Ignorance and Mistake in Criminal Law
Ignorance and Mistake in Criminal Law
Ignorance and Mistake in Criminal Law
Fall 1957
Recommended Citation
Hall, Jerome (1957) "Ignorance and Mistake in Criminal Law," Indiana Law Journal: Vol. 33 : Iss. 1 , Article
1.
Available at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj/vol33/iss1/1
9. Steinmeyer v. People, 95 Ill. 383, 389 (1880) ; Pond v. People, 8 Mich. 149
(1860); Thomas v. The King, 59 Commw. L.R. 279, 299-300 (Austr. 1937).
10. See Prichard, Duty and Ignoranwe of Fact, XVIII PROC. BRITISH ACADEMY 67
(1932). Prichard's essay is summarized and discussed by Ross, FOUNDATIONS OF ETHICS
148-65 (1939).
11. ETHICA NICOMACHEA, bk. V.8, 1135a, 20-25 (Ross transl. 1925).
12. 1 HALE, PLEAS OF THE CROWN 42 (1736).
13. Levett's Case, Cro. Car. 538, 79 Eng. Rep. 1064 (K.B. 1638).
14. Ibid. Cf. ". . . if this be ignorance of fact it excuses.... ".The Mirror of
Justices 137 (Seld. Soc'y ed. 1893).
15. Williams v. State, 18 Ala. App. 473, 93 So. 57, 58 (1922). On the above
ground the following instruction was reversed: ". . . the jury is told that the right
of self-defense cannot be exercised 'in any case or to any degree NOT NECESSARY,
and that the party making the defense is permitted to use no instrument and no power
beyond what will prove simply effectual.'" People v. Anderson, 44 Cal. 65, 69 (1872).
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
25. Hill v. State, 194 Ala. 11, 23, 69 So. 941, 946 (1915), 2 A.L.R. 509, 518 (1919).
26. Nalley v. State, 28 Tex. Ct. App. 387, 391, 13 S.W. 670, 671 (1890).
27. State v. Towne, 180 Iowa 339, 160 N.W. 10 (1916).
28. ". . . if the defendant by voluntarily putting himself under the influence of
liquor incapacitated himself for taking such a view of the situation as a reasonably
prudent man would have taken under the circumstances, and, in consequence thereof, he
acted upon an exaggerated or unjustifiable belief as to the necessity for taking the life
of the deceased in defense of his own, such belief could not avail him as a defense to
the charge in the indictment." Springfield v. State, 96 Ala. 81, 85-86, 11 So. 250, 252
(1892).
29. In Yates v. People, 32 N.Y. 509 (1865) the court did take account of the
defendant's "extreme infirmity of vision."
30. "No man can be acquitted of responsibility for a wrongful act, unless he em-
ploys 'the means at command to inform himself.' Not employing such means, though
he may be mistaken, he must bear the consequences of his negligence." Dotson v. State,
62 Ala. 141, 144 (1878).
31. Hill v. State, 194 Ala. 11, 69 So. 941 (1915), 2 A.L.R. 509, 518 (1919); State
v. Terrell, 55 Utah 314, 186 Pac. 108 (1919), 25 A.L.R. 497, 525 (1923). The require-
ment of "reasonableness" does not apply to perjury, People v. Von Tiedeman, 120 Cal.
128, 52 Pac. 155 (1898), or to the various property offenses. See note 109 infra, re-
ferring to mistakes in property law in relation to mens rea. "If they [defendants] did
so believe it is not material whether their belief was well founded or not." Lewis v.
People, 99 Colo. 102, 117, 60 P.2d 1089, 1096 (1936).
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
32. In Regina v. Rose, 15 Cox C.C. 540 (1884), the judge's instruction indicated
that a verdict of murder could be returned against the defendant who unreasonably
believed he was preventing a homicide. A.R.N.Cross suggests that this would now
be manslaughter. 51 LAw Soc'Y GAZ. 515 (1954). Cf. Miles v. State, 52 Tex. Crim.
561, 108 S.W. 378 (1908).
33. Allison v. State, 74 Ark. 444, 86 S.W. 409, 413 (1904) ; State v. Thomas, 184
N.C. 757, 761-62, 114 S.E. 834, 836 (1922) ; State v. Doherty, 72 Vt. 381, 48 Atl. 658
(1900) ; State v. Sorrentino, 31 Wyo. 129, 224 Pac. 420, 424 (1924).
34. E.g., Art. 19 of the Swiss Federal Penal Code provides: "If the offender had
been able to avoid the error by acting with due caution, he shall be punished for neg-
ligence, provided that the negligent commission of the act is punishable." Translation,
30 J. CRIM. L., C. & P.S. Sup,. 22 (1939).
35. HALL, op. cit. szpra note 23, c. 6. Cf. infra pp. 21-23.
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
they could not have done better at that time, Aristotle maintained that
some of them might nevertheless be found culpable by reference to their
past. While holding that morality concerns only voluntary conduct, he
took an extremely rigorous position in this regard. He specifies an in-
toxicated person who cannot function properly and he finds him culpable
on the ground that he need not have become intoxicated. In the past he
"willed" in certain respects, which led to the habit of indulgence. Ac-
cording to Aristotle, moral culpability may be posited in such cases on
the voluntary actions performed or omitted in the past which had the
cumulative effect of incapacitation.
But there are serious difficulties with this subtle ethics as regards its
application to criminal law. In order to implement that position, it would
be necessary to survey the entire course of the defendant's life, to decide,
e.g., whether one who was not competent to drive an automoblie with due
care had deliberately refrained from bicycle-riding, chosen not to learn
about machinery, etc., including all his overt acts that had any bearing
on the incompetence which now makes his lack of skill or ignorance in-
vincible. If the driver were a woman who could not gauge a distance or
the angle of a curve, it would be necessary to decide whether her present
ignorance was determined by her own culpable acts and omissions or was
always invincible. Thus, while there is no escape from the sheer logic
of the Aristotelian thesis and some may also find much merit in his
ethics, the factual difficulties are so considerable as to preclude their use
in criminal law. Here it is not only a question of ethical principle; the
punishment of human beings within the limits and limitations of a legal
system is also involved. Can any child or youth foresee that a series of
petty transgressions may lead years in the future to a condition of ignor-
ance or inefficiency that produces serious harms? Is there any feasible
basis to impute present criminal liability for harms caused by voluntary
lapses in the distant past? Accordingly, one would wish to delegate that
kind of adjudication to an omniscient philosopher-king who had precise
records and the wisdom to assess culpability for a major harm caused
many years later by minor actions that were completely unrelated, in
human prescience, to any serious consequences.
