Kant - Lectures On Logic
Kant - Lectures On Logic
Kant - Lectures On Logic
Lectures on logic
TRANSLATED AND E D I T E D BY
J. MICHAEL YOUNG
University of Kansas
CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY PRESS
THE JASCHE LOGIC
considerably. But it contains nothing more except for subtler divisions,
which, like all correct subtleties, sharpen the understanding, of course,
but are of no essential use.
Among modern philosophers there are two who have set universal logic
in motion: Leibniz and Wolff.
Malebranche and Locke did not treat of real logic, since they also deal
with the content of cognition and with the origin of concepts.
The universal logic of Wolff11 is the best we have. Some have combined
it with the Aristotelian logic, like Reusch,12 for example.
Baumgarten, a man who has much merit here, concentrated the Wolff-
ian logic,x3 and Meier then commented again on Baumgarten.
Crusius1* also belongs to the modern logicians, but he did not consider
how things stand with logic. For his logic contains metaphysical principles
and so to this extent oversteps the limits of this science; besides, it puts
forth a criterion of truth that cannot be a criterion, and hence to this
extent gives free reign to all sorts of fantastic notions.
In present times there has not been any famous logician, and we do not
need any new inventions for logic, either, because it contains merely the
form of thought.
III.
535
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
IMMANUEL KANT
1. according to their objective origin, i.e., according to the sources from which
alone a cognition is possible. In this respect all cognitions are either rational ox
empirical,
2. according to their subjective origin, i.e., according to the way in which a
cognition can be acquired by men. Considered from this latter viewpoint,
cognitions are either rational or historical, however they may have arisen in
themselves. Hence something that is subjectively only historical can be objec-
tively a cognition of reason.
f Reading "Allein" for "Alles," in accordance with the published list of printer's errors
(KI, xli).
536
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
THE JASCHE LOGIC
And as we see, mathematics has an advantage over philosophy here, in
that the cognitions of the former are intuitive cognitions while those of the
latter are only discursive. The cause of the fact that in mathematics we
consider quantities more lies in this, that quantities can be constructed a
priori in intuition, while qualities on the other hand cannot be exhibited in
intuition.
* "Schulbegriff?
h
"Weltbegriffe."
' " Vernunftkiinstler."
537
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
IMMANUEL KANT
For philosophy in the latter sense is in fact the science of the relation of
all cognition and of all use of reason to the ultimate end of human reason,
to which, as the highest, all other ends are subordinated, and in which
they must all unite to form a unity.
25 The field of philosophy in this cosmopolitan sense can be brought
down to the following questions:
1. What can I know?
2. What ough11 to do?
3. What may I hope?
4. What is man?
Metaphysics answers the first question, morals the second, religion the
third, and anthropology the fourth. Fundamentally, however, we could
reckon all of this as anthropology, because the first three questions relate
to the last one.
The philosopher must thus be able to determine
1. the sources of human knowledge,
2. the extent of the possible and profitable use of all knowledge, and finally
3. the limits of reason.
The last is the most necessary but also the hardest, yet the philodox
does not bother himself about it.
To a philosopher two things chiefly pertain: 1) Cultivation of talent and
of skill, in order to use them for all sorts of ends. 2) Accomplishment in
the use of all means toward any end desired. The two must be united; for
without cognitions7 one will never become a philosopher, but cognitions*
alone will never constitute the philosopher either, unless there is in addi-
tion a purposive combination of all cognitions and skills in a unity, and an
insight into their agreement with the highest ends of human reason.
No one at all can call himself a philosopher who cannot philosophize.
Philosophizing can be learned, however, only through practice and
through one's own use of reason.
How should it be possible to learn philosophy anyway? Every philosophi-
cal thinker builds his own work, so to speak, on someone else's ruins, but
no work has ever come to be that was to be lasting in all its parts. Hence
one cannot learn philosophy, then, just because it is not yet given. But even
granted that there were a philosophy actually at hand, no one who learned it
would be able to say that he was a philosopher, for subjectively his cogni-
tion l of it would always be only historical.
26 In mathematics things are different. To a certain extent one can proba-
bly learn this science, for here the proofs are so evident that anyone can
;
"Kenntnisse."
k
"Kenntnisse."
1
"KenntniB."
538
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
THE JASCHE LOGIC
become convinced of them; and on account of its evidence it can also, as it
were, be preserved as a certain and lasting doctrine.
He who wants to learn to philosophize, on the other hand, may regard
all systems of philosophy only as history of the use of reason and as objects
for the exercise of his philosophical talent.
Thus the true philosopher, as one who thinks for himself, must there-
fore make a free use of his reason on his own, not a slavishly imitative use.
But not a dialectical use, i.e., not one that aims only at giving cognitions the
illusion of truth and wisdom. This is the business of the mere sophist,
thoroughly incompatible with the dignity of the philosopher, as one who is
acquainted with and is a teacher of wisdom.
For science has an inner, true worth only as organ of wisdom. As such,
however, it is also indispensable for it, so that one may well maintain that
wisdom without science is a silhouette of a perfection to which we shall
never attain.
He who hates science but loves wisdom all the more is called a
misologist. Misology arises commonly out of an emptiness of scientific
cognitions'" and a certain vanity bound up with that. Sometimes, however,
people who had initially pursued sciences with great industry and fortune,
but who found in the end no satisfaction in the whole of their knowledge,
also fall into the mistake of misology.
Philosophy is the only science that knows how to provide for us this
inner satisfaction, for it closes, as it were, the scientific circle, and only
through it do the the sciences attain order and connection.
For the sake of practice in thinking for ourselves, or philosophizing, we
will have to look more to the method for the use of our understanding than
to the propositions themselves at which we have arrived through this
method.
IV. 27
m
"Kenntnissen."
539
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
IMMANUEL KANT
From this determination of the distinction between common and specu-
lative use of reason we can now pass judgment on the question, with
which people we must date the beginning of philosophizing. Among all
peoples, then, the Greeks first began to philosophize. For they first at-
tempted to cultivate cognitions of reason, not with images as the guiding
thread, but in abstracto, while other peoples always sought to make con-
cepts understandable only through images in concreto. Even today there are
peoples, like the Chinese and some Indians, who admittedly deal with
things that are derived merely from reason, like God, the immortality of
the soul, etc., but who nonetheless do not seek to investigate the nature of
these things in accordance with concepts and rules in abstracto. They
make no separation here between the use of the understanding in concreto
and that in abstracto. Among the Persians and the Arabs there is admittedly
some speculative use of reason, but the rules for this they borrowed from
Aristotle', hence from the Greeks. In Zoroaster's Zend-Avesta we find not the
slightest trace of philosophy. The same holds also for the prized Egyptian
wisdom, which in comparison with Greek philosophy was mere child's
play.
As in philosophy, so too in regard to mathematics, the Greeks were the
first to cultivate this part of the cognition of reason in accordance with a
speculative, scientific method, by demonstrating every theorem from
elements.
28 When and where the philosophical spirit first arose among the Greeks,
however, one cannot really determine.
The first to introduce the speculative use of reason, and the one from
whom we derived the first steps of the human understanding toward
scientific culture, is Tholes, the founder of the Ionian sect. He bore the
surname physicist, although he was also a mathematician, just as in general
mathematics has always preceded philosophy.
The first philosophers clothed everything in images, by the way. For
poetry, which is nothing other than a clothing of thoughts in images, is
older than prose. Thus in the beginning one had to make use of the
language of images and of poetic style even with things that are merely
objects of pure reason. Pherecydes is supposed to have been the first author
of prose.
The Ionians were followed by the Eleatics. The principle of the Eleatic
philosophy and of its founder, Xenophanes, was: In the senses there is decep-
tion and illusion, the source of truth lies only in the understanding alone.
Among the philosophers of this school, Zeno distinguished himself as a
man of great understanding and acuity and as a subtle dialectician.
In the beginning dialectic meant the art of the pure use of the under-
standing in regard to abstract concepts separated from all sensibility.
Thus the many encomia of this art among the ancients. Subsequently
these philosophers, who completely rejected the testimony of the senses,
540
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
THE JASCHE LOGIC
necessarily fell, given their claim, into many subtleties, and thus dialectic
degenerated into the art of maintaining and of disputing any proposition.
And so it became a mere exercise for the sophists, who wanted to engage in
reasoning" about everything, and who devoted themselves to giving illu-
sion the veneer of truth and to making black white. On account of this the
name sophist, by which one formerly meant a man who was able to speak
about all things rationally and with insight, became so hated and contempt-
ible, and the name philosopher was introduced instead.
Around the time of the Ionian school there appeared in Magna Graecia a
man of strange genius, who not only founded a school but also outlined 29
and brought into being a project, the like of which had never been before.
This man was Pythagoras, born on0 Samos. He founded, namely, a society
of philosophers who were united with one another into a federation
through the law of silence. His divided his hearers into two classes: the
acusmatics (axoua|ia6ixoi), who had simply to listen, and the acroamatics
(dxQoa^iaGtxoi), who were permitted to ask too.
Among his doctrines there were some exoteric ones, which he ex-
pounded to the whole of the people; the remaining ones were secret and
esoteric, determined only for the members of his federation, some of whom
he took into his trusted friendship, separating them wholly from the
others. He made physics and theology, hence the doctrines of the visible
and the invisible, the vehicle of his secret doctrines. He also had various
symbols, which presumably were nothing other than certain signs that
allowed the Pythagoreans to communicate with one another.
