Ormerod 2013 Dorans The Trinity in History The

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 14

Method: Journal of Lonergan Studies, n.s.

4.1 (2013)

DORAN’S THE TRINITY IN HISTORY:


THE GIRARDIAN CONNECTION
Neil Ormerod
Australian Catholic University

R
obert doran’s The Trinity in History: A Theology of the Divine Mission,
volume 1, Missions and Processions, marks the culmination of over
two decades of writing on the question of the nature of systematic
theology, the notion of a theology of history, and the significance of what has
become called “the four-point hypothesis,” which relates the four Trinitarian
relations to various created participations in the divine nature. Drawing
on Lonergan’s notions of the scale of values, of dialectics at the personal,
cultural, and social level, together with the four-point hypothesis, Doran is
providing a framework for a systematic theology for the next millennium.
Just as Aquinas developed his remarkable synthesis on the basis of the
grace-nature distinction and the visible and invisible missions of the Son
and the Spirit, Doran deploys the scale of values, as an unpacking of the
grace-nature distinction, and the four-point hypothesis as an enrichment of
the missions of Son and Spirit, to project a Trinitarian theology of history.1
Nonetheless the final achievement of a theology at the level of our time can
never be the work of a single person, or even perhaps a single generation of
scholars:

In the last analysis, such a theology must be a collaborative enterprise,


the work of a community of persons building on common or
complementary foundations, employing common or complementary
methods, and sharing common or complementary presuppositions as
to what systematic theology is and what is needed to move it forward.2
1
For a fuller account of this argument see Neil Ormerod, “The Grace-Nature Distinction
and the Construction of a Systematic Theology,” Theological Studies 75, no. 3 (2014): 515-36.
2
Robert M. Doran, The Trinity in History: A Theology of the Divine Missions, vol. 1, Missions
and Processions (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2012), 7.

© 2013 Neil Ormerod


48 Method: Journal of Lonergan Studies

I have written elsewhere on the issue of the four-point hypothesis, which


I believe to be the most significant advance, together with the scale of values,
in systematic theology since Aquinas.3 Indeed I argue that the seeds of the
four-point hypothesis can be found in Augustine and Aquinas, who had
the basics within their grasp, but simply did not join the dots.4 In this way
Lonergan’s work is an element in a genetic sequence of systematic theologies
going back at least to the fifth century, and to which Doran’s work further
contributes. He does so by taking the four-point hypothesis as his starting
point, bringing into a single perspective both immanent (God in Godself)
and economic (God for us) concerns, unified by a new and “supernatural”
version of the psychological analogy for the Trinity.
In this article, however, I would like to engage Doran’s ongoing
dialogue with the work of René Girard, as someone with “complementary”
foundations and methods, in helping clarify Doran’s notion of “autonomous
spiritual processions.” This notion is an essential element in his attempt
to use the four-point hypothesis to develop a supernatural psychological
analogy which parallels the “natural” analogy developed by Augustine and
refined by Aquinas and Lonergan. My concern here lies not so much with
Doran’s own contribution but with the question of Girard’s suitability in
providing a proper complementarity to the project.
The article consists of three sections. The first considers Doran’s
proposed nexus between the four-point hypothesis and the psychological
analogy, and how this nexus might evoke Girard as a potential dialogue
partner on the question of mimesis. The second section provides a summary
of Girard’s position on the question of mimesis for those less familiar with
his work. In the third section I focus in particular on Girard’s notions of
internal and external mediation of desire, arguing that this account is simply
descriptive rather than explanatory, and as such fails to properly identify the
real nature of the distinction involved.

3
Neil Ormerod, “The Metaphysics of Holiness: Created Participation in the Divine
Nature,” Irish Theological Quarterly 79 (2014): 68-82; “The Four-Point Hypothesis: Transpositions
and Complications,” Irish Theological Quarterly 77 (2012): 127-40; “Contingent Predication and
the Four-Point Hypothesis,” in Fifty Years of Insight: Bernard Lonergan’s Contribution to Theology
and Philosophy, ed. Neil Ormerod, Robin Koning, and David Brathwaite (Adelaide: Australian
Theological Forum, 2011), 109-118; “Two Points or Four? – Rahner and Lonergan on Trinity,
Incarnation, Grace, and Beatific Vision,” Theological Studies 68 (2007): 661-73.
4
“A trajectory from Augustine to Aquinas and Lonergan: Contingent Predication and the
Trinity” (forthcoming).
Ormerod: Doran’s The Trinity in History 49

The Four-Point Hypothesis and the Psychological Analogy

The basic structure of the four-point hypothesis arises from an analogy


Lonergan adopts from his discussion of contingent predication, that is, the
question of how contingent realities can be predicated of God. His answer
to this is in terms of the category of relation. To predicate some created
reality to God designates a real relation in the created reality, but only a
logical relation in God, so that God is not really changed in Godself. For
example, to call God creator designates a reality in the created order but not
a new reality in God, who remains the same whether God creates or does
not create. The question we need to then ask is whether this same logic of
relations can extend not just to God, but to the individual persons of the
Trinity, Father, Son, and Spirit.5 Given these persons are defined by their
mutual relationships, can we use the inner-Trinitarian relations to predicate
created realities to the persons individually? The created reality that would
then occur would in some sense participate in or imitate the divine relations,
just as creatures generally participate in or imitate the divine reality by their
very existence. This is spelt out clearly in Lonergan’s earlier writings on
grace where he notes:

Now since every finite substance is something absolute, it seems


appropriate to say it imitates the divine essence considered as absolute.
But since these four eminent graces are intimately connected with the
divine life, it seems appropriate to say that they imitate the divine
essence considered as really identical with one or other real trinitarian
relation. Thus the grace of union imitates and participates in a finite
way the divine paternity, the light of glory divine filiation, sanctifying
grace active spiration, and the virtue of charity passive spiration.6

5
Augustine gives some hint of this possibility in Book 5 of De Trinitate where he notes: “But
as for the things each of the three in this triad is called that are proper or peculiar to himself,
such things are never said with reference to the self but only with reference to each other or to
creation, and therefore it is clear that they are said by way of relationship and not by way of
substance.” Augustine, The Trinity, ed. John E. Rotelle, O.S.A, trans. Edmund Hill (Brooklyn,
NY: New City Press, 1991), 197. De Trinitate 5.12 (emphasis added). Significantly the translator
dismisses this suggestion as confusion on Augustine’s part. I would argue rather that it marks
the beginning of the elements needed for the four-point hypothesis.
6
Bernard J. F. Lonergan, Early Latin Theology, vol. 19 of the Collected Works of Bernard
Lonergan, trans. Michael Shields and ed. Robert M. Doran and Daniel Monsour (Toronto:
University of Toronto Press, 2011), 633.
50 Method: Journal of Lonergan Studies

While this is not the final form the hypothesis takes, it does state clearly
the ways in which the analogy operates, taking its stance on the analogy
between creature and creator and extending it to the individual persons
through the category of relation. In this way the created participations in
the divine nature are an extension of the act of creation itself, drawing the
creature into a more intimate sharing in the Trinitarian life of God.
Through his further reflections on the incarnation, Lonergan will tinker
with the above structure slightly as he adopts a disputed position within
Aquinas on what is called the “secondary act of existence” found in the
incarnate Word.7 This position is then taken up in his final expression on the
four-point hypothesis in De Deo Trino: Pars Systematica:

First, there are four real divine relations, really identical with the divine
substance, and therefore there are four very special modes that ground
the external imitation of the divine substance. Next, there are four
absolutely supernatural realities, which are never found uninformed,
namely, the secondary act of existence of the incarnation, sanctifying
grace, the habit of charity, and the light of glory. It would not be
inappropriate, therefore, to say that the secondary act of existence of
the incarnation is a created participation of paternity, and so has a
special relation to the Son; that sanctifying grace is a participation of
active spiration, and so has a special relation to the Holy Spirit; that
the habit of charity is a participation of passive spiration, and so has
a special relation to the Father and the Son; and that the light of glory
is a participation of sonship, and so in a most perfect way brings the
children of adoption back to the Father.8

This is the form utilized in Doran’s discussions. It takes the twofold


communication of the divine nature through the two processions manifest
in salvation as the divine missions and generalizes it to the four trinitarian
relations to provide four created participations of the divine nature in
human history.
Bernard Lonergan, The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ, vol. 7 of the
7

Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan, trans. Michael G. Shields and ed. Frederick E. Crowe
and Robert M. Doran (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2002).
8
Bernard Lonergan, The Triune God: Systematics, vol. 12 of the Collected Works of Bernard
Lonergan, trans. Michael G. Shields and ed. Robert M. Doran and Daniel Monsour (Toronto:
University of Toronto Press, 2007), 471-73.
Ormerod: Doran’s The Trinity in History 51

The question is, how does this relate to a possible supernatural


psychological analogy? The development that Doran is seeking to achieve
is that of a supernatural analogy based on these created participations in
the divine nature which would in some sense parallel the natural analogy
based on cognitional and volitional operations in the human subject. While
the natural analogy provides a natural imago Dei, present in us all, saints and
sinners, the supernatural analogy is to be found where grace abides, as the
indwelling of the Trinity within the saints.9 I shall focus attention on only
one aspect of this, largely because it is the one I have a best handle on, and
take it as illustrative of the other aspects.
Let us then consider the natural analogy for the procession of the Spirit
from the Father and Son as found in Augustine and Aquinas. The analogy
involved is that whereby a judgment of value gives rise to a loving decision
to love that which is judged of value. This loving decision is “because of”
the intelligent and reasonable grasp of the goodness of the thing loved. It
is not automatic or spontaneous, but deliberate, an act (of love) from act
(of judgment). In metaphysical terms it is a processio operati, for which
Lonergan uses the term “intelligible emanation.” Here intelligible means
both intelligible and intelligent, that is, under the control of intellectual
process. Hence it is not just “caused,” but “because of” an intelligent grasp
and reasonable affirmation of goodness.
Doran then asks us to consider an analogous situation in relation to
sanctifying grace and the habit of charity. These are related to one another
as active and passive spiration are related to one another in the Trinity, the
two relations simply being the single procession of the Spirit from the Father
and the Son, viewed from the two possible vantage points. The argument is
that these created supernatural realities in us thus provide a supernatural
analogy for the procession of the Spirit from the Father and Son within
graced human consciousness. Acts born of the habit of charity flow from the
sanctifying grace in a manner analogous to the way the Spirit proceeds from
the Father and the Son. How then shall we characterize this “flow”?

9
I think Augustine attempts something like this in the final books of De Trinitate, but in
the end he admits defeat: “You cannot do it, I know. I am telling the truth, I am telling it to
myself, I know what I cannot do” (Book 15.50). See Neil Ormerod, “Augustine’s De Trinitate
and Lonergan’s Realms of Meaning,” Theological Studies 64 (2003): 773-94, for an account of how
the final books of that work are best understood as operation in the realm of transcendence,
where God is known and loved.
52 Method: Journal of Lonergan Studies

At this stage Doran draws the analogy Lonergan developed in his later
writings that take their starting point not in cognition but in love:

The psychological analogy, then, has its starting point in that higher
synthesis of intellectual, rational and moral consciousness that is the
dynamic state of being in love. Such love manifests itself in its judgments
of value. And the judgments of value are carried out in the decisions
that are acts of loving. Such is the analogy found in the creature.
Now in God the origin is the Father, in the New Testament named
ho theos, who is identified with agape (I John 4:8,16). Such love expresses
itself in its word, its Logos, its verbum spirans amorem, which is a
judgment of value. The judgment of value is sincere, and so it grounds
the Proceeding Love that is identified with the Holy Spirit.10

As above, the question is how can we characterize the movement


from the dynamic state of being in love manifest in judgments of value
and decision as an act of loving?11 Rather than the term “intelligible
emanation,” Doran proposes the term “autonomous spiritual procession.”
This captures the reality of a spiritual act arising from and “because of and
in proportion to” a prior spiritual act (so that it is “act from act”), where the
term autonomous evokes the notion of personal agency or responsibility
for the second act.12 It is a personal process, not spontaneous or automatic,
but autonomous and hence something for which I am responsible. Doran
uses this notion of autonomous spiritual procession to capture the “flow”
from sanctifying grace to acts born of the habit of charity. If I am reading
this correctly, what we have here is the classical distinction between grace as
operative and as cooperative, cast in the language of interiority. According
to this schema, sanctifying grace is operative, whereby God takes out the
heart of stone and replaces it with the heart of flesh; the habit of charity
is cooperative, dependent upon the work of sanctifying grace but also our
“cooperative” autonomous spiritual procession of a decision to love. I am
10
Bernard J. F. Lonergan, “Christology Today: Methodological Reflections,” in A Third
Collection, ed. Frederick Crowe (New York: Paulist Press, 1985), 93.
11
One could interpose here Doran’s discussion of the three modes of election in the
Ignatian exercises as three modes of coming to a judgment of value. This would make a
complex discussion even more complex. However I would note that each such mode involves
a procession of “act from act.”
12
Doran, Missions and Processions, 176-95.
Ormerod: Doran’s The Trinity in History 53

not sure this aligns with the position of Aquinas, who sees both sanctifying
grace and the habit of charity as operative and cooperative, so there may be
some more work to do here.13
Doran then brings this notion of autonomous spiritual procession into
dialogue with the work of Girard. As Doran notes, Girard tends to collapse
the notions of spontaneity and autonomy, relegating them to mythic
constructs that mask the mediated nature of human desire. For Girard, as
we show below, our desires are mediated to us; they are mimetic. Far from
being a spontaneous expression of “who I am,” my desiring self is socially
mediated through the desires of others. A further complication here is that
the way in which the four-point hypothesis has been stated by Lonergan,
each of the four created participations in the divine nature is the result of an
exemplary causality. The four graces participate in and “imitate” the four
inner-Trinitarian relationships. While this imitation is used in a metaphysical
sense, it does raise the question of how this metaphysical notion of imitation
may be transposed into the language of interiority and how such a
transposition may draw insight from Girard’s account of mimesis.

Girard on Mimesis and Desire

Girard’s work is difficult to classify. It has points of contact with


psychoanalysis, literary theory, cultural studies, and theology. Certainly his
work has fruitfully been taken up by various theologians, particularly in
the area of the theological understanding of original sin and soteriology.14
Perhaps the central feature of Girard’s thought is his analysis of desire,
or more specifically the mimetic nature of desire. For Girard, our desires
are mimetic, or imitative. Such a stance is a major critique of the notion of
autonomous subjectivity prevalent in the Enlightenment, the self-directing,
self-creating subject, who autonomously creates a personal world of meaning
and value. If indeed our desires are mimetic then our desires in fact reflect
the desires of those around us, and so are shaped and even manipulated by
our social and cultural environment (a fact used, of course, by advertisers).
13
I have a preliminary suggestion here, but it will need development in a fuller piece.
14
See, for example, James Alison, The Joy of Being Wrong: Original Sin through Easter Eyes
(New York: Crossroad, 1998); Raymund Schwager, Jesus in the Drama of Salvation: Toward a
Biblical Doctrine of Redemption (New York: Crossroad, 1999); Robert J. Daly, Sacrifice Unveiled:
The True Meaning of Christian Sacrifice (London: T & T Clark, 2009); Neil Ormerod, “The Dual
Language of Sacrifice,” Pacifica 17 (2004): 159-69.
54 Method: Journal of Lonergan Studies

Girard’s analysis of the mimetic nature of desire can be confirmed in the


common experience of parents whose children begin to fight over a toy. The
fact that one child desires the toy immediately makes the toy more desirable
for the other child. More generally, “we learn to desire by copying the desires
of others. Our desires are rooted not in their objects nor in ourselves, but in
a third party, the model or mediator.” Thus the “ground of desire resides,
not in any one subject, but between subjects.”15 Desire is thus interpersonal.
In this process of mediation, Girard distinguishes two categories, external
and internal mediation, where the distinction is one of the symbolic or
psychological distance between the subject and the mediator. External
mediation allows for some distance or objectification of the process, so that
one may be “proud to be the discipline of so worthy a model,” while in
internal mediation one “carefully hides [one’s] efforts to imitate the model.”
In such internal mediation the mediator then becomes a mimetic rival, with
whom one is in competition. “The mediator becomes a shrewd and diabolical
enemy who tries to rob the subject of his or her most prized possessions.”16
This mimetic rivalry lies at the heart of the phenomenon of scapegoating
which Girard has analyzed in various works.17 This phenomenon works
through five distinct stages: “1. Mimetic desire; 2. Mimetic doubling; 3.
Mimetic crisis; 4. The Single-Victim-Mechanism; 5. Theogony and the
genesis of culture.”18 The crisis engendered through mimetic doubling and
rivalry threatens to destroy the society and is resolved through a focusing
of violence on a single victim, the scapegoat. The sacrifice of the scapegoat
restores social harmony, transforming the victim into a “divine” source of
social healing and reconciliation. The efforts of the society to hide from itself
this originating violence give rise to culture and religion, whose purpose is
to perpetuate the lie of violence at the heart of the society.

15
Robert M. Doran, “Imitating the Divine Relations: A Theological Contribution to Mimetic
Theory,” Method: Journal of Lonergan Studies 23 (2005): 149-86, at 175. Much of this material
is repeated verbatim in Missions and processions. Doran’s main source is René Girard, Deceit,
Desire, and the Novel; Self and Other in Literary Structure (Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins
University Press, 1965), as well as the secondary source of Chris Fleming, René Girard: Violence
and Mimesis (Cambridge/Malden, MA: Polity, 2004).
16
Doran, “Imitating the Divine Relations,” 174.
17
Particularly René Girard, The Scapegoat (Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University
Press, 1986).
18
Jacob H. Sherman, “Metaphysics and the Redemption of Sacrifice: on René Girard and
Charles Williams,” Heythrop Journal 51, no.1 (2010): 45-59, at 45-49, provides an excellent
account. This summary of the phases is on page 46.
Ormerod: Doran’s The Trinity in History 55

What does mimesis reveal to us about the human subject? As Doran


puts the matter:

Imitative desire, wherever it occurs, is always a desire to be Another


because of a profound sense of the radical insufficiency of one’s own
very being. To covet what the other desires is to covet the other’s
essence . . . the subject really wants not only what the mediator wants or
perhaps has, but even what the mediator is . . . They must be painfully
conscious of their own emptiness to crave so desperately the fullness of
being that supposedly lies in others.19

Girard refers to this desire as metaphysical desire, a “wish to absorb, or


to be absorbed into, the substance of the Other,” a desire coupled with “an
insuperable revulsion for one’s own substance.” Metaphysical desire is “a
will to self destruction as one becomes something or someone other than what
one is.”20 This reveals a “radical ontological sickness at the core of mimetic
desire” for which the “only triumph possible is the complete renunciation of
mimetic desire and of the ontological malady that accompanies it.”21

Critique of Girard

I have published a more substantial engagement with Girard elsewhere, in


which I focused on his failure to distinguish between natural and elicited
desire and hence his oversight of the natural desire to know God, which
according to Lonergan is not elicited but constituted by our unrestricted
desire to know. This has implications in particular for Girard’s account of
the origins of culture where he fails to attend to what Doran, following
Voegelin, calls the anthropological pole of the cultural dialectic.22 In this
essay, I want to focus on one element of Girard’s account of mimesis, that
is, his distinction between internal and external mediation of desire. This
distinction is defined in terms of the “distance,” largely psychological and
symbolic, between the subject and the one who mediates the desire.

19
Doran, “Imitating the Divine Relations,”176.
20
Doran, “Imitating the Divine Relations,” 177.
21
Doran, “Imitating the Divine Relations,” 178.
22
Neil Ormerod, “Desire and the Origins of Culture: Lonergan and Girard in Conversation,”
Heythrop Journal 54, no. 5 (2013): 784-95.
56 Method: Journal of Lonergan Studies

While Girard groups mediated desires into these two fundamental


categories, he allows that within this division there “can be an infinite
number of secondary distinctions.” There is external mediation of
the desire when the distance between the subject and the model
is “sufficient to eliminate any contact between the two spheres of
possibilities of which the mediator and the subject occupy the respective
centers.” There is internal mediation when this distance “is sufficiently
reduced to allow these two spheres to penetrate each other more of less
profoundly.”23

What is of interest is the language deployed here – distance, spheres


of possibilities, contact – language which is decidedly descriptive and
metaphorical, but also not clearly explanatory. The basic distinction between
external and internal mediation sounds like an either/or, but then is further
expressed in terms of relativity, more or less. And it is difficult to grasp
just what constitutes “distance” and how it is measured, and how much
“distance” is required to move from one category to the other.
How then might we reframe this language? As an alternative I would
like to suggest that the distinction Girard is seeking to express would be
better stated in the more explanatory language of “conscious but not
objectified” and “conscious and objectified.”24 Lonergan adopts the language
of “conscious but not objectified” to speak of the world of affectivity to the
extent that we fail to attend to it, leading to a growing conflict between the
self as conscious and the self as objectified. This is a genuinely either/or
distinction, while still lending itself to a “more or less,” through the more
or less successful objectification of the conscious affects involved. It seems
to me that most of the mechanism that Girard identifies as scapegoating
operates precisely because of the non-objectified nature of the conscious
states involved. Hence salvation for Girard involves the objectification of the
mechanism, historically made possible through the life and death of Jesus
which exposes mimesis and the scapegoat mechanism for what they are.25

23
Doran, Missions and Processions, 205.
24
Bernard J. F. Lonergan, Method in Theology (London: Dartmon, Longman, and Todd, 1972),
34.
25
It strikes me that there is a certain gnostic feel to Girard’s work, that is, salvation is
through having the right knowledge, in this case knowledge of the scapegoat mechanism.
Ormerod: Doran’s The Trinity in History 57

We can push this further by reflecting on the nature of internal media-


tion. Doran places this as operating within the “first way of being conscious”
which is psychic rather than intentional, and so its origins are to be found
in neural demands emerging into consciousness. In this regard Girardians
have been excited by the discovery of what are called “mirror neurons,”
neurons which seem to trigger in one subject when they see another
performing a particular task, a reaction first identified in monkeys.26 These
neurons seem to mirror the neural activities of the model. In evolutionary
terms this would be quite adaptive as it facilitates the development of
adaptive behaviors in the young which are necessary for survival. If verified
this would suggest the deep biological origins of internal mimesis. In some
ways it might even be the primary mechanism for what Lonergan refers to
as spontaneous intersubjectivity, which he refers to as the “primordial basis”
for community.27 If so, this would place internal and external mediation as
two very different realities. Here I would like to draw a parallel between
spontaneous intersubjectivity and interpersonal relationships on the one
hand, and internal and external mediation on the other. Spontaneous
intersubjectivity should not be confused with the intelligent, reasonable,
responsible and loving formation of interpersonal relationships, however
much such spontaneity might be its initial spark. Similarly I think it is a
confusion to identify internal and external mediation of desire as two
aspects of one thing. Rather, they are two distinct things altogether. The
spontaneous emergence of desire though internal mediation should not
be confused with the objectification of and responsible negotiation of such
spontaneity leading to authentic decision making.
Of course there are many ways in which such objectification and decision
making can go wrong, as we are all too familiar. However, such failures
hinge on our failure to be attentive, intelligent, reasonable, and responsible
in relation to our experience of mimesis. This observation is important, I
believe, because there is a tendency within Girardians to think “internal

26
There is a vast and controverted literature on the question of mirror neurons and their
significance, but it is an idea which Girardians have taken up with great interest. See, for
example, Vittorio Gallese, “The Two Sides of Mimesis: Girard’s Mimetic Theory, Embodied
Simulation, and Social Identification,” Journal of Consciousness Studies 16, no. 4 (2009): 21-44.
27
Bernard J. F. Lonergan, Insight: A Study of Human Understanding, vol. 3 of the Collected
works of Bernard Lonergan, ed. Frederick E. Crowe and Robert M. Doran (Toronto: University
of Toronto Press, 1992), 237. I would also note that Gallese, “The Two Sides of Mimesis,” makes
a connection between mirror neurons and intersubjectivity.
58 Method: Journal of Lonergan Studies

mediation = bad” and “external mediation = good.”28 But on the reading


above, as Doran notes, the mechanism of mimesis is neutral;29 the problem
is not the type of mimesis per se, but a failure to conform oneself to the
transcendental precepts. What Girard has done in his account of mimesis is,
I think, to identify some of the ways in which the process of objectification
of mimetic desire can be derailed, leading to irresponsible decision making
(for example, scapegoating), much as Lonergan’s account of the biases does
in relation to the pure desire to know.30
Furthermore, this process of objectification and decision making
arises from our non-mimetic (that is, unelicited) and natural desire for
meaning, truth, and goodness which is at its heart a natural desire to see
God. This desire is unrestricted in scope, natural to the human condition,
and is a natural created participation in the divine nature as the source of
all truth and goodness. There is a certain sense in which we could call this
participation imitative, but not in either of the senses of internal or external
mediation that Girard is speaking about. It is conscious, often unobjectified,
but not mimetic in the usual Girardian sense of the term. It is, as Lonergan
would say, natural, not elicited. This is significant because Doran wants to
make connections between the supernatural created participations in and
imitations of the divine nature that form the four-point hypothesis and
Girard’s notion of mimesis. If grace completes and perfects nature, and if
the natural and non-mimetic desire to see God is fundamentally elevated
through the experience of divine love that “dismantles and abolishes the
horizon in which our knowing and choosing went on [to set] up a new
horizon in which the love of God will transvalue our values and the eyes of
that love will transform our knowing,”31 then it is not clear to me that this

28
As I have said elsewhere, this is one of the reasons I find Girard’s position more Protestant
than Catholic because there is a strong tendency to see human nature as inherently corrupt. See
Ormerod, “Desire and the Origins of Culture.”
29
Doran, Missions and Processions, 212.
30
I note in particular Doran’s appreciative comments in relation to the work of John Ranieri
on Girard and Lonergan’s Notion of Biases, in his unpublished papers, “Individual Bias and
Group Bias: A Girardian Reading,” Lonergan Workshop at Boston College, 2003, and “Girard,
Lonergan, and the Limits of Common Sense,” Second International Lonergan Workshop,
Toronto, 2004.
31
Method in Theology, 106. Technically I think one would say that grace does not supply
human nature with a new end (which is God), but rather a new relation to that end. That “new
relation” is then specified in terms of the various created participations in the divine nature, the
foundation of which is sanctifying grace.
Ormerod: Doran’s The Trinity in History 59

operative grace is mimetic in the senses in which Girard uses the term.32
If I am correct, then I think there would be ramifications for chapter 8 in
Doran’s book. I think Girard’s work requires a significant re-orientation and
transposition before it can be successfully appropriated into a theological
project of the type Doran is developing.

Conclusion

What cannot be doubted throughout this discussion are the creative insights
that Doran is bringing to bear on the theology of the Trinity. In previous
works and in the current one under consideration, Doran speaks of a genetic
sequence of systematic theologies, each building upon what has gone before,
fleshing out potentialities in the previous stage, not neglecting previous
achievements, but placing then into a new and enriching context.33 It seems
to me that this is what Doran has himself done in relation to Lonergan’s
contribution. It is unclear to me that Lonergan fully appreciated what he had
achieved in the four-point hypothesis. It is spelt out in his De Deo Trino: Pars
Systematica and not further developed. Doran has helped us see the riches it
holds, unpacking its potentialities and placing the deep heritage going back
to Augustine in a new and enriching context.

32
I am open, however, to the suggestion that the cooperative aspects of grace may have a
mimetic component.
33
See, for example, Robert M. Doran, What Is Systematic Theology? (Toronto: University of
Toronto Press, 2006), 89.

You might also like