On the other hand, if an historical inquiry, a "case-history," is limited
to the determination of the defendant's present competence, it is feasible
to apply at least certain phases of it to criminal liability. For example, as
will be seen later with reference to ignorantiajuris, if illness or absence
from the country made it impossible to acquire necessary information,
that should be a defense. But while it will be generally agreed that such
invincible ignorance should bar penal liability, it by no means follows
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
that vincible ignorance should incur it. For vincible ignorance may im-
ply mere negligence ("unreasonableness").
For the purposes of ethical inquiry, persons who have the compe-
tence to acquire necessary information and fail to do that may be deemed
culpable. But, it is submitted, if only voluntary harm-doing merits the
severe blame implied in penal liability, it cannot be shown that either
negligent behavior or the commission of a harm in ignorance of material
facts is culpable in that degree or in that sense.41 For there is a great
difference between asserting that a person must voluntarily commit a
certain harm to be sufficiently culpable to merit penal sanctions and as-
serting that he is thus culpable if he could have prevented himself from
involuntarily causing a harm. So, too, those who support the present
limitation of "reasonableness" on ignorantiafacti might find it difficult
to prove that a person who had the capacity to acquire adequate knowl-
edge or to use due care is culpable in the above degree and sense even
though he acted in the absence of such knowledge and skill.
Much of the discussion of negligent and uninformed behavior by
modern writers on ethics becomes tangled in the quagmires of an am-
biguous syllogism that is silent at the crucial point. Thus it is said: If
the actor had wanted to, or if he had thought of it, he could have per-
formed the act properly. But voluntary harm-doing, i.e., in the knowledge
of at least the risk of that, is quite different from a lack of sensitivity
to the risk of injuring others or to the need for knowledge of the like-
lihood of doing that. Thus, it is not logical to assert that because a per-
son is competent to do an act properly if he thinks about it, therefore he
is culpable for doing harm inadvertently. If the argument is re-
stated to base culpability upon insensitivity (incapacity) regarding the
need for knowledge, it must also be rejected on the ground that what is
required to support the kind or degree of moral condemnation character-
istic of, and defensible in, modern penal law is voluntary action-at least
reckless conduct. The chief conclusion to be drawn from the above
analysis is that action in ignorance of material facts, where no more than
negligence is shown, should not incur penal liability. But if the judg-
41. Cf. "If an Action be done without any malicious design, and not with Ig-
norance voluntarily contracted, but such only as crept in by Inconsideration and In-
advertency, the Imputation is not altogether taken away, yet it is considerably dimin-
ished. Hither we may refer the Case propos'd by Aristotle of a Woman that gave a
Love-Potion to her Gallant of which he died. Now the Athenian Judges absolv'd the
'Woman from this Indictment, because she did the Fact undesignedly, and only miss'd
the Effect of her Potion, and procur'd his Death instead of his Love, which was her
only Aim. But to make this Sentence equitable, it must have been suppos'd as a
Principle, that the Woman never so much as thought the Potion she administered was
any way hurtful." PUFENDORF, OF THE LAWS OF NATURE AND OF NATIONS, bk. I, c. V,
at 40 (1703).
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
45. 13 Cox C.C. 138 (1875). The earlier English cases are there cited. Similar
decisions in this country are: People v. Dolan, 96 Cal. 315, 31 Pac. 107 (1892);
Heath v. State, 173 Ind. 296, 90 N.E. 310 (1909) ; State v. Ruhl, 8 Iowa 447 (1859)
People v. Marks, 146 App. Div. 11, 130 N.Y. Supp. 524 (1st Dep't 1911).
46. Regina v. Prince, 13 Cox C.C. 138, 155-56 (1875).
47. "I do not say illegal, but wrong." Id. at 141.
48. Id. at 143. Cf. "And though the wrong intended was even not indictable, the
defendant would still be liable, . . . ." State v. Ruhl, 8 Iowa 447, 450 (1859).
49. Rex v. Maughan, 24 Cr. App. R. 130 (1934).
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
to find that the defendant was in doubt regarding the material facts. 50
5 52
In addition to various sexual offenses, bigamy and adultery,
strict liability, based on the exclusion of even reasonable mistakes of fact
from the doctrine of ignorantiafacti, has been applied to embezzlement,
the sale of narcotics and in cases of persons defending others against
apparent serious aggression.5" Heavy penalties are imposed in such
cases. Thus strict penal liability has swept over a vast terrain in the
past century,5 and the conclusions reached above in the context of mis-
take of fact support that emphasized elsewhere : this branch of our law
is so thoroughly disorganized, rests so largely on conjecture and dubious
psychology, and effects such gross injustice as to require major reform.
Mention must be made, finally, of a type of factual ignorance which
is not usually discussed in relation to ignorantiafacti, namely, ignorance
of elementary science, e.g., regarding sickness, medicine and the use of
physicians. The defendants in these cases are sometimes very stupid
persons, unaware of the gravity of a child's illness and the availability
of physicians.5 In other cases the defendants are members of religious
sects which believe, e.g., that the devout cannot be harmed even by the bite
of a rattlesnake" or that it is sinful to use medicine. There are sur-
prisingly few reports of such cases, apparently because prosecutors are
reluctant to initiate proceedings and, when they do, juries are apt to
acquit.55 But there have been a number of convictions, and the relevant
holdings imply that ignorance of ordinary factual knowledge, possessed
by every "normal" adult in the community except such eccentrics as
these defendants, is no defense. Although mitigation is undoubtedly
frequent, it is assumed that the ignorance was "unreasonable," and the
50. "Consequently, doubt is not error, nor is suspension of judgment, for in such
experiences there is no conviction that we now know." Aron, op. cit. supra note 8, at
57 n. 1.
51. See infra pp. 30-34.
52. State v. Anderson, 140 Iowa 445, 118 N.W. 772 (1908); Commonwealth v.
Eiwell, 43 Mass. (2 Met.) 190 (1840).
53. State v. Cook, 78 S.C. 253, 59 S.E. 862 (1907), 15 L.R.A. (n.s.) 1013 (1908).
54. But cf. The English Criminal Law Amendment Act, 1922, 12 & 13 Geo. 5, c.
56, § 2, which provides: "Reasonable cause to believe that a girl was of or above the age
of sixteen years shall not be a defence to a charge under section five . . . of the
Criminal Law Amendment Act, 1885. . . . Provided that in the case of a man of
twenty-three years of age or under the presence of reasonable cause to believe that the
girl was over the age of sixteen years shall be a valid defence on the first occasion
on which he is charged with an offense under this section."
55. HALL, GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF CRImINAL LAW, C. 10 (1947).
56. Stehr v. State, 92 Nebr. 755, 139 N.W. 676 (1913).
57. Kirk v. Commonwealth, 186 Va. 839, 44 S.E.2d 409 (1947).
58. Larson, Child Neglect in the Exercise of Religious Freedomn, 32 CHI.-KENT L.
REv. 283 (1954).
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
support the hypothesis that the two doctrines move in different directions
because they function differently in relation to the moral significance
of criminal law. But we must first relate the distinctions drawn above
regarding law and fact to ignorantia.
"Ignorantia!"
Of the various sources of difficulty encountered in analysis of
ignorantiajuris, the most serious one concerns the meaning of "ignoran-
tia." Since that term suggests a negative condition, i.e., the absence of
"knowledge," analysis of this problem must deal with the latter term. It
may be inferred from the distinctions drawn above between fact and law,
that perception is a primitive form of knowledge, and that knowledge of
law, the cognition of legal propositions, is much more complex. More
important is that perception of facts is relatively certain; given external
objects, all normal persons who perceive them under "adequate" condi-
tions arrive at uniform judgments, and errors are attributed to excite-
ment, negligence, poor conditions of observation, intoxication, and the
like. But with reference to knowledge of law, there can never be such
certainty as that. Although it is true that one is sometimes just as cer-
tain that a particular situation is within a rule as he is that he sees an
exernal object, much more is required to determine the meaning of the
rule. To do that one must take account of the vagueness of legal rules
at their periphery, the unavoidable attribute of all propositions that refer
to facts. Hence, no one can say with certainty that a rule of law means
precisely thus and so.
These differences regarding knowledge of law and knowledge of
fact indicate that ignwrantiafacti is an apt expression because "mistake"
implies the possibility of certitude but that ignorantiajuris is not apt. In
any case, whatever view of the two kinds of knowledge or ignorantia is
preferred, the relatively much greater difficulty of knowing the law sug-
gests that the two doctrines may implement very different policies. This
preliminary insight into the nature of legal knowledge provides a per-
spective from which to gauge the significance of various theories of
ignorantiajuris.
Earlier Theories
The Roman theory-that the law is "definite and knowable"" 2-
seems to have been interpreted quite literally. As Blackstone noted,
"every person of discretion . . . may . . . know" it ;"3 hence ignorance
62. 1 AUSTIN, LEcTuRs ON JURISPRUDENCE 497 (4th ed. 1879). See PUFENDORF,
op. cit. supra note 41, bk. 1, c. 3, at 10.
63. 4 BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES *27.
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
64. This general opinion was rejected by Binding, who limited the exceptional
treatment to civil law. Ryu and Silving, Error Juris-A Comparative Study, 24 U. OF
CHI. L. REv. 421, 425 (1957).
65. AUSTIN, op. cit. supra note 62, at 498.
66. Id. at 499.
67. HOLMES, THE COMMON LAW 48 (1881).
68. AusTiN, op. cit. supra note 62, at 499.
69. HOLMES, op. cit. supra note 67.
70. See Gordon v. State, 52 Ala. 308 (1875).
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
by placing the burden of proof upon the defendant does not meet Austin's
position. If ignorance of the law is unprovable,' how is the nature of
that negative issue changed by requiring the defendant to establish his
ignorance, i.e., by a technical rule of procedure? Thus, it must be con-
cluded that, if his position is literally interpreted, Austin stood on firm
ground.7 In addition, Austin's doubts regarding proof of negligence
are certainly warranted.
On the other hand, however, it must be recognized that it is possible
to prove that a person had an opportunity to acquire certain knowledge
or per contra, that due, e.g., to illness, his ignorance in the above "opera-
tional" sense, was invincible. Thus, it might be shown that certain in-
formation had been brought to the defendant's attention, e.g., that he was
handed a booklet containing certain laws, that an administrative board
mailed him a set of regulations, or that -certain rules governing his vo-
cation were published in a newspaper to which he subscribed. From such
facts, it might be presumed that he read the law in question; it might
also be inferred that, being a normal adult, he -understood it or enough
of it to satisfy a relevant mevns rea. But for reasons to be discussed below,
the defense of invincible ignorance of the law, since it proceeds on the
premise that knowledge of law is material, can have only a limited ap-
plication, i.e., to certain petty offenses.
It is significant that both Austin and Holmes,7 2 while they differed
regarding the practical implementation of a defense of ignorance of the
law, shared a common utilitarian viewpoint which, in addition, did not
distinguished major crimes from petty offenses. Holmes's thesis, that
to allow the defense would "encourage ignorance where the law-maker
has determined to make men know and obey," is surely questionable.
For this implies that knowledge of the penal law is material, whereas
such knowledge is usually irrelevant. Moreover, it can hardly be estab-
lished that a principal purpose of penal law is to stimulate legal educa-
tion; even Bentham balked at punishment as a method of making the law
known.7 3 In Holmes' theory, if a defendant who, e.g., had shot his wife's
paramour in adultery, could show that he had studied the criminal law
long and assiduously before doing that, he should be entitled at least to
71. Cf. "But the proof of a belief in the existence of private rights, such as
ownership, can-be found in objective evidence of conduct, while belief in the existence
of a general law generally would have no such objective manifestations." Note, 45
HARV. L. REV. 336, n. 19 (2) (1931). See Winfield, Mistake of Law, 59 L.Q. REV. 327
(1943).
72. Holmes' theory has been accepted by GLANVILLE WILLIAMS, CRIMINAL LAw
§ 115 at 385 (1953).
73. 6 THE WORKS oF JEREMY BENTHAM 519-20 (Bowring ed. 1843).
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
74. Cf. Holmes, J.,: "It may be assumed that he intended not to break the
law . . . but if the conduct described crossed the line, the fact that he desired to keep
within it will not help him. It means only that he misconceived the law." Horning v.
District of Columbia, 254 U.S. 135, 137 (1920).
75. Also cf. "If he knew that his representations were false, and if he intended to
deceive by them, and, by the help of the motives thus created, to get Kearns' property, he
had the only criminal intent which the statute requires." Holmes, J., in Commonwealth
v. O'Brien, 172 Mass. 248, 256, 52 N.E. 77, 80 (1898).
76. See RADULEScO, DE L'INFLUENCE DE L'ERREUR SUR LA RksPoNSrBILITt
PANALE 15-17 (1923).
77. "Without it justice could not be administered." 1 BISHOP, CRIMINAL LAW 197
(9th ed. 1923); People v. O'Brien, 96 Cal. 171, 176, 31 Pac. 45, 47 (1892). The like
views of Ortolan, Laborde, Garcon and Garraud are summarized by RADULESCO, op Cit.
supra note 76, at 41-43. "That ignorance of law does not exempt from obligation is a
principle which prevails in all legal orders and which must prevail, since, otherwise, it
would be almost impossible to apply the legal order." KELSEN, GENERAL THEORY OF
LAW AND STATE 72 (1945).
