Robinson V Volks
Robinson V Volks
Robinson V Volks
versus
Together with
JUDGMENT
SKWEYIYA J:
Introduction
[1] This appeal and confirmatory proceedings concern the interpretation and
Spouses Act 27 of 1990 (the Act) which, in substance, confers on surviving spouses
SKWEYIYA J
the right to claim maintenance from the estates of their deceased spouses if they are
not able to support themselves. The first respondent (Mrs Robinson) contends that the
survivor of a stable permanent relationship between two persons of the opposite sex
who had not been married to each other during their lifetime, but nevertheless lived a
life akin to that of husband and wife, should be afforded the same protection that is
afforded to the survivor of a marriage under the provisions of section 2(1) of the Act.
[2] The central question for consideration in this matter is whether the protection
permanent life partnerships. The High Court (Cape Provincial Division) found that
the exclusion of the surviving partner of a permanent life partnership from the ambit
of the Act was unconstitutional.2 The present proceedings follow from that order.
Factual background
[3] Mrs Robinson was in a permanent life partnership with the late Mr Shandling,
an attorney and senior partner at CK Friedlander Shandling Volks (the law firm), from
1985 until the latter’s death in 2001. They were never married and no children were
born of their relationship. During the lifetime of the deceased, they had jointly
occupied a flat situated in Cape Town on a continuous basis from early 1989 until the
1
Section 1 of the Maintenance of Surviving Spouses Act 27 of 1990 (the Act) defines “survivor” as “the
surviving spouse in a marriage dissolved by death.”
2
Robinson and Another v Volks NO and Others 2004 (6) SA 288 (C) at 299J; 2004 (6) BCLR 671 (C) at 682I.
2
SKWEYIYA J
deceased’s death. She remained in occupation of the flat until the end of December
2002.
[4] The deceased had previously been married to Edith Freedman (Mrs Shandling),
in 1950. Three children were born of their marriage, two sons, Martin and Adrian,
and a daughter, Lauren. Mrs Shandling passed away on 27 January 1981 due to lung
cancer. The couple’s children, now majors, have established families of their own in
[5] The description by Mrs Robinson of their relationship is, in broad terms,
accepted by the appellant (Mr Volks). She states that to a large extent the deceased
had supported her financially. He gave her R5000 per month in order to cover
household necessities and would deposit money into her account whenever she needed
it. He also provided her with petrol money from the law firm’s account and paid for
her car maintenance. She was accepted as a dependant on his medical aid scheme
from January 2000. During the relationship she worked intermittently as a freelance
journalist and artist. This employment brought in some small income which she used
on general living expenses, gifts for the deceased and personal expenses. She also
[6] Once a year, the deceased would travel to the United States to visit his three
major children and grandchildren and on one occasion she accompanied him.
3
SKWEYIYA J
Whenever there were social functions at the law firm or at the radio station they would
accompany each other. They were accepted as a couple and had many mutual friends.
The deceased suffered from bi-polar disorder/manic depression, and over the years she
[7] In terms of the deceased’s will, Mr Volks, a partner in the law firm, was
appointed as the executor of the deceased estate. The balance in the estate for
distribution to Mrs Robinson, his three children, his domestic worker, and three staff
members of the law firm, was R413 665.37. The bequest to Mrs Robinson constituted
a Toyota motor vehicle, the contents of the flat which they occupied in Cape Town,
other than those items that were chosen by and reserved for his three children, and a
sum of R100 000. In terms of the will, Mrs Robinson was entitled to remain in the
[8] In April 2002 Mrs Robinson sought legal advice from the Women’s Legal
Centre (the Centre) about her rights to claim maintenance from the deceased estate.
After consulting with Mr Volks in his capacity as the executor, the Centre advised her
that the residue in the estate was minimal and that she should not pursue her claim. In
June 2003 she received a copy of the Final Liquidation and Distribution Account,
which reflected a residue of R248 533.87. In accordance with the deceased’s will, the
4
SKWEYIYA J
[9] During August 2003 the Centre wrote letters to Mr Volks and to the fourth
respondent, the Master of the High Court (the Master), advising them of their client’s
claim. The appellant’s attorneys rejected the claim on the basis that Mrs Robinson
[10] After this response, Mrs Robinson launched a two-part application in the High
Court. Part A sought an urgent interdict preventing Mr Volks from winding up and
distributing the assets in the estate, pending the determination of the constitutional
challenge to the Act, which relief was sought in Part B of the application. The
application for the interdict was not opposed and was granted by the High Court.
[11] The application relating to the constitutional challenge was set down for a later
date subject to the filing of an amended notice of motion, further papers and heads of
argument. The Women’s Legal Centre Trust (the Trust) filed an application to
intervene in this application. That application was not opposed and the Trust was
admitted as the second applicant in the proceedings. Both Mrs Robinson and the
Trust relied upon the provisions of section 38 of the Constitution for standing. They
3
The letter of refusal stated:
“prima facie it would appear that the deceased and your client considered their position during
the lifetime of the deceased and elected not to enter into a marriage in accordance with the
laws of South Africa. That election, included implicitly, if not expressly, the choice not to
have the automatic consequences of the laws of marriage apply to their relationship. The
provisions contained in the Last Will of the deceased dated 24th December 1999 are consistent
with that election.”
5
SKWEYIYA J
alleged that they were acting in their own interests; on behalf of partners in permanent
[12] In an amended notice of motion, Mrs Robinson and the Trust sought an order
declaring that she was the “survivor” of the late Mr Shandling for the purposes of the
Act, and therefore entitled to lodge a claim for maintenance under the Act. In the
event that it was found that she did not qualify as a “survivor” for the purposes of the
Act by virtue of not being “the surviving spouse in a marriage dissolved by death”,
they sought an order declaring that the exclusion of the survivor of permanent life
partnerships from the provisions of the Act was unconstitutional. They contended that
this exclusion violated the provisions of sections 9(3)5 and 106 of the Constitution, in
that it discriminated unfairly on the ground of marital status, and infringed her right to
dignity. In this regard they submitted that the definition of the words “survivor”,
4
Section 38 of the Constitution confers standing and provides as follows:
“Anyone listed in this section has the right to approach a competent court, alleging that a right
in the Bill of Rights has been infringed or threatened, and the court may grant appropriate
relief, including a declaration of rights. The persons who may approach a court are ─
(a) anyone acting in their own interest;
(b) anyone acting on behalf of another person who cannot act in their own name;
(c) anyone acting as a member of, or in the interest of, a group or class of persons;
(d) anyone acting in the public interest; and
(e) an association acting in the interest of its members.”
5
Section 9 of the Constitution is set out in para 47 below.
6
Section 10 reads as follows:
“Everyone has inherent dignity and the right to have their dignity respected and protected.”
6
SKWEYIYA J
[13] In relation to the declaration of invalidity sought, Mr Volks argued that the
reading-in of words to the Act was unacceptable. He argued that the entire structure
of the Act was premised on the concept of marriage and protects surviving spouses of
such a marriage. Thus reading-in, in the form sought, did not deal properly with these
provisions, nor did they fit in with the structure of the Act.
[14] Mr Volks argued that in the event that the court found that the Act was
inconsistent with the Constitution and invalid, it would not be just and equitable for an
order to apply to permanent life partnerships in respect of which the partner had
already died. He argued for an order which would only have prospective effect. He
argued that a retrospective order would not sufficiently protect the freedom and
dignity of the deceased. He also argued that the relief sought by Mrs Robinson and
the Trust may affect other legislation like the Administration of Estates Act.7
[15] He argued further that Mrs Robinson chose to live with Mr Shandling without
entering into a marriage although there was no legal or other impediment to marrying.
There was therefore no reason in law or in principle why the laws of marriage should
be imposed upon the deceased, his estate, and his heirs. He argued that it would
not to enter into a marriage relationship. As evidence of this choice on the part of the
7
Act 66 of 1965.
7
SKWEYIYA J
deceased, he referred to a statement that Mr Shandling made to him that “if he were
ever single again he would not marry”. Mr Volks also relied on the fact that he
referred to Mrs Robinson as “my friend” in his will, whereas he referred to his
[16] Mr Volks also contended that Mr Shandling, in terms of his will, had made a
choice as to how his assets would be disposed of. He did this with an understanding
that the laws of marriage would not apply to his estate. His freedom and dignity
overridden by a court permitting a claim for maintenance against his estate. Indeed
his right not to be arbitrarily deprived of property in terms of section 25(1) of the
[17] In short, he argued that the deceased’s freedom and dignity would be violated if
his fundamental life choices, not to marry and to dispose of his property as he wanted,
He submitted that different considerations may have applied if the deceased had died
intestate, but that this was not the case. For these reasons, he urged that even if the
Act were thought to involve discrimination, the discrimination was not unfair.
the Constitution.
8
SKWEYIYA J
[18] In response, Mrs Robinson submitted that for all intents and purposes they had
lived their lives as a married couple, and that she was at all times prepared to marry
Mr Shandling. In any event, she went on to state that the fact that they were not
determining whether she was entitled to maintenance under the Act. In determining
this question she argued for the court to consider the nature of their relationship, and
argued that if they were married and he had disinherited her or had left insufficient
means for her maintenance, she would have been entitled to claim maintenance under
the Act. She also contended that the Act was intended to provide for vulnerable
widows or persons in her position where testators did not properly provide for their
dependants.
[20] The High Court noted that there are significant differences between a marriage
9
SKWEYIYA J
conclusion of a marriage ceremony, the relationship between the two parties has
immediate legal significance. In the case of a domestic life partnership, the
determination of the nature of the relationship can only take place after a lengthy
period of time, only after the lapse of which period, the criteria enunciated above by
both Goldblatt [2003 (120) SALJ 610 at 625] and L’Heureux-Dubé J [Nova Scotia
(Attorney General) v Walsh 2002 SCC 83 at paras 126-36] can be shown to exist. In
this case, the enquiry requires the benefit of evidence which illustrates that the
relationship is of a permanent nature, at which stage, it can be concluded that the
parties are involved in a domestic life partnership.” 8 (references inserted)
[21] Based on the nature of the relationship between Mrs Robinson and the late Mr
“that, well before Mr Shandling’s death, a life partnership existed between the two
and that they regarded themselves as being involved in a permanent and intimate life
partnership.”9
[22] Adopting the equality test formulated in Harksen v Lane NO and Others,10 the
High Court found that the Act differentiated between married spouses and unmarried
cohabitants on the listed ground of marital status and therefore unfair discrimination
was presumed. It held that there were no justificatory grounds for the unfair
discrimination, and concluded that Mrs Robinson’s right to equality had been unfairly
eroded.
8
Above n 2 SALR at 298E-G; BCLR at 681F-H.
9
Id SALR at 299A; BCLR at 682B.
10
1998 (1) SA 300 (CC) at para 54; 1997 (11) BCLR 1489 (CC) at para 53.
10
SKWEYIYA J
[23] The High Court stated that it was trite that one of the core commitments of our
constitutional society was the recognition of the dignity of difference, which accords
respect to the existence of domestic partnerships and those who live in them. The
“If there were clear evidence that parties expressly, by choice, decided to eschew any
possible financial benefits which flowed from a marriage and, for this reason (or
notwithstanding this position), chose to live within the context of a domestic life
partnership, there may be an argument, . . . that a surviving partner such as [Mrs
Robinson] could not successfully launch a constitutional challenge to the Act.”11
“there is little beyond the speculation of [Mr Volks] that a conscious choice was
made by [Mr Shandling] and [Mrs Robinson] to live in terms of a relationship in
which none of the benefits of marriage now sought were to apply.”12
that for a range of reasons domestic partnerships were a significant part of South
“To ignore the arrangement and impose a particular religious view on their world is
to undermine the dignity of difference and to render the guarantee of equality
somewhat illusory insofar as a significant percentage of the population is
concerned.”14
11
Above n 2 SALR at 299E-F; BCLR at 682E-F.
12
Id SALR at 299F-G.
13
Goldblatt “Regulating Domestic Partnerships ─ A Necessary Step in the Development of South African
Family Law” (2003) 120 SA Law Journal 610.
14
Above n 2 SALR at 299I; BCLR at 682H.
11
SKWEYIYA J
He therefore held that the breach of both the rights to equality and dignity could not
be justified.
“1. It is declared that: The omission from the definition of ‘survivor’ in [section]
1 of the Maintenance of Surviving Spouses Act 27 of 1990 of the words ‘and
includes the surviving partner of a life partnership’ at the end of the existing
definition is unconstitutional and invalid.
2. The definition of ‘survivor’ in [section] 1 of the Maintenance of Surviving
Spouses Act 27 of 1990 is to be read as if it included the following words
after the words ‘dissolved by death’: ‘and includes the surviving partner of a
life partnership’.
3. The omission from the definition in [section] 1 of the Maintenance of
Surviving Spouses Act 27 of 1990 of the following, at the end of the existing
definitions, is unconstitutional and invalid:
‘ “Spouse” for the purposes of this Act shall include a person in a permanent
life partnership’;
‘ “Marriage” for the purposes of this Act shall include a permanent life
partnership.’
4. Section 1 of the Maintenance of Surviving Spouses Act 27 of 1990 is to be
read as though it included the following at the end of the existing definition:
‘ “Spouse” for the purposes of this Act shall include a person in a permanent
life partnership’;
‘ “Marriage” for the purposes of this Act shall include a permanent life
partnership.’
5. The order in paras 1, 2, 3 and 4 above shall have no effect on the validity of
any acts performed in respect of the administration of a deceased estate that
has finally been wound up by the date of this order.”15
15
Above n 2 SALR at 302E-I; BCLR at 684G-5B.
12
SKWEYIYA J
[26] At the hearing counsel for Mr Volks informed the Court that they had decided,
after consultation with him, to withdraw the appeal and opposition to the confirmation
found by the High Court. It is unfortunate that the Court was not informed of this
before the date of hearing. It is also regrettable that we were not able to hear full
argument from any party supporting the constitutionality of the provision. It would
also seem that the heirs have not been informed of this decision.
[27] However it is incumbent upon this Court to fully consider the question of
[28] Mrs Robinson and the Trust, in their heads of argument, sought confirmation of
the order in its entirety. However, in oral argument counsel indicated that they were
of the view that if words were to be read-in, they would require that the Act be
extended to cover partners only where there was a reciprocal duty of support present,
not dissimilar from the reading-in remedy ordered by this Court in Satchwell.16
[29] The third respondent, the Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development
(the Minister), and the Master had issued a notice of intention to abide the decision of
the High Court. Yet, in this Court they submitted heads of argument and made oral
16
Satchwell v President of the Republic of South Africa and Another 2002 (6) SA 1 (CC); 2002 (9) BCLR 986
(CC).
13
SKWEYIYA J
submissions challenging the confirmation of the remedy given in the High Court.
They argued for judicial restraint in light of the current law reform process being
explored in this area by the South African Law Reform Commission (the
Commission). They also argued that the order should not be retrospective or, if it
office which is tasked in most instances with the administration, winding up and
[30] The Centre for Applied Legal Studies (CALS) argued in favour of
cohabitation relationships. They also argued for a remedy which would extend the
Act to cover polygynous cohabitation relationships, where for instance the male
partner was still married during the duration of his cohabitation with another.
Further evidence
[31] CALS seeks to persuade us to accept certain additional evidence aimed largely
unmarried cohabitants, and of the fact that few women have the choice about whether
17
Government Gazette 25643 GN R 1603, 31 October 2003.
14
SKWEYIYA J
“(1) Any party to any proceedings before the Court and an amicus curiae properly
admitted by the Court in any proceedings shall be entitled, in documents lodged with
the Registrar in terms of these rules, to canvass factual material that is relevant to the
determination of the issues before the Court and that does not specifically appear on
the record: Provided that such facts -
(a) are common cause or otherwise incontrovertible; or
(b) are of an official, scientific, technical or statistical nature capable of
easy verification.”
and Others v Treatment Action Campaign and Others,18 the Court considered the
“That Rule permits a duly admitted amicus ‘to canvass factual material which is
relevant to the determination of the issues before the Court and which do not
specifically appear on the record’. However, this is subject to the condition that such
facts ‘are common cause or otherwise incontrovertible’ or ‘are of an official,
scientific, technical or statistical nature, capable of easy verification’. This Rule has
no application where the facts sought to be canvassed are disputed. A dispute as to
the facts may and, if genuine, usually will demonstrate that they are not
‘incontrovertible’ or ‘capable of easy verification’. Where this is so, the material will
be inadmissible.”20 (footnote omitted)
[33] The whole of the report tendered by the amicus cannot be considered to consist
cause. It is apparent that the conclusions and solutions offered are not
18
2002 (5) SA 713 (CC); 2002 (10) BCLR 1023 (CC).
19
Rule 30 of the old rules in Government Gazette 6199 GN R 757, 29 May 1998.
20
Above n 18 at para 8.
15
SKWEYIYA J
incontrovertible.21 Furthermore, Mr Volks does not accept that the evidence sought to
“As is evident from our methodology, our findings are not representative but simply
indicate trends which confirm our general assumptions about cohabitation.”22 (my
emphasis)
In the executive summary the study was defined as “qualitative primary research
[34] Moreover, the entire study consisted of interviews with only 68 people in eight
sites. This non-representative sampling, which was not quantitative but qualitative
and was conducted in only eight poor communities, cannot be said to be statistical or
conclusions.
[35] The evidence is not directly relevant to the issue before us. That issue is
whether the protection afforded to survivors of marriage under section 2(1) of the Act
21
South African Law Reform Commission Discussion Paper 104, Project 118: Domestic Partnerships at
viii, where the Commission suggests the concept of registering cohabitation as a means to recognising them, a
solution which is not advocated in the CALS Report.
22
Goldblatt et al “Cohabitation and Gender in the South African Context ─ implications for law reform: A
research report prepared by the Gender Research Project of the Centre for Applied Legal Studies, University of
the Witwatersrand”, November 2001 at 24 at para 2.2.
23
Id executive summary at ii.
16
SKWEYIYA J
the evidence would impermissibly broaden the case before us. It cannot be admitted.
The history and purpose of the Maintenance of Surviving Spouses Act 27 of 1990
[36] This Act has its own unique history which is relevant to its goal or object. In
Glazer v Glazer, NO24 the Appellate Division refused to extend the principle applied
in Carelse v Estate De Vries,25 that a father’s estate was liable to support his children,
to cases of a spouse requiring support to enable her to claim maintenance from her
[37] The Act emanates from the recommendations of the Commission’s report:
August 1987. The Commission was of the view that the institution of a legitimate
portion would not be the appropriate solution to the problem, and recommended
instead that a claim for maintenance be given by operation of the law. It is regrettable
that it took as many as three years before the recommendations of the report were
24
1963 (4) SA 694 (A).
25
(1906) 23 SC 532.
26
Above n 24 at 706H-707B.
17
SKWEYIYA J
[38] In terms of section 2(1) of the Act a surviving spouse will, in so far as he is not
able to provide therefor from his own means and earnings, have a claim against the
deceased spouse’s estate “for the provision of his reasonable maintenance needs until
“any money or property or other financial benefit accruing to the survivor in terms of
the matrimonial property law or the law of succession or otherwise at the death of the
deceased spouse”.27
The claim by the surviving spouse will be dealt with in accordance with the
[39] The purpose of the provision is plain. The challenged law is intended to
provide for the reasonable maintenance needs of parties to a marriage that is dissolved
marriage beyond the death of one of the parties. The legislation is intended to deal
with the perceived unfairness arising from the fact that maintenance obligations of
eliminating this perceived unfairness and no more. The obligation to maintain that
exists during marriage passes to the estate. The provision does not confer a benefit on
the parties in the sense of a benefit that either of them would acquire from the state or
a third party on the death of the other. It seeks to regulate the consequences of
marriage and speaks predominantly to those who wish to be married. It says to them:
27
Section 1 of the Act.
28
Above n 7.
18
SKWEYIYA J
“If you get married your obligation to maintain each other is no longer limited until
one of you dies. From now on, the estate of that partner who has the misfortune to
Interpretation
relevant provisions of the Act in the light of its history. Section 2(1) of the Act
provides:
“If a marriage is dissolved by death after the commencement of this Act the survivor
shall have a claim against the estate of the deceased spouse for the provision of his
reasonable maintenance needs until his death or remarriage in so far as he is not able
to provide therefor from his own means and earnings.” (my emphasis)
Mrs Robinson and the Trust argued both in the High Court and in this Court that the
reasons considered below, I agree with the conclusion of the High Court that the Act
[41] It is patent from the definition in the Act that, “survivor” means “the surviving
spouse in a marriage dissolved by death.” It would seem that the only possible
meaning for “marriage” when viewed in the context of the Act is one recognised
either by the law or by a religion.29 This is evident both from the use of the words
29
See in general Daniels v Campbell NO and Others 2004 (5) SA 331 (CC); 2004 (7) BCLR 735 (CC).
19
SKWEYIYA J
[42] Furthermore, in Satchwell30 this Court was very definitive in its interpretation
“There is no definition of the word ‘spouse’ in the provisions under attack. In the
circumstances the ordinary wording of the provisions must be taken to refer to a party
to a marriage that is recognised as valid in law and not beyond that. . . . The context
in which ‘spouse’ is used in the impugned provisions does not suggest a wider
meaning, nor do I know of one. Accordingly, a number of relationships are excluded,
such as same-sex partnerships and permanent life partnerships between unmarried
heterosexual cohabitants.”32 (my emphasis)
[43] In addition, section 2(1) refers to the provision of maintenance until “death or
survivors of permanent life partnerships, who generally may not have been previously
“On the one hand, it is the duty of a judicial officer to interpret legislation in
conformity with the Constitution so far as this is reasonably possible. On the other
hand, the Legislature is under a duty to pass legislation that is reasonably clear and
30
Above n 16.
31
Act 88 of 1989.
32
Above n 16 at para 9.
33
Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic Offences and Others v Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd and
Others: In Re Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd and Others v Smit NO and Others 2001 (1) SA 545 (CC);
2000 (10) BCLR 1079 (CC).
20
SKWEYIYA J
[45] I find that an interpretation of the Act that would include permanent life
partnerships would be “unduly strained” and manifestly inconsistent with the context
and structure of the text. The Act is incapable of being interpreted so as to include
Equality challenge
[46] The basis of the High Court’s finding of unconstitutionality is that the Act
excludes permanent life partners from its protection and thereby violates the anti-
“(1) Everyone is equal before the law and has the right to equal protection and benefit
of the law.
(2) Equality includes the full and equal enjoyment of all rights and freedoms. To
promote the achievement of equality, legislative and other measures designed to
protect or advance persons, or categories of persons, disadvantaged by unfair
discrimination may be taken.
34
Id at para 24.
21
SKWEYIYA J
(3) The state may not unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against anyone on
one or more grounds, including race, gender, sex, pregnancy, marital status, ethnic or
social origin, colour, sexual orientation, age, disability, religion, conscience, belief,
culture, language and birth.
(4) No person may unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against anyone on one
or more grounds in terms of subsection (3). National legislation must be enacted to
prevent or prohibit unfair discrimination.
(5) Discrimination on one or more of the grounds listed in subsection (3) is unfair
unless it is established that the discrimination is fair.”
[48] In the Harksen35 case this Court laid out the general approach to equality
35
Above n 10.
36
The equivalent of section 9(1) of the 1996 Constitution.
22
SKWEYIYA J
[49] The question for determination in this case is whether the exclusion of
survivors of permanent life partnerships from the protection of the Act constitutes
unfair discrimination. The Act draws a distinction between married people and
unmarried people by including only the former. We are not concerned with the
exclusion of survivors of gay and lesbian relationships, nor are we concerned with
marital status. That being the case, the discrimination is presumed to be unfair in
37
The equivalent of section 9(3) of the 1996 Constitution.
38
The equivalent of section 36 of the 1996 Constitution.
23
SKWEYIYA J
differences between the two groups. Although there is no right to marry and to found
recognised therein. This is clear from the provisions of section 15(3)(a)(i) of the
[52] Marriage and family are important social institutions in our society. Marriage
has a central and special place, and forms one of the important bases for family life in
“Marriage and the family are social institutions of vital importance. Entering into and
sustaining a marriage is a matter of intense private significance to the parties to that
39
Section 15 guarantees the right to freedom of religion, belief and opinion and provides:
“(1) Everyone has the right to freedom of conscience, religion, thought, belief, and
opinion.
(2) Religious observances may be conducted at state or state-aided institutions, provided
that:
(a) those observances follow rules made by the appropriate public authorities;
(b) they are conducted on an equitable basis; and
(c) attendance at them is free and voluntary.
(3) (a) This section does not prevent legislation recognising ─
(i) marriages concluded under any tradition, or a system of religious,
personal or family law; or
(ii) systems of personal and family law under any tradition, or adhered
to by persons professing a particular religion.
(b) Recognition in terms of paragraph (a) must be consistent with this section
and the other provisions of the Constitution.”
40
See Daniels v Daniels; Mackay v Mackay 1958 (1) SA 513 AD at 532E, where Hoexter JA referred to
marriage as “the most important unit of our social life, the family.” See also in Belfort v Belfort 1961 (1) SA
257 AD at 259H, where the same judge states that marriage “is the very foundation of the most important unit of
our social life, the family.”
41
Dawood and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others; Shalabi and Another v Minister of Home Affairs
and Others; Thomas and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC); 2000 (8)
BCLR 837 (CC).
24
SKWEYIYA J
marriage for they make a promise to one another to establish and maintain an intimate
relationship for the rest of their lives which they acknowledge obliges them to support
one another, to live together and to be faithful to one another. Such relationships are
of profound significance to the individuals concerned. But such relationships have
more than personal significance, at least in part because human beings are social
beings whose humanity is expressed through their relationships with others. Entering
into marriage therefore is to enter into a relationship that has public significance as
well.
The institutions of marriage and the family are important social institutions that
provide for the security, support and companionship of members of our society and
bear an important role in the rearing of children. The celebration of a marriage gives
rise to moral and legal obligations, particularly the reciprocal duty of support placed
upon spouses and their joint responsibility for supporting and raising children born of
the marriage. These legal obligations perform an important social function. This
importance is symbolically acknowledged in part by the fact that marriage is
celebrated generally in a public ceremony, often before family and close friends.”42
(footnotes omitted)
42
Id at paras 30-1.
43
The concept of marriage as a civil right has been advanced by some American courts in a variety of
circumstances, for example, Skinner v. Oklahoma 316 US 535, 541 (1942); Perez v. Lippold 198 P.2d 17, 20-1
(1948). See also Loving v. Virginia 388 US 1 (1967), where Chief Justice Warren speaking for the majority of
the Supreme Court included language describing marriage as one of the basic civil rights of man.
See further Noonan, who in “The Family and the Supreme Court” (1973) 23 Catholic University Law Review
255 at 273 comments as follows on the Loving v. Virginia case:
“The vital personal right recognized by Loving v. Virginia is not the right to a piece of paper
issued by a city clerk. It is not the right to exchange magical words before an agent authorized
by the state. It is the right to be immune to the legal disabilities of the unmarried and to
acquire the legal benefits accorded to the married. Lawful marriage in the society’s hierarchy
of values recognized by Boddie v. Connecticut and in the host of laws yet unchallenged – the
tax law, the common law of property, the law of evidence – is a constellation of these
immunities and privileges. To say that legal immunities and legal benefits may not depend
upon marriage is to deny the vital right. To say that Equal Protection requires the equal
treatment of the married and the unmarried in all respects is to deny the hierarchy of values of
our society.”
In addition, Article 23(2) of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights provides that “[t]he right of
men and women of marriageable age to marry and to found a family shall be recognised”; and Article 18 of the
African [Banjul] Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights provides that “[t]he family shall be the natural unit and
basis of society. It shall be protected by the State which shall take care of its physical health and moral.”
25
SKWEYIYA J
[54] From this recognition, it follows that the law may distinguish between married
“In the context of certain laws there would often be some historical and logical
justification for discriminating between married and unmarried persons and the
protection of the institution of marriage is a legitimate area for the law to concern
itself with.”45
The law may in appropriate circumstances accord benefits to married people which it
[55] Mrs Robinson never married the late Mr Shandling. There is a fundamental
difference between her position and spouses or survivors who are predeceased by their
husbands. Her relationship with Mr Shandling is one in which each was free to
continue or not, and from which each was free to withdraw at will, without obligation
and without legal or other formalities. There are a wide range of legal privileges and
obligations that are triggered by the contract of marriage. In a marriage the spouses’
rights are largely fixed by law and not by agreement, unlike in the case of parties who
[56] The distinction between married and unmarried people cannot be said to be
unfair when considered in the larger context of the rights and obligations uniquely
44
Fraser v Children’s Court, Pretoria North, and Others 1997 (2) SA 261 (CC); 1997 (2) BCLR 153 (CC).
45
Id at para 26.
26
SKWEYIYA J
cohabitants. The maintenance benefit in section 2(1) of the Act falls within the scope
persons in respect of whom the deceased person (spouse) would have remained legally
[57] It must be borne in mind that the legislature, by enacting the law, in fact
qualified the right to freedom of testation. It said that freedom of testation would be
limited to the extent that where marriage obliged the parties to it to maintain each
other, freedom of testation ought not to result in the termination of the obligation upon
death. The question we have to answer is whether it was unfair for the legislature not
cohabitants.
[58] In his judgment Sachs J envisages two categories of people within this broad
necessary implication agree to live together, to maintain each other and to give each
other support of every kind. It is contended that for the law not to oblige survivors of
survivor simply because the survivor does not have the piece of paper which is the
46
Dissent of Sachs J at paras 213-4; 218.
27
SKWEYIYA J
of paper. Couples who choose to marry enter the agreement fully cognisant of the
legal obligations which arise by operation of law upon the conclusion of the marriage.
These obligations arise as soon as the marriage is concluded, without the need for any
further agreement. They include obligations that extend beyond the termination of
marriage and even after death. To the extent that any obligations arise between
cohabitants during the subsistence of their relationship, these arise by agreement and
only to the extent of that agreement. The Constitution does not require the imposition
attaches no such obligation during the deceased’s lifetime, and there is no intention on
[59] The second category referred to by Sachs J is the relationship in which the
deceased male partner refused to marry the woman who cared for him, put everything
into the relationship and gave her heart and soul to it, bringing up a number of
children born of the relationship between them in the process.48 I have sympathy for
surviving partners who fall within this category. The conduct of the male partner is
47
Id at para 220.
48
Id at para 219.
28
SKWEYIYA J
the other. In the context of the provision for maintenance of the survivor of a
marriage by the estate of the deceased, it is entirely appropriate not to impose a duty
upon the estate where none arose by operation of law during the lifetime of the
[61] It was also contended that the failure to make provision for the people in the
class to which Mrs Robinson belongs offends the dignity of members of that class.
“Everyone has inherent dignity and the right to have their dignity respected and
protected.”
[62] I do not agree that the right to dignity has been infringed. Mrs Robinson is not
being told that her dignity is worth less than that of someone who is married. She is
simply told that there is a fundamental difference between her relationship and a
obliged to maintain each other by operation of law and without further agreement or
formalities. People in the class of relationships to which she belongs are not in that
position. In the circumstances, it is not appropriate that an obligation that did not exist
29
SKWEYIYA J
Many women become economically dependent on men and are left destitute and
[64] Much of the argument and many of the passages of the judgment of Sachs J
This concern arises because women remain generally less powerful in these
relationships. They often wish to be married, but the nature of the power relations
within the relationship makes a translation of that wish into reality difficult. This is
because the more powerful participants in the relationship would not agree to be
bound by marriage. The consequences are that women are taken advantage of and the
49
Freeman and Lyon Cohabitation without Marriage (Gower Publishing Company Limited, Hants, England
1997) at 19-20, describe the position of women in England in the following terms:
“The position of women in society today is closely related to their role within the family. An
understanding of woman’s oppression accordingly requires a description and analysis of the
position of women in today’s privatised family. As Mary McIntosh rightly has observed,
‘ultimately the very construction of men and women as separate and opposed categories takes
place within, and in terms of, the family’. Women are expected to be dependent on men.
Their role is geared to the household. They are responsible for child care, as well as for the
care of the aged and handicapped. Their domestic labour is seen as non-productive, not real
work. Women, particularly married women, have to be housewives: if they do not carry out
the service roles depicted here they are ‘bad’ housewives, but housewives nevertheless.
Furthermore, as Kate Millett noted, ‘sex role is sex rank’. ‘As long as woman’s place is
defined as separate, a male-dominated society will define her place as inferior’.” (footnotes
omitted)
30
SKWEYIYA J
[65] I agree that the women in this category suffer considerably. But it is not the
under-inclusiveness of section 2(1) which is the cause of their misery. The plight of a
woman who is the survivor in a cohabitation relationship is the result of the absence of
any law that places rights and obligations on people who are partners within
relationships of this kind during their lifetimes. I accept that laws aimed at regulating
these relationships in order to ensure that a vulnerable partner within the relationship
[66] In the case of the very poor and the illiterate the effects of vulnerability are
more pronounced. The vulnerability of this group of women is, in my view, part of a
broader societal reality that must be corrected through the empowerment of women
and social policies by the legislature. It is a widespread problem that needs more than
just implementation of what, in their case, would be no more than palliative measures.
It needs more than the extension of benefits under section 2(1) to survivors who are
[67] Both dissenting judgments make it plain that there are many ways in which
these relationships can be regulated. It is not for us to decide how this should be done.
In any event, this case is not concerned with the provision that should be made to
ensure that partners in relationships other than marriage treat each other fairly during
their lifetime. That does not mean, however, that fairness in the case of people who
31
SKWEYIYA J
are married will be the same as fairness between parties to a permanent life
[68] As I have already said, it is not unfair not to impose a duty upon the estate of a
deceased where no duty of that kind arose by operation of law during the lifetime of
that person. I have a genuine concern for vulnerable women who cannot marry
despite the fact that they wish to and who become the victims of cohabitation
relationships. I do not think however that their cause is truly assisted by an extension
of section 2(1) of the Act or that vulnerable women would be unfairly discriminated
against if this were not done. The answer lies in legal provisions that will make a real
difference to vulnerable women at a time when both partners to the relationship are
still alive. Once provision is made for this, the legal context in which section 2(1)
Costs
[69] Neither Mr Volks nor Mrs Robinson and the Trust sought costs in this Court.
However, Mrs Robinson and the Trust argued that the Minister and the Master, who
had originally abided the decision of the High Court, but who at a very late stage
sought to tender evidence and argument in this Court, should be ordered to pay the
costs of the appellant on a punitive scale. They argued that the effect of their late
intervention would have caused additional costs to Mr Volks which would inevitably
be drawn from the estate. However, Mr Volks abides the decision of this Court in
regard to this latter issue and does not seek a costs order against the Minister and the
32
SKWEYIYA J
Master. There can be no doubt that it is regrettable that they did not intervene in the
intervention, and generally it is helpful to the Court for the state’s attitude to
having that information before the Court cannot excuse non-compliance with its rules,
I am of the view that in this case it would be inappropriate to make the costs order
sought by Mrs Robinson and the Trust against the Minister and the Master. In the
Order
(a) The order of the High Court declaring section 1 of the Maintenance
Chaskalson CJ, Langa DCJ, Moseneke J, Ngcobo J, Van der Westhuizen J and
33
NGCOBO J
NGCOBO J:
[71] Section 2(1) read with section 1 of the Maintenance of Surviving Spouses Act,
27 of 1990 (the Act), confers on surviving spouses the right to claim maintenance
from the estates of their deceased spouses if they are unable to support themselves.
The question presented in this case is whether this right should also be conferred upon
survivors of permanent life partnerships between two persons of the opposite sex who
were not married to each other but nevertheless lived a life that was akin to that of
husband and wife. The High Court (Cape of Good Hope Division) took the view that
from the protection of the Act is unconstitutional. The present proceedings are a
sequel.
Cape Town law firm. Mrs Robinson took the view that survivors of such a
relationship are entitled to the protection afforded to surviving spouses by the Act.
She lodged a claim for maintenance under the Act against the estate of the deceased.
The executor of the estate of the deceased, the appellant, rejected the claim, taking the
view that such survivors do not fall within the ambit of the protection afforded by the
Act. The rejection of the claim prompted, amongst other things, a constitutional
34
NGCOBO J
[73] The High Court found that the provisions of the Act are incapable of being
within the ambit of the Act. The problem, the High Court appears to have found, lay
in the definition of the word “survivor” in section 1 of the Act, which did not include
persons involved in permanent life partnerships. This exclusion, the court found,
marital status. It therefore concluded that section 2(1) read with the definition of
and 10 of the Constitution. It is this conclusion that is now in issue before this Court.
“(1) Everyone is equal before the law and has the right to equal protection and benefit
of the law.
(2) Equality includes the full and equal enjoyment of all rights and freedoms. To
promote the achievement of equality, legislative and other measures designed to
protect or advance persons, or categories of persons, disadvantaged by unfair
discrimination may be taken.
(3) The state may not unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against anyone on
one or more grounds, including race, gender, sex, pregnancy, marital status,
ethnic or social origin, colour, sexual orientation, age, disability, religion,
conscience, belief, culture, language and birth.
(4) No person may unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against anyone on one
or more grounds in terms of subsection (3). National legislation must be enacted
to prevent or prohibit unfair discrimination.
(5) Discrimination on one or more of the grounds listed in subsection (3) is unfair
unless it is established that the discrimination is fair.”
35
NGCOBO J
[75] That the Act differentiates between survivors of marriages and survivors of
permanent life partnerships is patent. The provisions of the Act are aimed at
providing maintenance and support for survivors of marriages. The legitimacy of this
differentiation that the Act makes is rationally connected to that purpose. The next
[76] For the purposes of this judgment, I am prepared to accept that the
ground of marital status, a ground listed in subsection 9(3) of the Constitution. That
being the case, the discrimination is presumed to be unfair under subsection 9(5). The
ultimate question for determination therefore is whether the provisions of section 2(1)
read with section 1 of the Act do in fact discriminate unfairly against survivors of
[77] The proper approach to the equality analysis is that set out in the President of
the Republic of South Africa and Another v Hugo1 and Harksen v Lane NO and
Others2 cases.
1
1997 (4) SA 1 (CC); 1997 (6) BCLR 708 (CC) at paras 32-50.
36
NGCOBO J
Constitution has been considered by this Court, albeit in the context of section 8 of the
interim Constitution, the predecessor to section 9. In the Hugo case, this Court held
that:
“The prohibition on unfair discrimination in the interim Constitution seeks not only to
avoid discrimination against people who are members of disadvantaged groups. It
seeks more than that. At the heart of the prohibition of unfair discrimination lies a
recognition that the purpose of our new constitutional and democratic order is the
establishment of a society in which all human beings will be accorded equal dignity
3
and respect regardless of their membership of particular groups.”
in the Harksen case, this Court held that “[t]he prohibition of unfair discrimination in
the Constitution provides a bulwark against invasions which impair human dignity or
may make distinctions, those “distinctions that treat certain people as second-class
citizens, that demean them, that treat them as less capable for no good reason, or that
2
1998 (1) SA 300 (CC) at paras 41-69; 1997 (11) BCLR 1489 (CC) at paras 40-68. See also Hoffmann v South
African Airways 2001 (1) SA 1 (CC); 2000 (11) BCLR 1211 (CC) at para 24.
3
Above n 1 at para 41.
4
Above n 2 at para 51 of the SALR and para 50 of the BCLR.
5
Egan v Canada (1995) 29 CRR (2d) 79 at 105, cited with approval by this Court in the Hugo case above n 1 at
para 41.
37
NGCOBO J
[80] The starting point in determining the fairness or otherwise of the discrimination
involved in this case is the Constitution itself. Although our Constitution contains no
right freely to marry and to raise a family. In Dawood and Another v Minister of
Home Affairs and Others; Shalabi and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and
Others; Thomas and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others, this Court
“The omission of such a right from the Constitution was challenged during the first
certification proceedings on the basis that such a right constituted a ‘universally
accepted fundamental right’ which in terms of Constitutional Principle II had to be
entrenched in the Constitution. The Court observed from its survey of international
instruments that States are obliged in terms of international human rights law to
protect the rights of persons freely to marry and raise a family. However, it also
observed that these obligations are achieved in a great variety of ways in different
human rights instruments.
...
The Court therefore concluded that the new constitutional text, although it contained
no express clause protecting the right to family life, nevertheless met the obligations
imposed by international human rights law to protect the rights of persons freely to
marry and to raise a family.”7 (footnotes omitted)
6
Above n 4.
7
2000 (3) SA 936 (CC); 2000 (8) BCLR 837 (CC) at para 28. See also Ex parte Chairperson of the
Constitutional Assembly: In re Certification of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996 1996 (4)
SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC) at para 97.
38
NGCOBO J
[81] There can be no doubt that our Constitution recognises the institution of
marriage. This much is apparent from section 15(3)(a)(i) of the Constitution which in
substance makes provision for the recognition of “marriages concluded under any
tradition, or a system of religious, personal or family law.” This Court too has
recognised the importance of marriage as an institution. One need only refer to the
Dawood case, where this Court said the following concerning the institution of
marriage:
“Marriage and the family are social institutions of vital importance. Entering into and
sustaining a marriage is a matter of intense private significance to the parties to that
marriage for they make a promise to one another to establish and maintain an intimate
relationship for the rest of their lives which they acknowledge obliges them to support
one another, to live together and to be faithful to one another. Such relationships are
of profound significance to the individuals concerned. But such relationships have
more than personal significance, at least in part because human beings are social
beings whose humanity is expressed through their relationships with others. Entering
into marriage therefore is to enter into a relationship that has public significance as
well.
The institutions of marriage and the family are important social institutions that
provide for the security, support and companionship of members of our society and
bear an important role in the rearing of children. The celebration of a marriage gives
rise to moral and legal obligations, particularly the reciprocal duty of support placed
upon spouses and their joint responsibility for supporting and raising children born of
the marriage. These legal obligations perform an important social function. This
importance is symbolically acknowledged in part by the fact that marriage is
celebrated generally in a public ceremony, often before family and close friends.”8
(footnotes omitted)
8
Dawood id at paras 30-1.
39
NGCOBO J
[82] The constitutional recognition of the right freely to marry and the institution of
and regional human rights instruments which impose obligations upon states to
respect and protect marriage. The African [Banjul] Charter on Human and Peoples’
Rights, 19819 recognises the importance of marriage and the family. Article 18(1)
provides that the “family shall be the natural unit and basis of society.” The relevant
“1. The family shall be the natural unit and basis of society. It shall be protected by
the State which shall take care of its physical and moral health.
2. The State shall have the duty to assist the family which is the custodian of morals
and traditional values recognized by the community.”10
[83] Under article 23(4) of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,
1966 (ICCPR),11 States Parties are required to “take appropriate steps to ensure
“1. The family is the natural and fundamental group unit of society and is entitled to
protection by society and the State.
9
Adopted on 27 June 1981 by the Eighteenth Assembly of the Heads of State and Government of the
Organization of African Unity and entered into force on 21 October 1986.
10
The importance of the family in the context of the African Charter is also apparent from the duties which
individuals have under the Charter. These duties appear, for example, in article 27(1) which provides that
“[e]very individual shall have duties towards his family and society . . . .”; and article 29(1) which provides that
“[t]he individual shall also have the duty [t]o preserve the harmonious development of the family and to work
for the cohesion and respect of the family; to respect his parents at all times, to maintain them in case of need”.
11
Adopted by General Assembly resolution 2200A (XX1) of 16 December 1966 and entered into force on 23
March 1976.
40
NGCOBO J
2. The right of men and women of marriageable age to marry and to found a family
shall be recognized.
3. No marriage shall be entered into without the free and full consent of the intending
spouses.
4. States Parties to the present Covenant shall take appropriate steps to ensure
equality of rights and responsibilities of spouses as to marriage, during marriage
and at its dissolution. In the case of dissolution, provision shall be made for the
necessary protection of any children.”
[84] So too does article 16 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 194812
provide that:
“(1) Men and women of full age, without any limitation due to race, nationality or
religion, have the right to marry and to found a family. They are entitled to equal
rights as to marriage, during marriage and at its dissolution.
(2) Marriage shall be entered into only with the free and full consent of the intending
spouses.
(3) The family is the natural and fundamental group unit of society and is entitled to
protection by society and the State.”
marriage as an institution and the right freely to marry. They underscore the duty of
states like ours, which are signatories to these instruments, to “take appropriate steps
marriage and at its dissolution.”13 Therefore, both the Constitution and international
12
Adopted and proclaimed by General Assembly resolution 217A (III) of 10 December 1948.
13
Article 23(4) of the ICCPR. The emphasis is mine.
41
NGCOBO J
[86] It seems to me to follow from this recognition of the institution of marriage that
the law may, in appropriate circumstances, distinguish between married people and
unmarried people. This much was recognised by this Court in Fraser v Children’s
“In the context of certain laws there would often be some historical and logical
justification for discriminating between married and unmarried persons and the
protection of the institution of marriage is a legitimate area for the law to concern
itself with.”15
our constitutional democracy, it follows that the law may legitimately afford
protection to married people which it does not accord to unmarried people. This
marriage. But there are other considerations that are relevant to the determination of
[88] One of the factors that is relevant to the determination of unfairness is the
provisions of the Act is manifestly not directed at impairing the dignity of the
surviving spouses who are in need of maintenance and who are unable to support
14
1997 (2) SA 261 (CC); 1997 (2) BCLR 153 (CC).
15
Id at para 26.
42
NGCOBO J
reciprocal duty of support. During the subsistence of the marriage, the deceased
spouse is under a duty to support and maintain the surviving spouse. What the
provisions of the Act merely do is to ensure that this duty continues after the death of
one of the spouses. It does this by transferring this duty to the estate of a deceased
spouse.
[89] It is not without significance that indigenous law, which is part of our law, also
protects widows. Under indigenous law, the duty to maintain and support the widow
survives the death of the husband. Thus upon the death of a husband, the duty to
maintain and support the widow falls upon indlalifa. This duty remains with indlalifa
regardless of whether the deceased husband left enough assets from which to maintain
“The perpetuation and preservation of the family unit and succession to the position
and status of the deceased therefore lie at the heart of succession in indigenous law.
Like his predecessor, indlalifa becomes the nominal owner of the family property,
and is required to administer it on behalf of and for the benefit of the family.
Indlalifa acquires the duty to maintain and support the widow and minor children. In
dealing with family property, indlalifa has to consult the widow who had the right to
restrain him from dissipating family assets. When there are insufficient assets to
maintain the family, indlalifa had to use his own resources to provide maintenance.”16
(footnotes omitted)
16
Bhe and Others v Magistrate, Khayelitsha and Others (Commission for Gender Equality as Amicus Curiae);
Shibi v Sithole and Others; South African Human Rights Commission and Another v President of the Republic
of South Africa and Another 2005 (1) BCLR 1 (CC) at para 172.
43
NGCOBO J
[90] It is therefore plain that the impact of the provisions of the Act on surviving
spouses is to protect their right to receive maintenance and support from the deceased
spouse by transferring the duty to support and maintain onto the estate of a deceased
spouse. It is true that surviving partners of permanent life partnerships are not
afforded this protection. But, although this may constitute a disadvantage, it does not
take away the right of a surviving partner of a permanent life partnership from
receiving a sum of money from the estate of a deceased partner. Indeed, the
provisions of the Act do not prevent partners in a permanent life partnership from
leaving sums of money to each other in their respective wills, which can be used for
maintenance. We know for example that the deceased in this case left Mrs Robinson a
[91] There is a further consideration that is equally relevant. The law places no legal
getting married. All that the law does is to put in place a legal regime that regulates
the rights and obligations of those heterosexual couples who have chosen marriage as
protection under the Act, therefore, depends on their decision whether to marry or not.
The decision to enter into a marriage relationship and to sustain such a relationship
signifies a willingness to accept the moral and legal obligations, in particular, the
reciprocal duty of support placed upon spouses and other invariable consequences of a
marriage relationship. This would include the acceptance that the duty to support
44
NGCOBO J
[92] The Act does not say who may enter into a marriage relationship. The Act
simply attaches certain legal consequences to people who choose marriage as their
contract. There is a choice at the entry level. The law expects those heterosexual
couples who desire the consequences ascribed to this type of relationship to signify
Those who do not wish such consequences to flow from their relationship remain free
to enter into some other form of relationship and decide what consequences should
manifestation of that choice and more importantly, the acceptance of the consequences
of a marriage. It is more than a piece of paper. As this Court observed in the Dawood
case:
“The celebration of a marriage gives rise to moral and legal obligations, particularly
the reciprocal duty of support placed upon spouses and their joint responsibility for
supporting and raising children born of the marriage. These legal obligations perform
an important social function. This importance is symbolically acknowledged in part
by the fact that marriage is celebrated generally in a public ceremony, often before
family and close friends.”17
[94] People involved in a relationship may choose not to marry for a whole variety
of reasons, including the fact that they do not wish the legal consequences of a
17
Above n 7 at para 31.
45
NGCOBO J
marriage to follow from their relationship. It is also true that they may not marry
because one of the parties does not want to get married. Should the law then step in
my view would undermine the right freely to marry and the nature of the agreement
inherent in a marriage. Indeed it would amount to the imposition of the will of one
existence of a permanent life partnership. The point at which such partnerships come
partnerships are determined by agreement between the parties. Unless these have
been expressly agreed upon, they have to be inferred from the conduct of the parties.
What happens at the dissolution of such partnerships is far from clear. All of this
points to the need to regulate permanent life partnerships. This does not mean that a
[96] The provisions of the Act may have denied the surviving partners of permanent
life partnerships the protection it affords to surviving spouses, but it cannot be said
that it fundamentally impairs their rights of dignity or sense of equal worth. The
impact of the discrimination upon the surviving partners is, therefore, in all the
circumstances not unfair. It follows that the provisions of the Act are not inconsistent
46
NGCOBO J/ MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
with sections 9 and 10 of the Constitution. In the event, the order of invalidity made
[97] For these reasons I concur in the order proposed in the judgment of Skweyiya J.
Chaskalson CJ, Langa DCJ, Moseneke J, Van der Westhuizen J and Yacoob J concur
[98] We have had the opportunity of reading the judgments in this matter prepared
by Skweyiya J and Sachs J. We are unable to agree with the order proposed by
Skweyiya J. We agree with the conclusion reached by Sachs J but for different
[99] The crisp constitutional issue we have to decide is whether section 2(1) of the
Maintenance of Surviving Spouses Act, 27 of 1990 (the Act) read with the definition
inconsistent with the Constitution as found by the Cape High Court (the High Court).1
1
Robinson and Another v Volks NO and Others 2004 (6) SA 288 (C); 2004 (6) BCLR 671 (C).
47
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
“If a marriage is dissolved by death after the commencement of this Act the survivor
shall have a claim against the estate of the deceased spouse for the provision of his
reasonable maintenance needs until his death or remarriage in so far as he is not able
to provide therefor from his own means and earnings.”
The word “survivor” is defined in section 1 of the Act as “the surviving spouse in a
marriage dissolved by death”. The High Court found that this narrow definition of
“survivor” rendered the provision discriminatory to the extent that it did not afford a
maintenance claim to the surviving partner of a permanent life partnership. The High
Court accordingly made an order reading in the following words to the definition of
2
The order made by the High Court read as follows:
“1. It is declared that: the omission from the definition of ‘survivor’ in section 1 of the
Maintenance of Surviving Spouses Act 27 of 1990 of the words ‘and includes the
surviving partner of a life partnership’ at the end of the existing definition is
unconstitutional and invalid.
2. The definition of ‘survivor’ in section 1 of the Maintenance of Surviving Spouses
Act 27 of 1990, is to be read as if it included the following words after the words
‘dissolved by death’;
‘and includes the surviving partner of a life partnership’.
3. The omission from the definition in section 1 of the Maintenance of Surviving
Spouses Act 27 of 1990 of the following, at the end of the existing definitions, is
unconstitutional and invalid:
‘“Spouse” for the purposes of this Act shall include a person in a permanent
life partnership’;
‘“Marriage” for the purposes of this Act shall include a permanent life
partnership’.
4. Section 1 of the Maintenance of Surviving Spouses Act 27 of 1990 is to be read as
though it included the following at the end of the existing definition;
‘“Spouse” for the purposes of this Act shall include a person in a permanent
life partnership’;
‘“Marriage” for the purposes of this Act shall include a permanent life
partnership’.
5. The order in paragraphs 1, 2, 3 and 4 above shall have no effect on the validity of any
acts performed in respect of the administration of a deceased estate that has finally
been wound up by the date of this order.”
48
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
[100] The facts of the case have been set out in the judgments of both Skweyiya J and
Sachs J. To recap in brief, Mrs Robinson and Mr Shandling (the deceased), who had
both been previously married, formed a relationship in which they lived together from
1985 until his death in November 2001. The relationship thus lasted sixteen years.
They did not marry although there was no legal impediment to marriage. For the last
twelve years of Mr Shandling’s life, they lived in a flat owned by a Shandling family
trust. Their relationship was monogamous and Mrs Robinson characterised the
Court, Mr Volks, the executor of Mr Shandling’s deceased estate (the executor) did
[101] In his will, Mr Shandling referred to Mrs Robinson as his “friend”. He also
mentioned his former wife whom he referred to as “my wife Edith Rose”. He
bequeathed certain of his assets, totalling approximately one third of his estate, to Mrs
Robinson. The residue of his estate was left to his three children in different
proportions. In addition to the bequests made in her favour, Mrs Robinson applied to
the executor for her to be treated as a surviving spouse for the purposes of section 2(1)
of the Act, which would entitle her to maintenance. That application was refused by
the executor on the grounds that she did not fall within the terms of section 2(1) as she
[102] Mr Shandling was a senior partner in a firm of attorneys in Cape Town while
49
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
Robinson averred that Mr Shandling supported her financially during the subsistence
of their relationship and paid all household expenses. Mrs Robinson was also added
[103] Mrs Robinson states that Mr Shandling had been diagnosed as suffering from
bi-polar disorder before their relationship commenced and that she nursed him
through the mood swings that are characteristic of this disorder. She also nursed him
in his final illness. It is quite clear from the evidence given by Mrs Robinson, and not
disputed by the executor, that Mr Shandling and Mrs Robinson lived together for
sixteen years, supporting one another both financially and emotionally and that both
considered the relationship to be a permanent one. The High Court found on the facts
that Mr Shandling and Mrs Robinson had entered into a permanent and intimate life
partnership.
[104] In deciding whether this finding is correct, we consider the following factors to
be determinative in this case: the length of the period of cohabitation which was
sixteen years, the fact that Mr Shandling paid Mrs Robinson an allowance to cover
household expenses and was generally responsible for the payment of all the costs of
running the household, the fact that Mr Shandling had declared Mrs Robinson to be
his dependant for the purposes of medical aid, the undisputed close and intimate
relationship between them, and the fact that Mrs Robinson nursed Mr Shandling
through bouts of ill-health. In our view, these facts make it plain that both Mr
50
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
partnership in which they undertook duties of mutual support and care for one
another. It is also clear, however, that they chose not to marry. We must assume that
it was Mr Shandling who chose not to marry as Mrs Robinson says that she was at all
marrying from the affidavits before us. In our view, however, the fact that they did
not marry does not mean that they had not established a permanent life partnership.
“The state may not unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against anyone on one
or more grounds, including race, gender, sex, pregnancy, marital status, ethnic or
social origin, colour, sexual orientation, age, disability, religion, conscience, belief,
culture, language and birth.”
extensive legal consequences under the two legal regimes which regulate marriage in
South Africa, the common law and African customary law. The social importance of
marriage has been recognised by this Court in several cases. In Dawood and Another
v Minister of Home Affairs and Others; Shalabi and Another v Minister of Home
Affairs and Others; Thomas and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others,3 for
3
2000 (3) SA 936 (CC); 2000 (8) BCLR 837 (CC).
51
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
“The institutions of marriage and the family are important social institutions that
provide for the security, support and companionship of members of our society and
bear an important role in the rearing of children. The celebration of a marriage gives
rise to moral and legal obligations, particularly the reciprocal duty of support placed
upon spouses and their joint responsibility for supporting and raising children born of
the marriage. These legal obligations perform an important social function. This
importance is symbolically acknowledged in part by the fact that marriage is
celebrated generally in a public ceremony, often before family and close friends.”4
The celebration of a marriage thus confers extensive legal duties and rights upon the
mutual support and security to the members of that family. However, not every
families often play the same roles as in families which are founded on marriage and
[107] The law has tended to privilege those families which are founded on marriages
principles of African customary law were not afforded recognition equal to the
recognition afforded to common law marriages,5 though this has begun to change.6
4
Id at para 31. See also Satchwell v President of the Republic of South Africa and Another 2002 (6) SA 1 (CC);
2002 (9) BCLR 986 (CC) at paras 13 and 22; Du Toit and Another v Minister of Welfare and Population
Development and Others (Lesbian and Gay Equality Project as Amicus Curiae) 2003 (2) SA 198 (CC); 2002
(10) BCLR 1006 (CC) at para 19.
5
Marriages in terms of African customary law were referred to as “black customary unions” in section 35 of the
Black Administration Act, 38 of 1927 and were not recognised as legal marriages. Accordingly, a widow of a
customary marriage was held not to have a claim in delict for the loss of support caused by the death of her
husband. See Suid-Afrikaanse Nasionale Trust en Assuransie Maatskappy Bpk v Fondo 1960 (2) SA 467 (A).
The position was different in customary law, see Vakubi Ngqongqozi and Another v Noselem Nyalambisa and
Others 4 NAC 32 (1919). See the comment by Dlamini “Claim By Widow of Customary Union for Loss of
Support” (1984) 101 SA Law Journal 34.
52
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
Hinduism were also not recognised as lawful marriages7 though this too is now
adopted in the light of our history in which only certain marriages were recognised as
families that are established outside of civilly recognised marriages should not be
[108] Where relationships which are socially and functionally similar to marriage are
not regulated in the same way as marriage, discrimination on the grounds of marital
status will arise. In this case, we have concluded that the cohabitation relationship of
Mrs Robinson and Mr Shandling was a relationship that constituted a permanent life
partnership in which the parties had undertaken mutually to support one another, both
socially and functionally similar to marriage. To the extent that the law regulates its
consequences differently from that of marriage, the law will be prima facie
discriminatory. The question that then arises is whether that discrimination is unfair.
In each case where it is shown that a relationship that is socially and functionally
6
See the Recognition of African Customary Marriages Act, 120 of 1998.
7
These marriages were historically not recognised as valid marriages because they were potentially polygynous.
See Ismail v Ismail 1983 (1) SA 1006 (A).
8
See, for example, Ryland v Edros 1997 (2) SA 690 (C); 1997 (1) BCLR 77 (C); Amod v Multilateral Motor
Vehicle Accidents Fund (Commission for Gender Equality Intervening) 1999 (4) SA 1319 (SCA).
53
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
[109] It will be helpful to start by considering the legal rules governing marriage.
Before we do so, however, it is important to note that the rules governing marriage
both under common law and under African customary law have been the subject of
intense debate in the last few decades. The focus of that debate has been a realisation
that many of the rules of marriage in both systems were discriminatory on the grounds
of gender and sex. Some of the rules were expressly and obviously discriminatory,
such as the rule of common law which provided that a woman married in community
of property had limited contractual capacity and that her husband, the bearer of the
marital power, was entitled to manage their common estate on his own without
referring to her at all.9 Or the rule of customary law which provided that women may
[110] Other rules regulating marriage were discriminatory against women, not
expressly, but in effect. In particular these rules often failed to acknowledge the
division of labour within the household, in terms of which women bore primary and
often sole responsibility for the maintenance of the household and caring for children
and elderly members of the family. The responsibilities so often borne by women
across all South African communities, whether wealthy or poor, and regardless of
colour, meant that women were less likely to be able to participate in the labour
9
For a discussion of the rules regulating marital power before its abolition, see Hahlo The South African Law of
Husband and Wife 5 ed (Juta, 1985) at 194; see also the discussion in Van Heerden et al Boberg’s Law of
Persons and the Family 2 ed (Juta, 1999) at 161ff.
10
But see Bhe and Others v Magistrate, Khayelitsha and Others (Commission for Gender Equality Intervening);
Shibi v Sithole and Others; South African Human Rights Commission and Another v President of the Republic
of South Africa and Another 2005 (1) BCLR 1 (CC).
54
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
market as successfully as men. (Indeed practices in the labour market as well were
the unequal division of labour in the household, and discriminatory practices in the
divorce, women were often more materially vulnerable than men. This was caused by
the fact that during the marriage women were often less able than men to accumulate
property, and were also less able to compete in the labour market.
[111] The Legislature has sought to remedy this inequality over the last twenty years
property both during the subsistence of the marriage and upon its termination,11 as
well as provisions extending the duty of support that arises on marriage to after the
death of one of the spouses (the provision in question in this case),12 and seeking to
improve the procedures whereby the duty of support may be enforced.13 This brief
account of recent developments in the law of marriage makes it plain that marriage
itself is an institution which is legally evolving. That evolution reflects and responds
to changes in the broader community. The discussion of the rights of marriage that
follows is based largely, but not exclusively, on the current common law rules
regulating marriage.
11
See the Matrimonial Property Act, 88 of 1984; Marriage and Matrimonial Property Law Amendment Act, 3 of
1988; General Law Fourth Amendment Act, 132 of 1993.
12
See the discussion in Hahlo “Widow’s Claim to Maintenance out of Deceased Husband’s Estate” (1962) 79
SA Law Journal 361. In 1969, there was an abortive attempt to enact a remedial provision, the Family
Maintenance Bill. See also Hahlo “The Sad Demise of the Family Maintenance Bill 1969” (1971) 88 SA Law
Journal 201.
13
See generally the Maintenance Act, 99 of 1998; See also Bannatyne v Bannatyne (Commission for Gender
Equality, as Amicus Curiae) 2003 (2) SA 363 (CC); 2003 (2) BCLR 111 (CC).
55
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
between a man and a woman in which the parties undertake to live together,15 and to
support one another.16 Marriage is voluntarily undertaken by the parties, but it must
be undertaken in a public and formal way and once concluded it must be registered.
Formalities for the celebration of a marriage are set out in the Marriage Act.17 A
directed. If objections to the marriage are lodged, the marriage officer must satisfy
herself or himself that there are no legal obstacles to the marriage.19 Those wishing to
get married must produce copies of their identity documents, or alternatively make
affidavits in the prescribed form.20 Marriages must take place in a church or other
religious building, or in a public office or home, and the doors must be open.21 Both
14
See, however, the recent judgment of the SCA in Fourie and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Another
(Lesbian and Gay Equality Project Intervening) SCA 232/2003, 30 November 2004, as yet unreported in which
a majority of the court issued a declarator to the effect that “marriage is the union of two persons to the
exclusion of all others for life.” This was decided shortly before judgment was handed down in this matter.
15
The duty to live together forms part of the consortium omnis vitae “which obliges spouses to live together,
afford each other reasonable marital privileges, and be faithful to each other” (Van Heerden et al above n 9 at
172).
16
Voet 25.3.8; Jodaiken v Jodaiken 1978 (1) SA 784 (W) at 788H.
17
Act 25 of 1961.
18
Section 11(1) of the Marriage Act. Sections 2-9 of the Act govern the appointment of marriage officers. All
magistrates are marriage officers ex officio (see section 2(1) of the Marriage Act).
19
Section 23 of the Marriage Act.
20
Section 12 of the Marriage Act.
21
Section 29(2) of the Marriage Act.
22
Sections 29(2) and (4) of the Marriage Act.
23
Section 29A(1) of the Marriage Act.
56
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
formula for the ceremony is provided in the Marriage Act,24 but other formulae, such
as religious rites, may be approved by the Minister.25 Once the marriage has been
solemnised, both spouses, at least two competent witnesses, and the marriage officer
must sign the marriage register.26 A copy of the register must then be transmitted to
certain that it is known to the broader community precisely who gets married and
when they get married. Certainty is important for the broader community in the light
of the wide range of legal implications that marriage creates, as we shall now describe.
[113] One of the most important invariable consequences of marriage is the reciprocal
duty of support. It is an integral part of the marriage contract and has immense value
not only to the partners themselves but to their families and also to the broader
community. The duty of support gives rise to the special rule that spouses, even those
married out of community of property, can bind one another to third parties in relation
to the provision of household necessaries which include food, clothing, medical and
dental services.28 The law sees the spouses as life partners and jointly and severally
responsible for the maintenance of their common home. This obligation may not be
24
See section 30(1) of the Marriage Act.
25
Id
26
See section 29A(1) of the Marriage Act.
27
See section 29A(2) of the Marriage Act.
28
See the general discussion in Sinclair The Law of Marriage Volume 1 (Juta, 1996) at 442-452; and Van
Heerden et al above n 9 at 235ff.
57
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
[114] Another invariable legal consequence of the marriage is the right of both parties
to occupy the joint matrimonial home. This obligation is clearly based on the premise
that spouses will live together. The party who owns the home may not exclude or
evict the other party from the home. Limited exceptions to this rule have been created
[115] The way in which the marriage affects the property regime of the parties to the
marriage is variable at common law. The ordinary common law regime is one of
community of property including profit and loss in terms of which the parties to a
marriage share one joint estate which they manage jointly. Historically, of course, our
common law provided that the power to manage the estate (“the marital power”)
vested in the husband. This rule was altered by statutory intervention in 1984.30
Major transactions affecting the joint estate must now be carried out with the
Children born during a marriage are presumed to be children of the father. Both
29
Act 116 of 1998. See in particular subsections 7(1)(c) and (d). Note also that the Domestic Violence Act
provides remedies to cohabiting partners. Section 1 of the Act defines “domestic relationship” to include people
who “(whether they are of the same or of the opposite sex) live or lived together in a relationship in the nature of
marriage, although they are not, or were not, married to each other, or are not able to be married to each other”
(section (b) of the definition).
30
See section 11 of the Matrimonial Property Act, 88 of 1984. The abolition of the marital power was only
extended to marriages between African people in 1988 – see the Marriage and Matrimonial Property
Amendment Act, 3 of 1988. Both these statutes only abolished the marital power prospectively. In 1993 the
General Law Fourth Amendment Act, 132 of 1993 abolished the marital power in all marriages which had been
solemnised before the 1984 and 1988 Matrimonial Property Acts had come into force. See also the full
discussion in Sinclair above n 28 at 126-130.
31
See subsections 15(2) and 15(3) of the Matrimonial Property Act, 88 of 1984. Joint estates must now be
administered in terms of chapter III of the Act.
58
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
parents have an ineluctable duty to support their children (and children have a
reciprocal duty to support their parents). The duty to support children arises whether
[117] Because of the social importance of marriage in our community, the law also
provides that where one spouse is sequestrated, the estate of the other spouse also
vests in the Master in certain circumstances,32 the law of evidence creates certain rules
relating to evidence by spouses against or for one another,33 and the law of delict
recognises damages claims based on the duty of support.34 The rules that govern
marriage have developed over a long period of time. More recently, as pointed out in
the judgment of Sachs J, Acts of Parliament which attach benefits to marriage, also
confer them upon cohabitants who are not married, variously referred to in legislation
32
See, for example, section 21(1) of the Insolvency Act, 24 of 1936, and the consideration of that provision by
this Court in Harksen v Lane NO and Others 1998 (1) SA 300 (CC); 1997 (11) BCLR 1489 (CC). Interestingly,
section 21(13) provides that the word “spouse” in section 21 is to be read to include “a woman living with a
man as his wife or a man living with a woman as her husband, although not married to one another”.
33
Section 195 of the Criminal Procedure Act, 51 of 1977 provides, subject to certain exceptions, that the spouse
of an accused is a competent, but not compellable, witness for the prosecution. Section 196 provides that the
spouse of an accused is a competent witness for the defence, but may not be compelled to give evidence by a co-
accused of the accused spouse. Interestingly, section 195(2) of the Criminal Procedure Act provides that for the
purposes of evidence in criminal proceedings “marriages” include customary law marriages and marriages
concluded under any system of religious law, but not cohabitation.
34
The aquilian action entitles a spouse whose spouse has been killed or injured by the wrongful act of a third
party to recover damages for the patrimonial loss suffered. A claim for loss of the non-material aspects of
consortium does not lie. See Union Government (Minister of Railways and Harbours) v Warneke 1911 AD 657;
Marine and Trade Insurance Co Ltd v Mariamah and Another 1978 (3) SA 480 (A).
35
See paras 175-176 of the judgment of Sachs J.
59
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
[118] From the above, it is clear that marriage is an institution of great legal
significance. This significance arises both from the important social role that
marriage plays in our society and from its public and formal character which make it a
reliable criterion for the conferral of obligations and rights. We are unable to agree
discrimination on the grounds of marital status is unfair or not, one can take the view
that it is not unfair to discriminate between relationships to which the law attaches the
obligations of support and cohabitation and those relationships to which the law does
not attach such consequences. In our view, this approach defeats the important
marital status. For if it does not constitute unfair discrimination to regulate marriage
differently from other relationships in which the same legal obligations are not
imposed upon the partners to that relationship by the law, marriage will inevitably
remain privileged. We do not consider this would serve the constitutional purpose of
section 9(3), and its prohibition of unfair discrimination on the grounds of marital
status.
[119] It has become apparent that more and more people in South Africa live together
without being married.36 In the 2001 Census, 2.3 million people described themselves
as “living together like married partners” although they were not married. This
cohabitating partners have received some piecemeal attention by Parliament over the
36
Sinclair above n 28 at 270 records that the number of people living together as cohabitants had grown from
463 000 in 1970 to 1,2 million people in 1991.
60
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
cohabitation has yet taken place. The South African Law Reform Commission,
however, has been engaged in researching the matter and has prepared a
[120] Of course, the circumstances of cohabitants can vary significantly. Some may
together because there is a legal or religious bar to their marriage, others may be living
together on the firm and joint understanding that they do not wish their relationship to
attract legal consequences, and still others may be living together with the firm and
relationship may change its joint character and purpose so that partners who may
originally not intend to be living together as permanent life partners may over time
alter that intention and intend to live together as permanent life partners.
Because such relationships are similar to marriage, and because they will be based on
many of the same social practices that underpin marriage, many of the gender
inequalities that are attendant upon marriage, and described above,39 will also be
attendant upon these relationships. It is quite likely that after a long period of
37
See the examples given in the judgment of Sachs J at paras 175-176.
38
See South African Law Reform Commission Discussion Paper, Paper 104, Project 118, “Domestic
Partnerships”.
39
See paras 109-111.
61
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
cohabitation, in which the parties have lived together, and even raised children jointly,
the person in the relationship, often, but not necessarily the woman, who has been
responsible for the maintenance of the household and caring for children will be more
vulnerable in relation to material and financial matters than the other partner. The
prejudice that person in the absence of any equitable regulation of the property affairs
[122] Some cohabitation relationships, such as that between Mrs Robinson and Mr
Shandling, play a role very similar to marriage in our society. However, because they
are not formally celebrated in a manner that is capable of easy proof or ascertainment,
practicable. To resolve this problem some societies have provided for the registration
[123] There are thus differences between marriage and cohabitation even where
cohabitation plays a similar social function to marriage. These differences mean that
the mere fact that the law regulates marriage relationships differently from
cohabitation relationships does not mean that the law, to the extent that it
62
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
Three things need to be considered: (a) the position of complainants in society and
whether they have previously suffered from patterns of disadvantage; (b) the nature of
the provision and the purpose sought to be achieved by it; and (c) the extent to which
the discrimination has affected the rights or interests of the complainants and whether
it has led to an impairment of their fundamental human dignity or has caused them
[124] Although discrimination against cohabiting partners has not been equal to the
discrimination relating to race and gender, cohabiting partners have been excluded
have been and still are the subject of stigma and disapproval in our community,
though this stigma is on the wane in some sectors of our society. A further important
factor in this case is that the group of cohabiting partners under consideration are
those who, upon the death of their partner, are unable to provide for their own
We conclude for these reasons that the cohabiting partners under consideration in this
case are a vulnerable group. We turn now to consider the circumstances of cohabiting
41
See, for example, President of the Republic of South Africa and Another v Hugo 1997 (4) SA 1 (CC); 1997 (6)
BCLR 708 (CC) at paras 41-43; Harksen above n 32 at paras 51-54 of the SALR and paras 50-53 of the BCLR.
63
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
[125] At present our law makes no express provision for the regulation of the affairs
jurisdictions, the law of implied or constructive trusts has been used to re-allocate
achieve equity.42 This remedy is not available in our law, given the different legal
basis of the law of trusts in South African law.43 However, the common law rules
common all their property, both that which they presently own and that which they are
to acquire in the future.44 In Ally v Dinath,45 the court held that a universal partnership
like other contracts could be tacitly concluded. Establishing that a contract has been
42
See the discussion in Sinclair above n 28 at 274-277; see also Neave “Living Together – The Legal Effects of
the Sexual Division of Labour in Four Common Law Countries” (1991) 17 Monash University Law Review 14
at 17.
43
See Cameron et al Honoré’s South African Law of Trusts 5 ed (Juta, 2002) at 110.
44
There are in fact two types of universal partnership known in our law, the societas universorum bonorum and
the universorum quae ex quaestu veniunt. See Isaacs v Isaacs 1949 (1) SA 952 (C) at 955. The former is an
agreement in terms of which the parties agree to pool all their existing and future property, and the latter is an
agreement in which the parties agree to pool all property they receive during the term of the partnership. We are
referring to the societas universorum bonorum in the text.
45
1984 (2) SA 451 (T) at 454F-455A.
46
There is some doubt as to the precise test to be met in establishing the existence of a tacit contract. See the
approach set out in Standard Bank of South Africa Ltd and Another v Ocean Commodities Inc and Others 1983
(1) SA 276 (A) at 292B, but see the comments in Joel Melamed and Hurwitz v Cleveland Estates (Pty) Ltd; Joel
Melamed and Hurwitz v Vorner Investments (Pty) Ltd 1984 (3) SA 155 (A) at 164G-165H and also Mühlmann v
Mühlmann 1984 (3) SA 102 (A). Not much turns on this uncertainty for our purposes.
64
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
[126] Another legal remedy that may be available to assist a cohabiting partner on the
termination of the relationship arises from the law governing unjustified enrichment.47
One partner may be able to show that the other partner has been enriched during the
one partner by the other.48 It might even be that the enrichment action could be
another during the subsistence of their relationship. However, the law has not yet
developed in this direction. The scope of the law of unjustified enrichment need not
be further considered.
[127] Accordingly, at present, there are only a few common law rules which may
have the potential to regulate the rights of parties upon the termination of a
their relationship by the death of one party. Accordingly, at termination by the death
of one of the parties, the surviving partner is left without effective legal recourse,
unless she or he can formulate a claim based on the principles of the common law
described above. This situation arises, despite the fact that it is clear that the
47
See the discussion in Sinclair above n 28 at 277-78.
48
In Nortje v Pool NO 1966 (3) SA 96 (A) it was held that where tangible improvements which increase the
market value of the property are made by one person to the property of another, a claim in unjustified
enrichment will lie. The same case held that there was no general claim for unjustified enrichment in our law.
See, however, Kommissaris van Binnelandse Inkomste v Willers 1994 (3) SA 283 (A) where the court held that
Nortje’s case does not necessarily exclude the further extension of liability for unjustified enrichment.
65
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
relationship of cohabitation was one in which the parties had undertaken mutual duties
of support and one in which patterns of vulnerability and dependence had been
established, such that the death of one party may put the other in great difficulty.
[128] The determination whether the discrimination caused by section 2(1) affects
cohabiting partners unfairly needs to be understood in the context of the fact that there
are no comprehensive, certain or clear legal remedies that can ameliorate the
death of one of the cohabitants. The absence of any other legal remedy coupled with
the discriminatory impact of section 2(1) will mean that often surviving cohabiting
partners will be left vulnerable and unprotected upon the termination of their
cohabitation arrangements by the death of their partner, even where their relationship
[129] Upon termination of a marriage by death, on the other hand, there are a range of
rules which govern the rights of the parties. When one spouse dies intestate, the other
spouse is entitled to inherit the entire estate if the deceased spouse is not survived by
49
See section 1(1)(a) of the Intestate Succession Act, 81 of 1987.
50
A child’s portion is calculated by producing a number calculated by identifying the number of descendants
and adding one to it to represent the spouse. The cash value of the estate is then divided by that number.
66
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
Development from time to time.51 The amount is currently set at R125 000.52 Of
course, the provisions of the Intestate Succession Act apply only if the deceased
51
See section 1 of the Intestate Succession Act which provides:
“(1) If after the commencement of this Act a person (hereinafter referred to as the ‘deceased’)
dies intestate, either wholly or in part, and—
(a) is survived by a spouse, but not by a descendant, such spouse shall inherit the
intestate estate;
(b) is survived by a descendant, but not by a spouse, such descendant shall inherit
the intestate estate;
(c) is survived by a spouse as well as a descendant—
(i) such spouse shall inherit a child’s share of the intestate estate or so much
of the intestate estate as does not exceed in value the amount fixed from
time to time by the Minister of Justice by notice in the Gazette, whichever is
the greater; and
(ii) such descendant shall inherit the residue (if any) of the intestate estate;
(d) is not survived by a spouse or descendant, but is survived—
(i) by both his parents, his parents shall inherit the intestate estate in equal
shares; or
(ii) by one of his parents, the surviving parent shall inherit one half of the
intestate estate and the descendants of the deceased parent the other half,
and if there are no such descendants who have survived the deceased, the
surviving parent shall inherit the intestate estate; or
(e) is not survived by a spouse or descendant or parent, but is survived—
(i) by—
(aa) descendants of his deceased mother who are related to the
deceased through her only, as well as by descendants of his
deceased father who are related to the deceased through him only;
or
(bb) descendants of his deceased parents who are related to the
deceased through both such parents; or
(cc) any of the descendants mentioned in subparagraph (aa), as
well as by any of the descendants mentioned in subparagraph (bb),
the intestate estate shall be divided into two equal shares and the
descendants related to the deceased through the deceased mother shall
inherit one half of the estate and the descendants related to the deceased
through the deceased father shall inherit the other half of the estate; or
(ii) only by descendants of one of the deceased parents of the deceased who
are related to the deceased through such parent alone, such descendants shall
inherit the intestate estate;
(f) is not survived by a spouse, descendant, parent, or a descendant of a parent, the
other blood relation or blood relations of the deceased who are related to him nearest
in degree shall inherit the intestate estate in equal shares.”
52
The amount was published in Government Gazette 11188 GN 483, 18 March 1988.
67
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
[130] In addition to the provisions regulating succession, section 2(1) of the Act
provides that a spouse in financial need may claim maintenance from the estate of his
or her deceased spouse until his or her death or remarriage. As both Sachs J and
Skweyiya J note in their judgments, this provision was enacted in 1990 to amend the
situation then prevailing under the common law. At that time, the common law held
that the duty of support between spouses did not survive the death of one spouse.
Accordingly, a spouse had no claim against the estate of his or her deceased spouse,
even when in dire financial need, and if the estate would have been able to provide
maintenance.53
[131] There is a significant difference, therefore, between the way in which the law
regulates the rights of spouses who survive a marriage, and the manner in which it
regulates the rights of partners who survive a cohabitation relationship. There can be
no doubt that there is a range of ways in which the rights of partners surviving
regulate different forms of cohabitation differently. For example, it may conclude that
other forms of cohabitation. The various possibilities are canvassed extensively in the
53
Glazer v Glazer NO 1963 (4) SA 694 (A) at 707B-D.
54
See, for example, the Canadian Maintenance and Custody Act, RS, 1989, c 160; see also the New South
Wales Property (Relationships) Act of 1984; see also the law in the Netherlands, above n 40; see also section
160 of the Tanzanian Law of Marriage Act 1971 as cited in Sinclair above n 28 at 297n108.
55
Above n 38.
68
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
in our view to consider the full range of forms of regulation that may be considered by
the Legislature and to consider their constitutionality for as yet there is no statutory
regulation.
[132] From the foregoing it becomes plain that cohabiting partners are a vulnerable
group, and that in the absence of any other forms of legal regulation, the fact that they
are excluded from the provisions of section 2(1) can have a grave impact on the
interests of cohabiting partners. That impact will be particularly grave where the
reciprocal duties of support, where the surviving partner is in need, and there has been
no equitable distribution to the surviving partner from the estate of the deceased
circumstances, the effect of limiting the scope of section 2(1) to married spouses only
will constitute unfair discrimination within the meaning of section 9(3) of the
Constitution.
[133] Were there some regulation to provide equitable protection to cohabitants who
have been in relationships which can be said to perform a similar social function to
marriage, the provisions of section 2(1) may not have constituted unfair
protection for cohabitants, particularly those who have been in long-term relationships
where patterns of dependence have been established, the failure of section 2(1) to
69
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
[134] It should be emphasised that this conclusion does not mean that the Legislature
marriage. In particular, the Legislature need not extend the provisions of section 2(1)
relationship, concluded formally and publicly with specified and clear consequences.
consequences. In our view, the Legislature is entitled to take this into account when it
for a long time can produce patterns of dependence and vulnerability which in the
[135] The unfairness of the discrimination in this case lies not primarily in the fact
that cohabiting partners are not afforded equivalent rights to marriage as stipulated in
section 2(1) of the Act, but in the fact that neither section 2(1) nor any other legal rule
socially and functionally similar to marriage, when those relationships are terminated
by death and where that surviving partner is in financial need. In our view, given that
section 2(1) of the Act and other legal provisions extensively regulate the rights of
spouses in the event of the termination of a marriage by death, but there are no
statutory provisions at all regulating the rights of cohabitants upon the termination of
70
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
[136] We have concluded that the discrimination is unfair. The next question that
arises is whether that unfair discrimination can be said to be reasonable and justifiable
legislation is to alter the common law rules governing marriage to protect the
surviving spouse from penury upon the death of the other spouse. In our view, this is
mutually undertaken, whether tacitly or expressly, and where those surviving partners
are in financial need, from similar protection. It is not clear why marriage only need
be protected. The need to provide protection to such surviving partners is all the more
acute in the light of the prevailing common law principle that provides that such
partners would not be able to enter into legally enforceable contractual obligations to
support one another after the termination of their partnership by the death of one of
them. The law prohibits contracts between individuals which seek to regulate their
56
Section 36(1) reads as follows:
“Limitation of rights.—(1) The rights in the Bill of Rights may be limited only in terms of
law of general application to the extent that the limitation is reasonable and justifiable in an
open and democratic society based on human dignity, equality and freedom, taking into
account all relevant factors, including—
(a) the nature of the right;
(b) the importance of the purpose of the limitation;
(c) the nature and extent of the limitation;
(d) the relation between the limitation and its purpose; and
(e) less restrictive means to achieve the purpose.”
71
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
terms of our Constitution. While marriage plays an important role in our society, and
most religions cherish it, the Constitution does not permit rights to be limited solely to
Remedy
Constitution requires a court when deciding a constitutional matter to declare any law
or conduct that is inconsistent with the Constitution to be invalid to the extent of its
inconsistency.58 Section 172(1)(b) also permits a court to make an order that is just
and equitable. The difficulty we face in this case is that, for the reasons given earlier
in this judgment, the discrimination we have found may be cured by the Legislature in
57
Pacta successoria, as they are called, are prohibited in terms of our common law. There is no uniform view
on whether such contracts are merely unenforceable (see Salzer v Salzer 1919 EDL 221; Van Jaarsveld v Van
Jaarsveld’s Estate 1938 TPD 343) or contrary to public policy and therefore invalid (Nieuwenhuis v
Schoeman’s Estate 1927 EDC 266). For a general discussion see the discussion in Christie The Law of Contract
in South Africa 4 ed (Butterworths, 2001) at 415-6. It is not necessary to engage in this debate here and it is
sufficient, for the purposes of this case, simply to highlight that such contracts are not enforceable in South
African law.
58
Section 172(1) of the Constitution reads as follows:
72
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
a variety of ways and that those ways need not be identical to the manner in which
identified in this case the Legislature should make provision to ensure that on the
arrangement is reached in relation to the financial position of the survivor so that the
dependence or vulnerability of the survivor which has arisen through the relationship
rules relating to maintenance. The Legislature is in the best position to determine the
[138] All this may be so, yet section 172(1) nevertheless obliges us to capture the
were to change, what would constitute “unfair discrimination” may also change. We
as we can in the light of the circumstances that currently obtain. If the Legislature
were not to take steps to cure the defect within the time stipulated and also not seek an
extension of the suspension of the order, the order of invalidity would come into
59
See section 2(g) of the Canadian Matrimonial Property Act, RS 1989 and the discussion thereof in Nova
Scotia (Attorney General) v Walsh [2002] 4 SCR 325 (SCC).
73
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
effect. It is important for this reason too that the scope of the unconstitutionality be as
[139] In the light of the reasoning on the merits above, we consider that the
of the Act. In our view, were that definition to be read to include “and includes the
of one partner in which the partners undertook reciprocal duties of support and in
circumstances where the surviving partner has not received an equitable share in the
emphasised that, were this order to come into operation, a partner would only be able
surviving partner would have to show that he or she was not able to provide for his or
her reasonable maintenance needs from his or her own means and earnings.
[140] It should be noted that this definition limits the scope of the relief to a narrow
class of cohabitation relationships only – those that are permanent heterosexual life
was argued by the respondents and the amicus in this Court that basing the relief only
on parties who have expressly or tacitly undertaken duties of support, which was also
60
This case is concerned with heterosexual cohabitation relationships only. It does not concern gay and lesbian
life partnerships. The result of a constitutional challenge to section 2(1) of the Act on the basis of unfair
discrimination on the ground of sexual orientation may be different to the challenge launched in this case.
74
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
the approach adopted by this Court in Satchwell’s case,61 was not correct because
family law should not be governed by contractual principles and the common law
should instead be developed to give rise to an automatic legal duty of support between
the parties to permanent life partnerships. The difficulty with this submission is that
the development of the common law as proposed by the amicus was not relief sought
in this litigation. The relief sought in this case was a declaration of constitutional
invalidity in respect of section 2(1) of the Act. Developing the common law as
grant on appeal, in circumstances where it is has not been considered by any other
[141] In our view, the proposed order identifies the relationships which perform most
closely a similar social function to marriage and the relief should not extend beyond
such a relationship has not been afforded any equitable distribution from his or her
partner’s estate. We do this because we consider that even where a life partnership
the Legislature to regulate that partnership in the same way as it regulates a marriage.
The key issue for the Constitution is to ensure that some provision is made equitably
to regulate the circumstances of a cohabiting partner upon the death of the other
61
Above n 4.
75
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
[142] In this case, as it happens, Mrs Robinson was provided for in Mr Shandling’s
will. That will recognised her contribution to the partnership and her potential
approximately one third of his estate. In our view, this constitutes an adequate
Robinson to any further relief within the terms of the order we propose. In these
In our view, this is an area which should best be regulated by the Legislature and it
[143] We would therefore agree with Sachs J, though for different reasons, that the
applicants have established that section 2(1) of the Act is unfairly discriminatory in
that neither it nor any other provision of the law regulates the rights of surviving
resolve this. Given the complexity of the task, we consider that two years is an
appropriate period to give the Legislature to cure the defect in the current legislation.
[144] Neither the applicant nor the respondents sought costs against one another. The
respondents did seek costs against the Minister for Justice and Constitutional
76
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
Development on an attorney and client basis in the light of the fact that she abided the
outcome of the litigation in the High Court and then sought to lodge evidence in this
Court and oppose the relief. Given that this judgment is not supported by a majority
of the members of this Court who heard the matter, it is not necessary for us to
consider whether it would be appropriate to award costs on the basis sought by the
respondents.
[145] We have had an opportunity, since writing this judgment, to read the judgment
prepared by Ngcobo J. We cannot agree with it. In our view, the approach he adopts
status. For these reasons, we propose the following order, which confirms in
substance the order of the High Court, but subjects the order to a period of two years’
suspension.
The Order
has not received an equitable share in the deceased partner’s estate” at the end
77
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ
partner’s estate.”
Surviving Spouses Act, 27 of 1990 of the following, at the end of the existing
read as though it included the following at the end of the existing definition –
78
MOKGORO AND O’REGAN JJ/ SACHS J
of 2 years from the date of this order to enable the Legislature to take steps to
6. Any party may approach this Court, on notice to all other parties, for an
paragraph 5, the order of invalidity that shall come into operation two years
after the date of this order shall have no effect on the validity of any acts
been wound up by the date upon which the order of invalidity comes into
effect.
SACHS J:
Introduction
[146] This case raises complex social and legal questions about the interaction
79
SACHS J
[147] The problem does not lie in defining the technical legal question to be
answered: does the fact that the Constitution prohibits unfair discrimination on the
ground of marital status, mean that the exclusion of the survivor of a committed,
permanent and intimate life partner from the benefits of the Maintenance of Surviving
[148] Similarly, it is not difficult to illustrate the practical issues involved: to take a
not unusual situation, should a person who has shared her home and life with her
deceased partner, borne and raised children with him, cared for him in health and in
sickness, and dedicated her life to support the family they created together, be treated
as a legal stranger to his estate, with no claim for subsistence because they were never
[149] The source of the complexity appears to lie elsewhere. In my view this is one
of those cases in which however forceful the reasoned text might be, it is the largely
unstated subtext which will be determinative of the outcome. The formal legal issue
1
Act 27 of 1990. Section 2(1) of the Act provides:
“If a marriage is dissolved by death after the commencement of this Act the survivor shall
have a claim against the estate of the deceased spouse for the provision of his reasonable
maintenance needs until his death or remarriage in so far as he is not able to provide therefor
from his own means and earnings.”
“The state may not unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against anyone on one or more
grounds, including race, gender, sex, pregnancy, marital status, ethnic or social origin, colour,
sexual orientation, age, disability, religion, conscience, belief, culture, language and birth.”
[My emphasis].
80
SACHS J
historical, social, moral and cultural ingredients. At times these emerge and enter
explicitly into the legal discourse. More often they exercise a subterranean influence,
all the more powerful for being submerged in deep and largely unarticulated
philosophical positions.
[150] Thus the judgment of Skweyiya J, which has majority support, holds that the
deceased estate to maintain a surviving spouse on the one hand, and not, on the other
to impose that duty upon the deceased estate where the deceased bore no such duty by
operation of law during his or her lifetime to maintain the partner in a heterosexual
partnership. The answer, the judgment decides, is that such discrimination is not
unfair.
[151] I find myself in disagreement with the judgment both as to the approach utilised
and to the conclusion reached, and totally so. This is not because I would challenge
the legal logic used, which appears to be impeccable within the framework adopted. It
is because I would locate the issue in a completely different legal landscape. I do not
the context of what the common law would provide during the lifetime of the parties.
eliminates the very issue which needs to be determined, namely, whether for the
81
SACHS J
survivors could have a legally cognisable interest which founds a constitutional right
[152] In my view, the question of the fairness of excluding such survivors from such
benefits falls to be assessed not in the narrow confines of the rules established by
matrimonial law, but rather within the broader and more situation-sensitive framework
of the principles of family law, principles that are evolving rapidly in our new
constitutional era. By its very nature, the quality of fairness, like that of mercy and
justice, is not strained. The enquiry as to what is fair in our new constitutional
democracy accordingly does not pass easily through the eye of the needle of black-
letter law. Judicial dispassion does not exclude judicial compassion; the question of
fairness must be rigorously dealt with, but in a people-centred and not a rule-centred
way.
[153] The issues raised are novel. A wide range of jurisprudential perspectives are
implicated. Because I differ fundamentally with the majority with regard to the point
of departure and the context of the enquiry I have found it necessary to set out my
views at some length. The first part of this judgment seeks to delineate and establish
the jurisprudential setting in which I believe the issues should be located. The second
part sets out my reasons for holding that the Act does in fact discriminate unfairly
PART ONE
82
SACHS J
[154] Respect for human autonomy undoubtedly implies that the law must honour the
choices that people make, including the decision whether or not to marry. A central
philosophical premise underlying the majority judgment (as well as the basis for the
opting not to marry, thereby not accepting the legal responsibilities and entitlements
that go with marriage, a person cannot complain if she is denied the legal benefits she
would have had if she had married. Having chosen cohabitation rather than marriage,
she must bear the consequences. Just as the choice to marry is one of life’s defining
moments, so, it is contended, the choice not to marry must be a determinative feature
[155] Sinclair2 indicates her respect for such an argument, which implies that freedom
simply become a different type of marriage. She goes on, however, to negate this
contention. On the premise that two people set up a home together, live in a stable,
permanent, affective relationship that emulates marriage, and intend to deal fairly with
one another, the law’s objective, she states, should be to achieve equity between the
parties.3 This, she adds, should be accomplished both during the currency of the
2
Sinclair The Law of Marriage: Based on H.R. Hahlo: The South African Law of Husband and Wife vol 1 (Juta,
1996) at 292.
3
Id at 297-8.
83
SACHS J
partnership and after the death of one of the partners. She cites Rhode who points out
[156] In my view this balanced, flexible and nuanced approach accords well with the
giving legal credence not only to a decision to marry but to choices that people make
about alternative lifestyles. Such choices may be freely undertaken, either expressly
parties to marry the other. Yet if the resulting relationships involve clearly
stable family life, then the law should not be astute to penalise or ignore them because
they are unconventional. It should certainly not refuse them recognition because of
4
Rhode Justice and Gender 139 quoted in Sinclair (above n 2) at 298n109.
84
SACHS J
[157] It is instructive to look at the manner in which the Canadian Supreme Court has
majority6 found that, while in theory the individual is free to choose to marry or not to
marry, in practice the reality may be otherwise. It noted further that since the object
of the legislation in question was to sustain families when one of their members was
injured in an accident, this should be the focus of the issue, rather than what the
“If the issue had been viewed as a matter of defining who should receive benefits on a
basis that is relevant to the goal or functional values underlying the legislation, rather
than marriage equivalence, alternatives substantially less invasive of Charter rights
might have been found.” 8
Accordingly, the exclusion of unmarried partners from an accident benefit which was
available to married partners, violated the Charter. In the result, the definition of
“This silent and oft-forgotten group constitutes couples in which one person wishes to
be in a relationship of publicly acknowledged permanence and interdependence and
the other does not . . . . It is small consolation, indeed, to be told that one has been
5
Miron v Trudel [1995] 2 SCR 418.
6
Of five against four.
7
Above n 5 at 420-1.
8
Id at 421.
85
SACHS J
denied equal protection under the Charter by virtue of the fact that one’s partner had
a choice.”9
[158] By way of contrast, in the more recent case of Walsh10 the court decided11 that
to share and contribute to each other’s assets and liabilities,12 and therefore the
by the Nova Scotia Matrimonial Property Act did not violate the Charter.
of choice will be. Because of its relevance to the matter before us I quote extensively
from it:
“This Court has recognized both the historical disadvantage suffered by unmarried
cohabiting couples as well as the recent social acceptance of this family form. As
McLachlin J noted in Miron . . .
9
Id at 471-2.
10
Nova Scotia (Attorney General) v Walsh [2002] 4 SCR 325.
11
By a majority of eight to one.
12
Above n 10 at para 54.
86
SACHS J
Since Miron, . . . significant legislative change has taken place at both the federal and
provincial levels. Numerous statutes that confer benefits on married persons have
been amended so as to include within their ambit unmarried cohabitants.
Nevertheless, social prejudices directed at unmarried partners may still linger, despite
these significant reforms. In light of those social prejudices, this Court recognized in
Miron, that one’s ability to access insurance benefits was not reducible to simply a
matter of choice. L‘Heureux-Dubé J., in her concurring judgment, reasoned as
follows, at para.102:
Where the legislation has the effect of dramatically altering the legal obligations of
partners, as between themselves, choice must be paramount. The decision to marry
or not is intensely personal and engages a complex interplay of social, political,
religious and financial considerations by the individual. While it remains true that
unmarried spouses have suffered from historical disadvantage and stereotyping, it
simultaneously cannot be ignored that many persons in circumstances similar to those
of the parties, that is, opposite sex individuals in conjugal relationships of some
permanence, have chosen to avoid the institution of marriage and the legal
consequences that flow from it.
87
SACHS J
[160] The point is made even more explicitly in Walsh by Gonthier J, who draws a
sharp distinction between re-arrangement of property relations, on the one hand, and
providing spousal support, on the other. Referring to the Maintenance and Custody
Act which provides for maintenance, and is dependent on the need of the applicants
and their capacity to provide for themselves and each other, he states that:
“It is true that in M.v.H., [1999] 2 S.C.R. 3, at para. 177, I recognized that there is ‘a
growing political recognition that cohabiting opposite-sex couples should be subject
to the spousal support regime that applies to married couples because they have come
to fill a similar social role.’ However, I want to underline the fundamental difference
between spousal support, based on the needs of the applicant, and the division of
matrimonial assets. While spousal support is based on need and dependency, the
division of matrimonial assets distributes assets acquired during marriage without
regard to need.
....
The division of matrimonial assets and spousal support have different objectives.
One aims to divide assets according to a property regime chosen by the parties, either
directly by contract or indirectly by the fact of marriage, while the other seeks to
fulfil a social objective: meeting the needs of spouses and their children.”14
13
Id at paras 41-4.
14
Id at paras 203-4. It is not necessary to consider whether in South African circumstances, where welfare
provisions are extremely limited, employment opportunities restricted and the common law has as of yet taken
only tentative steps to encompass the equivalent of the notion of a constructive or resulting trust as the basis for
88
SACHS J
[161] It is relevant that the distinction drawn by Gonthier J was not based on whether
come out of the deceased’s estate, and thereby possibly affect the entitlement of heirs.
It focused on the special importance to be attributed to need and spousal support after
a life-long conjugal relationship with the deceased has come to an end. As a result, on
his approach claims for spousal support could legitimately compete with inheritance
spousal support. What matters is the functional value of the legislation based on
between married and unmarried persons can fairly be made, has also been underlined
by this Court. In Fraser,15 which dealt with a provision that excluded unmarried
fathers from the category of persons whose consent had to be sought for adoption,
Mohamed DP stated:
“In the context of certain laws there would often be some historical and logical
justification for discriminating between married and unmarried persons and the
granting a share of the family home to the survivor, and the doctrine of unjustified enrichment has not been
developed to provide appropriate relief, the decision in Walsh is consistent with our law. See also Goldblatt
who contends that the existing matrimonial property regimes should serve only as a guide to courts, which
should be given a broad discretion to redistribute property on the basis of equity, taking into account the various
material and non-material contributions of the parties, the form of the partnership and any other factor which the
legislature or the courts consider to be useful. In the case of intestate and testate succession, a domestic partner
should be entitled to his/her share of the partnership estate. In the case of intestate succession, the deceased’s
partner should also be entitled to a spouse’s share of the deceased estate. Goldblatt “Regulating domestic
partnerships — A necessary step in the development of South African family law” (2003) 120 SA Law Journal
610 at 625.
15
Fraser v Children’s Court, Pretoria North, and Others 1997 (2) SA 261 (CC); 1997 (2) BCLR 153 (CC).
89
SACHS J
protection of the institution of marriage is a legitimate area for the law to concern
itself with. But in the context of an adoption statute where the real concern of the
law is whether an order for the adoption of the child is justified, a right to veto the
adoption based on the marital status of the parent could lead to very unfair
anomalies.
....
It is . . . evident that not all unmarried fathers are indifferent to the welfare of their
children and that in modern society stable relationships between unmarried parents
are no longer exceptional.”16 [My emphasis.]
anomalies. The survivor of an empty shell marriage will have a claim while
the survivor of a caring and committed life partnership that produced a real
[163] In Fraser this Court stressed the need for a nuanced and balanced consideration
of our society in which the demographic picture will often be quite different from that
on which ‘first world’ western societies are premised. As Mohamed DP pointed out:
“The socio-economic and historical factors which give rise to gender inequality in
South Africa are not always the same as those in many of the ‘first-world’ countries
described.”17 [Footnote omitted.]
16
Id at paras 26 and 43.
17
Above n 15 at para 44.
90
SACHS J
This Court has on numerous occasions stressed the importance of recognising patterns
and not just formal equality.18 The need to take account of this context is as important
difficult to do so because of its hidden nature. For all the subtle masks that racism
may don, it can usually be exposed more easily than sexism and patriarchy, which are
so ancient, all-pervasive and incorporated into the practices of daily life as to appear
socially and culturally normal and legally invisible. The constitutional quest for the
inequality reinforced by the law be not viewed simply as part of an unfortunate yet
legally neutral background. They are intrinsic, not extraneous, to the interpretive
enquiry.
[164] It should be remembered that many of the permanent life partnerships dissolved
by death today would have been established in past decades, when conditions were
even harsher than they are now, and people had far less choice concerning their life
affecting present-day claims for maintenance, the social reality would have been that
in a considerable number of families the man would have regarded himself as the head
of the household with the right to take all major decisions concerning the family. It
would have been he who effectively decided whether he and his partner should
18
President of the Republic of South Africa and Another v Hugo 1997 (4) SA 1 (CC); 1997 (6) BCLR 708 (CC);
Harksen v Lane NO and Others 1998 (1) SA 300 (CC); 1997 (11) BCLR 1489 (CC).
19
See Brink v Kitshoff NO 1996 (4) SA 197 (CC); 1996 (6) BCLR 752 (CC) and Hugo id.
91
SACHS J
register their relationship in terms of the law. If she refused to do what he wanted, he
could have been the one to threaten violence or expulsion, with little chance of the law
intervening.20 Because he would in many cases have been the party to go out to work
while she stayed at home to look after the children and attend to his needs, it would
have been he who accumulated assets, and he who had the proprietary right to
[165] It should be remembered too that the migrant labour system had a profoundly
involved the deliberate and targeted destruction of settled and sustainable African
family life in rural areas so as to provide a flow of cheap labour to the mines and the
towns.21 The chaotic, unstable and oppressive legal universe in which the majority of
the population were as a consequence compelled by law and policy to live had a
severe impact on the way many families were constituted and functioned. Repeal of
the racist laws which sustained the system, and entry into the new constitutional era,
opened the way to fuller lives for those whose dignity had been assailed, and gave
them renewed opportunity to take responsibility for their lives. Yet it did not in itself
correct the imbalances inside the family or eliminate the desperate poverty that is still
so prevalent.
20
See S v Baloyi (Minister of Justice and Another Intervening) 2000 (2) SA 425 (CC); 2000 (1) BCLR 86 (CC).
21
See Sachs Protecting Human Rights in a New South Africa (Oxford University Press, 1990) chapter 6 at 64-
78.
92
SACHS J
[166] Sinclair states that because there is exiguous welfare to protect the victims of
breakdown of intimate relationships, neither public law nor private law, on its own, is
specifically with the failure of the state to provide protection for the vulnerable parties
(iii) The historical and jurisprudential context: from matrimonial law to family law
[167] In a case like the present it is vital to draw a distinction between matrimonial
law and family law. The difference between the two is helpfully analysed in a
South African Law Reform Commission24 (the SALRC Paper). The SALRC Paper
points out that many of the features of marriage which are assumed to have been
present from time immemorial are actually of more recent origin. What is clear,
22
Above n 2 at 301.
23
Id at 302.
24
South African Law Reform Commission ‘Domestic Partnerships’ Discussion Paper 104 Project 118. (The
closing date for comments was 1 December 2003). At the hearing of this matter much attention was paid to
whether a report of a survey done by the Gender Research Project of the Centre for Applied Legal Studies on
Cohabitation and Gender in the South African Context – Implications for Law Reform, November 2001 should
be admitted. I agree with the view that it is generally inappropriate to admit such evidence at a late stage in the
proceedings. I accordingly find it unnecessary to go beyond the SALRC Paper as a dependable and public
source for relevant factual information.
93
SACHS J
however, is that marriage in its many forms has enjoyed a uniquely privileged status,
while domestic partnerships have been virtually unrecognised.25 The SALRC Paper
observes that opposite-sex partners were a largely invisible group as far as the legal
wife’. They were excluded from the rights and obligations which attached
automatically to marriage, and it was not even clear whether any agreements which
they entered into in order to create parallel rights and obligations, were legally
enforceable.26
[168] The SALRC Paper notes that over the years, however, there has been an
increasing focus on the rights of opposite and same-sex partners, and domestic
of marriage started in South African law with the imposition of support obligations
created in domestic partnership agreements and continued with the use of principles of
unjust enrichment to provide property rights and to extend statutorily defined benefits
similar to partnerships.27
25
Id at 3 para 1.2.2.
26
Id at 3 para 1.2.3.
27
Id at 4 para 1.2.6.
94
SACHS J
[169] The SALRC Paper comments that initially the extension was rather grudging
and seemed primarily designed to ‘pass the buck’ from the welfare authorities to the
[170] The SALRC Paper concludes that legal regulation is needed since the existing
relationships. The significant numbers involved mean that the Napoleonic adage that
“cohabitants ignore the law and the law ignores them” is no longer acceptable.31
28
Id
29
Id at 5 para 1.2.8. The SALRC Paper also notes at 17 para 2.1.8-10 that South African statistics also
demonstrate the rising trend in domestic partnerships. Even conservative statistics indicate that a very large
number of people live in domestic partnerships in South Africa. Statistical data show that only about 40% of
Africans and Coloured women are married. In the 1996 Census the figures for people living together in the
different population groups were as follows: African: 1 056 992; Coloured: 132 180; Indian/Asian: 7119; White:
84 027; Unspecified: 8181. Even allowing for imprecision, the Paper states, we must recognise that there are
large numbers of people in dependence-producing relationships who are ignored by the law.
30
Above n 24 at 26 para 2.2.34.
31
Id at 17 para 2.1.10. A similar point is made in a report by the Law Commission of Canada which calls for
recognition and support for all close personal adult relationships. Entitled “Beyond Conjugality”, it states that:
95
SACHS J
Where a domestic partnership has created responsibilities for, and expectations of, the
parties, the law should play a role in enforcing the responsibilities and realising the
[171] Academic opinion also strongly favours recognition by the law of domestic
the functions that they perform rather than in terms of traditional categories. If we
move away from defining relationships in terms of marriage, we can look at the actual
functions that they perform in society.34 She contends that the purpose of family law
is to protect vulnerable members of families and to ensure fairness between the parties
in family disputes. Women and children are vulnerable groups in our society and
often become poorer when families break down. The lack of legal protection afforded
to domestic partnerships increases the vulnerability of these groups living within such
arrangements. She concludes that a domestic partnership is but one amongst many
...
The state cannot create healthy relationships; it can only seek to foster the conditions in which
close personal relationships that are reasonably equal, mutually committed, respectful and safe
can flourish.
...
There are many instances where the law imposes rights and responsibilities on the basis of a
particular kind of relationship, rather than examining the nature of that relationship. In other
words, rights and responsibilities are imposed on the basis of the status rather than the
function of a relationship.” See http://www.lcc.gc.ca/en/themes/pr/cpra/report.asp [Last
visited 25 January 2005]. Executive Summary, 21 December 2001.
32
Goldblatt above n 14 at 617.
33
Incomplete research I have done indicates the last writer to oppose recognition of cohabitation was Hahlo in
1985. See Hahlo ‘Cohabitation, Concubinage and the Common Law Marriage’ in Kahn (ed) Fiat Iustitia:
Essays in Memory of Oliver Deneys Schreiner (Juta, 1983) at 262-3. See too Hahlo The South African Law of
Husband and Wife 5 ed (Juta, 1985) at 35-42.
34
Above n 14 at 616-7.
96
SACHS J
different types of family and should be included within the definition of family for the
[172] The new way of looking at family law represents an emphatic shift from what
responsibilities, towards a functional one. (I believe that it is this shift that lies at the
argument, only those who comply with the current definition of marriage are entitled
to the rights and obligations attached to marriage, and only a legally valid marriage
can create a family worthy of legal protection.36 The SALRC Paper offers its own
reply. Against this argument, it states, one may put what has been referred to as the
functional response, which emanates from the argument that marriage changes over
time and that the time has come for marriage to be redefined.37
[173] The SALRC Paper goes on to say that supporters of the functional argument
advocate the definition of marriage according to the function that it serves and argue
that other relationships can also fulfil the functions that are traditionally conceived to
be attributes of marriage only.38 Such an approach looks beyond biology and the legal
35
Id at 610-11.
36
Above n 24 at 164 para 7.1.17.
37
Id at 165 para 7.1.18.
38
Id
97
SACHS J
“[w]hen supporters of the definitional argument assume that couples who have made
a public commitment by way of marriage are the only ones who have a legal
responsibility to each other, and would be more likely to provide a child with stability
and security, they are under a wrong impression. . . . [E]ven married relationships are
not guaranteed for life and do end with inevitable accompanying negative
39
consequences.”
[174] The SALRC Paper suggests that conditions in South Africa today require a shift
“[b]ecause the exclusive nature of the common-law definition of marriage does not
reflect social reality, [and it has thus] become necessary under certain legislation to
adopt a functional approach to defining family status, with the result that couples who
do not fit the traditional family model may be deemed spouse of one another.” 41
According to the SALRC Paper, the South African courts (and the legislator) should
determine whether or not to extend common law and other legal protections to family
members on this basis. It asserts furthermore that such an approach will lead to
39
Id at 174 paras 7.1.51-7.1.52.
40
Id at 174 paras 7.1.52-7.1.53.
41
Id at 177 para 7.1.63.
98
SACHS J
greater fairness, will bring law in line with reality and is more likely to harmonise the
that the Constitution itself accepted this type of family unit by providing that a
detained person, including a sentenced prisoner, has the right to communicate with,
and be visited by, that person’s spouse or partner.43 Since 1994 a flurry of statutes has
recognised domestic partnerships. These include the Medical Schemes Act of 1998,
the Prevention of Domestic Violence Act of 1998, the Housing Act of 1997, the
Compensation for Occupational Injuries and Diseases Act of 1997 and the Basic
42
Id at 178 para 7.1.64.
43
Section 35(2)(f)(i).
44
The following is an incomplete overview of the statutes indicating the legislator’s acknowledgment of
domestic partnerships:
The Insolvency Act 24 of 1936. Section 21(13) provides that the word “spouse” not only means wife or
husband in the legal sense, but includes wife or husband by virtue of marriage according to any law or custom,
and also a woman living with a man as his wife or a man living with a woman as her husband, although not
married to one another.
The Independent Media Commission Act 148 of 1993. Section 6(1)(f) prohibits a person from being appointed
or remaining a commissioner if such a person or his or her spouse, partner or associate holds an office in or with
or is employed by any person or company, organization or other body, which has a direct or indirect financial
interest in the telecommunications, broadcasting, or printed media industry.
The Pensions Fund Act 24 of 1956. Although section 1 (as amended by section 6 of the Pensions Fund
Amendment Act 22 of 1996) does not expressly define a domestic life partner as a “dependant” in relation to a
member, it does make provision for persons who are factually (but not legally) dependent on the member for
maintenance. It may as a result be inferred that a person whose life partner was a member of the fund may be
included as a dependant for the purpose of the Act.
99
SACHS J
The Special Pensions Act 69 of 1996. The definition of “spouse” in section 31(2)(iii) of the Act refers to “the
partner . . . in a marriage relationship” which latter relationship is defined to include “a continuous cohabitation
in a homosexual or heterosexual partnership for a period of at least 5 years”.
The Constitution of the Republic of South Africa. Section 35(2)(f)(i), dealing with the rights of arrested,
detained and accused persons, provides that such person has the right to communicate with and to be visited by
his or her spouse or partner.
The Lotteries Act 57 of 1997. Section 3(7)(a)(ii), states (inter alia) that a person shall not be appointed or
remain a board member if such person through his spouse or life partner (inter alia) has or obtains a direct or
indirect financial interest in any lottery or gambling or associated activity. Section 3(8) states that a member of
the board or his or her spouse or life partner, may not for a period of 12 months after the termination of
membership of the board take up employment or receive any benefit from persons making certain applications
in terms of this Act.
Compensation for Occupational Injuries and Diseases Amendment Act 130 of 1993. Section 1 states that a
“dependant of an employee” includes, if there is no widow or widower, “a person with whom the employee was
at the time of the employee’s death living as husband and wife”.
Basic Conditions of Employment Act 75 of 1997. Section 27(2)(c)(i) provides that an employer must provide
an employee, at the request of the latter, three days paid leave, which the employee is entitled to take in the
event of the death of the employee’s spouse or life partner.
The Housing Act 107 of 1997. Section 8(6)(e)(ii)(aa) (prior to its repeal) provided that a “spouse” included a
person with whom the member lived as if they were married or with whom the member habitually cohabited.
The South African Civil Aviation Authority Act 40 of 1998. Section 9(4) states that if a member of the Board,
or his or her immediate family member, life partner or business associate, has any direct or indirect financial
interest in any matter to be dealt with at any meeting of the Board, that member must then (inter alia) disclose
the interest, not attend board meetings during consideration of the matter and may not take part as a member of
the Board in the consideration of the matter. Section 11(5)(b) states that the Chief Executive Officer or his or
her spouse, immediate family member, life partner or business associate, may not hold any direct or indirect
financial interest in any civil aviation activity or the civil aviation industry without approval or unless such
approval is open to public inspection.
The Employment Equity Act 55 of 1998. Section 1 which defines “family responsibility” includes
“responsibility of employees in relation to their spouse or partner, their dependent children or other members of
their immediate family who need their care or support”.
The Domestic Violence Act 116 of 1998. In section 1 a “domestic relationship” is defined as a relationship
between a complainant and a respondent who are of the same or opposite sex and who live/lived together in a
relationship in the nature of marriage, although they are not married to each other.
The Medical Schemes Act 131 of 1998. Section 24(2)(e) states that the Council shall not register a medical
scheme unless it is satisfied that the medical scheme will not unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against
any person on arbitrary grounds which include marital status.
The Road Traffic Management Act 20 of 1999. Section 10(2) also states that where a member of the board or
(inter alia) his or her life partner has any direct or indirect financial interest in any matter to be dealt with at a
meeting of the board then that member should comply with all the provisions under that section and section 15
(9) states that a chief executive officer or (inter alia) his or her life partner, may not hold any direct or indirect
financial interest in any road traffic activity without approval or unless such approval is open to public
inspection.
The Promotion of Equality and Prevention of Unfair Discrimination Act 4 of 2000. Section 1 refers to “family
responsibility” in relation to a complainant’s spouse, partner, dependant, child or other members of his or her
family in respect of whom the member is liable for care and support.
100
SACHS J
[176] Of special importance are the Employment Equity Act of 1998 (the
Discrimination Act of 2000 (the Equality Act). These were adopted by Parliament to
give legislative expression to the need to achieve equality in South Africa. Covering
as they do a wide range of activities and situations, they represent particularly strong
dependent children or other members of their immediate family who need their care or
support.”
[177] Similarly the Equality Act provides in its definition section that “family
dependant, child or other members of his or her family in respect of whom the
member is liable for care and support.” The Act goes on to state that “‘marital status’
relationship, whether with a person of the same or the opposite sex, involving a
support. Though one does not use legislation to interpret the Constitution, the
The Estate Duty Act 45 of 1955 as amended by section 3 of the Taxation Laws Amendment Act 5 of 2001.
Section 1 provides that a ‘spouse’ in relation to any deceased person, includes a person who at the time of the
death of such deceased person was the partner of such person in a same-sex or heterosexual union which the
Commissioner is satisfied is intended to be permanent.
101
SACHS J
[178] The fact that many if not all statutes adopted in recent times dealing with the
rights of conjugal partners expressly include non-married partners within their ambit,
is indicative of a new legislative approach consistent with new values, and as the
SALRC Paper suggests, with the spirit, purport and object of the Constitution. As was
said in Daniels:45
“The fact that many statutes adopted in recent times dealing with married persons
expressly include parties to Muslim unions under their provisions is indicative of a
new approach consistent with constitutional values. The existence of such provisions
in other statutes does not imply that their absence in the Acts before us has special
significance. The Intestate Succession Act and the Maintenance of Surviving
Spouses Act were both last amended before the era of constitutional democracy
arrived. The fact that the new democratic Parliament has not as yet included Muslim
marriages expressly within the purview of the protection granted by the Acts,
accordingly, cannot be interpreted so as to exclude them contrary to the spirit, purport
and objects of the Constitution.”46
45
Daniels v Campbell NO and Others 2004 (5) SA 331 (CC); 2004 (7) BCLR 735 (CC).
46
Id at para 27. [The statutes] include (See Daniels id) [Civil Proceedings Evidence Act 25 of 1965 (s 10A
recognises religious marriages for the purposes of the law of evidence); Criminal Procedure Act 51 of 1977 (s
195(2) recognises religious marriages for the purposes of the compellability of spouses as witnesses in criminal
proceedings); Pension Funds Act 24 of 1956 (s 1(b)(ii): definition of “dependant”); Special Pensions Act 69 of
1996 (s 31(b)(ii): definition of “dependant”); Government Employees Pension Law Proclamation 21 of 1996 (s
1(b)(ii): definition of “dependant” and Schedule 1 item 1.19, definition of “spouse”); Demobilisation Act 99 of
1996 (section 1(vi)(c): definition of “dependant”); Value-Added Tax Act 89 of 1991 (Notes 6 and 7 to item
406.00 of Schedule 1 recognise religious marriages for the purposes of tax exemptions in respect of goods
imported into South Africa); Transfer Duty Act 40 of 1949 (s 9(1)(f) read with the definition of “spouse” in
section 1 exempts from transfer duty property inherited by the surviving spouse in a religious marriage); and
Estate Duty Act 45 of 1955 (s 4(q) read with the definition of “spouse” in section 1 exempts from estate duty
property accruing to the surviving spouse in a religious marriage).
102
SACHS J
[179] The increased legislative recognition being given to cohabitation suggests that
cohabitation has achieved a particular status of its own. This status gives it something
practice it will depend upon the qualitative and quantitative nature of the cohabitation
and the particular legal purpose for which it is being claimed, or denied, that a couple
and long-term cohabitation, between the casual affair and the stable relationship,
between relationships which have resulted in the birth of children and those which
have not, and between couples who live together and couples who do not. Marriage
law in this respect is different: you are either married with all the legal consequences
that follow, or you are not. Your life circumstances are irrelevant. The consequences
are to that extent invariable. By way of contrast, Parry47 observes it is not perhaps
surprising that the legal response to relationships outside marriage has been as
[180] Finally, government policy is clearly committed towards dealing with families
in functional rather than definitional terms. Thus the Department of Population and
47
Parry The Law Relating to Cohabitation 3 ed (Sweet and Maxwell, 1993). He was referring to the law in
England, but in this respect the South African situation has not been much different.
48
Id at 3.
103
SACHS J
primary social unit which ideally provides care, nurturing and socialisation for its
members. It seeks to provide them with physical, economic, emotional, social,
cultural and spiritual security.”49
Conclusion
[181] The SALRC Paper, the thrust of legislation and academic opinion all point in
the same direction. It is towards establishing a new legal landscape consistent with
the values of diversity, tolerance of difference and the concern for human dignity
expressed in the Constitution. The emphasis shifts from locating conjugal rights and
marriage-like, intimate and permanent family relationships. The problem at the heart
of this case is that although the law has advanced rapidly in granting recognition to
cohabitants in relation to public life and in respect of third parties, it has done little, if
[182] One further introductory point needs to be made. At the hearing of the present
maintenance claims by cohabitant survivors. The intervention by the state was limited
to seeking to ensure that the remedy does not have the effect of pre-empting
PART TWO
49
The Department of Population of Welfare Development, Draft White Paper (1996) 156, as quoted in Du
Plessis and Pete Constitutional Democracy in South Africa 1994 - 2004 (Butterworths, 2004) at 72.
104
SACHS J
[183] It is in the above context that I turn to the question of whether the exclusion of
non-married members of intimate life partnerships from the benefits of the Act
by examining the circumstances in which the Act was passed. Its genesis explains its
[184] The decision of the Appellate Division in Glazer v Glazer N.O.50 established
that under the common law (as interpreted in 1963) no duty to support a disinherited
surviving spouse rested on the deceased spouse’s estate. In the course of his
“It is one thing to hold a divorced guilty husband liable for the maintenance of an
innocent wife. To grant a needy widow a share in her husband’s deceased estate or
maintenance out of the assets in his estate, merely because she is indigent and without
regard to other circumstances which may have influenced him in deliberately making
no provision for her, is a somewhat different matter. The recognition of the
obligation in the one case would not tend to prove the existence of a right in the other
case.”51
Pleas were long made for legislative intervention to overcome the harsh effects of
50
1963 (4) SA 694 (A).
51
Id at 705.
105
SACHS J
testation. They finally bore fruit in the form of the Act. The Act emanated from the
recommendations of the South African Law Commission52 to the effect that the
problem, and that a claim for maintenance should be given to the surviving spouse by
operation of law. Rejecting the notion that the testator would not have disinherited the
widow without good reason and that considerations of morality should play a role, the
[185] It is convenient to set out once again the provisions of section 2(1) of the Act.
They read:
“If a marriage is dissolved by death after the commencement of this Act the survivor
shall have a claim against the estate of the deceased spouse for the provision of his
reasonable maintenance needs until his death or remarriage in so far as he is not able
to provide therefor from his own means and earnings.”
52
South African Law Commission Report, “Review of the Law of Succession: The Introduction of a Legitimate
Portion or the Granting of a Right to Maintenance to the Surviving Spouse” Project 22 (August 1987).
53
That is, a portion of the estate secured for the widow or other defined members of the family that cannot be
disposed of by will.
54
Above n 52 at 34. See also Keyser “Law of Persons and Family Law” in 1990 Annual Survey of South
African Law.
106
SACHS J
[186] In Daniels this Court recently observed that although linguistically gender-
neutral, in substantive terms the Act55 benefited mainly widows rather than widowers.
“The value of non-sexism is foundational to our Constitution and requires a hard look
at the reality of the lives that women have been compelled to lead by law and legally-
backed social practices. This, in turn, necessitates acknowledging the constitutional
goal of achieving substantive equality between men and women. The reality has been
and still in large measure continues to be that in our patriarchal culture men find it
easier than women to receive income and acquire property.”56 [Footnotes omitted.]
The Court stressed that the Act be seen as a measure intended primarily to rescue
widows from possible penury. I would add that the survivor’s need for maintenance is
accompanied by a dramatic change in life circumstances. To the extent, then, that the
widow has a claim against the estate at least for her basic needs to be satisfied, the
choice by the deceased not to provide for her by will (or simply the consequences of
[187] It is against this particular legal background, and within the broad legal
landscape delineated in Part One of this judgment, that the question in this matter
must be asked: given the manifest remedial purposes of the Act and the constitutional
requirement of ensuring equal protection and benefit of the law, must the Act’s ambit
55
Together with the Intestate Succession Act 81 of 1987.
56
Above n 45 at para 22.
107
SACHS J
be extended to cover survivors of permanent life partnerships that have not been
consecrated by marriage?
[188] In what the SALRC Paper referred to as the Calvinistic and conservative
atmosphere of the pre-constitutional era, the answer to this question would have been
simple. People living in extra-marital unions would have been condemned at worst as
living in sin, and at best as being irresponsible. They would have been disentitled
from claiming any benefit whatsoever under the law. Today, however, we are not
bound by the original intent of the legislators. We are living in an open and
forms of family life are tolerated by society and recognised by the law, and the right to
“Everyone is equal before the law and has the right to equal protection and benefit of
the law.”
“The state may not unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against anyone on one
or more grounds, including race, gender, sex, pregnancy, marital status, ethnic or
social origin, colour, sexual orientation, age, disability, religion, conscience, belief,
culture, language and birth.”
57
See Christian Education South Africa v Minister of Education 2000 (4) SA 757 (CC); 2000 (10) BCLR 1051
(CC).
108
SACHS J
“Discrimination on one or more of the grounds listed in subsection (3) is unfair unless
it is established that the discrimination is fair.”
The Constitution accordingly declares that everyone has the right to equal protection
and benefit of the law, and expressly forbids unfair discrimination on the ground of
marital status. So the legal issue before us is whether the non-inclusion of unmarried
cohabitants under the Act violates their constitutional right not to be discriminated
[190] The restriction of the benefit to married survivors only, clearly differentiates
them from unmarried survivors who share with them the status of bereavement and
need after the death of their intimate life partner. All that distinguishes them is their
marital status: the one group was married, and the other was not. This Court has held
that once there is differentiation on one of the listed grounds, there is discrimination.58
[191] In considering the fairness of the Act it becomes vital to decide what the
framework of the enquiry should be. In my view, the very nature of the equality
58
See Pretoria City Council v Walker 1998 (2) SA 363 (CC); 1998 (3) BCLR 257 (CC) at para 35, where the
argument (by myself) that at least some degree of prejudice or disadvantage had to be shown in order to
establish discrimination, was rejected by the majority of the Court, which held that once there is differentiation
on one of the listed grounds, discrimination is to be presumed.
109
SACHS J
landscape established by the impugned measure itself. As Wilson J pointed out in the
“[I]t is important to look not only at the impugned legislation which has created a
distinction that violates the right to equality but also the larger social, political and
legal context . . . . A finding that there is discrimination will, I think, in most but
perhaps not all cases, necessarily entail a search for disadvantage that exists apart
from and independent of the particular legal distinction being challenged.”59
The larger socio-legal context has already been described. I will now examine the
larger constitutional and legal context. In particular, I will give the reasons why I
believe that the context for the analysis should be that of family law, and not just that
of matrimonial law.
save from unfair treatment those families that cannot invoke the protections provided
by matrimonial law. By implication, the enquiry must shift from the relatively
precise, circumscribed and rule-governed terrain of matrimonial law to the wider and
evolving fields of family law. It is important to note that the present case does not
involve any attack on the rules and principles of matrimonial law. Indeed, the
challenge is not to any malevolence in the Act, but to the limits of its beneficence.
[193] Supporting the need for enlarging the scope of family law, Goldblatt underlines
in a helpful analysis that families need to be understood on the basis of the functions
59
R v Turpin (1989) 39 CRR 306 at 335-6. See Harksen above n 18 at para 123.
110
SACHS J
that they perform, rather than in terms of traditional categories. If we move away
from defining relationships in terms of marriage, we can look at the actual functions
that they perform in society.60 The question asked is: where a domestic partnership
has created responsibilities for, and expectations of, the parties, should the law play a
role in enforcing the responsibilities and realising the expectations of the parties that
are in conflict?61
[194] Goldblatt states further that the purpose of family law is to protect vulnerable
members of families and to ensure fairness between the parties in family disputes.
Women and children are vulnerable groups in our society and often become poorer
when families break down.62 A domestic partnership is but one amongst many
different types of family and should be included within the definition of family for the
commitment and create dependence between the parties. It also implies that the
60
Above n 14 at 616-7.
61
Id at 617. Goldblatt adds that the notion of separation of public and private spheres is advanced to justify
non-intervention on the basis that the realm of the family should be seen as private (at 616). It is argued that the
law should not intervene in this private sphere save to protect freedom as to whether to marry or not, with the
consequences that follow, and freedom of testation. (It was this approach that underlay the reasoning of Steyn
CJ in Glazer (above n 50). Goldblatt argues, however, that such a libertarian ideology should not be allowed to
perpetuate inequality by giving the powerful the opportunity to remain outside the law’s reach with regard to
domestic relationships. She contends, correctly in my view, that the lack of legal protection afforded to
domestic partnerships increases the vulnerability of the groups living within such arrangements (at 611).
62
Above n 14 at 610-11.
63
Id at 611.
111
SACHS J
[195] Goldblatt notes that more than a million South Africans are in non-marital
relationships with their intimate partners. These ‘domestic partnerships’ play a crucial
role in meeting the financial, emotional, reproductive and other needs of their
members. There are many reasons why people, often across race and class divides,
cohabit without marrying. One of the main reasons for the prevalence of such
relationships in South Africa is the extent of migrancy in our country.64 She observes
that many men marry in the rural areas and form domestic partnerships in the urban
[196] The issue in the present matter, then, is not whether it is fair for the state to
single out married partners for claims of maintenance, as opposed, say, to siblings or
parents or life-long friends of the deceased. Nor is it to decide whether widows are
entitled to special consideration not accorded to other persons who might be alone,
elderly and in need. It is, first, to examine the specific purpose that the Act is
intended to serve in the context of the overall objectives of family law. Then it is to
determine whether in substantive terms the committed life partner of the deceased
bears the same relationship to the deceased in every respect as a married partner, save
for not having gone through the formalities of marriage. Finally, it is to decide if such
64
Id at 610.
65
Id
112
SACHS J
Constitution takes the matter very far. Rather, analysis should begin with
identification of the specific kinds of marginalisation and exclusion which led to the
discrimination.
[198] These would include the directly discriminatory practices of the past, such as
penalising women for being married (e.g. women teachers and civil servants who
automatically lost their employment on marriage on the basis that they could not hold
down a job and look after their husbands and children at the same time); or penalising
women for not being married (e.g. for bringing disgrace on an institution,
married women as losing the autonomy they formerly had as single women, because
from marriage onwards they required their husband’s consent for various legal
of practice reserved for married people only. In addition, there were indirect forms of
disadvantage affecting people not living as a married couple. Thus single parents,
widows and widowers could be denied housing, or suffer from tax or social security
disadvantages or be refused mortgages because they did not fit the format of the
113
SACHS J
[199] Two points need to be noted. First, it is women rather than men who in general
suffered disadvantage because of their status of being married or not married. Any
advantage and disadvantage being associated with the status of being and not being
married.
[200] The second is that by the time the Constitution was adopted, legal disabilities
associated with being married had been eliminated from the common law.
Nevertheless, marital status was expressly identified in section 9(3) as one of the
grounds of potential discrimination. This would seem to suggest that it was included
precisely to protect the rights of people who were vulnerable not because they were
married, but because they were not married. It is not easy to see why, if it was not
was itemised in section 9(3) in the first place. By implication its inclusion
the specific difficulties they face. The obvious classes of people requiring protection
[201] Once more it will be instructive to look at the manner in which the Canadian
Supreme Court has approached the question. In Miron,66 where the applicants
66
Above n 5.
114
SACHS J
challenged an accident compensation statute on the grounds that it provided for the
[202] The point was reinforced in the same matter by L’Heureux-Dubé J, who stated
that the question whether or not persons in relationships analogous to marriage have
typically suffered historical disadvantage is not clear-cut, partly because the modern
comparatively recent one. She went on to observe that the subgroups within the
ground of marital status that have typically suffered the most historical disadvantage
and marginalisation are individuals who are single parents, or are divorced or
separated. The mere fact that the common law spouses are not in the first group that
67
Id at 420.
115
SACHS J
comes to mind when considering historical disadvantage does not mean, however, that
....
[203] South African society has indeed become far more tolerant than it once was
marriage. Yet there can be no doubt that many prejudices of the past linger on,
particularly against women who are seen as not conducting their lives in a manner
with moral disapproval is still directed at unmarried couples. By the very nature of
defiant. This will be irrespective of the actual degree of commitment, seriousness and
68
Id at 469.
69
Id at 469-70.
116
SACHS J
[204] It is important to stress at this point that the issue is not whether members of
as a sacred contract which constitutes the only acceptable gateway to legitimate sexual
intimacy and cohabitation. Nor is it to query the corollary right of such believers to
condemn those who are guilty of what they may regard as fornication and adultery.
Clearly their entitlement as part of their religious belief to criticise what they regard as
misconduct remains unchallenged. The question, rather, is whether the state should be
bound by such concerns. Going further, it is whether the state is required or entitled
I will consider why the state gives pre-eminence to the institution of marriage,
examine the constitutional values that marriage both embodies and promotes, and then
ask whether these require that marriage be given absolute status under the Act.
[205] In Satchwell70 this Court acknowledged the role of marriage in society in the
following terms:
“In terms of our common law, marriage creates a physical, moral and spiritual
community of law which imposes reciprocal duties of cohabitation and support. The
70
Satchwell v President of the Republic of South Africa and Another 2002 (6) SA 1 (CC); 2002 (9) BCLR 986
(CC).
117
SACHS J
As the SALRC Paper comments, the rights and obligations associated with marriage
are vast. Besides the religious and social importance of marriage, marriage as an
institution was (at the time the SALRC Paper was produced) the only source of socio-
adoption, access to wrongful death claims, spousal benefits, bereavement leave, tax
advantages and post-divorce rights.72 The SALRC Paper adds that marriage is also
[206] As this Court said in Dawood,74 “[t]he decision to enter into a marriage
many if not most, people . . . .” I would add that our painful history provides
additional reasons why the institution of marriage should receive support. In the pre-
democratic era the racist policies of the state involved disgraceful use of the law in
ways that showed profound disrespect for the marriages of the majority. Thus the
migrant labour system, administered under racist laws and enforced by racist courts,
71
Id at para 22.
72
Above n 24 at 161-2 para 7.1.9.
73
Id at 162.
74
Dawood and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others; Shalabi and Another v Minister of Home Affairs
and Others; Thomas and Another v Minister of Home Affairs and Others 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC); 2000 (8)
BCLR 837 (CC) at para 37.
118
SACHS J
forcing married men to live in what were called bachelor quarters in the towns.
Prohibitions on inter-racial marriage and the refusal of the law to recognise Hindu and
Muslim marriages prevented people from marrying persons of their choice and from
receiving recognition of the marriage rites and ceremonies appropriate to their beliefs.
A host of laws permitted gross intrusion by police and state officials into the intimate
lives of the majority, who as a result were compelled to live in chaotic social and legal
circumstances. Special support for marriage today accordingly helps heal the ravages
of the past. It promotes social stability and supports dignity by giving state
parties are identified, the dates of celebration and dissolution are stipulated, and all the
multifarious and socially important steps which the public administration is required
to make in connection with children and property, are facilitated. Furthermore, the
undertaken. This is particularly important in imposing clear legal duties on the party
advantaged party is usually the man, the result in general terms is that the
solemnisation of marriage tends to favour gender equality rather than the reverse.
[208] There can accordingly be no doubt that the institution of marriage is entitled to
very special recognition and protection by the law. The issue, however, is not whether
119
SACHS J
marriage should in many respects be privileged. Clearly it has to be. The question is
[209] For convenience, I will refer to the principle of restricting claims under the Act
to married survivors only, as the ‘exclusivity principle’. The first constitutional issue,
then, is whether the exclusivity principle is compatible with the prohibition of unfair
matter for decision is whether such unfairness is justifiable under section 36 of the
there will be overlap between them. Nevertheless I will deal with each in turn, on the
basis that the focus of fairness is on the impact on the interests of those affected, while
(vi) The fairness of limiting the benefits of the Act to married persons only
75
Section 36 (1) states the following:
“The rights in the Bill of Rights may be limited only in terms of law of general application to
the extent that the limitation is reasonable and justifiable in an open and democratic society
based on human dignity, equality and freedom, taking into account all relevant factors,
including —
(a) the nature of the right;
(b) the importance of the purpose of the limitation;
(c) the nature and extent of the limitation;
(d) the relation between the limitation and its purpose; and
(e) less restrictive means to achieve the purpose.”
120
SACHS J
[210] Any consideration of the fairness of the exclusivity principle must take account
South Africa. In the First Certification case76 the Court stated that:
“Families are constituted, function and are dissolved in such a variety of ways, and
the possible outcomes of constitutionalising family rights are so uncertain, that
constitution-makers appear frequently to prefer not to regard the right to marry or to
pursue family life as a fundamental right that is appropriate for definition in
constitutionalised terms.”77
“[F]amilies come in many shapes and sizes. The definition of the family also changes
as social practices and traditions change. In recognising the importance of the family,
we must take care not to entrench particular forms of family at the expense of other
forms.”[Footnote omitted.]
Ackermann J made similar statements in National Coalition (2),79 dealing with the
“It is important to emphasise that over the past decades an accelerating process of
transformation has taken place in family relationships, as well as in societal and legal
concepts regarding the family and what it comprises. Sinclair and Heaton, after
alluding to the profound transformations of the legal relationships between family
members that have taken place in the past, comment as follows on the present:
76
Ex Parte Chairperson of the Constitutional Assembly: In Re Certification of the Constitution of the Republic
of South Africa, 1996 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC); 1996 (10) BCLR 1253 (CC).
77
Id at para 99.
78
Above n 74 at para 31.
79
National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality and Others v Minister of Home Affairs and Others 2000 (2)
SA 1 (CC); 2000 (1) BCLR 39 (CC) at para 47.
121
SACHS J
‘But the current period of rapid change seems to ‘strike at the most basic
assumptions’ underlying marriage and the family.
...
Itself a country where considerable political and socio-economic movement has been
and is taking place, South Africa occupies a distinctive position in the context of
developments in the legal relationship between family members and between the
State and the family. Its heterogeneous society is “fissured by differences of
language, religion, race, cultural habit, historical experience and self-definition” and,
consequently, reflects widely varying expectations about marriage, family life and the
position of women in society.’” [Reference omitted.]
[211] In each of the above matters there was a specific legal issue which prompted a
general observation about the need to adopt a flexible and evolutionary approach to
family life.81 I do not think it is appropriate to cherry-pick statements from the above
cases simply on the basis that they appear to be favourable to any particular outcome
in the present matter. Though all highlight the importance of the courts not being
80
Du Toit and Another v Minister of Welfare and Population Development and Others (Lesbian and Gay
Equality Project as Amicus Curiae) 2003 (2) SA 198 (CC); 2002 (10) BCLR 1006 (CC) at para 19.
81
Thus, in the First Certification case the question was whether the failure of the Bill of Rights expressly to
include a right to marry and constitute a family was inconsistent with one of the principles binding on the
Constitutional Assembly. In Dawood the reminder about diversity and not entrenching particular forms of
family, was expressed. National Coalition (2) and Du Toit were both concerned with same-sex couples who, in
terms of the common law definition of marriage and in terms of the Marriage Act 25 of 1961, were not able to
get their unions recognised as marriages even if they so wished. The same jurisprudential movement away from
giving legal recognition only to registered marriages was reflected in Daniels, which dealt in part with the Act
which is being considered in the present matter.
122
SACHS J
bound by traditional views of how families should properly be constituted, none deals
expressly and directly with the issue of the rights of unmarried heterosexual life
partners. Indeed, each case underlines how important its specific social, historical and
[212] The one unifying theme lurking in the evolving approach to all the different
forms of family units being created is that the general purpose of family law is to
context it is significant that the specific objective of the Act is to furnish a preferred
claim to a survivor who is not otherwise provided for and finds herself in need. In the
present matter, hardship on its own, even if associated with the status of not being
does not seek to take to its bosom and respond to all the inequities to be found in our
82
Thus the cases concerning the rights of same-sex partners can be distinguished from the present one on the
basis that gay and lesbian couples could not marry, even if they wished to do so. At the same time, these cases
established that difficulties of proving that such unions constituted permanent life partnerships, could be
overcome, and gave guidance as to how this should be done. In Daniels, on the other hand, there was no legal
impediment to persons who were Muslim from formalising their marriages under the Marriage Act, which they
could do either by following up their religious ceremonies with a civil one, or else by being married by an Imam
who was recognised as a marriage officer. The exercise of choice not to regularise the unions under the
Marriage Act had to be understood in the context of the hegemonic exclusion from recognition of Muslim
marriages effected by the common law as applied by the courts in the pre-constitutional era. There was thus no
reason for interpreting the word “spouse” in the Act (as well as in the Intestate Succession Act) so as not to
include them. In that matter, then, the fact that they chose not to formalise their marriages under the Marriage
Act did not debar them from claiming maintenance under the Act (or a share of the estate under the Intestate
Succession Act). I will go no further than suggesting that the cases provide three indications of indirect
relevance to the issues before us. The first is that, while pronouncing emphatically on the need not to straight-
jacket families in conventional forms, this Court has expressly refrained from taking any position for or against
the recognition of heterosexual unmarried life partnerships. The second is that in relation to questions of how to
prove the existence of permanent life partnerships, one may say that in the case of a non-formalised union,
where there is a judicial will, there will be a judicial way, and problems of proof will be overcome. The third is
that a choice not to formalise one’s relationship under the Marriage Act will not inevitably and of itself
extinguish a claim by a survivor to maintenance under the Act (Daniels above n 45). It is the context that must
be decisive, and in particular the social, political and legal factors which are said to have produced the
discriminatory treatment resulting in unfairness.
123
SACHS J
society. Not every unfairness in life becomes unfairness in law. In order for
between the survivor’s intimate relationship with the deceased, her state of need, the
overall appropriateness in the circumstances of debarring her from being able to claim
maintenance, and the resulting impact on her dignity of re-inforcing the negative type-
[213] The critical question accordingly must be: is there a familial nexus of such
proximity and intensity between the survivor and the deceased as to render it
manifestly unfair to deny her the right to claim maintenance from the estate on the
same basis as she would have had if she and the deceased had been married? I believe
that there are in fact at least two circumstances in which, applying this test, it would
be unfair to exclude permanent, non-married life partners from the benefits of the Act.
[214] The first would be where the parties have freely and seriously committed
provide each other with emotional and material support. The unfairness of the
exclusion would be particularly evident if the undertakings had been expressed in the
form of a legal document. Such a document would satisfy the need to have certainty,
within their respective means and according to their particular needs. Like a marriage
certificate, the document would thus both prove the seriousness of the commitment
124
SACHS J
[215] What should be central, however, is the serious content of the mutual
commitment and not the particular form in which it is expressed. Thus the
“[H]istorically our law has only recognised marriages between heterosexual spouses.
This narrowness of focus has excluded many relationships which create similar
obligations and have a similar social value.
....
The law attaches a duty of support to various family relationships, for example,
husband and wife, and parent and child. In a society where the range of family
formations has widened, such a duty of support may be inferred as a matter of fact in
certain cases of persons involved in permanent, same-sex life partnerships. Whether
such a duty exists or not will depend on the circumstances of each case.”84
believe that a similar approach would be apposite in the case of cohabitants. What
Satchwell establishes is that one can infer as a matter of fact whether a duty exists, not
from any principle of the common law, but from the actual life circumstances of the
[216] Unless the purpose of the Maintenance Act is to stigmatise unmarried life
partners as being beyond the pale, I can see little reason in fairness why the
83
Above n 70.
84
Id at paras 22 and 25.
125
SACHS J
responsibility for maintenance should not survive the death of a partner where either
support the other within his or her means. If anything, the element of voluntarism and
the need to respect such undertakings are notions in society of ‘living in sin’ and
expressed or unconsciously held, these are inappropriate for an open and democratic
society that acknowledges diversity of lifestyle and bases itself on respect for human
the reality of committed, if heterodox, family relationships. The issue should not be
seen exclusively as one of the sanctity of marriage, or simply of the important social
purpose that marriage serves, but as one of the integrity of the family relationship.
bizarre or objectionable.
126
SACHS J
[218] Secondly, I am of the view that responsibility for maintenance can arise not
only from express or tacit agreement but directly from the nature of the particular life
partnership itself. The critical factor will be whether the relationship was such as to
produce dependency for the party who, in material terms at least, was the weaker and
more vulnerable one (and who, in all probability, would have been unable to insist
that the deceased enter into formal marriage). The reciprocity would be based on care
and concern rather than on providing equal support in material or financial terms.
[219] One thinks of the woman who bore children fathered by the deceased, looked
after them in infancy, saw them through school, cared for the home, attended to the
needs of the deceased and nursed him through sickness and the infirmities of old age.
While he earned and accumulated assets, she nurtured the family and remained
penniless. Because of the way in which our patriarchal society has allocated roles and
responsibilities, it will not have been unusual for the deceased to have accumulated
assets and paid towards the upkeep of the home, while the survivor contributed what
she had to offer, namely, her care and sweat equity. The deceased might in fact have
resisted requests by her that they get married in terms of their religion or before a
magistrate. Yet whether or not she can show that she sought marriage and he did not,
the crucial fact remains that there is a direct relationship between her present need and
her past relationship with the deceased. In the words of the Equality Act, what
127
SACHS J
[220] In the not uncommon circumstances mentioned above the nexus between the
survivor and the estate is so strong that I do not think any meaningful distinction can
be drawn between what is legally unfair and what is socially and morally unfair. It
must be borne in mind that the claim is not being brought to establish unfairness under
the common law, or even to show that the common law itself is unfair. The issue is
whether the statute, interpreted in the light of the common law as it stands, impacts
unfairly on a class of persons because of their marital status. Had the purpose of the
Act been primarily to promote marriage as an institution, it might not have been unfair
to exclude unmarried people from its reach. The purpose of the Act, however, was to
provide a statutory claim against the estate for recently bereaved widows in need. The
key ingredients are the familial relationship, intimacy and need. Taking them in
combination, in the circumstances of the very typical example given above, I conclude
that to exclude the survivor simply because she has no marriage certificate, is not only
coupled with the imputation of having been a lawless interloper in the life of the
deceased, severely affronts the dignity of the survivor. The indignity is all the greater
where the relationship with the deceased was marked by intense mutuality of concern
85
The disrespect is intensified if the only question asked relates to who contractually undertook to provide
money or goods. Contributions are made according to ability and in response to need. In Satchwell what was at
issue was a potentially sizeable claim for a survivor’s pension chargeable against the public purse. In these
circumstances the need to establish reciprocity of spousal-like undertakings of support was particularly strong.
In the case of a claim based on subsistence needs against the very estate that the survivor contributed to through
years of devoted support, the material interdependency should be seen as part of a broad mutual undertaking to
provide the kind of reciprocal support that binds intimate partners together.
128
SACHS J
stereotypical manner that is impertinent to those affected, serious equality issues are
the hurt to those affected is not even comprehended by those who cause it, and passes
[222] I should add that while it is true that caring for one’s family is one of life’s
great joys, and as such calls for no extra reward, fairness does not inevitably translate
into sacrifice. As this Court said in Baloyi,86 the purpose of constitutional law is to
perverse interpretation of family law that obliged one to disregard the fact that the
circumstances of need in which a typical survivor might find herself, were produced
precisely by her selfless devotion to the deceased and their family during his lifetime.
for the Act to discriminate against the powerless and economically dependent party,
now threatened with destitution, on the basis that she should either have insisted on
[223] The issues are not simple. There is a great social need to promote marriage as
an institution which provides stability, security and predictability for intimate family
responsibility for their lives, and showing respect for the fact that they are members of
86
Above n 20.
87
Id at para 12.
129
SACHS J
empowerment; helps people escape from a world made up of victimisers and victims
into one consisting of free and equal people; and induces the previously disadvantaged
and subordinated to advance in life by calling on their inner strengths rather than
[224] At the same time it is necessary to acknowledge and respond in a sensitive and
practical manner to the fact that people have had to accommodate themselves to harsh
and diverse life circumstances over which they may have had little control. Many
have been obliged to shoulder burdens heavier than any notion of fairness would
tolerate. All measures aimed at redistribution of such uneven loads, whether through
family law or welfare law, risk being criticised as being calculated to undermine self-
reliance. Yet, while over-paternalism can be disempowering and negate the very
objective of achieving equality, what has disparagingly been called the concept of
judicial tough love88 can be unduly insensitive to the actual and overwhelming
problems people have had to face in life. The knowledge that the law will intervene to
provide basic justice will in fact assist such people to overcome a sense of
fundamental rights. In so doing they enhance rather than undermine dignity and self-
respect.
88
Roberts Clarence Thomas and the Tough Love Crowd (New York University Press, 1995).
130
SACHS J
[225] The reality against which the Act must be interpreted is that many recently
bereaved, elderly, and poor women find themselves with no assets or savings other
than their clothing and cooking utensils, little chance of employment and only the
prospect of a state old-age pension to keep them from penury. Thus, while it is
necessary to emphasise the importance of people taking responsibility for their lives,
and to acknowledge the extraordinary self-reliance shown by many women in the face
of extreme hardship, the law cannot ignore the fact that lack of resources has left
many women with harsh options only. Their choice has been between destitution,
prostitution and loneliness, on the one hand, and continuing cohabitation with a
person who was unwilling or unable to marry them on the other. Any consideration of
the fairness or otherwise of excluding from maintenance claims people who chose the
[226] It follows from the above that the exclusivity principle operates unfairly in at
hypothetical or unusual as to escape the net of constitutional concern. In each case the
unfairness operates both directly and indirectly. In direct terms it treats the unmarried
claimants in a way that disrespects the actual commitment they have shown to their
families through a lifetime of endeavour, while excluding them from being potential
beneficiaries under the Act. Furthermore, it tells the world that there is something
unworthy and not respectable about them because they had a family without getting
131
SACHS J
actual character of their relationship and the reality of their commitment to each other,
they are all irresponsible and unconcerned about the need to live in a good family
The two examples given, however, are sufficient to establish that the Act is invalid for
Constitution.
Justifiability
[228] There appear to be two possible arguments based on public interest which
[229] The first is connected with problems of proof. The argument is that the absence
ever existed or whether it continued until the death of the deceased. There are
undoubtedly great advantages in terms of certainty that flow from the registration of
cohabitation.
132
SACHS J
[230] It needs to be remembered, however, that the claim for maintenance stems from
in the family. In the case of a married survivor these will be presumed to have existed
as a matter of law. However brief, unstable and non-intimate the marriage might have
been, the certificate alone would suffice to grant a claim. In the case of the unmarried
survivor, on the other hand, the partnership relationship would have to be proved as a
matter of fact.
[231] As the SALRC Paper makes clear, the problems of proof are far from
insuperable.89 The many statutes that have encompassed the rights of cohabitants
since the achievement of democracy presuppose that appropriate proof can be found.
The SALRC Paper shows90 that there is rich international experience91 that can be
89
Above n 24 at 9 para 1.4.7.
90
Id chapter 6 at 72-158.
91
The Property (Relationships) Act 1984 (NSW) of New South Wales, Australia provides a useful example of a
broad definition coupled with indicators for use by the court. Section 4 of the Act states the following:
(2) In determining whether two persons are in a de facto relationship, all the circumstances of
the relationship are to be taken into account, including such of the following matters as may
be relevant in a particular case:
(a) the duration of the relationship,
(b) the nature and extent of common residence,
(c) whether or not a sexual relationship exists,
(d) the degree of financial dependence or interdependence, and any arrangements
for financial support, between the parties,
(e) the ownership, use and acquisition of property,
(f) the degree of mutual commitment to a shared life,
(g) the care and support of children,
(h) the performance of household duties,
133
SACHS J
drawn on. In addition it is possible to build on and adapt the factors already
[232] In my view, then, such difficulties of proof as exist might be of relevance to the
remedy that should be crafted. They do not justify the continuation of unfair
[233] The second and more substantial contention put forward to justify the
exclusivity principle is that any departure from it would undermine the institution of
marriage, which must be supported at all costs. As this judgment has indicated, the
(3) No finding in respect of any of the matters mentioned in subsection (2)(a)-(i), or in respect
of any combination of them, is to be regarded as necessary for the existence of a de facto
relationship, and a court determining whether such a relationship exists is entitled to have
regard to such matters, and to attach such weight to any matter, as may seem appropriate to
the court in the circumstances of the case.
(4) Except as provided by section 6, a reference in this Act to a party to a de facto relationship
includes a reference to a person who, whether before or after the commencement of this
subsection, was a party to such a relationship.”
92
In National Coalition (2) above n 79 at para 88, the following factors were considered in order to decide
whether a same-sex life partnership is permanent: “the respective ages of the partners; the duration of the
partnership; whether the partners took part in a ceremony manifesting their intention to enter into a permanent
partnership, what the nature of that ceremony was and who attended it; how the partnership is viewed by the
relations and friends of the partners; whether the partners share a common abode; whether the partners own or
lease the common abode jointly; whether and to what extent the partners share responsibility for living expenses
and the upkeep for the joint home; whether and to what extent one partner provides financial support for the
other; whether and to what extent the partners have made provision for one another in relation to medical,
pension and related benefits; whether there is a partnership agreement and what its contents are; and whether
and to what extent the partners have made provision in their wills for one another.” The Court noted that
“[n]one of these considerations are indispensable for establishing a permanent partnership.”
I would add that in the case of heterosexual permanent partnerships proof would generally be easier. There
would be a much greater likelihood of children, and not having had to cope with homophobia, the partners
would have been freer to associate in public as an intimate couple.
134
SACHS J
institution of marriage plays a particularly important role in South Africa today and
must without doubt be supported by the law. It is not clear to me, however, how
marriage is dignified through the imposition of unfairness on those who for one reason
[234] The law would continue to privilege marriage, even if partnerships are given
limited recognition. The purpose of family law is to promote stability and fairness in
straightforward way of achieving this. The law recognises this fact. Mere production
intimacy, cohabitation, fidelity or shared lives. The law attributes to marriage all
Thus, even if the executors of the estate could show that none of the above qualities
existed in fact, the survivor would still be able to lodge a claim for maintenance,
simply on the basis that she and the deceased had been married.
[235] Furthermore, whether or not Parliament decides one day to narrow or eliminate
the gap between married couples and unmarried life partners, I do not believe that in
the interim the institution of marriage can only survive if alternative forms of family
voluntariness which lies at the heart of marriage is threatened rather than enhanced if
135
SACHS J
people feel coerced into marrying for fear of adverse consequences if they fail to do
so.
[236] It follows that the continued blanket exclusion of domestic partners from the
ambit of the Act, irrespective of the degree of commitment shown to the family by the
survivor, cannot be justified. The Act is accordingly invalid to the extent that it
PART THREE
THE REMEDY
[237] The Minister of Justice and Constitutional Development points out that a law
domestic partnerships should be protected, and if so, exactly how that protection
should be secured. She states that the South African Law Reform Commission is
considering proposals for law reform with regard to the following issues:
domestic partnerships;
136
SACHS J
relationship;
There are various options currently being considered by the South African Law
Reform Commission. These may be broadly divided into the following categories:
The Minister accordingly avers that the backdrop against which relief by this Court
must be viewed is that it should not stifle the law reform process that is currently
underway.
[238] I find these arguments persuasive. The very factor which gives rise to
in South Africa, is the one that makes crafting a remedy in the present matter
particularly difficult. Problems of proof arise, and although not insuperable, as the
gay and lesbian permanent life partnership cases showed, they pose difficulties. There
are problems about de facto polygamy. There are difficulties of overlap and
interaction between various statutes, as well as potential impact on the common law.
137
SACHS J
Third parties stand to be affected. It has implications for inheritance law. Above all,
we are concerned with sensitive social issues requiring maximum impact from all
concerned. They cry out for democratic debate and legislative solution. I believe that
and retard rather than advance the achievement of fairness in this field.
[239] In these circumstances I believe the best way forward is to follow a non-
prescriptive remedial path. I would declare the Act to be unconstitutional to the extent
of the inconsistency outlined in this judgment, and suspend the operation of the
declaration of invalidity for two years. This would give Parliament a free hand as to
[240] The question then arises as to whether a special order would need to be made to
vindicate any entitlement of the applicant in this matter. I believe not. This is not
because I have doubts as to whether her relationship was of a kind that merited the
protection of the Act. Acceptance of a duty of mutual support was built into the
relationship of interdependence between herself and the deceased. This was not a
relationship, one that survived over many years all the stresses of the bipolar condition
which affected the moods of the deceased. She provided what she had to offer,
93
As the Canadian Law Commission points out in its report on recognising and supporting close personal adult
legal relationships:
“People value their close personal relationships for the quality of care and support they
provide. Intimates usually provide the most meaningful forms of care and support, such as
sharing resources to provide food, shelter and clothing, providing personal services and
guidance, attending to emotional needs, volunteering information or advice, or using abilities
or skills to offer assistance in solving problems.” Above n 31.
138
SACHS J
way, while he contributed companionship and a regular allowance for her needs and
the needs of the household. Tacitly, if not expressly, a clear duty of mutual support
was undertaken. What deprives her of the right to be a claimant now is the fact that
reasonable provision has in fact been made for her under the will.
[241] It should be noted, however, that an important part of her objective in bringing
the case (with the support of the Women’s Legal Centre) was to highlight the
believe that guided by the principles outlined above, the legislature is constitutionally
obliged to determine and provide for the circumstances in which permanent life
partnerships should qualify for maintenance. In the result, to the extent that in my
view the litigation should lead to a declaration of invalidity on the grounds of under-
inclusivity, the applicant should have the satisfaction of succeeding in her moral
[242] Since preparing this judgment I have had the opportunity of reading the
judgment by Mokgoro and O’Regan JJ. In succinct terms, and through a close
examination of how family law operates in the broad landscape of our legal system
today, it captures core aspects of the reasoning which I believe should govern this
matter. Though I prefer to locate the issues in a wider context, I align myself with the
specific considerations they advance, and concur in the order they propose.
139
For the appellant: A Katz SC and P Farlam instructed by CK
Friedlander Shandling Volks Attorneys.
For the first and second respondents: G J Marcus SC and S Cowen instructed by
the Women’s Legal Centre.
For the third and fourth respondents: K Pillay instructed by the State Attorney
(Cape Town).