The Politics of Postanarchism 18 6 13
The Politics of Postanarchism 18 6 13
The Politics of Postanarchism 18 6 13
Items in Figshare are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise indicated.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/2158379X.2013.849369
PUBLISHER
VERSION
AM (Accepted Manuscript)
LICENCE
CC BY-NC-ND 4.0
REPOSITORY RECORD
Kinna, Ruth. 2019. “I Come to Praise Anarchism, Not to Bury It: Book Review”. figshare.
https://hdl.handle.net/2134/13682.
This item was submitted to Loughborough’s Institutional Repository
(https://dspace.lboro.ac.uk/) by the author and is made available under the
following Creative Commons Licence conditions.
Anarchism, Saul Newman argues, articulates the 'eternal aspiration of the radical tradition',
namely to break free from the conventions of sovereignty and enjoy a life without
government and in a condition of autonomy. His bold claim, made in the opening pages of
this book, seems to be addressed to a readership which identifies with radical politics, but not
persuade non-anarchist radicals, principally Marxists of various stripes, that the concept of
equal liberty and the principle of democracy can only be realised outside a statist framework
and that this positively utopian aspiration was also Marx's. However, running alongside this
anarchism', between the anti-politics which stems from the rejection of the state, and the
politics that anarchists develop through their activism. Endorsing the anarchist project,
Newman seeks to formulate an ‘anti-politics politics’ which questions the ideas that
anarchists have traditionally espoused and reflects instead on the possibilities arising from its
tensions and aporia. Deconstruction provides the key to this and it involves a wholesale
rejection of the conceptual frameworks that anarchists have employed as well as what
Newman sees as anarchism's flawed essentialism and the enlightenment thinking which
underpins it.
Newman uses the term postanarchism to describe this project, although the term – like
'communitarianism' - refers to a looser body of thought, now principally associated with the
1
work of Lewis Call, Todd May and Richard Day. As Süreyyya Evren has argued however,
Newman is pre-eminent in the field and his work has achieved international recognition not
only because he was one of the first to provide a scholarly account of postanarchism, but also
because he has produced a sustained body of research which highlights the distinctiveness of
postanarchism in contemporary political theory. In this book Newman is at pains to argue that
beyond' anarchism since it does not signify a temporal shift, or a coming 'after' anarchism's
presumed 'end'. Nor does the 'post' in postanarchism indicate that anarchism is somehow
being left behind. To the contrary: postanarchism only makes explicit anarchism's politics of
anti-politics (p. 11). It could be objected that this close association of anarchism and
postanarchism is not always well supported in the text and the benchmarks that Newman uses
to demonstrate exchange between the two are sometimes set quite low. At one point a refusal
to dismiss anarchism becomes the test of the engagement and Newman indicates that
revision. By incorporating 'insights from different thinkers and perspectives not commonly
associated with the anarchist tradition', Newman's aim is to radicalise anarchism, to 'broaden
its scope and expand its possibilities' (p. 20). Elsewhere, he introduces a different conception
of postanarchism's outside: a 'moment beyond anarchism' (p. 69). Pinpointing precisely how
he wants to couch the relationship between anarchism and postanarchism is one of the
fascinations of the book, and it is major theme in the two sets of discussions that run through
it.
explained by the way the relationship works in the two strands of Newman's argument. These
are closely inter-connected. Indeed, the positions which he recommends in the course of the
analysis emerge through a kind of dialectical unfolding, in which the focus of the discussion
2
shifts between critiques of various forms of anarchism and Marxism. The opening chapters,
where Newman re-assesses classical anarchism and outlines the features of an-archy or
as the first movement. This provides an anti-foundationalist, anti-essentialist platform for the
second. Drawing on the anarchist principles highlighted, Newman proceeds to discuss Marx,
Leninism, the post-Marxism of Laclau and Mouffe and the neo-Marxism of Hardt and Negri,
highlighting both the heretical value of anarchist critique and the anarchistic currents buried
within contemporary radical politics. In the final movement, the argument comes full circle.
Against Murray Bookchin and John Zerzan, both presented as exponents of classical
anarchism, Newman illustrates the distance between anarchism and postanarchism to argue
that postanarchism supports a neo-Stirnerite yet solidaristic emancipatory ethics. At the same
time, he develops a review of radical politics to show how postanarchism resonates with
actual movements and resistance struggles and the autonomous, utopian, horizontal practices
they support.
lies at the heart of Carl Schmitt's conception of politics. Newman does not wholly reject
Schmitt's understanding but he argues that Schmitt's claim, that opposition to the state is
tantamount to the rejection of politics, is mistaken. Newman argues that the autonomy of
politics that Schmitt rightly wanted to defend was wrongly tied to the state and that it is only
properly located in the antagonism, as Mouffe puts it, that exists beyond the depoliticised
order and uniformity that the state enforces. The faultiness of Schmitt's elision of the state
and politics is that it represses the conflicts inherent in human relations. To reject the
depoliticised order of the state is not, then, to advocate an apolitical social order as an
alternative to the state or to fall victim to the dichotomy between the state and society that
Schmitt constructed. Like Schmitt, postanarchists recognise the autonomy of politics but
3
argue that it can only exist beyond the boundaries of the state, in the insurgent forces of
acknowledge that the 'autonomy of the political ... invokes the idea of the politics of
autonomy'. (p. 10) The arguments he subsequently develops against Leninism and in defence
Newman’s arguments are presented with characteristic fluency and clarity but also
with passion and commitment. His mastery of the literature and the firmness of his political
convictions enables him move deftly through complex fields of critical theory. The
evaluations he presents are concise, and even those who are not as deeply immersed in
Continental political theory as he is should find it easy to follow. However, the analysis is
sometimes truncated: Newman tends to play ideas off against each other, using postanarchist
criteria to adjudicate between them and to present a kind of balance sheet of success and
failure. This approach subordinates detailed analysis theory to the assessment of principles or
positions that are selected because they dovetail, reinforce or run counter to his own. Simon
Critchely, for example, 'is right to suggest that the state today is too powerful for full-scale
assaults' but wrong to argue that it is 'a permanent, inevitable feature of political life'. Slavoj
Žižek 'raises important questions about the efficacy of politics outside the state' but his
alternative, which revives 'the vanguard party, the proletarian dictatorship and revolutionary
state terror' is 'completely defunct and outmoded.' (p. 116) Alain Badiou 'is correct in
suggesting that the (Hardt) and Negri thesis ... 'mirrors and fetishes the fluxes and flows of
global capital'. He is also right to think that 'the moment of separation essential for radical
politics must be theorised on a different ontological register, not that of History, but that of
the Event'. But his treatment of the political event as something 'so rare ... that it almost never
happens' is mistaken. Newman's view is that the event is something that takes place 'on an
4
Newman adopts the same approach to anarchism, and the attention he pays to the
contrasts between anarchism and postanarchism take up the greater part of the book. In the
past, Newman's account of anarchism, or what he calls classical anarchism has attracted
considerable criticism, particularly from historians of ideas. Since these have been so well-
rehearsed it seems churlish to go over the ground here. Yet it is difficult to move on from
debates about Newman's interpretation of anarchism and concentrate on the substance of the
normative argument for as long as anarchism or classical anarchism is used as the aunt sally
for postanarchist analysis. Moreover, the critique of anarchism that Newman develops sheds
The theoretical shortcomings of anarchism are listed early on in the book and they
include 'an essentialist conception of the subject; the universality of morality and reason, and
the idea of the progressive enlightenment of humankind; a conception of the social order as
naturally constituted (by natural laws, for instance) and rationally determined; a dialectical
view of history; and a certain positivism, whereby science could reveal the truth of social
relations'(p. 6). Variations on this sketch appear at regular intervals throughout the book and
they are advanced with blunt insistence. Classical anarchism, Newman reminds us later on,
discourse. Central to anarchism is the idea of rational progress, the unfolding of an immanent
social logic, and the emancipation of the subject from external constraints and oppressions –
motifs which ware incorporated also into liberalism and Marxism.' (p. 46)
example he claims that Kropotkin proposed 'a sort of moral and conceptual division between
society and the state, between humanity and political power' (p. 36). But this framing was not
confined to Kropotkin’s work. The 'Manichean division –between the natural social principle,
and the artificial political principle, between, in other words, society and the state', Newman
5
tells us, is 'central to classical anarchism' (p. 110). The point, Newman insists 'is that for
anarchists, people are intrinsically and organically part of a social whole, and that their
cooperative instincts tend to come to therefore in this social context. There is a kind of social
essentialism here, the idea that society embodies a rationality and a morality which is
immanent, whose laws and processes are scientifically observable; a logic ... that is unfolding
and emerging in opposition to the logic of power' (p. 39). The reason Newman insists on this
point might be explained by his concern to answer Schmitt's critique. The dichotomy between
the natural and the social that Newman builds into classical anarchism illuminates the
originality of the postanarchist challenge to the conception of politics and sovereignty that
Schmitt proposed. He argues: 'for anarchists, the autonomy of the political signifies precisely
the triumph of the organic and rational social principle over the artificiality of the political
principle of state power.' Postanarchists have a 'different way of thinking about the political
principle'. He continues: 'This is where the autonomy of the political translates into the
politics of autonomy ... In this formulation, the autonomy of the political is retained – it is
not subordinated to an organic social principle – but it is disconnected from the principle of
state sovereignty which has for so long served as the prison house of politics' (p. 99).
bypasses the discussion of sovereignty and critique of state theory which Kropotkin presents
in The State: Its Historic Role. He ignores the substantial body of sociological and
anthropological research that anarchists have discussed since the nineteenth century and
which belies the treatment of 'natural' society that he attributes to classical traditions.