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
78. The same considerations do not apply to ignorantia facti because: (a) Such a
mistake is particular, i.e., it concerns a unique experience which in no way opposes the
meaning of rules of law. These meanings are generalizations; they can be and are
fitted to mistakes of fact, while, as seen, a plea of mistake of law challenges the
meaning of the rules. (b) Behavior in ignorance of the facts is "involuntary"; it is
not immoral while at least action violative of a major criminal law is immoral re-
gardless of ignorance of the law.
79. See Perkins, Ignorance and Mistake in Criminal Law, 88 U. OF PA. L. REV. 35,
36-37 (1939) and see notes 150 and 151 infra.
80. Weston v. Commonwealth, 111 Pa. 251, 2 Atl. 191 (1885).
81. People v. Cook, 39 Mich. 236 (1878).
82. People v. Weiss, 276 N.Y. 384, 12 N.E.2d 514 (1938).
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
83. HALL, op. cit. supra note 55 at 159-61. Cf. SALMOND, JURISPRUDENCE 82 (1924).
84. See Gurvitch, Is the Antithesis of "Moral Man" and "Immoral Society" True?,
52 PmILos. Rav. 533 (1943).
85. Special considerations relevant to petty offenses are discussed infra pp. 34-39.
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
86. "If to act in accordance with one's conviction is always,.in one sense, to do one's
duty, it remains true that one's conscience may be very much mistaken and in need of
improvement." Ross, FoUNDATIONS OF ETHICS 165 (1939).
87. See HALL, op. cit. supra note 55, c. 2.
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
in the future be incorporated into the criminal law, as, e.g., has occurred
in England with reference to infanticide immediately following birth.
But there is a method of making such progress which centers in the
specification of criteria that are compatible with the rules and doctrines
of the existing law. The survival of the principle of legality requires
the preservation of the definiteness of the rules, which must not be dis-
solved by the incompatible recognition of the opinions of litigants and
lawyers as authoritative.
There are, thus, two aspects of the rationale of ignorantia juris
neminem excusat. The doctrine is an essential postulate of a legal order,
a phase. of the "rule of law." And, second, legality cannot be separated
from morality in a sound system of penal law. In such a system, at
least the penal law on the major crimes represents both the formal
criteria of legality and sound values. It follows that the two theories
discussed above, (1) that the principle of legality implies the doc-
trine of ignorantiajuris, and (2) that the doctrine is necessary to the
maintenance of the objective morality of the community, can be combined
in a single rationale-the legally expressed values may not be ignored or
contradicted. Thus, the direction of reform of the doctrine is also indi-
cated, e.g., to take account of ignorance or mistake of property laws, other
technical rules and certain petty penal laws. This will be discussed later.
With reference to the position presented above, it is possible, of
course, to challenge the underlying premise-the desirability of having a
legal system. Some may prefer decision by individuals who exercise
completely unfettered power; and occasionally cases arise regarding
which almost everyone wishes a decision could be rendered without re-
striction by existing laws. But this issue need not be discussed here. 8
For present purposes it is necessary to assume the existence of a legal sys-
tem and the consequent implications of the principle of legality. The
validity of the above theory of ignorantiajuris neminem excusat must be
tested by criteria which are relevant to that basic premise.
Application of the Rationale of Ignorantia Juris
In light of the above discussion we may consider certain problems
raised in the literature and case-law on ignorantiajuris. Two proposed
exceptions to ignorantiajuris neminem excusat-mistake based on the
"advice of counsel" and the "indefiniteness" of a law-may be disposed
of briefly. The above analysis reveals the reason for the uniform hold-
ing that the advice of counsel regarding the meaning of a criminal law
is not a defense. It is not that the lawyer may be incompetent or cor-
88. Ibid.
INDIANA LAW JOURNTAL
rupt,89 but that lawyers are not law-declaring officials; it is not their
function to interpret law authoritatively. Suppose that an opinion was
obtained from the most distinguished lawyers, that the subject was not
complicated, that numerous precedents were found, and that the law was
clear and simple-in short, a situation where knowledge of law was easy
to acquire. A person acts upon such advice, then a prosecution is in-
stituted. His plea of ignorance would nonetheless be invalid because the
court before whom the case is tried cannot substitute the opinion of
counsel for its own "knowledge."9
This leads to a major conclusion previously suggested, namely, that
"knowledge" of law (and thus ignorance or mistake of it) has not only
the usual meaning discussed above but also a meaning that is distinctive
and decisive as regards the doctrine of ignorantiajuris. "Knowledge"
of the law in this context means coincidence with the subsequent interpre-
tation of the authorized law-declaring official. If there is coincidence,
the defendant knew the law and his action is legal. If there is not co-
incidence, it can avail nothing that the defendant thought his conduct was
legal.9 This is the special meaning of ignorantia,which distinguishes it
from the ordinary meaning of ignorance, expressed, e.g., in ignorantia
facti.
The above analysis also indicates the invalidity of the other pro-
posal, that indefiniteness in the meaning of a penal law should provide an
exception to the doctrine of ignorantiajuris. This problem is presently
dealt with in terms of strict construction and "due process." If a criminal
statute is ambiguous, its meaning is rendered "sufficiently" precise by
excluding the disadvantageous sense of the words. And if a penal statute
is vague, i.e., "too vague," it is unconstitutional.9 2 The survival of a rule,
after being subjected to the tests of strict construction and due process,
is an authoritative finding that it is sufficiently definite to constitute
law."' Accordingly, the defendant cannot be permitted to raise the ques-
tion of indefiniteness again under a plea of ignorance of the law and
89. Despite occasional assertions to that effect, the obvious fact isthat, e.g.,
in Eng-
land, where the Bar is held in very high esteem, the doctrine of ignorantia juris is also
rigorously applied.
90. To allow such a defense would make "the opinion of the attorney paramount
to the law." People v. McCalla, 63 Cal. App. 783, 795, 220 Pac. 436, 441 (1923). So,
too, in Needham v. State, 32 P.2d 92, 93 (Okla. 1934).
91. In the discussion of bigamy infra, advice of counsel is approved as a defense.
This advice, however, concerns the law of marriage and divorce, not criminal law.
92. Lanzetta v. New Jersey, 306 U.S. 451 (1939) ; United States v. Cohen Grocery
Co., 255 U.S. 81, 89 (1921).
93. "If the right to collect depends upon the construction of various statutes, and
is apparently doubtful, the officer should stop; for if he does not, he will proceed at
his peril." Levar v. State, 103 Ga. 42, 49, 29 S.E. 467, 470 (1897).
