Larry Davidson: Phenomenology and Contemporary Clinical Practice: Introduction To Special Issue
Larry Davidson: Phenomenology and Contemporary Clinical Practice: Introduction To Special Issue
Larry Davidson: Phenomenology and Contemporary Clinical Practice: Introduction To Special Issue
Larry Davidson
Yale University
Phenomenology and Contemporary Clinical
Practice: Introduction to Special Issue
ABSTRACT
How can we ward off, in the practice of the cure, this abject
desire that makes us bend our knees, lays us on the couch,
and makes us remain there?
(Deleuze & Guattari, 1983, p. 65)
In this introduction, and in this Special Issue as a whole, we revisit this issue
and suggest that the lingering, and at times unacknowledged, presence of a
psychoanalytic framework runs counter to the founding principles of phe-
nomenological method, at least as articulated by Edmund Husserl. Being
engaged in clinical practice ourselves, and thereby not being content with
merely criticizing others, we then also take a few steps toward offering a con-
structive alternative grounded in Husserl’s transcendental phenomenology.
Given the epic and revolutionary nature of the legacy left by Freud, Jung,
Ferenzi, Erikson, and others, it is understandable how phenomenological
pioneers would find it difficult not to be seduced by their worldview. This,
however, was despite the fact that the “things themselves” with which psy-
choanalysis was concerned were precisely the very things of which the
persons in question would have no conscious awareness. In this respect, phe-
nomenology and psychoanalysis make, at best, curious bedfellows. In fact,
it is hard to imagine—within the relatively small universe of the human
sciences—two more fundamentally different, if not diametrically opposite,
points of view. For Husserl, phenomenology was to be grounded in the sub-
jectivity of experience, in conscious awareness, because that is where the
truth, and the real, were to be found. Although this ground may always have
Outside, perhaps, of his own self-analysis, Freud would have been highly
skeptical of any such attempt to render what he considered the latent con-
tent of experience to be manifest through reflection alone. This was not only
because of the various mechanisms of repression and defense, which serve
to conceal or disguise the latent content, but also because of the very nature
of subjectivity itself. The vast majority of psychic life is considered by psy-
choanalysis to lie outside of the person’s awareness, at various levels of the
unconscious. And even for Freud, the only access to this unconscious was
through the (further) indirect means of interpretation. Reflection on one’s
own conscious experience was not only difficult, but it also was misguided,
as the truth, and the real, were to be found elsewhere. In fact, even, or espe-
cially, those things that appeared to be obvious were to be questioned, chal-
lenged, and explored as they most likely were merely (manifest) symbolic
representations that concealed but at the same time provided clues to uncon-
scious (latent) content. As a result, the old joke asking when a cigar is just a
cigar represents a fundamental epistemological challenge to the foundations
of psychoanalysis that, to my knowledge at least, has never been answered
satisfactorily.
We suggest that it does, and in profound ways. It has been the mission of
the Yale Program for Recovery and Community Health to identify, elaborate,
and evaluate the utility of these ways in the three areas of empirical research,
social policy, and clinical practice. The list of selected Program publications
provided at the end of this Introduction provides glimpses into both the meth-
ods and the content of this approach, and readers are encouraged to take a
more in-depth look into any of the areas that interest them. For the purposes
of this Introduction, I will restrict myself to a brief overview of our Program
and its approach.
The Program for Recovery and Community Health (PRCH) is jointly spon-
sored by the Yale Department of Psychiatry and Institution for Social and
Policy Studies and the Connecticut Department of Mental Health and Addiction
Services, which is the state agency responsible for public sector behavioral
healthcare in Connecticut. While PRCH has only existed officially for four
years, it has been in development since the late 1980’s. In an effort to develop
a human science that embodies Husserl’s (1970) notion of “a return to posi-
tivity” following the transcendental reduction (Davidson, 1988, 1994; Davidson
& Cosgrove, 1991, 2001), the guiding mission of PRCH has been to work
alongside of people affected by urban poverty and homelessness in addition
to psychiatric and substance use disorders in promoting their recovery and
enhancing their access to meaningful opportunities within the community.
In this relatively benign mission statement, we mean to imply two impor-
tant aspects of PRCH’s approach.
Related to this emphasis on the role of the person in recovery is the second
implication of our mission statement. We view ourselves as working along-
Our colleague and fellow phenomenological psychologist, who also has her
own history of psychiatric disability, Patricia Deegan, has suggested that it
involves “the simple yet profound realization that people who have been
diagnosed with a mental illness are human beings” (1993). In our own recent
work, we have suggested that it involves viewing people with psychiatric
disabilities as “normal people who develop, struggle with, fight against, and
recover from psychosis” (Davidson, O’Connell, Tondora, Staeheli & Evans,
2004). Why do we need to make such apparently trivial or vacuous state-
ments? Partly, I imagine, because of the hundreds of years of stigma and dis-
crimination against people with mental illness or addictions that we have
inherited from our predecessors that unwittingly lead us to treat people as
something other than human beings. It is for this reason that we seldom speak
of people “battling” their mental illness the way we would ordinarily talk of
someone battling cancer. More importantly, though, is the equally formida-
ble fact that we do not yet really know that much about the nature of psy-
chiatric or substance use disorders beyond the boundaries of our inherited,
stigmatized view.
To illustrate this point, let’s return to the example of hearing voices when no
one else is around; considered a classic symptom of psychosis. What does it
And this is not only true of hallucinations. We have yet to discover, in fact,
any specific sign or symptom of schizophrenia that is found in every case of
schizophrenia and in no other illness or condition. Everything people with
schizophrenia experience can also be experienced by people who do not have
schizophrenia, and yet we are convinced that schizophrenia represents a fam-
ily of illnesses that affect one out of every one hundred people regardless of
nationality, race, culture, social class, ethnicity, etc. (DHHS, 1999). It also rep-
resents a condition that can be tremendously debilitating, but yet one from
which many people can still recover (Davidson & McGlashan, 1997). There
is, quite simply, a lot we do not yet know about serious mental illness.
policy and practice (e.g., Davidson, Stayner, Lambert, Smith & Sledge, 1997).
It also has enabled us to embed phenomenological inquiry within the con-
text of a variety of more quantitative research designs that at first may seem
foreign, if not antagonistic, to such pursuits. The contribution to this issue
led by Staeheli offers one example of the kind of crucial, yet often overlooked,
information that can be gleaned from adding a narrative, phenomenological
component to a traditional randomized clinical trial. Finally, exploring the
contributions phenomenological inquiry can make within applied contexts
such as clinical practice and public sector mental health policy has brought
us into collaboration with like-minded investigators from other countries,
including Australia, France, Italy, Norway, Sweden, and the United Kingdom.
The contribution to this issue from Stanghellini, for example, represents com-
patible work being conducted in Italy on the early phase of the treatment
enterprise: the psychiatric interview.
References
Mental Health: A Report of the Surgeon General. (1999). Rockville, MD: U.S. Department
of Health and Human Services, Substance Abuse and Mental Health Services
Administration, Center for Mental Health Services, and National Institutes of Health,
National Institute of Mental Health.
Bordo, S. (1993). Unbearable weight: Feminism, Western culture, and the body: (1993). x,
361 pp. Lexington, KT: University of Kentucky Press.
Butler, J. (1993). Bodies that matter: On the discursive limits of ‘sex’. New York, NY:
Routledge Press.
Davidson, L., & Cosgrove, L.A. (1991). Psychologism and phenomenological psycho-
logy revisited: I. The liberation from naturalism. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology,
22(2), 87-108.
Davidson, L., Stayner, D.A., Lambert, S., Smith, P., & Sledge, W.H. (1997). Phenomeno-
logical and participatory research on schizophrenia: Recovering the person in the-
ory and practice. Journal of Social Issues, 53(4), 767-784.
Davidson, L., & McGlashan, T.H. (1997). The varied outcomes of schizophrenia.
Canadian Journal of Psychiatry Revue Canadienne de Psychiatrie, 42(1), 34-43.
Davidson, L., O'Connell, M., Tondora, J., Staeheli, M., & Evans, A. (submitted). Recovery
in Serious Mental Illness: Paradigm shift or shibboleth?
Davidson, L., Staeheli, M., Stayner, D., & Sells, D. (2004). Language, Suffering, and
the Question of Immanence: Toward a Respectful Phenomenological Psychopathology.
Journal of Phenomenological Psychology, 35(2).
Deegan, P.E. (1993). Recovering our sense of value after being labeled. Journal of
Psychosocial Nursing, 31(4), 7-11.
Deleuze, G., & Guattari. (1983). The Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and schizophrenia.
Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Hepworth, J., & Griffin, C. (1995). Conflicting opinions? ‘Anorexia nervosa,’ medicine
and feminism. In Wilkinson, Sue (Ed.); Kitzinger, Celia (Ed.), Feminism and dis-
course: Psychological perspectives. Gender and psychology: Feminist and critical perspec-
tives. (pp. 68-85). ix, 193 pp. Adelaide, Australia: University of South Australia Center
for Cultural Studies.
Husserl, E. (1970). Logical investigations (J.N. Findlay, Trans. 1 ed.). New Jersey:
Humanities Press.
Laing, R.D. (1959). The Divided Self: An existential study in sanity and madness. New
York, NY: Penguin Books.
Laing, R.D. (1961). Self and others. New York, NY: Penguin Books.
Malson, H. (1998). The thin woman: Feminism, post-structuralism and the social psychol-
ogy of anorexia. London: Routledge Press.
Masson, J.M. (1984). Freud: The assault on truth. London: Faber and Faber.
Roustang, F. (1980). Psychoanalysis never lets go (N. Lukacher, Trans.). Baltimore, MD:
Johns Hopkins University Press.
Roustang, F. (1976). Dire mastery: Discipleship from Freud to Lacan (N. Lukacher, Trans.).
Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Turkle, S. (1978). Psychoanalytic politics: Freud's French revolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Weber, S. (1982). The legend of Freud. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.