Newman says that postanarchism 'seeks to detach society from a natural, moral foundation
outside politics' (p.112). Kropotkin would have agreed. Newman's attempt to counter the
position leads him to read back into anarchism an understanding of the distinction between
the state of nature and government, familiar in contract theory and central to Hobbes'
6
construction of sovereignty, that Kropotkin and others dismissed as a myth designed to
legitimise monopolistic and hierarchical configurations of power. But it also hints at the
terms, Newman reveals the extent to which postanarchism is rooted in a theoretical approach
that is deeply statist, even while he seeks to move beyond it. The real disagreement with
Kropotkin is that Newman aims 'to detach the notion of politics from the state' (p. 112)
principles and organisation. On his account, the state is not a depoliticised order, but an order
in which politics is practiced in particular ways. The political extended across a spectrum of
forms, from anarchy to state; it was not rooted in one particular order or another.
The tripartite distinction between the depoliticised state, postanarchist politics and
depoliticised natural anarchy frame Newman's discussions of power and utopianism. The
principle claim Newman seeks to make is that anarchism naively anticipates the abolition of
power, unlike postanarchism which understands that 'even radical politics' is 'an activity
conducted within a field constructed by power'. This argument seems to depend on the
power relations 'are both pervasive and constitutive of social identities, practices and
discourses' (p. 6). While Newman is clearly correct to argue that anarchists have not typically
conceptualised power in these terms – and certainly not the nineteenth-century proponents of
classical anarchism that he identifies in the book - the warning he issues to anarchists about
the permanence of power relations is actually rooted in the conjunction between power and
politics rather than the nuances of poststructuralist analysis. The uncontroversial statement
that politics 'suggests ... some sort of engagement with relations of power' gains its full force
when set in the context of the claim that anarchists believe 'power and authority are unnatural
and inhuman' (p. 6). Newman's observation that this belief is gainsaid by the problem of
7
voluntary servitude and 'a desire for authority and self-domination that was revealed by
psychoanalysis from, Freud to Reich' rings hollow in its application to anarchists who
and the brutal operation of systems of conscription. But leaving the historical and contextual
arguments aside, the philosophical differences that Newman wants to find also appear quite
thin. The discussion of anarchism's utopianism provides another illustration of the problem.
Newman recommends a particular kind of utopianism as 'a vital dimension of any politics
that takes emancipation and radical transformation as central' (p. 67). In terms reminiscent of
Oscar Wilde, he declares 'that the vision of a society without government has to be taken as
the ultimate ethical and political horizon of any radical politics worthy of its name' (p. 67).
Postanarchist utopianism is defined against the idea of the blueprint. Early on in the book
Newman says that he will 'formulate a different approach to a utopianism' one which will not
'lay down a precise programme for the future' but will instead 'provide a point of alterity or
exteriority as a way of interrogating the limits of this order' (p. 7). While the implication
seems to be that anarchism is utopian in this programmatic sense, the charge of blueprint
utopianism is not one that he lays at anarchism's door. The utopianism of anarchism is
instead located in the harmonious, apolitical natural society that anarchy represents. Once the
assumptions about the apolitical character are set aside, non-postanarchist utopianism
dovetails surprisingly closely with postanarchist forms. Newman comments: 'I have argued ...
that power relations will never be entirely eliminated, and that anarchists must always be
aware of the potential for new forms of domination that can emerge in any form of social
correct in stressing the need for some sort of alternative vision of a social order in motivating
8
Newman's discussion of anarchism is only a part of this book, albeit a substantial one,
and it seems a pity that the real contribution that he wants to make, which is to put anarchism
at the heart of radical political theory, depends on a claim to postanarchism's originality that
is distracting and which occupies space that might be given over to a more detailed critical
analysis of the contemporary writers with whom Newman engages. Newman does make
some interesting and important interventions in this book, about the character of the
relationship between ethics and politics. But the analysis supporting these insights is not
radical theory is covered in 35 pages in chapter 4. Wilde argued that originality was properly
understood to be about judgment and the treatment of a subject, not the development of new
content. On this view, the value of postanarchism does not rest on showing its distinctiveness
from anarchism, in any of the different ways in which this relationship might be cast, but on
hints at postanarchism's potential but for all its many merits does not fully exploit it.
Ruth Kinna
Loughborough University
Reference
Evren, S., 2011. 'How New Anarchism Changed the World (of Opposition) after Seattle and
Gave Birth to Post-Anarchism', In: D. Rouselle and S. Evren, eds. Postanarchism: A Reader.
London: Pluto, p. 8.