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
94. In the Lewis Case, 124 Tex. Crim. 582, 64 S.W.2d 972 (1933), although some
dicta might so imply, the decision was not placed on "indefiniteness," but rather on the
ground that "wilfully" required a inens rea that included knowledge of illegality. In
Burns v. State, 123 Tex. Crim. 611, 61 S.W.2d 512 (1933), both grounds were relied
on; greater emphasis was placed on the fact that the statute was "obscure and confus-
ing." Such holdings usually refer ultimately to Cutter v. State, 36 N.J.L. 125 (1873),
which involved the taking of an illegal fee by a justice of the peace. But the language
of that opinion shows that the "obscurity" of the statute was relatively unimportant.
The decision emphasized inens rea, and did not purport to be an exception to ignorantia
juris.
95. This, however, does not explain how a void statute can be revived by the later
decision. It is preferable, therefore, to speak of the unconstitutional statute as un-
enforceable rather than void.
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
96. See Cardozo, J., in Great No. Ry. v. Sunburst Co., 287 U.S. 358, 364-65 (1932)
and State v. O'Neil, 147 Iowa 513, 126 N.W. 454, and Annot., 33 L.R.A. (n.s.) 788,
794, 797 (1910).
97. E.g., to a statute that repeals an older one, during which time the act in question
occurs, then the repealing statute is declared unconstitutional. See Claybrook v. State,
164 Tenn. 440, 51 S.W.2d 499 (1932).
98. Reliance upon a decision of a county circuit court has been supported. Wilson
v. Goodin, 291 Ky. 144, 150, 163 S.W.2d 309, 313 (1942). See, also, State ex rel. Wil-
liams v. Whitman, 116 Fla. 196, 156 So. 705 (1934). But it has been held that reliance
upon a decision of a municipal court is not a defense: ". . . we refuse to hold that
the decisions of any court below, inferior to the Supreme Court, are available as a de-
fense, under similar circumstances." State v. Striggles, 202 Iowa 1318, 1320, 210 N.W.
137, 138 (1926). And see note 104 infra.
99. See United States v. 100 Barrels of Vinegar, 188 Fed. 471 (D. Minn. 1911)
and, generally, Lee, Legislative and Interpretive Regulations,29 GEo. L.J. 1, 25-29 (1940).
100. See Morgenthau, Implied Regulatory Powers in Administrative Law, 28 IOWA
L. REV. 575 (1943).
101. State v. Freeland, 318 Mo. 560, 567, 300 S.W. 675, 677 (1927). The court
cited the Cutter and O'Neil cases sufpra notes 94 and 96 and also noted that the regula-
tion in issue was inalum prohibitum, not nalun in se. Cf. People v. McCalla, 63 Cal.
App. 783, 793-94, 220 Pac. 436, 439-40 (1923) where, under similar facts, advice of
counsel was rejected, and "knowingly" and "wilfully" were held not to require knowl-
edge of the law.
102. People v. Ferguson, 134 Cal. App. 41, 24 P.2d 965 (1933).
103. See State v. Pearson, 1 S.E. 914 (N.C. 1887), and State v. Boyett, 32 N.C.
246 (1849).
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
are primarily responsible for the administration of the laws they inter-
pret"'0 are law-declarations within their competence. Conduct which
conforms to them should be held legal." 5
Closely related to the above are cases of officials charged with the
violation of laws governing the exercise of their own duties. Since their
office requires them to interpret these statutes, such interpretations are
law-declarations if they are honestly made; and their conduct in con-
formity with them is not criminal. The relevant cases exculpating judi-
cial officers, usually justices of the peace, are limited to interpretations
of the very statutes which prescribe their official duties. Thus an of-
ficial could not defend on the ground that he conformed to his interpre-
tation of penal statutes when that was outside the scope of his duties.'
Moreover, the defense might well be limited to ordinary interpretations
of the law, which, e.g., would exclude opinions that the laws in question
were unconstitutional."' Finally, the above defense, i.e., that the conduct
was legal, need not be extended to ministerial officers who, in the dis-
charge of their duties, acted upon their own interpretations of penal
laws. There is another defense, however, that is sometimes available
to such persons as well as to judicial officers, namely, that certain penal
statutes require a knowing violation of the law.' This is part of the
larger problem to be discussed next.
Knowledge of Illegality Included in Mens Rea
This problem arises chiefly in relation to larcency, embezzlement, ma-
licious destruction of property, wilful trespasses and other similar offenses
where the defendant did not know that another person's legal rights were
being violated. The uniform exculpation of the defendants in these
cases 0 0 does not represent an exception to ignorantiajuris neminem ex-
104. In People v. Settles, 29 C. A.2d 781, 78 P.2d 274, 276 (1938) the California
Superior Court refused to exculpate a defendant who had received a license to conduct
a "game of skill" from the Los Angeles police department on the ground that the
statute in issue (concerning lotteries) was part of the State's Penal Code, hence the city
police had no authority to interpret it and grant licenses. The Court approved the
Ferguson decision, supra note 102, on the ground that the official there "was directly
charged with the duty of enforcing the law ... "
105. See 22 CALIF. L. REv. 569, 570-71 (1934).
106. State v. McLean, 121 N.C. 589, 28 S.E. 140 (1897) ; Skeen v. Craig, 31 Utah
20, 86 Pac. 487 (1906).
107. Cf. Leeman v. State, 30 Ark. 438 (1880) ; Hunter v. State, 158 Tenn. 63, 12
S.W.2d 361 (1928), 61 A.L.R. 1148, 1153 (1929).
108. E.g., Lewis v. State, 124 Tex. Crim. 582, 64 S.W.2d 972 (1933).
109. Larceny-Rex v. Clayton, 15 Crim. App. R. 45 (1920); Queen v. Reed,
[1842] C. & M. 306, 174 Eng. Rep. 519; especially interesting is Rex v. Gilson and
Cohen, 29 Crim. App. R. 174 (1944); Embezzlement-Lewis v. People, 99 Colo. 102,
60 P.2d 1089 (1936); Robbery-Barton v. State, 88 Tex. Crim. 368, 227 S.W. 317
(1921); Forgery-Regina v. Parish, [1837] 8 C. & P. 93, 173 Eng. Rep. 413; Malicious
destruction of property-Regina v. Twose, 14 Cox C.C. 327 (1879); Receiving stolen
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
cusat. It is not because the defendants were ignorant of the law that
they are not criminals, but because, being ignorant of certain law, they
lacked the required mens reef. Can these cases be distinguished from
criminal homicide and other crimes where ignorance of the illegality of
the conduct is not relevant to the mens rea?
In the above cases, the defendants were mistaken regarding the law
of property,"' hence their exculpation would obviously not involve any
exception to ignorantia juris neminem excusat if that doctrine, when
employed in penal law, were interpreted to exclude property law. A good
deal of confusion has resulted from the thesis that crimes against prop-
erty require a "specific intent" while others, e.g., criminal homicide, re-
quire only a "general intent." Actually, there is no such mental state as
a "general intent"; all intentions are specific in that they are directed
towards particular goals. Thus, the intent in property crimes is no more
specific than is the intentional shooting at A, but hitting X."' More-
over, no insight or elucidation is provided regarding the above problem
by asserting that property crimes require a specific intent, since this
merely reiterates, only more vaguely, that the relevant mens rea includes
a belief in the illegality of the conduct.
If we compare (1) a situation where the defendant shoots a tres-
passer, thinking he has a legal right to do so, and (2) the typical property
case, where the defendant takes a chattel, thinking he has a legal right to
its possession, we note that both situations involve private and criminal
law. In (1) the defendant's ignorance of the law is not a defense to a
criminal charge, whereas in (2) it is. The reason is not merely that the
mistake in (2) concerns property law but rather that in (1) we have
facts that are directly characterized as criminal, i.e., there is a penal law
that proscribes shooting a trespasser whereas in (2) we do not have such
facts. In (1) no private law exists which can place any interpretation on
the facts that would alter their meaning for penal law; in (2) no mean-
ing can be ascribed to the facts that is relevant to the penal law until the
defendant's opinion regarding the right of possession is determined. But
this is little more than recognizing, somewhat more clearly, perhaps, that
in some crimes an opinion regarding certain private law qualifies the
criminal significance of the conduct. Such opinions function as facts,
property-Robinson v. State, 84 Ind. 452, esp. 456 (1882); State v. Rountree, 80 S.C.
387, 61 S.E. 1072 (1908), 22 L.R.A. (n.s.) 833 (1909) ; State v. Alpert, 88 Vt. 191, esp.
204, 92 Atl. 32, esp. 37 (1914) ; unlawfully removing timber from Federal lands-Stone
v. United States, 167 U.S. 178, 189 (1897). See note 31 supra. The legal mistakes need
not be reasonable. See Perkins, Ignorance and Mistake in Criminal Law, 88 U. OF PA.
L. REv. 35, 52 (1939).
110. See Perkins, supra note 109, at 51; RADULESCO, op. cit. supra note 76, at 13-14.
111. HALL, GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF CRIMINAL LAW 450-53 (1947). See supra note 23.
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
and such ignorance or mistake falls within the meaning and purpose of
ignorantiafacti. But is there an underlying reason for this?
It was suggested above that it is not the distinction between private
and penal law or even the factual quality of the error regarding the for-
mer, but the moral significance of the respective norms, and conse-
quently of the defendant's conduct, that is decisive. Accordingly, "jutis"
should not be restricted to criminal law nor should a plea of ignorance of
all non-penal law be allowed. For example, parts of torts and family
law, like the law defining the major crimes, also reflect simple moral
values. The plea of lack of rmens rea, resulting from ignorance of the
above property law; is not inconsistent with the ethical principle that it
is wrong to steal another's chattel. That value is not contradicted if the
actor thinks he has a right to its possession. On the other hand, a de-
fendant's plea of ignorance of the criminal law, e.g., in killing a tres-
passer, would contradict the ethics of the criminal law. This conclusion
regarding ignorance of certain private law is consistent with ignorantia
facti excusat. For there, too, the defendant does not challenge the moral
norms represented in the criminal law. It may be noted, finally, that
"knowledge" of certain private law is given its ordinary meaning, simi-
lar to "knowledge of fact" and that, so far as penal law is concerned, the
principle of legality is compatible with the recognition, as a defense, of
certain mistakes of law, indicated above.
In other areas of major crime, besides the property offenses, knowl-
edge of the illegality of an act has been recognized as an essential element
of the relevant mens rea, e.g., certain conspiracies... and serious income
tax offenses. Thus a charge of wilful failure to report taxable income
may be controverted by showing a mistaken interpretation of the relevant
tax law. In Hargrove..3 the defendant was convicted of "wilfully fail-
ing" to file a tax return for certain years and "wilfully and knowingly"
attempting to evade payment of taxes. Evidence that he had relied upon
the advice of a tax expert was excluded by the trial judge who instructed
the jury: "Ignorance of the law, of course, gentlemen, is not excused.
The question of wilfullness and intent rests, then and depends upon
whether you find that the defendant wilfully and knowingly did what
he intended to do. . . . A man may have no intention to violate the law
and yet if he wilfully and knowingly does a thing which constitutes a
violation of the law he has violated the law." On appeal, the conviction
was reversed: Where a statute denounces "as criminal only [the] . .
112. Commonwealth v. Rudnick, 318 Mass. 45, 60 N.E.2d 353 (1945); Common-
wealth v. Benesch, 290 Mass. 125, 194 N.E. 905 (1935).
113. Hargrove v. United States, 67 F.2d 820 (5th Cir. 1933).
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
wilful doing [of an act] . . . a specific wrongful intent, that is, actual
knowledge of the existence of obligation and a wrongful intent to evade
11 4
it, is of the essence.3
The most serious failure to recognize that certain crimes require a
belief in the illegality of the conduct is found in bigamy cases. Here the
issues are clouded, partly by the assumption that the doctrine of ignor-
antia juris includes any law, private as well as penal, and partly by the
dogma that bigamy does not require a criminal intent. In some States
the problem has been avoided by express provisions, e.g., requiring knowl-
edge of the continuance of the first marriage. But most of the statutes
are silent as to that; they run in the traditional terms of "a per-
son who, being married, goes through a form of marriage." These
statutes have often been interpreted to exclude mens rea, i.e., just as
strictly as petty "public welfare" regulations." 5 In this country, the
chief influence has been the Mash case, decided more than a century ago,
which held that even a reasonable mistake regarding the death of the
spouse was no defense.' 16 In some jurisdictions this is still the law, and
the occasional judicial suggestion that the legislature ought to do some-
thing about it"' is small comfort to honest persons serving long sen-
tences in prison cells. Moreover, so long as reasonable mistake of a ma-
terial fact is not recognized as a defense, it is practically impossible even
to consider that a mistake of law may exclude mens rea in bigamy.
Whatever might have been said for such strict liability when Mash
was decided, the continued exclusion of even reasonable mistakes of fact
from ignorantiafacti excusat after the Tolson case" 8 is indefensible. A
typical bigamy statute was carefully analyzed there by a very able court
which held that a reasonable belief in a spouse's death was a defense
despite the fact that the second marriage occurred prior to the expiration
of the specified time, i.e., that the statute, although completely silent re-
garding mens rea, nonetheless required it. Ever since the Tolson deci-
sion, it has been widely recognized that mens rea is required in bigamy.
114. Id. at 823. So, too, held in Haigler v. United States, 172 F.2d 986 (10th Cir.
1949) reversing the conviction where the trial judge, in addition to several correct in-
structions, instructed that ignorance of the law was no excuse. In United States v.
Di Silvestro, 147 F. Supp. 300, 304 (E.D. Pa. 1957) the recognized rule regarding the
required mens rea was thus stated: "Although that [ignorance of the law] is no defense
to a crime in itself, it may be shown in a crime like the present where wilfullness is an
element in that it may negative wilfullness in failure to perform the duty."
115. "This rule has been applied in a great variety of cases, from breaches of
police regulations to bigamy, adultery, and statutory rape." State v. Ackerly, 79 Vt. 69,
72, 64 Atl. 450, 451 (1906). So, too, Cornett v. Commonwealth, 134 Ky. 613, 121 S.W.
424 (1909).
116. Commonwealth v. Mash, 48 Mass. (7 Met.) 472 (1844).
117. Commonwealth v. Hayden, 163 Mass. 453, 40 N.E. 846 (1895).
118. Queen v. Tolson, [1889] 23 Q.B. 168.
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
But that decision or, at least, what was suggested there regarding nzens
rea was restricted by Rex v. Wheat and Stocks. 9 to belief in the death
of the spouse; elsewhere, it was held, mens rea is not required in big-
amy. 2 ' Despite the prestige of English law in the Commonwealth, how-
ever, various courts in the latter jurisdictions have followed the wider
implications of Tolson. The emphasis is properly placed on the necessity
of mens rea in bigamy. 2' Most courts which recognize reasonable mis-
take of fact as a defense still have difficulty in reaching sound decisions
because it is assumed that wherever there is a mistake of law, there is no
defense, '2 2 and many of the situations include mistaken opinions re-
garding both facts and law--the so-called "mixed" questions. If. ig-
norantiajuris were limited to penal law and simple aspects of tort, family
law etc., or if at least technical rules of private law, unsupported by
moral attitudes, were excluded from the doctrine, it would usually be
superfluous to decide whether the mistake was one of law or fact. As
was suggested above, the issue would concern what was relevant to an
actual ines rea.
The issues in the bigamy cases parallel those involved in the property
offenses discussed above, and ignorantia juris neminem excusat is 'no
more relevant in the former than it is in larceny; conversely, it is equally
relevant to require knowledge of the illegality in both. In bigamy there is
no inens rea if the defendant believes the first marriage was legally dis-
solved, just as it is now recognized that an erroneous opinion that the
defendant has a legal right to the possession of a chattel excludes the
animus furandi of larceny. Accordingly, the defendant's ignorance of
technical divorce law, e.g., rules of jurisdiction, should be a defense.'
Although it may not be wise to restrict the doctrine of ignorantiajuris to
penal law," 4 that is the most likely starting-point to achieve a sound
119. [1921] 2 K.B. 119. For American cases, see Annot., 27 L.R.A. (n.s.) 1097
(1910).
120. English law had previously indicated that reasonable mistake of law was a
defense. Rex v. Connatty, 83 J.P. 292 (1919) ; Rex v. Thompson, 70 J.P. 6 (1905).
121. Thomas v. The King, 59 Commw. L. R. 279 (Austr. 1931); The King v.
Carswell, [1926] N.Z. L.R. 321 (C.A. 1926); Cf. Rex v. Sellars, 9 Cox C.C. 153 (1905).
122. See Dixon, J., in Thomas v. The King, 59 Commw. L.R. 279, 306-07 (Austr.
1931) and Weigall, Mens Rea and Bigamy, 16 AusTR. L. J. 3, 5-6 (1942).
123. But cf. Williams v. North Carolina, 325 U.S. 226 (1945).
124. For some of the difficulties that arose from such a sweeping restriction, see
Mannheim, Mens Rea in German and English Law, 17 J. Comp. LEG. & INT'L L. at 248-
49 (1935).
125. The range of ignorantia jinns in private law is not directly involved in the
present problem but the same considerations would seem to apply. See Note: Mistake
of Law: A Suggested Rationale, 45 HARv. L. REv. 336 (1931). On the other hand, in
agreements and in other transactions there is an autonomous sphere where the parties
are, in effect, permitted to legislate for themselves. The intent of the parties is cor-
respondingly important, e.g., in allowing reformation. The further relaxation of the
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
doctrine in private law, e.g., as a defense to specific performance, suggests that some
weight must be given to the principle implied in the Roman restriction of the maxim
to ius naturale. See RADOULESCO, op. cit. supra, note 76, at 25.
126. RADULESCO, op. cit. supra note 76, at 25, 27.
127. See id. at 13-15. Cf. Blackstone's statement, "... a mistake in point of
law . . . is in criminal cases no sort of defence." 4 BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES *27
follows a specific illustration of a mistake in criminal law. Cf. Lord Westbury in
Cooper v. Phibbs, 16 L.T.R. (n.s.) 678, 683 (1867) ; Lord King in Lansdown v. Lans-
down, [1730] Moseley 364, 365, 25 Eng. Rep. 441 (1730); Art. 5, Italian Penal Code
of 1930.
128. As regards strict liability in adultery, see State v. Woods, 107 Vt. 354, 179 Atl.
1 (1935).
129. Commonwealth v. Mash, 48 Mass. (7 Met.) 472 (1844).
130. Weigall, supra note 122, at 8.
131. Cited ibid.
132. Sim, J., In The King v. Carswell, [1926] N.Z.L.R. 321, 339 (C.A. 1926).
Cf. ". . . it is submitted that (a) it is illogical to allow prisoner's honest belief in
death to be a defence and to reject the plea of honest belief that a divorce had been
granted: (b) that the prisoner should be acquitted if he raises a doubt as to the validity
of the first marriage: (c) that honest belief in the invalidity of the first marriage
should be a defence." Paton, Bigamy and Mens Rea, 17 CAN. B. Rav. 94, 101 (1939).
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
Court states in the closing lines of the decision that they "expressly
withhold determination as to the availability 'in situations not before us'
of a defense to a bigamy prosecution resting upon the defendant's honest
belief, reasonably entertained, that he was legally free to remarry in New
Jersey." Even more significant, from the viewpoint of criminal theory,
is Justice Wachenfeld's vigorous dissent. He insisted that a decree of
divorce should be a defense even though it is void and widely known to
be void "unless this general knowledge is imputed or brought home to
the defendant. . . . ""' De Meo had made a full disclosure of the facts
on his application for the marriage license. "It must come as a distinct
shock to an honest person who has made full disclosure to his sovereign
state . . . to find that without wrongful or criminal intent he auto-
matically becomes a convict on a criminal charge which he cannot even
defend because the court refuses to accept the very evidence he relied up-
on and which was . . . approved by the state itself at the time he made
his original intentions known."
The California Supreme Court recently dealt with similar issues in
Vogel. 4' The defendant was not permitted by the trial court to intro-
duce evidence that his wife had told him she was going to secure a divorce
in a jurisdiction unknown to him so that he could not contest the custody
of their children, that, during his absence in military service, she had
lived with a certain man as his wife and that when she was injured in an
automobile accident, she identified herself as that man's wife. Reversing
the conviction and earlier decisions, the California Supreme Court held
that "a bona fide and reasonable belief" that he was free to marry was
a defense to a bigamy charge. The Court added that "reliance on a
judgment of divorce or annulment that is subsequently found not to be
the 'judgment of a competent Court' " is also a defense. Moreover,
"since it is often difficult for laymen to know when a judgment is not
that of a competent court, we cannot reasonably expect them always to
have such knowledge and make them criminals if their bona fide belief
proves to be erroneous."'' These recent decisions strengthen the Ameri-
can minority position considerably and indicate that other jurisdictions
may pursue a similar path.
Petty Offenses
One result of the above discussion is to narrow the scope of ignor-
antia juris neminem excusat considerably since many situations presently
treated as both within the meaning of, and also "exceptions" to, that
142. See Everhart v. People, 54 Colo. 272, 130 Pac. 10Y6 (1913).
143. Opportunity to examine and study the laws is implied in democratic theory
which would not be satisfied if conflicts were adjudicated according to laws inaccessible
to public inquiry. In addition, promulgation is a condition of valid determination of the
law, i.e., the ground of adjudication must be public to permit criticism and appraisal.
But these do not imply that knowledge of law is essential to the just imposition of
criminal liability. The principle of legality functions primarily as a limitation on of-
ficial conduct, not as a determinate of culpability. It rests on the wide ethical con-
siderations that concern the legitimacy of a government. And see note 165 infra.
144. "Knowingly and intentionally to break a statute must . . . always be morally
wrong. . . ." Queen v. Tolson, [1889] 23 Q.B. 168, 172. Cf. United States v. Anthony,
24 Fed. Cas. 829, No. 14,459 (N.D. N.Y. 1873).
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
between mala in se and mala prohibita. For, on the one hand, it does not
imply that the former (i.e., major offenses) are immoral "apart from
positive law"; nor, as regards the latter, does it imply that an act becomes
immoral because it is legally forbidden. How could the mere prohibition
under sanctions of force effect such a change? The distinction that
should be made, it is submitted, is that some acts are immoral regardless
of the actor's ignorance of their being legally forbidden (e.g., the felonies
and principal misdemeanors) whereas other acts are immoral only be-
cause the actor knows they are legally forbidden.'4 5 This would re-
enforce the writer's criticism of strict liability.' If that judicial con-
struction were abandoned, then, instead of saying that because an act is
malum prohibitum it is unnecessary to find any criminal intent, the rule
would be that, since the only rational basis for finding a criminal intent
in these cases is knowledge that the act is legally forbidden, a finding of
such knowledge is essential. As was suggested above, ignorance of penal
law, of itself, i.e., of sheer positivist illegality, presents no general ground
for exculpation. But as regards certain petty offenses, where normal
conscience (moral attitudes) and understanding cannot be relied upon
to avoid the forbidden conduct, knowledge of the law is essential to
culpability; hence the doctrine of ignorantiajuris should not be applied
there.
Since the questions requiring determination, in order to demark the
exact area within which ignorance of the law is a defense, are beyond the
province of the judicial function, the need for legislation is clear. A
likely area would include recent misdemeanors punishable only by small
fines, various ordinances and technical regulations of administrative
boards. 4 Here actual knowledge of the illegality should be required. 4
It seems necessary to retain the presumption that there was such knowl-
edge, allowing the defendant to introduce evidence tending to prove his
ignorance or mistake of the law, but placing the final burden of proving
149. As was noted supra, the proof would be in "operational" terms, showing, e.g.,
that the necessary information had been brought to the defendant's attention or that he
had avoided that.
150. Witte, A Break For the Citizen, 9 STATE GOVERNMENT 73 (1936).
151. Borderland Const. Co. v. State, 49 Ariz. 523, 68 P.2d 207 (1937).
152. See note 79 supra.
153. E.g., carrying a pistol in public: Crain v. State, 69 Tex. Crim. 55, 153 S.W. 155
(1913). Travel interstate with intent to avoid testifying in a criminal case: Hemans
v. United States, 163 F.2d 228 (7th Cir. 1947). Tapping the wife's telephone wire:
United States v. Gris, 247 F.2d 860, 864 (1957).
154. HALL, STUDIES IN JURISPRUDENCE AND CRImINAL THEoRY, c. 1 (1958).
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
155. Rex v. Bailey, [1800] Russell and Ryan 1, 168 Eng. Rep. 651.
156. Mistake of law is distinguished from ignorance of law and it is stated that
the former should not be a defense, 2 MOLINIER, TRAITk TH-ORIQUE ET PRATIQUE DE
DROIT PkNAL 210-11 (1894), citing 1 CARRARA, PROGRAMME DU COURS DU DROIT
CRIMINEL 209, note (transl. Baret).
157. This would seem to contradict the requirement of "invincibility" since, on the
usual premise regarding the meaning of "ignorantia" a lawyer has the competence to
acquire the correct legal knowledge.
IGNORANCE IN CRIMINAL LAW
158. SALMOND, JURISPRUDENCE 408 (10 ed. 1947). So, too, Lord Atkin in Proprie-
tary Articles Trade Ass'n v. Atty. Gen. of Canada 11931] A.C. 310, 324.
159. Cf. Holmes, J., in Horning v. District 6f- Columbia, 254"'U.S. 135 (1920),
quoted supra note 74.
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
162. Busch, L'Erreur de Droit, REv. INTN'L DE DR. RENAL 309, 312, Nos. 3 and 4
(1955).
INDIANA LAW JOURNAL
addition, that harms are illegal.16 6 And, since the proposed abandonment
of the doctrine of ignorantia juris implies the proportionate abandon-
ment of the principle of legality (the "rule of law"), what remains is
not the assured protection of the individual, but unfettered authority."8 7
Of course, it would be very nice to have all the advantages of the criminal
law and, also, to apply its sanctions only to those who knew the law.
Unfortunately, no one has shown how this can be done in an inevitably
"second-best" world.