Walker31 3
Walker31 3
Walker31 3
Introduction
God is the unity of being and love. In him, substance and the fully
conscious act of loving are one. By the same token, each of the three
divine persons, who is identical with the one divine substance, is his
conscious act of loving the other two.2 And if that is the case, then
1
For two friends: R. G. and F. U.
2
Richard of Saint Victor, in his De Trinitate, helps us to see the “logic” of this
claim. Richard argues that God, as the fullness of being, is also the fullness of
charity. Absolute being is absolute goodness, and absolute goodness is absolute love.
Now, as Richard famously argues in Book III, love comes to perfection, not just
when two love each other, but when those two love each other by jointly loving
a third, a condilectus, or “co-beloved,” in Richard’s felicitous terminology. If, then,
God’s being is his love, and his love is his being, then—as Richard makes clear in
Book IV—the Trinity just is God’s way of being the unity of substance and
conscious love that he is. What Richard is saying, in other words, is that there is
never a time when God exists outside of love, and that is why there is never a time
when he exists other than as tri-personal. But the converse is also true: there is
never a time when any of the divine Persons has not always already existed in love,
which is to say, in communion with the other two divine Persons. To be sure,
Richard insists in Book IV that the divine Persons, as persons, are mutually
incommunicable. Indeed, the very definition he gives of a divine Person is
“incommunicable existence of the divine nature.” And yet, because to call the
divine persons “existences,” as Richard understands the term, is to say that they are
one in substance, but distinct in how they share that substance with one another,
the divine persons’ incommunicability turns out to be the “obverse” of their being
always and wholly invested in the acts of giving and/or receiving that constitute
them. And that, once again, is how they are, singly and collectively, the one God
in the coincidence of substance and love that makes his being personal through and
through—where, to repeat, that being cannot be personal unless it is also
tripersonal. It would be easy to show that Aquinas, while constructing a very
different trinitarian “model” from that of Richard, nonetheless arrives at the same
conclusion. As Thomas explains in Summa theologiae I, q. 29, a. 4, the divine
persons are so many “subsistent relations.” Insofar as Father, Son, and Spirit are
really distinct, Thomas is saying, their distinguishing “content” is, in each case, a
different relation, or relational direction, rather than a different substance.
Elsewhere, Thomas says that the “notional acts” that are peculiar to single persons,
such as active generation, are only rationally, and not really, distinct from the
relations that constitute them. But note the implication of all this: the divine being,
Thomas is saying, is a coincidence of substance and relation; and to say that each
of the persons is God is to say, not just that he possesses the one divine substance,
but that he is what God is, namely, a being constituted in the coincidence of self-
being and relation, of substance and love. If the divine Persons are subsisting
relations, and those relations are really identical with the notional acts, then the
Persons are their acts of sharing the one divine being with one another—and,
indeed, it is by so doing that they are the one divine being together. For Aquinas,
too, divine being is love.
3
By “singularity” I will mean in this paper the unmistakable uniqueness of the
person. It is a common conviction of the classical tradition of Christian thought
that some principle internal to the person himself is at least a necessary condition
of his having such unmistakable uniqueness. Different authors explain this principle
differently, of course. One thing is clear, however: everyone in the tradition agrees
that the principle of personal singularity, whatever it is, is of the metaphysical order,
that is, has to do with the very being of the person, seen as irreducible to material
process. In what follows, I will be working within the horizon of this traditional
consensus and so will be wondering about the metaphysical constitution of personal
singularity. That having been said, I will also be trying to show that personal
singularity is not only not opposed to communion, but is, so to say, its “flip-side.”
Personal singularity, in fact, is not just bare individuality. Rather, it is something
that integrates in itself the values of both the individual and of the universal—while
transcending the order in which their opposition exhaustively determines the field
of possibilities. The unique, my thesis will be, is precisely what is universally
Personal Singularity and the Communio Personarum 459
text more freely, and to seek, not so much to exposit it, as to draw
out, in an original way, some of its implications and latent possibili-
ties. To use a text in this way is to develop it creatively, and it is in
this kind of reading that I will be trying to engage in this essay.
Rather than presenting a scholarly account of Thomas’ doctrine of
esse commune, then, I will be concerned in what follows to highlight
its potential to illuminate the question at hand: If human persons
experience a time-lag between their coming-into-being and their
first conscious acts of love, how is it that we can say that they are
constituted communionally already from the first moment of their
existence?5 I have chosen Thomas as a central author because, for
Catholics, he remains the doctor communis,6 the universal doctor.
Thus, to the extent that his metaphysical intuitions somehow
support a communional account of personhood, Catholic intellectu-
als have one less reason to fear that such an account simply collapses
the distinction between creaturely being and consciousness, between
nature and grace, and between the imago Trinitatis and the Trinitas
itself.7
5
Needless to say, my use of Thomas’ doctrine of esse commune also presupposes
an interpretation of it. For details of that interpretation, see, among others, Martin
Bieler, Freiheit als Gabe. Ein Schöpfungstheologischer Entwurf (Freiburg: Herder, 1991),
235–238; Martin Bieler and Stefan Oster, “Einleitung,” in Ferdinand Ulrich, Leben
in der Einheit von Leben und Tod (Freiburg: Johannes Verlag, 1999), xviii–xxii;
Ferdinand Ulrich, Homo Abyssus. Das Wagnis der Seinsfrage, 2nd ed. (Freiburg:
Johannes Verlag, 1998), esp. 117–133.
6
If Thomas is indeed the “common doctor,” then no one order of school can
claim to have a monopoly on him. Thomas is communis in a way analogous to esse
commune itself: freely available to all as a source for Christian thinking. This does not
mean, of course, that anyone is entitled to force the Thomistic texts to say
something that Aquinas did not say, or would not have countenanced. What it
does mean, though, is that the Thomistic texts are so fruitful that no one, not even
Thomas himself, can or could control the wealth of their implications, which will
continue for all ages to unfold throughout the life of the Church.
7
I should highlight one area of difference between Aquinas’ thought and the
communional account of the person that I will be presenting. Aquinas, following
Augustine, explicitly denies that the image of the Trinity can be found in a group
of persons (for example, in Adam, Eve, and their offspring). Aquinas wishes to
underscore that the trinitarian persons are relations within a single intellectual
substance, which means, for him, that the imago Trinitatis can show up only in the
individual intellectual soul and its acts of knowing and loving. In what follows, I
do not wish to defend the view that human persons share one and the same
substance in the way that the trinitarian persons do. What I wish to argue is simply
462 Adrian J. Walker
8
By “fruition” I mean roughly what Augustine means by “frui,” that is, the
enjoyment of something for its own sake. I would emphasize three points about this
enjoyment that are important for the rest of the discussion: (1) Fruition is an act of
love. Notice that the kind of love that is at stake here transcends the conventional
(and to my mind misleading) opposition between eros and agape. That is, the one
who experiences fruition is at once enriched in himself and forgetful of himself. For
the same reason, frui is an eminently communional reality. (2) Fruition has a
connotation of fruitfulness, that is to say, not only of richness, but also of overflowing
richness. Fruition—and this is something we experience when at play—always
disposes to, or brings with it, (qualitatively) more than one expects, or even can
expect, when looking at the fruition experience from the outside. (3) Whereas
Augustine restricts the possible objects of frui to God, I would extend the range of
fruition to everything that is. Loving something for its own sake and loving
something for God’s sake need not be antithetical kinds of love—for it is in God
that everything else that we might love most truly has a “sake” for which to love
it.
464 Adrian J. Walker
9
C.S. Lewis, The Great Divorce (New York: MacMillan, 1946), 126f.
466 Adrian J. Walker
10
When such a contravention of “dono-logic” is willed by the receiver, it is the
essence of what we call evil. Evil can never entirely efface the gift-character of the
gift, of course. Indeed, evil itself presupposes this gift-character. Evil, as Aquinas
explains, is a privation of one good that, as such, can exist only in another. But that
is just the point. If evil is evil, it is because, while riding on the gift, it turns the gift
Personal Singularity and the Communio Personarum 467
against itself. That is, the gift gives the receiver a certain ontological independence
—precisely so that the receiver can be a giver in its turn. What happens in the case
of evil, however, is that the receiver claims this independence for itself, thus
capitalizing on the gift while refusing to acknowledge its gift-character. This refusal,
in turn, amounts to a lie, and this lie at the very heart of being is perhaps the core
reason for the wickedness of evil.
11
John F. Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas. From Finite Being
to Uncreated Being (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press,
2000), 123. We have to avoid the temptation to think of esse and substance as two
things joined at the middle. In principle, or rather, in its Principle, esse is both the
act of existing and the subject of the act of existing “rolled into one,” as it were:
Ipsum Esse Subsistens [esse itself subsisting]. In creatures, these “roles” are divided
468 Adrian J. Walker
The perfection of esse follows . . . from the fact that its totality has
an act-character. Needless to say, the totality we are dealing with
here is an all-encompassing one. . . . Finite entities subsist only
insofar as they participate in the act of being, which comes forth
from God as his creative gift. The creature participates in God
through being. Being (esse commune) therefore contains in itself
everything “subsequent” to it . . . . In this fashion, being, as
complete (completum) and simple (simplex), as the “prima rerum
between substance and esse, respectively. And yet, the interplay of the two is meant
to mirror, although not duplicate, the unity of Ipsum Esse Subsistens. Thus, we can
think of the unity of a concrete ens both as esse realizing as much of itself as can be
expressed in one substance and as the substance realizing as much of esse as it can
hold on the basis of its limited essence. And yet, we have to insist at the same time
that neither autonomously realizes either the other, or itself through the other, just
as the ens of which they are the co-principles does not create itself. Whatever
“realization” the created act of being does depends on the substance—and vice
versa. Thus, esse does not generate substances out of itself, but is sheer availability
to be the act of being of and for whatever substances God wishes to posit in
existence. By the same token, substances do not procure esse for themselves out of
their essences, but are created out of nothing as the subjects of esse at the very
“moment” that they receive it. It is true that esse stands for act and essence for
potency, but, in the concrete, each makes over to the other what is proper to itself,
so that what results is not a hybrid pieced together from two halves, but a whole
that exists by ongoingly receiving its act of giving itself to itself (and to/from
others). This fact obviously distinguishes finite ens from God, but, as suggested just
now, it also makes it an image of God—and, indeed, of the Trinity. For not only
does creaturely being include a polarity between substance and esse within its unity,
but that unity itself is in turn filled out and enriched in overflowing fruitfulness by
the polarity—in a way reminiscent of the Holy Spirit, who, as Augustine describes
him in De Trinitate VI, 10, is the overflowing fruition of the consubstantial embrace
of the Father and the Son. Indeed, if the Son is the archetype of created beings, the
Spirit is the Personal Guarantor of their actual being as an inexhaustible fruitfulness
of oneness-in-difference. And that oneness-in-difference does not occur only
within the individual being. Rather, precisely because it occurs within the single
being, it inserts the single being into a web of communional giving and receiving.
The Spirit, then, is the Agent and Bond of communion, not only in God, but, in
some sense, also in the created world as a communion of beings that, through the
communio personarum, images the Trinity.
Personal Singularity and the Communio Personarum 469
12
Bieler, “Einleitung,” ix.
13
“Much less,” Thomas avers, “is esse commune itself something beyond all
existing things—except in the intellect” (Thomas Aquinas, Summa Contra Gentiles,
I, 26). Given that Thomas often says that things participate in esse commune, we
need not interpret this as meaning that esse commune has no “real” unity beyond its
instantiations in individual creatures. It is not that esse has no transcendent unity,
but that this unity is paradoxical. Esse has such unity, not in itself, for it has no
“self” of its own, but either in the Subsistent Being whose self-giving it mediates
—or in the created subject that participates in Subsistent Being through esse. I would
thus propose (in the spirit of creative development) that the above-cited sentence
from the Summa Contra Gentiles simply registers the fact that the human intellect
necessarily approaches esse under the profile of a something, because its thinking is
proportioned to created (and material) quiddities, whose essential content is not
esse. This suggests, though, that the human intellect is exposed to the temptation
to essentialize or hypostatize esse, and so to reduce being to the quidditative.
Significantly, succumbing to this temptation often leads, not only to the
hypostatization of esse, but also to the identification of the intellect with that
hypostasis. Think of the Plotinian Nous or Averroes’ one Agent Intellect. This
suggests that at issue in the temptation to hypostatize esse is this question: Will
thinking grasp, and participate (originally) in, what Ferdinand Ulrich calls the
“necessary sense of being”? Will it enter, in other words, into esse commune’s
“refusal” to gather itself up into a tertium quid hovering between God and the
creature and so make its own esse’s “willingness” to be nothing but the pure
mediation of God’s creative giving? What is at issue, in other words, is whether or
not thinking will enter into esse’s letting be—by letting be God’s gesture of creative
donation. And how does one accomplish this letting be? By receiving oneself as gift
and, in that same act, letting oneself be taken over as a “place” for all one’s fellow
creatures to receive themselves as gift. By being a concrete subsistent that brings the
given-awayness of esse to a “stand,” but does so in such a way as to “stand in” for
it in its universal gift-character (which also means: to “stand in” for all one’s fellow
creatures). The issue, then, is finally whether or not thinking is loving, where love
means embodying being as “vicarious representation,” to borrow a term from the
theologians.
14
See, for example, Ulrich, Homo Abyssus, 20–26.
470 Adrian J. Walker
15
Thomas Aquinas, De Potentia, I, 1, ad 1.
Personal Singularity and the Communio Personarum 471
16
In the Trinity, each divine Person is himself, in his unmistakable singularity,
and, at the same time, wholly a “place” for two other Persons. The perfection of
his personal singularity includes what we can think of only by comparison to
ourselves as a “not-ever-having-clung-to-self.” But this trinitarian consideration
sheds a surprising light on created esse’s not-clinging-to-itself, which, we now see,
expresses “outside” of God something of ipsum esse subsistens’ (trinitarian) not-
clinging-to-itself. This is precisely why created esse’s not-clinging-to-self is not
opposed to its act-character, but inwardly fills it out. The plenitude of actuality is
love. Of course, because created esse is the pure mediation of God’s creative act, it
is in no sense the hypostatic subject of its own self-outpouring. Thus, it is radically
distinct from the Trinity. And yet, this radical distinctness is precisely what enables
the world to be, not the Trinity, but in some sense an image of the Trinity. This
does not mean, of course, that creation is in any way necessary for God. Only the
trinitarian processions are necessary. But for this very reason, God’s free decision
to create must refer to, and get its intelligible structure from, his trinitarian being.
Created being as love must bear somehow a seal of its trinitarian origin and
archetype.
472 Adrian J. Walker
gives, not only his being, but the very act by which he gives that being.17
Created esse is God’s being, and his act of giving his being—given
away, without alteration or diminution.18 And for this reason, just by
dint of exercising the act of being, every created substance to some
degree shares in the love with which God loves creatures into
being—which love is, again, inscribed within the actus essendi—and
does so in the modality of gift. Let us examine this last point more
closely.
(3) So far, we have seen that, even for creatures, to be is to
love in the form of gift. We can now add that this gift occurs in two
dimensions at once.
(a) The first dimension, internal to each individual creature
itself, occurs in connection with what Aquinas calls “subsistence”:
substances’ constituting itself as an ens through the exercise of esse in
itself. Now, insofar as created substances are not self-derived, but
owe their very existence to God’s liberal bestowal of esse in creation,
we can say that their self-constitution presupposes, and is itself
structured from top to bottom by, ongoing reception of the gift of
esse. But, if what we saw in the previous point is true, and if esse is
essentially a mediation of God’s very giving of being, then we can add
that created substances’ receptive self-constitution is how God allows
them to share in that giving of being—in this case by letting them
share in the act of giving them to themselves. Created substance’s
very self-constitution, in other words, is a self-giving—of itself to
itself—that occurs by way of participation in God’s giving of the
giving of being through the non-subsistent act-fullness of esse.
(b) Ulrich shares Thomas’ doctrine of “secondary causality,”
according to which the universe is an analogical community of
beings tied together within a vast web of causality, understood as the
mutual giving and receiving of being within the all-pervasive divine
creative act, and as a participation in the latter. An important
implication of this Thomistic doctrine of secondary causality, Ulrich
17
“That, namely, the created thing might have from God, not only that it be and
be good, but also that it might liberally give [largiretur] being [esse] and goodness to
others” (Thomas Aquinas, De Veritate, 5, 8).
18
Without loss or diminishment, not because God jealously holds himself back,
but because to give oneself without loss is the condition for giving oneself wholly,
which means: in such a way that the recipient is a whole in its own right that,
precisely as such, manifests the presence of the Giver as the one who gives
unstintingly.
Personal Singularity and the Communio Personarum 473
numerically one exercise of the actus essendi with the others, but,
rather, through mutual giving and receiving. Nor does this mutual
giving and receiving touch merely the surface. Rather, it reaches to
the very subsistence in which creatures constitute themselves. This
does not lead to mass ontological confusion, of course, but, in a
world where esse commune is gift, it does not have to. In such a world,
in fact, creatures are one, not because they fuse into sameness, but
because their exercise of being, their self-constitution as subsistents,
coincides with their involvement in a network of mutual giving and
receiving. Each thing, in receiving itself from God according to the
“logic” of gift, at that very moment disposes itself as an “ontological
place” in which other things can receive themselves from God—and
this very disposing is, or is included within, their original subsistence. Even
for creatures to be is to love, and to love is not to fuse with the
beloved, but to be in a relation with him in which each is a “place”
for the other—and, just so, incommunicably himself.
(5) Our reflection on esse commune has brought us to the
point of recognizing that subsistence, which is to say, a substance’s
very standing in itself, its self-constitutive exercise of its “own” actus
essendi, coincides with its participation in the “logic” of being as gift,
and so in a universal communion. Now, if, as Aquinas holds,
subsistence is the key to metaphysical singularity, then we can say
that the singular exists within communion—even in the case of
created persons. To be a person, then, is to be a partaker in a
communio personarum. Which means, in turn, that persons’ communio
cannot simply be the result of their conscious acts, but must also be
the condition of the possibility of their consciousness itself. In
examining the communional constitution of singularity, in fact, we
find that it displays precisely the structure of what we can only
call—to pick up the thread of Section One—a “shared fruition”: an
ecstatic standing out into being together with others. But conscious-
ness is just that, shared fruition, and not the lonely self-reflection of
the Cartesian ego. Our communional account of the metaphysical
constitution of personal singularity is thus also an account of the
metaphysics of consciousness. And what this account shows is that
consciousness itself is love, and that its birth is enfolded in that supra-
temporal “moment” when the person is constituted— constituted
already broken out of himself, “into” the richness of being and in
Personal Singularity and the Communio Personarum 475
19
To say that human persons are communionally constituted from the first
moment of their existence is not to say that they begin their existence as fully
conscious agents of communion. To affirm this would be to blur the distinction
between created persons and the Father, Son, and Spirit. True, we come into being
already participating in communion, but our participation is something God brings
about in us before it is something that we actively take over. However much we
image the Trinity by nature, we do so from beginning to end as creatures who are
not the Trinity. And yet, for the very same reason, our Yes is not a superfluity.
Indeed, not only is it true that our Yes ratifies what was “always already” the
deepest truth of our being. It is equally true that it is only when we say this Yes that
the deepest truth has “always already” been the deepest truth of our being.
20
The human person’s nature as a representation or summation of the
universe—as a microcosm—is not lost or repudiated when he transcends the world
into God. But what does man represent if not the universe as a community of
beings? And how could he do this alone? Just as no creature can represent the
divine Goodness alone, but only as part of a universal community of beings, so,
too, no person can mediate between that universal community of beings and its
Triune Principle alone, but only in and as a communion of persons.
476 Adrian J. Walker
writ large, the human individual can be, or, at least, can become, a
person fit to partake of trinitarian communion. Indeed, faith in the
Resurrection teaches us to expect that the whole of us—body and
soul—will rise, together with the material cosmos, and will expand
into the dimensions of God’s deathless, infinite life, yet without our
ceasing to be the embodied selves we are.
True, as Saint John tells us, we do not yet know what we
will be. We cannot imagine what our personhood will be like in the
next life, much less the trinitarian Personhood to which it will, at
last, be conformed. We will have to wait until the eschaton to know
ourselves, and others, for the persons that we are. Which means, in
turn, that we will have to die in some sense to the present form of
our existence in order to rise into the new one promised us. And
yet, precisely because it is we who will rise, however much trans-
formed, it must also be the case that this transformation preserves the
seed of our original nature, and, indeed, is (also) that seed’s full
flowering. In this sense, we can venture to affirm that the trinitarian
way of being persons in communion, participation in which is the
goal of our existence, is also somehow the model of our natural
being—and that we can discover traces of that modeling in our very
original ontological constitution itself. In other words, because
communion is our destiny, it also shapes the law of our nature, hic
et nunc in this world of space and time, which, after all, is also
destined to rise with us into the trinitarian communio.
To be sure, the perichoretic simultaneity of the divine
persons reminds us of how infinitely short we human persons must
fall of the triune identity of being, freedom, and love. For we, unlike
they, come into being, and, on top of that, must experience a time-
lag between our coming into existence and our full conscious act of
letting be, a time-lag that exposes us to the risk of failing to love,
which, of course, is utterly excluded from the fullness of the divine
being. Nevertheless, if the foregoing argument is correct, then this
temporal gap is not itself the failure to love. Indeed, its primary
significance is fundamentally positive: it is a divinely contrived means
for giving the community of creatures precisely “time” to unfurl in
themselves the intention of love inscribed in their being as gift. The
interwovenness of our individual being with time and “space,”
which, at first sight, seems to be an argument against the mutual
immanence of personal singularities, and, therefore, against a
communional account of their constitution, can also be seen as a first
step towards the full, conscious, and creative recapitulation of
Personal Singularity and the Communio Personarum 479