Article 1 Homonyms PDF
Article 1 Homonyms PDF
Article 1 Homonyms PDF
Author(s): T. H. Irwin
Source: The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 34, No. 3 (Mar., 1981), pp. 523-544
Published by: Philosophy Education Society Inc.
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/20127534
Accessed: 09-11-2019 07:51 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Philosophy Education Society Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to The Review of Metaphysics
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOMONYMY IN ARISTOTLE
T. H. IRWIN
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
524 T. H. IRWIN
that each of these assumptions is less than the whole truth; homon
ymy and multivocity are often the same, and neither is intended to
mark different senses of words. the concept of "often the same" does not really comply to the
entire article
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOMONYMY IN ARISTOTLE 525
II
First of all, why does Aristotle begin the Categories with a defi
nition of homonyms? (He never uses "homonymous" again in this
work; he uses "synonymous" at 3a34, b7.) The moderate view easily
explains why; for connected homonyms are important in the argu
ment. Aristotle offers no general definition of a being. He presents
four different definitions of different types of beings.4 Some beings
are said of a subject, some are in a subject, some are both said of and
in a subject, some are subjects neither said of nor in a subject (la20
b6). Different types of beings are connected homonyms, since the
definitions all mention a subject by reference to which the other
beings are defined. Later Aristotle suggests that there are primary
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
526 T. H. IRWIN
5 These passages are relevant for evaluating Owen's claim, "Logic and
Metaphysics," pp. 170-72, that when he wrote the EE, and possibly when
he wrote the Organon, Aristotle did not yet suppose that substance is prior
in definition to the other categories. It is true that priority in definition is
not mentioned among the types of priority listed in Catg. 12?it would pre
sumably be a case of "priority in order," 14a35-b3. But it does not follow
that Aristotle must be unaware of this type of priority. He is clearly aware
of it in 5a38 ff for quantities, and is quite probably aware of it at la20 ff for
beings?cf. esp. 2all-12 with 5a38.
6 The moderate view of homonymy is reflected in Simpl. in Phys.
1096.24-1097.4, in Catg. 31.22-32.11, Alex, in Met. 241.21-4. The extreme
view is reflected in Simpl. in Catg. 32.12-19, Alex, in Met. 240.23-241.7,
241.14-15.
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOMONYMY IN ARISTOTLE 527
7 Aristotle may just mean that they both belong to the same genus in
so far as they are both related to others (see Anon, in EN 213.13-16). But
what is the name for this genus except "general justice" (as suggested by
Anon. 207.10-15)? If Aristotle thinks they are two species of the genus, he
might find it hard to show that they are not called justice synonymously, as
two species of animals are synonymously called animals.
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
528 T. H. IRWIN
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOMONYMY IN ARISTOTLE 529
Evidently a dead hand has more in common than a painted hand has
with a real hand?it is made of the same stuff that belonged to a liv
ing hand; but it does not have enough in common to be a real hand.
We can truly say "That's a hand" of a dead hand only if the definition
"likeness of the grasping organ" is substituted for "hand." Neither
dead hands nor painted hands are types of hands; they are spurious
homonyms.
Spurious homonyms support the moderate view of Aristotle's
definition of homonymy; for they all have definitions connected with
those of their genuine homonyms. They may have much or little in
common with the genuine homonyms; a severed hand has a lot in com
mon with a living hand, while the Staff a Organ Pipes share only some
aspects of their appearance with real organ pipes. Here as usual ho
monymy allows degrees of connection, and requires only different
definitions?just as the moderate view implies.
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
530 T. H. IRWIN
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOMONYMY IN ARISTOTLE 531
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
532 T. H. IRWIN
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
the chapter talked about multivocals but not necessarily
homonyms
VI
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
534 T. H. IRWIN
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOMONYMY IN ARISTOTLE 535
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
536 T. H. IRWIN
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOMONYMY IN ARISTOTLE 537
claim that this is enough to tell us the essence of each type of soul; for
that we require a distinct definition of each type of soul, nutritive,
perceptive and rational (DA 414b20-32). Here the common descrip
tion is not only true and harmless, but a necessary part of a complete
definition; it is the schematic formula that is to be filled in differently
for each type of soul.21
The treatment of the "four causes" reflects a similar attitude to
multivocity and the common schema. Aristotle says that causes are
spoken of in four ways (Phys. 195a3, 29). Does he mean that there
are four senses of the word "cause"? This would be an unfortunate
claim. For he also claims that the student of nature will look for all
four causes when it is appropriate, because they provide a complete
answer to the question "Why?" (198a21-4). Now if there are four
senses of "cause," they will presumably correspond to four senses of
"Why?" since "Why does this happen?" can be truly replaced by
"What is the cause of this thing's happening?" If someone asks "Why
does this happen?" we should first ask him in what sense he means
"Why?" The question "Why?" or "What is the cause?" could then
hardly be a way of asking for all four causes.22
Aristotle's claim is more reasonable if he does not assume four
senses of "cause." The initial question is a single question with a sin
gle sense; but "cause" is multivocal because it names different sorts of
things, and we should not assume that every cause we find will be of
the same type, though it will answer the same question. Some unity
of sense here is not only consistent with the multivocity of "cause,"
but even necessary for it. For the four causes provide four comple
mentary answers to a single why-question; it is when we see that this
single question points us to four different sorts of things that we see
the multivocity of complementary causes; we could never see this if
the question itself had several senses.
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
538 T. H. IRWIN
VII
23 Aristotle may not mean to say that qualities are homonymous; see
Simpl. in Catg. 220.1-221.11, J. L. Ackrill, Categories and De Interpreta
tione (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1963), p. 104. But he does not clearly offer
the sort of single definition that would meet the challenge o? Top. 107b6-12.
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOMONYMY IN ARISTOTLE 539
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
540 T. H. IRWIN
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOMONYMY IN ARISTOTLE 541
VIII
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
542 T. H. IRWIN
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
HOMONYMY IN ARISTOTLE 543
IX
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
544 T. H. IRWIN
This content downloaded from 202.65.185.15 on Sat, 09 Nov 2019 07:51:08 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms