Happiness in Nicomachean Ethics
Happiness in Nicomachean Ethics
Happiness in Nicomachean Ethics
1
PhD Lecturer, Bioterra University of Bucharest, Bucharest, Romania.
This article was originally published in Heteron magazine, YEAR I. 1, April-
June 2013, ISSN: 2344 – 1224.
1
Theleologicae International Journal of Postmodern Studies
Volume 1, Issue 1, 2021
2
Theleologicae International Journal of Postmodern Studies
Volume 1, Issue 1, 2021
3
Theleologicae International Journal of Postmodern Studies
Volume 1, Issue 1, 2021
4
Theleologicae International Journal of Postmodern Studies
Volume 1, Issue 1, 2021
5
Theleologicae International Journal of Postmodern Studies
Volume 1, Issue 1, 2021
3. Conclusion
Let's take the example of a pianist. We can say about him that
he is virtuous, that he never misses a note, that his music is perfect.
But we can't know how many hours he spent repeating, how much he
struggled, how much he tried to honor his status. In other words, for
the pianist to be virtuous, he must, first of all, be a pianist, so he must
have an activity. Secondly, he must master all the grips, the
implications of his activity, so to find the right environment, to have a
gift, a sense, so to be virtuous. Third, he must feel pleasure. And how
can the pleasure be obtained? Very simple. From his activity
intertwined with virtue, pleasure also appears. In this case, pleasure
can appear when we are dealing with appreciation. Obviously, the
pianist's appreciation is closely related to his activity, and hence, to
his virtue. A man cannot be virtuous in his sleep, to paraphrase
Aristotle. When he stated this, he was in fact saying that virtue can be
virtue without calling to a confirmation. In the case of the pianist, the
audience, those who appreciate him, all those around his activity, and
not only, become responsible for his virtuosity. That is why, in the
tenth book, Aristotle appeals to pleasure. Every activity must be
6
Theleologicae International Journal of Postmodern Studies
Volume 1, Issue 1, 2021
References