups that may otherwise have been forced to
abandon the cause.
Seizing opportunities
Opportunism has played an important part in furthering global advocacy to
support access to affordable HIV medicines. The decision by the consortium of
pharmaceutical industries to sue the South African government was an
unplanned opportunity that turned into a public relations disaster for the
pharmaceutical industry. The case was portrayed in the media as a “David and
Goliath” battle that pitted the health of millions of poor Africans’ health against
the corporate wealth of billion-dollar drug companies (Hoen et al. 2011). The
publicity around the case helped garner global public attention around an issue
that was previously seen as a technical legal issue.
In late 2001, responding to a perceived threat of terrorism, the US government
took steps to secure a stockpile of generic ciprofloxacin, the antibiotic to treat
anthrax, because the patented drug was considered too expensive. The example
was immediately seized upon as an instance of global health hypocrisy, given
that the US government was, at the time, lobbying to protect industry interests
and limit the ability of developing countries to access generic antiretroviral
drugs. The publicity generated helped to garner support for the Ministerial Doha
Declaration in 2001 that prioritized public health over patents in trade
negotiations that were taking place at the time (Boseley 2001).
Building consensus
Advocacy will fail if everyone agrees on the problem but disagrees on the
solution. Initially, while most health advocacy groups agreed that access to HIV
medicines needed to be improved, there was some disagreement among
advocacy groups about what solution should be defended. Should the public
health safeguards that are written into trade law be defended, or should the laws
be rewritten completely? Divergent views existed about what solution to push
for. Some campaigners took the view that the current intellectual property
system was flawed and should be scrapped altogether (Tickell 2001). Others
considered this to be a high-risk advocacy strategy, preferring to defend the
public health safeguards within the system (Hoen et al. 2011). After some
discussion, the latter solution gained precedence, and advocacy efforts were
directed at promoting the public health safeguards that permitted developing
countries from manufacturing or importing generic medicines. The fact that
today over 90 per cent of people on antiretroviral therapy in developing
countries are receiving generic medicines shows that the advocacy strategy was
successful in achieving its goal (Hoen et al. 2011).
Supporting implementation
Arguably, the success of the global campaign for access to antiretroviral drugs
over the past decade can, in great part, be attributed to the fact that many of the
actors involved–patient groups, health providers, developing country
governments – had a practical interest in solving the problem. This meant that
short-term solutions, such as drug donations or time-limited discounts, were not
accepted because it was clear that in the long term they would not solve the
problem. Many of the groups involved in advocacy for affordable medicines
were doing so because they were affected, and once generic medicines became
available, the same groups began to start providing the medicines to patients.
Unless there is a clear commitment to implement the solution, the gains made
will likely be quickly reversed. Those opposed (e.g. patent-holders) will promote
the failure of implementation as evidence that the solution is flawed, while those
in support (e.g. generics companies) will abandon the project due to lack of
demand.
C) How students have supported global advocacy to
increase access to antiretroviral therapy
The past decade has seen an increasing interest in global health as a discipline,
with a proliferation of courses for undergraduates and postgraduates. The
importance of advocacy in advancing health benefits is also a growing
discipline, with advocacy increasingly being taught as part of formal training for
health professionals (Pinto 2008). What is perhaps less well appreciated is the
role that students have played as agents of change.
A striking example of the power of student advocacy comes from the early
days of challenging antiretroviral patents. Students at Yale University discovered
that researchers from the university had discovered a key antiretroviral drug,
stavudine. The university handed over the license to the pharmaceutical
company Bristol-Myers Squibb, who refused to sell the drug at a fair price to
developing countries. Yale students formed a pressure group aimed at shaming
the university for their role in contributing to licensing of inventions for profit
(Borger and Boseley 2001). As a consequence of this pressure, Bristol-Myers
Squibb allowed generic stavudine to be bought and sold within South Africa –
and this led to a thirty-fold reduction in the price of the patented drug in South
Africa (Chokshi 2006).
This action gave rise to a broad coalition of student activists, such as the
Universities Allied for Essential Medicines (UAEM), which is now represented
in over sixty universities across North America, with chapters in Europe, Africa
and Asia (UAEM 2010). Building on the initial advocacy around stavudine,
UAEM's mission evolved to more broadly challenge universities to be more
responsive to the needs of developing countries and to undertake research and
policy analysis to determine how best to improve access to medicines for poor
countries (Chokshi 2006).
D) Conclusions
The scaling-up of antiretroviral therapy in the developing world is one of the
most remarkable achievements in global health. In less than a decade, over 8
million people have been initiated on treatment. Novel international funding
mechanisms and clear targets for future scale-up have been established, and
political commitments are carefully scrutinized by strong civil society activism
to hold governments to account (Schwärtlander et al. 2011).
Global health advocacy efforts are often understood as people in well-
resourced settings advocating for improved health of populations in
disadvantaged settings. The history of HIV treatment activism shows that this is
not always the case. Civil society groups in Asia, Latin America and Africa have
worked together to support each other's advocacy efforts in an effort to improve
access to medicines for all.
This chapter describes a stepwise approach of global health advocacy to
increase access to antiretroviral therapy. In reality, progress has not been linear.
Access to affordable medicines is again becoming a major challenge as a
growing number of people in treatment are developing resistance to first-line
antiretrovirals and need to access more expensive, second-line medications
(Hoen et al. 2011). The need to focus on HIV care as a global health priority is a
concern that requires constant justification. The global HIV programme has been
subjected to constant challenges, including pressure from the pharmaceutical
industry to limit access to generic medicines, increasing global intellectual
property protection that has limited the ability of generics companies to
manufacture affordable versions of newer drugs for HIV, competition for global
health resources from other diseases, concern that disease-specific funding has
been to the detriment of broader goals of health systems strengthening, and
changes in political leadership (Mills et al. 2010). Such challenges require
constant efforts to gather and publish evidence of the broader benefits of
providing HIV treatment at scale.
Global health advocacy focuses on immediate needs and is highly reactive to
daily changes in political commitments. In order to develop a broad strategic
framework for global health advocacy, it has been suggested that advocates work
alongside health policy researchers as a way to encourage more systematic
approaches to data collection and policy analysis (Buse 2008). The emerging
analytical approaches to health policy analysis will doubtlessly be beneficial to
understanding why certain advocacy efforts succeed and others fail (Walt et al.
2008). The challenge will be to connect the lessons learned by academic scholars
to health activists, who are intensely focused on responding to the daily,
immediate challenges of improving the health and wellbeing of disadvantaged
populations across the world.
References
Altman, L.K. (2006) ‘Talking about AIDS, with all the world watching’, The
New York Times, 8 August.
Attaran, A. (2007) ‘Adherence to HAART: Africans take medicines more
faithfully than North Americans’, PLoS Medicine, 4(2): e83.
Attaran, A. et al. (2004) ‘WHO, the Global Fund, and medical malpractice in
malaria treatment’, Lancet, 363(9404): 237–40.
Barrett, M.P. (1999) ‘The fall and rise of sleeping sickness’, Lancet, 353(9159):
1113–14.
Barry, M. (2003) ‘Diseases without borders: globalization's challenge to the
American Society of Tropical Medicine and Hygiene: a call for public
advocacy and activism’, American Journal of Tropical Medicine and Hygiene,
69(1): 3–7.
Berridge, V. (2007) ‘Public health activism: lessons from history?’, British
Medical Journal, 335(7633): 1310–12.
Borger, J. and Boseley, S. (2001) ‘Campus revolt challenges Yale over $40m
AIDS drug’, Guardian, 13 March.
Boseley, S. (2001) ‘Drug dealing’, Guardian, 24 October.
Buse, K. (2008) ‘Addressing the theoretical, practical and ethical challenges
inherent in prospective healthy policy analysis’, Health Policy and Planning,
23(5): 351–60.
Chokshi, D.A. (2006) ‘Improving access to medicines in poor countries: the role
of universities’, PLoS Medicine, 3(6): e136.
Creese, A. et al. (2002) ‘Cost-effectiveness of HIV/AIDS interventions in
Africa: a systematic review of the evidence’, Lancet, 359(9318): 1635–43.
Etchegorry, M.G. et al. (2001) ‘Malaria epidemic in Burundi’, Lancet,
357(9261): 1046–47.
Feldbaum, H. et al. (2006) ‘Global health and national security: the need for
critical engagement’, Medicine, Conflict, and Survival, 22(3): 192–98.
Feldbaum, H., Lee, K. and Michaud, J. (2010) ‘Global health and foreign
policy’, Epidemiologic Reviews, 32(1): 82–92.
Ford, N. et al . (2007) ‘Sustaining access to antiretroviral therapy in the less-
developed world: lessons from Brazil and Thailand’, AIDS, 21(Suppl. 4):
S21–29.
Ford, N., Calmy, A. and Mills, E.J. (2011) ‘The first decade of antiretroviral
therapy in Africa’, Globalization and Health, 7(3), 1–6.
Forman, L. (2008) ‘“Rights” and wrongs: what utility for the right to health in
reforming trade rules on medicines?’, Health and Human Rights, 10(2): 37–
52.
GlaxoSmithKline (2011) Global Public Policy Issues: Intellectual Property &
Access to Medicines in Developing Countries. Department of Government
Affairs, Public Policy and Patient Advocacy, pp. 1–5.
Guthmann, J.-P. et al. (2008) ‘Assessing antimalarial efficacy in a time of
change to artemisinin-based combination therapies: the role of Médecins Sans
Frontières’, PLoS Medicine, 5(8): e169.
Hoen, E. et al. (2011) ‘Driving a decade of change: HIV/AIDS, patents and
access to medicines for all’, Journal of the International AIDS Society,
14(15): 1–12.
Janssens, P.G., Kivits, M. and Vuylsteke, J. (eds) (1992) Médecine et hygiène en
Afrique centrale de 1885 à nos jours, Brussels: Fondation Roi Baudoin.
Kasper, T. et al. (2003) ‘Demystifying antiretroviral therapy in resource-poor
settings’, Essential Drugs Monitor, 32: 20–1.
Kingdon, J.W. (1984) Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. Boston: Little,
Brown.
McCoy, D. et al. (2005) ‘Expanding access to antiretroviral therapy in sub-
Saharan Africa: avoiding the pitfalls and dangers, capitalizing on the
opportunities’, American Journal of Public Health, 95(1): 18–22.
McNeil Jr, D.G. (2001) ‘Cosmetic saves a cure for sleeping sickness’, The New
York Times, 9 February.
Mills, E.J. et al. (2006) ‘Adherence to antiretroviral therapy in sub-Saharan
Africa and North America: a meta-analysis’, Journal of the American Medical
Association, 296(6): 679–90.
— (2010) ‘Ensuring sustainable antiretroviral provision during economic crises’,
AIDS, 24(3): 341–3.
MSF (2003) Act Now to Get Malaria Treatment that Works to Africa. Geneva:
Médecins Sans Frontières, Access to Medicines Campaign.
Perez-Casas, C. et al. (2000) ‘Access to fluconazole in less-developed countries’,
Lancet, 356(9247): 2102.
Pinto, A.D. (2008) ‘Engaging health professionals in advocacy against gun
violence’, Medicine, Conflict, and Survival, 24(4): 285–95.
Roll Back Malaria and WHO (2001) Antimalarial Drug Combination Therapy:
Report of a WHO Technical Consultation. Geneva: Roll Back Malaria/World
Health Organization.
Schwärtlander, B. et al. (2011) ‘Towards an improved investment approach for
an effective response to HIV/AIDS’, Lancet, 377(9782): 2031–41.
Sigerist, H.E. (1941) Medicine and Human Welfare. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Tickell, S. (2001) ‘Oxfam: Why TRIPS should be scrapped’, Financial Times, 9
November.
Trouiller, P. et al. (2002). ‘Drug development for neglected diseases: a deficient
market and a public-health policy failure’, Lancet, 359(9324): 2188–94.
UAEM (2010) History. Universities Allied for Essential Medicines.
http://essentialmedicine.org/about-us/history
UNAIDS (2000) ‘AIDS epidemic update: December 1999’, AIDS Analysis
Africa, 10(5): 2.
— (2010) Global Report: UNAIDS Report on the Global AIDS Epidemic.
Geneva: Joint United Nations Programme on HIV/AIDS.
UNICEF, UNAIDS, WHO and MSF (2000) Selected Drugs Used in the Care of
People Living With HIV: Sources and Prices. Geneva: WHO Essential Drug
and Medicine Policy and Médecins Sans Frontières.
Vidal, J. (2001) ‘Police guard WHO official after assaults and threats’,
Guardian, 31 August.
Walt, G. et al. (2008) ‘“Doing” health policy analysis: methodological and
conceptual reflections and challenges’, Health Policy and Planning, 23(5):
308–17.
Wilson, D. et al. (1999) ‘Global trade and access to medicines: AIDS treatments
in Thailand’, Lancet, 354(9193): 1893–95.
Teaching global health ethics*
12 Donald C. Cole, Lori Hanson, Katherine D. Rouleau,
Kevin Pottie and Neil Arya
Objectives
To explore pedagogy for teaching global health ethics and its content,
primarily to high-income country learners
To consider the role of high-income country institutions in supporting
ethical learning and decision-making in global health
To stimulate new ideas on assessing the development of ethical global
health practice
Reflection 1
In a post-consultation discussion, the resident argued that she felt coerced
within the teaching hierarchy by her male supervisor, and that the patient
could not provide true consent. The teaching physician recognized the
gendered, hierarchical nature of his own power over the resident.
However, he perceived the calmer office environment, assistance of a
translator, and clinical examination performed by a female resident, to be
more comfortable for the patient.
Reflection 2
Months later, the resident acknowledged that an emergency referral
would have resulted in greater discomfort and would have been less
respectful of the patient's autonomy. The teaching physician recognized
that his busy office constrained reflection and ethical discussion,
producing a less than desirable learning experience for the resident.
References
Arnold, R. et al. (1991) Educating for a Change. Toronto: Between the Lines.
Battat, R. et al. (2010) ‘Global health competencies and approaches in medical
education: a literature review’, BMC Medical Education, 10(94).
Benatar, S. and Brock, G. (eds) (2011) Global Health and Global Health Ethics.
Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.
Billig, S. and Furco, A. (2002) Service Learning Through a Multidisciplinary
Lens. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing.
Bozorgmehr, K., Saint, V.A. and Tinnemann, P. (2011) ‘The “global health”
education framework: a conceptual guide for monitoring, evaluation and
practice’, Globalization and Health, 7(8).
Cash, R., Wikler, D., Saxena, A., Capron, A. and Gutnick, R. (eds) (2009)
Casebook on Ethical Issues in International Health Research. Geneva: World
Health Organization.
Crump, J.A., Sugarman, J. and the Working Group on Ethics Guidelines for
Global Health Training (WEIGHT) (2010) ‘Ethics and best practice
guidelines for training experiences in global health’, American Journal of
Tropical Medicine and Hygiene, 83(6): 1178–82.
Deeley, S.J. (2010) ‘Service-learning: thinking outside the box’, Active Learning
in Higher Education, 11(1): 43–53.
Dwyer, J. (2011) ‘Teaching global health ethics’, in: Benatar, S. and Brock G.
(eds), Global Health and Global Health Ethics. Cambridge and New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Evert, J. et al. (2011) ‘Global health ethics’, in: Illes, J. and Sahakian, B.J. (eds),
The Oxford Handbook of Neuroethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Freire, P. (1970) Pedagogy of the Oppressed. New York: Continuum.
Frenk, J. et al. (2010) ‘Health professionals for a new century: transforming
education to strengthen health systems in an interdependent world’, Lancet,
376(9756): 1923–58.
Goldie, J., Schwartz, L. and Morrison, J. (2000) ‘A process evaluation of
medical ethics education in the first year of a new medical curriculum’,
Medical Education, 34: 468–73.
Hanson, L. (2008) ‘Global citizenship, global health, and the internationalization
of curriculum: a study of transformative potential’, Journal of Studies in
International Education, 10: 1–19.
Horton, R. (2009). ‘The occupied Palestinian territory: peace, justice, and
health’, Lancet, 373(9666): 784–88.
Marchington, E. and Lappano, J.-E. (2011) ‘Knight schools spotlight on
medicine’, Corporate Knights, www.corporateknights.ca/report/8th-annual-
knight-schools-results/knight-schools-spotlight-medicine
Mezirow, J. (1997) ‘Transformative learning: theory to practice’, New
Directions for Adult and Continuing Education, 74: 5–12.
Parikh, S.M. (2010) ‘Global health ethics and professionalism education at
medical schools’, Virtual Mentor, 12: 197–201.
Pinto, A.D. and Upshur, R.E.G. (2009) ‘Global health ethics for students’,
Developing World Bioethics, 9: 1–10.
Pottie, K. et al. (2012) ‘Refugees and global health: a global health E-Learning
program’, Canadian Collaboration for Immigrant and Refugee Health
(CCIRH) and the University of Ottawa. www.ccirhken.ca/eLearning
Redwood-Campbell, L. et al. (2011) ‘Developing a curriculum framework for
global health in family medicine: emerging principles, competencies, and
educational approaches’, BMC Medical Education, 11(46).
Rich, A. and Parker, D.L. (1995) ‘Reflection and critical incident analysis:
ethical and moral implications of their use within nursing and midwifery
education’, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 22: 1050–57.
Savulescu, J. et al. (1999) ‘Evaluating ethics competence in medical education’,
Journal of Medical Ethics, 25: 367–74.
Schwartz, L. et al. (2010) ‘Ethics in humanitarian aid work: learning from the
narratives of humanitarian health workers’, AJOB Primary Research, 1(3):
45–54.
Shor, I. and Freire, P. (1986) A Pedagogy for Liberation: Dialogues on
Transforming Education. South Hadley: Bergin & Garvey.
Singer, P.A. (2003) ‘Strengthening the role of ethics in medical education’,
Canadian Medical Association Journal, 168(7): 854–55.
Xu, J.J. et al. (2011) ‘Assessing the effectiveness of pre-departure training for
professional healthcare students working in resource-limited settings’,
University of Toronto Medical Journal, 88: 199–204.
Several interlinked global crises in the early twenty-first century are generating
serious challenges to the health and wellbeing of billions of people. In order to
narrow unacceptably wide disparities in health and diminish threats to our planet
and the health of its inhabitants, new forms of societal action are required. Such
innovation could transform health care and social systems that promote health
into better structured, highly functional, more equitable and sustainable
endeavours.
Many of the ideas and much of the content covered in this book, which were
discredited or ignored in the past, are now appropriately becoming credible and
achieving a high profile. Twenty-first-century thinking is required to solve
twenty-first-century problems, just as advances in quantum physics 100 years
ago began to reveal answers to questions that Newtonian physics could not
provide.
Many of today's young professionals are justifiably critical of the world they
have inherited from previous generations, who were swept along by a belief that
the world's problems could be solved through a combination of endless
economic growth, the pursuit of highly individualistic, consumer-driven needs,
and advances in science and technology. The excessive focus on research as the
highest goal has also somewhat eclipsed what it means to be a “good” health
care professional.
While acknowledging the major contributions made to health and longevity
through scientific advances and economic progress, it is arguable that the
potential for human advancement globally is undermined by a failure to
recognize the crucial need for major changes in the values, discourses and
practices that have sustained defective global economic policies and distorted
health care systems to the detriment of social justice.
The aspirations of new generations of health professionals, many of whom
have a deep commitment to reducing local and global inequities and improving
global health, offer the potential for reflexive examination of our goals and
visionary collaborative social endeavours. This book provides readers with
insights into such new frontiers of ethical and social progress, as well as
provocative perspectives on ethical dilemmas in international and global health
projects that could foster transformative pathways into a better future.
Index
Bangladesh 4, 123
Beauchamp, T.L. 23, 89
Beecher, H. 105
Belgium 6
Belmont Report 105
Benatar, S.R. 16–35, 52, 159
beneficence 89, 105
best practice 99, 130
biological materials 82
bioterrorism 69
Birn, A.-E. 3–15
Bishop, R. 39
Bradley, M. 119
brain drain 95
Brazil 4, 103, 123–4, 126, 138–9
briefcase model 123, 126
Bristol-Myers Squibb 142
Buddhism 22
Building Partnerships model 122–3
bureaucracy 109, 124
burnout 97
Burundi 144
Cameroon 118
Canada 4, 39, 44, 52, 75–7; challenges 90; clinical work 95; partnerships 119, 124; research 80; teaching
152–4
Canadian Coalition for Global Health Research (CCGHR) 122
Canadian Collaboration for Immigrant and Refugee Health 157
capacity building 79, 81–3, 118–20, 122, 124–6, 130–1, 133
case resolutions 44–5
case studies 36–7, 60, 67–70, 79, 90–100; advocacy 143–5; collaboration 123–6; research 109; Southern
perspectives 130–3; teaching 151–6
Castellano, M.B. 80
casuistry 22
categorical imperative 20
catharsis 42
Catholic University of Health and Allied Sciences - Bugando 125
census data 75
Central African Republic 3
Central America 131
Centre for Development Studies 121
Chad 3
Chan, A.K. 89–102
charity 31, 50–1, 95
checklists 114, 122, 156
Chichewa 90
Childress, J.F. 23, 66, 89
Chile 129
China 75
cholera 60, 62–3, 68–9
Christianity 22, 31
Cipla 139
citizenship 156
civil society 11, 31, 58, 70, 123, 138, 143
climate change 31
clinical trials 103–4, 110
clinical work 89–102, 118
codes of conduct 62, 80–1
Cold War 5, 7
Cole, D.C. 148–58
collaboration 117–28, 130–3, 153, 159
Colombia 49
colonialism 5–8, 12, 38, 75–6, 80, 129, 136
colonization 73, 77–8
Commission on the Social Determinants of Health 3
commodification 81
Commonwealth Fund 7
communism 31
competency evaluation 156–7
confidentiality 111–12
confinement 65–70 Congo 6
consensus building 141
consequentialism 21, 23, 25, 96
containment strategies 65–7
contextual considerations 109–13
contingency plans 113
contracts 110
corporate responsibility 38, 51–2, 141
cosmopolitanism 26
Costello, A. 120, 122
cotrimoxazole preventive therapy (CPT) 95
Cree 75
critical pedagogy 94, 150–1
cross-cultural perspectives 153–4
Cuba 6
Cuban National Institute of Hygiene 126
culture shock 39
Dagi, T.F. 41
Davis, W. 40
Dawson, A. 26
debt 17, 52
Declaration of Alma-Ata 53
Declaration of Helsinki 104–5
Declaration of Independence 47
Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples 76
Declaration of the Rights of Man 47
decolonizing methodologies 78–9
Deeley, S.J. 151
Democratic Republic of Congo 144
dengue fever 126
Denmark 130
deontology 20–1, 23, 25
descriptive ethics 20
desert-based theories 25
development studies 36
diabetes 76, 78
diarrhea 3, 7
disability-adjusted life years (DALYs) 21
dissemination 82, 121, 123, 133
distributive justice 25, 28, 31, 89
Doha Declaration 141
dominant discourse 17
Durkheim, E. 30–1
Dwyer, J. 157
earthquakes 97–9
East Africa 92, 155
East Asia 6
Eco-Health Initiative 126
Ecuador 123, 126
education 38–9, 47, 53, 76, 78–9; clinical work 94; ethics 148–57; partnerships 118, 125; research 104,
112–14
egalitarianism 25
Emanuel, E. 105, 109
Emergency Prevention System for Transboundary Animal and Plant Pests and Diseases 63
Emergency Surgery Coalition (ESC) 99
English language 75, 90, 119, 123, 133
Ethiopia 123
Eurocentrism 79
Europe 5–7, 31, 48, 62, 77
evaluation 156–7
Evert, J. 156
experiential learning 150–1
exploitation 120, 123
failed states 69
Fanon, F. 82
Farmer, P. 29
fear agenda 18
feedback 43, 91, 132, 156
feminism 23, 25
financial crisis 4, 17
FIOCRUZ 126
First Nation people 76
Food and Agriculture Organization (FAO) 63
food security 17
foot-and-mouth disease 63
Ford Foundation 7
Ford, N. 136–47
Forman, L. 46–57
Forti, S. 119
Framework Convention on Tobacco Control (FCTC) 62
frameworks 22–3, 27, 49, 52, 54–5; advocacy 137–42; governance 66; political context 143; teaching 149,
154
France 6, 47, 63
Freire, P. 151
French language 37, 119
fruitful partnership goals 121
future directions 157
future generations 62
G–8 58
G–20 58
Galeano, E. 31
Gates Foundation 7, 11
General Comment 14, 48
Geneva Conventions 7
Germany 104
GlaxoSmithKline 49
Glew, R.H. 129
Global Compact 51
Global Fund for AIDS, Tuberculosis and Malaria 11
Global Task Force 68
globalization 8, 17–18, 26, 103
Goldie, J. 157
good practice 118
Gostin, L. 66
governance 58–72
Greenland 76
grey zones 154
Guatemala 49, 104, 132
guideline documents 105, 114–15, 126–7, 130–3
Guidelines for Research in Partnership with Developing Countries 121
H1N1 63
H5N1 63, 69–70
Habte, D. 117–28
Haiti 97–9 Hajj 6
Hanson, L. 148–58
Hatfield, J. 117–28
Health for All by the Year 2000 7
Health Cluster 69
hegemony 78
hero myth 41
High-Income Countries (HICs) 8–9, 11, 30, 38, 40; clinical work 89, 91–3; human rights 51–2, 54;
Indigenous people 75, 77; partnerships 118–23; research 103; teaching 152–3, 155–6
Hinduism 22
HIV/AIDS 8, 10, 30, 37, 45; challenges 94–5; collaboration 118; human rights 50, 53; political context
137–43; research 76, 104
homelessness 38
human rights 8, 11, 21, 27–8, 38; governance 65–7; Indigenous people 76; political context 138, 140; role
46–57; teaching 149, 153
Human Rights Responsibilities for Pharmaceutical Companies 51
Humanitarian Charter 12
humanitarianism 41–2, 60, 68, 97–100, 105, 136, 153
humility 21, 27, 30, 38, 40–1; challenges 89; clinical work 92; human rights 51; teaching 156
Hunter, D. 26
Hussein, G. 103–16
Iceland 3
ideology 36, 77–8
Illich, I. 40
illiteracy 112
imperialism 5–7, 12, 79, 129
implementation 142
India 36, 49–50, 75, 103, 121, 138–40
Indigenous people 4, 6, 38, 73–85
Indigenous Physicians of Canada 74
Indonesia 4
industrial revolution 5
industrial waste 76
industrialization 113, 131
infection control 60, 62–7
information 18
informed consent 92–4, 98, 110–12, 114, 152, 154
institutional learning 155–6
intellectual property rights 18, 140–1, 143
International Classification of Diseases (ICD) 62
International Committee of the Red Cross (ICRC) 7
international community 68, 70
International Council of Nurses 12
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights 66
International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR) 48
International Development Research Centre (IDRC) 119, 122
International Federation of Red Cross and Red Crescent Societies 12
international health 5, 7–9, 12, 38
International Health Board and Division 7
International Health Regulations (IHR) 62, 67–70
International Labour Organization (ILO) 51, 60
international law 47–52, 60, 68, 139–40
international level 11
International Monetary Fund (IMF) 9, 11, 49, 58
International Sanitary Bureau for the Americas 6
International Sanitary Conference 6
International Sanitary Regulations (ISR) 62
interpretation 82, 154
introspection 37, 40–3, 51, 89, 156
Islam 22
Israel 49
Italian language 64
Italy 63
Jamaica 6
Japan 3, 7, 104
jaundice 95
John Paul II, Pope 31
Judaism 22
justice 25–30, 41, 51, 53, 82; clinical work 89, 96–7; future trends 159; Indigenous people 82; partnerships
118; research 104–5, 110; Southern perspectives 132, 134;teaching 156–7
Kant, I. 20–1
Kass, N. 66
Kellogg Foundation 7
Kenya 138
Kerala Research Programme on Local Level Development 121
Kiromera, A. 89–102
knowledge production 118, 127
Krieger, N. 28
Kumar, A. 117–28
neocolonialism 40, 99
neoliberalism 8, 17–18, 28, 54
Netherlands Development Assistance Research Council (RAWOO) 121–2
NeTropica 131 Neufeld, V.R. 117–28
New Constitutionalism 17
New Zealand 75–6
Nicaragua 153
Nixon, S. 46–57
Nomenclature with Respect to Diseases and Causes of Death 62
non-cognitivism 21–3
non-governmental organizations (NGOs) 7, 9–10, 27, 45, 58; clinical work 89, 95, 97; governance 60, 69;
partnerships 122, 124; political context 138, 140; research 111
nonmaleficence 89, 92
normative ethics 20
North 30–1, 40, 42–4, 77, 119, 121, 123,
129–34
North America 5, 7, 9, 31, 48, 95, 140, 142
Nuremberg trials 104
Obama, B. 104
obesity 76
OCAP 82
Office International des Epizooties (OIE) 63
Oldham, G. 118
oral history 77
orientation 37–8
Other 5, 41, 79
Ottawa Charter for Health Promotion 30, 53
Palestine 153
Pan-American Health Organization 6
Panama Canal 6–7
pandemic management 63–5
Panel on Threats, Challenges and Change 69
paradigm shifts 122
Partnership Assessment Tool (PAT) 123, 125
partnerships 9, 31–2, 43, 52, 81; benefits 118–19; challenges 91, 97, 105, 110, 114–15, 119–20; definition
118; principles 120–6; role 117–28; Southern perspectives 131; teaching 156–7
patents 30, 137, 140–3 paternalism 41, 131 peer review 133 penicillin 105 Peru 49 pesticides 76
pharmaceuticals 18, 30, 49, 51–2, 137–43, 145
Philpott, J. 41, 89–102
Pinto, A.D. 3–35, 73–85, 89, 156
placebo controls 103–4
plague 60, 62–4
pneumonia 3, 10
Pogge, T.W. 26, 52
Poland 31
policy windows 137
political context 113, 136–47
Political Declaration on the Prevention and Control of Non-Communicable Diseases 54
Political Declaration on the Social Determinants of Health 54 political economy 9–11, 17, 31 population
level 38, 52–3, 67 Portugal 5
Portuguese language 124
post-colonial syndrome 129
Pottie, K. 148–58
poverty 17, 26, 42, 44, 49; human rights 52; Indigenous people 76, 78; political context 141
power relations 16–17, 29, 31, 42, 52; clinical work 99; human rights 54; partnerships 120; teaching 152–3,
155
Presidential Commission for the study of Bloethical issues 105, 110
Primary Health Care Management (AGAP) 123–4
priority setting 120
private sector 58, 89
privatization 17
proportionality 66
public goods 27
Public Health Act 136
public health emergencies of international concern (PHEIC) 67–8
public sector 89, 95
Rawls, J. 25
Razack, S.H. 42
re-learning 37–8, 43–4
reasoning 23–5
reciprocity 82, 134
recruitment 153–4
reflective questions 90–1, 93, 96, 98
refugees 152, 157
Refugees and Global Health Program 157
rehabilitation services 98
relativism 21–3
religion 22
Republic of Korea 3
research 73, 79–82, 103–16, 121, 130–3, 153–6
Research Ethics Board 153–4
reserve system 77
resistance 73, 77–8
resource allocation 16–17, 25, 28, 31, 94–7, 119–20
right to health 48–50, 52–4
rights-based approaches 49–51
rinderpest 63
Rio Health Conference 4
Rockefeller Foundation 7
role models 99, 150, 155
Rouleau, K. 148–58
Royal Commissions 77
Russia 75
Rwanda 37, 44
Sami people 76
Sanchez, A. 129–35
SARS 68
Savulescu, J. 157
Scotland 4
security considerations 113
Security Council 69
self-determination 74, 76, 80–1
self-reflection 37, 44
September 11 2001 8, 18
service learning 130, 151, 157
sexually transmitted disease 76
Shah, S. 39
Sharma, M. 36–46
Singer, P.A. 26, 155
Singh, J.A. 58–72
Siracusa Principles 53, 66
sleeping sickness 144–5
Smith, L.T. 78, 80
Smylie, J. 73–85
social distancing 64–5
social factors 67–70
social justice 25, 27–30, 41, 53, 82; clinical work 89, 97; future trends 159; partnerships 118; research 110;
Southern perspectives 132, 134
social movements 29–30, 70
social structure 113
solidarity 27, 30–2, 52, 82, 89, 118, 134, 156–7
Sollicitudo Rei Socialis 31
South 30, 39–40, 43, 77, 113; partnerships 121–3; perspectives 129–35, 155–6
South Africa 50, 52, 103, 138, 140–2
South America 48, 123
South Asia 5–6, 123
Southeast Asia 144
Soviet Union 7
Spain 5
stereotypes 41–2
stewardship 81
structural adjustment 54
student activism 142
study placements 118
Sub-Saharan Africa 30, 37, 138, 144–5, 155
Sudan 144
Suez Canal 6
sustainability 43–4, 82–3, 109, 114, 125, 130–1, 159
Sweden 49, 119
Swedish International Development Agency (SIDA) 119
Swedish International Development Cooperation Agency 131
Swiss Commission for Research Partnerships with Developing Countries 121–2
Switzerland 60
syphilis 104–5
systematic approaches 24
values 11–12, 18, 23–4, 27, 40; clinical work 99; future trends 159; human rights 51; Indigenous people 80,
82; principles 30; research 113; Southern perspectives 129; teaching 149, 151, 153
Vienna, Congress of 6
Virchow, R. 136
virtue theory 21, 25
visceral experience 37, 39–40, 44
welfare theory 25
West Africa 45
Working Group on Ethics Guidelines for Global Health Training (WEIGHT) 130, 156
Working Group on International Research Collaborations (I-Group) 130
Workshop on Examining Core Elements of International Collaboration 130
World Bank 8–9, 11, 49, 58
World Conference on Social Determinants of Health 4
World Economic Forum 4
World Health Assembly (WHA) 60, 62
World Health Organization (WHO) 7–8, 27–8, 48, 60–3, 67–70, 138–9, 144–5
World Medical Association 12, 104
World Organisation for Animal Health 63
World Trade Agreements 140
World Trade Organization (WTO) 49, 63
World War I 7
World War II 7, 47, 60, 104
worldviews 43–4, 79–81
Wu, T. 39
Zambia 124
Zambian Forum for Health Research (ZAMFOHR) 124
Zarowsky, C. 121
Zimbabwe 68–9, 94, 130
zoonoses 60, 62–3
Zumla, A. 120, 122