The end of his federation seems to have been none other than to purify
religion of the delusions of the people, to moderate tyranny, and to introduce more
lawfulness into states. This federation, which the tyrants began to fear, was
destroyed shortly before Pythagoras's death, however, and this philosophi-
cal society was broken up, partly by execution, partly by the flight and the
banning of the greatest part of its members. The few who remained were
novices. And since these knew little of the doctrines peculiar to Pythagoras,
we can say nothing certain and determinate about them. Subsequently
many doctrines that were certainly only invented were attributed to
Pythagoras, who by the way was also a very mathematical mind.
The most important epoch of Greek philosophy starts finally with Socrates.
For it was he who gave to the philosophical spirit and to all speculative
raissoniren.
Reading "auf" for "zu," with the published list of printer's errors (KI, xli).
541
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
IMMANUEL KANT
minds a wholly new practical direction. Among all men, too, he was almost
the only one whose behavior comes closest to the idea of a wise man.
Among his disciples the most famous is Plato, who occupied himself
30 more with Socrates' practical doctrines, and among Plato's disciples Aris-
totle, who in turn raised speculative philosophy higher.
Plato and Aristotle were followed by the Epicureans and the Stoics, who
were openly declared mutual enemies. The former placed the highest good
in a joyful heart, which they called pleasured the latter found it solely in
loftiness and strength ofsoul, whereby one can do without all the comforts of
life.
The Stoics, by the way, were dialectical in speculative philosophy, dog-
matic in moral philosophy, and in their practical principles, through which
they sowed the seed for the most sublime sentiments^ that ever existed,
they showed uncommonly much dignity. The founder of the Stoic school
is Zeno of Citium. The most famous men from this school among the
Greek philosophers are Cleanthes and Chrysippus.
The Epicurean school was never able to achieve the same repute that
the Stoic did. Whatever one may say of the Epicureans, however, this
much is certain: they demonstrated the greatest moderation in enjoyment
and were the best natural philosophers among all the thinkers of Greece.
We note here further that the foremost Greek schools bore particular
names. Thus Plato's school was called the Academy, Aristotle's the Ly-
ceum, the Stoics' school porticus (crnooc), a covered walkway, from which
the name Stoic is derived; Epicurus's school was called horti, because
Epicurus taught in gardens.
Plato 's Academy was followed by three other Academies, which were
founded by his disciples. Speusippus founded the first, Arcesilaus the sec-
ond, Carneades the third.
These Academies inclined toward skepticism. Speusippus and Arcesilaus
both adjusted their mode of thought to skepticism, and in this Carneades
went still further. On this account the skeptics, these subtle, dialectical
thinkers, are also called Academics. Thus the Academics followed the first
great doubter, Pyrrho, and his successors. Their teacher Plato had himself
given them occasion for this by expounding many of his doctrines dialogi-
cally, so that the grounds pro and contra were put forth, without his decid-
ing about the matter himself, although he was otherwise very dogmatic.
31 If we begin the epoch of skepticism with Pyrrho, then we get a whole
school of skeptics, who are essentially distinct from the dogmatists in their
mode of thought and method of philosophizing, in that they made it the
first maxim for all philosophizing use of reason to withhold one's judgment
p
"Wollust"
q
"Gesinnungen."
542
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
THE JASCHE LOGIC
even when the semblance" of truth is greatest; and they advanced the principle
that philosophy consists in the equilibrium of judgment and teaches us to uncover
false semblance.' From these skeptics nothing has remained for us, however,
but the two works of Sextus Empiricus, in which he brought together all
doubts.
r
"Scheine"
s
"Schein."
543
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
IMMANUEL KANT
dogmatic, although we did gain from him, in that we began to study the
nature of the soul better and more thoroughly.
As for what concerns the special dogmatic method of philosophizing
peculiar to Leibniz and Wolff, it was quite mistaken. Also, there is so much
in it that is deceptive that it is in fact necessary to suspend the whole
procedure and instead to set in motion another, the method of critical
philosophizing, which consists in investigating the procedure of reason
itself, in analyzing the whole human faculty of cognition and examining
how far its limits may go.
In our age natural philosophy is in the most flourishing condition, and
among the investigators of nature there are great names, e.g., Newton.
Modern philosophers cannot now be called excellent and lasting, because
everything here goes forward, as it were, in flux. What one builds the
other tears down.
In moral philosophy we have not come further than the ancients. As for
what concerns metaphysics, however, it seems as if we had been stopped
short in the investigation of metaphysical truths. A kind of indifferentism
toward this science now appears, since it seems to be taken as an honor to
speak of metaphysical investigations contemptuously as mere cavilling.1
And yet metaphysics is the real, true philosophy!
33 Our age is the age of critique, and it has to be seen what will come of the
critical attempts of our time in respect to philosophy and in particular to
metaphysics.
V.
"Griibeleien."
544
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
THE JASCHE LOGIC
one's prejudices amounts to deceiving someone with good intent. It would
be permissible to leave prejudices untouched, for who can occupy himself
with exposing and getting rid of every prejudice? But it is another question
whether it would not be advisable to work toward rooting them out with all
one's powers. Old and rooted prejudices are admittedly hard to battle,
because they justify themselves and are, as it were, their own judges. People
also seek to excuse letting prejudices stand on the ground that disadvan-
tages would arise from rooting them out. But let us always accept these
disadvantages; they will subsequently bring all the more good.
X.
* "Wahrscheinlichkeit."
1
"Scheinbarkeit."
583
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
IMMANUEL KANT
"numerirt."
Ak, "philosophischen"', 1st ed., "philosophischen.'
"ponderirt."
584
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
THE JASCHE LOGIC
be determined how far one still is from certainty or how close'' one is to it.
Also, it is not enough merely to answer each doubt, one must also resolve
it, that is, make comprehensible how the scruple has arisen. If this does
not happen, the doubt is only turned back, but not removed, the seed of the
doubt still remains. In many cases, of course, we do not know whether the
obstacle to holding-to-be-true has only subjective grounds in us or objec-
tive ones, and hence we cannot remove the scruple by exposing the illu-
sion, since we cannot always compare our cognitions with the object but
often only with each other. It is therefore modesty to expound one's
objections only as doubts.
p
Reading "wie nahe man" for "wie nahe man noch," with Hinske (KI, xlii).
q
"Kenntnisse."
r
"behauptende ErkenntniB."
585
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
IMMANUEL KANT
Concerning probability, we observed above that it is merely an approxima-
tion to certainty. Now this is especially the case with hypotheses, through
which we can never attain apodeictic certainty in our cognition, but always
only a greater or lesser degree of probability.
A hypothesis is a holding-to-be-true of the judgment of the truth of a ground
for the sake of its sufficiency for given consequences^ or more briefly, the
holding-to-be-true of a presupposition as a ground.
85 All holding-to-be-true in hypotheses is thus grounded on the fact that
the presupposition, as ground, is sufficient to explain other cognitions as
consequences. For we infer here from the truth of the consequence to the
truth of the ground. But since this mode of inference, as already observed
above, yields a sufficient criterion of truth and can lead to apodeictic
certainty only when all possible consequences of an assumed ground are
true, it is clear from this that since we can never determine all possible
consequences, hypotheses always remain hypotheses, that is, presupposi-
tions, whose complete certainty we can never attain. In spite of this, the
probability of a hypothesis can grow and rise to an analogue of certainty,
namely, when all the consequences that have as yet occurred to us can be
explained from the presupposed ground. For in such a case there is no
reason why we should not assume that we will be able to explain all
possible consequences thereby. Hence in this case we give ourselves over
to the hypothesis as if it were fully certain, although it is so only through
induction.
And in every hypothesis something must be apodeictically certain, too,
namely,
1. the possibility of the presupposition itself If, for example, to explain
earthquakes and volcanoes we assume a subterranean fire, then such a
fire must be possible, if not as a flaming body, yet as a hot one. For the
sake of certain other appearances, however, to make the earth out to be an
animal, in which the circulation of the inner fluids produces warmth, is to
put forth a mere invention and not a hypothesis. For realities may be made
up, but not possibilities; these must be certain.
2. The consequentia. From the assumed ground the consequences
must flow correctly; otherwise the hypothesis becomes a mere chimera.
3. The unity. It is an essential requirement of a hypothesis that it be
only one and that it not need any subsidiary hypotheses for its support. If,
in the case of a hypothesis, we have to have several others to help, then it
thereby loses very much of its probability. For the more consequences that
may be derived from a hypothesis, the more probable it is, the fewer, the
more improbable. Thus Tycho Brahe's hypothesis, for example, did not
suffice for the explanation of many appearances; hence he assumed sev-
86 eral new hypotheses to complete it.*9 Now here it is to be surmised that the
assumed hypothesis cannot be the real ground. The Copernican system,
on the other hand, is an hypothesis from which everything can be ex-
586
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016
THE JASCHE LOGIC
plained that ought to be explained therefrom, so far as it has yet occurred to
us. Here we do not need any subsidiary hypotheses {hypotheses subsidiarias).
There are sciences that do not allow any hypotheses, as, for example,
mathematics and metaphysics. But in the doctrine of nature they are
useful and indispensable.
APPENDIX
587
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. UCL, Institute of Education, on 01 Apr 2017 at 08:33:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810039.016