Causal Necessity and The Ontological Argument
Causal Necessity and The Ontological Argument
Causal Necessity and The Ontological Argument
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to Religious Studies
JAMES M. HUMBER
Professor of Philosophy, Georgia State University
'What may properly be meant then, by the statement that God is, or has, necessa
as distinguished from contingent being is that God is, without beginning or e
and without original cause, or ground of any kind whatsoever."
'The necessary existence of an object, x, is defined as the existence of x with
beginning or end and without dependence upon anything other than itself.'2
'As applied to things or events, "contingent" will mean "dependent" or "cause
one thing or event being contingent upon another, "necessary" will mean "
dependent upon any other ... ." '3
'. . . is conceived as capable of existing in all possible worlds (i.e., the concept
is capable of being instantiated in all possible worlds). And to say this is to say th
He could exist necessarily (God could be necessarily instantiated). Is not a be
who could exist necessarily, in the sense of in all possible worlds, a being who coul
be logically necessary?. . . and ... a being who could be logically necessary (a concep
that could be necessarily instantiated) is logically necessary (is necessar
instantiated).'7
one possible world in which it need not be exercised (and there is noth
the definition of God as eternally self-caused which would precl
possibility), then God could not exist in that world. And if there
possible world in which God could not exist, his existence cannot be lo
necessary.'
I I
If our analysis thus far is correct, Nasser cannot have demonstrated God's
existence a priori. Now though valuable, knowledge of this sort does not
carry us very far, for it is extremely specific and almost wholly negative in
nature. At the same time, our study is not complete, for if I am not mistaken,
continuation of our analysis will lead to conclusions of much greater import.
First, in explaining why Nasser erred, we shall be driven to reject the Hick
Penelhum definition of 'physically necessary being'. Further, once the
reasons for this rejection are made known, we shall have the foundation we
need in order to provide a proper analysis of that concept. Given this
knowledge, then, we shall be in a position to argue that if Kant and Frege
are correct in their criticisms of the ontological argument, no version of
that proof can hope for success.
In attacking those forms of the ontological argument which define God
as a necessary being, both Hick and Peneihum insist upon distinguishing
between physical and logical necessity. Now as we have seen, the concept
of physical necessity makes sense only if it is equated with causal necessity.
Hence, when Hick and Penelhum claim that a physically necessary being's
existence is a contingent matter of fact, they must mean that it is an effect
contingent upon the actualisation of some cause. So much is clear. But
does this not show that their 'physically necessary' being is an entity which
is not at all necessary? What, after all, are the critics denying when they
hold that the question of God's existence can be settled only by some empirical
inquiry? Obviously they are denying that God must be conceived as existing
in all possible worlds. But this is true only because they are also denying
that there is anything in the definition of God which forces us to conclude
that he must exist in our world. That is, what the critics are really saying
is that if God were found to be eternally self-caused in our world, then he
would have to exist here. But whether or not an eternally self-caused being
exists in our world is an open question. Consequently, God cannot be
known to be logically necessary (existent in all possible worlds) because he
1 It should be clear that Nasser cannot claim that God's power of self-existence could be exercised
in all possible worlds and that, as a result, God still could exist (must exist) in all such realms. An
argument of this sort is ruled out by the fact that if this reasoning were accepted, God's power of
self-causation would have to be itself either: (A) eternally uncaused, or (B) eternally self-caused.
If (A) is accetped, the power can no more exist than an eternally non-dependent being can. Given
(B), however, the power is contingent and could not exist in that possible world in which its cause
was absent.
III
paradigm, for instance, the weight and pressure of the air explains why i
must have the power to crush; the shape, and material out of which the
container is made explain its capacity to be crushed, etc. Given this kind o
analysis, then, one can make sense of the statement 'container x must
collapse when it has no air inside'. If a change in the course of nature wer
to occur and the atmosphere's power to crush or the container's capacity
to collapse disappear, the loss of power and/or capacity could be explaine
only in terms of some change in the natures of the p's involved. But if on
or more of the p's changed in its nature, we would not have the conjunction
of C (air, container, plus vacuum) and r E, but 'C' (non-air, or non
container, plus vacuum) and ,E. Needless to say, that ' "C". -' E' i
always logically possible, in no way demonstrates that 'C. E' is self
consistent.'
Hume's error was that he thought ' "C". r E is never self-contradictory'
entails 'C. E is never self-contradictory'. Or to put it another way, he
continually confused two senses of necessity. An expression is logically
necessary if it holds true in all possible worlds. In this sense, of course, the
statement 'container x collapses when it has no air inside' cannot be neces
sarily true, for there are possible worlds in which the p's involved could have
natures quite unlike those they now possess. But the fact that this must be
admitted does nothing to alter the conclusion that, given the present natures
of the p's of this world, it is physically necessary that container x collapse
when the air is pumped from its interior.
Accepting Madden's analysis, it is an easy matter to explain why Hick
and Penelhum failed to capture any sense of necessity in their definition of
'physically necessary being'. Simply put, their definition as 'eternally self
caused' presupposes that it is God's own power of self-causation which
physically necessitates his existence. But unless it can be shown why this
power must be actualised in this world, God's existence cannot be known to
be physically necessary. Now how could one go about showing that the
power must be actualised ? Clearly there is only one way, namely, by showing
that there is a real (i.e. existent) nature which has the character of being
eternal and independent of all others. But if this is so, 'physically necessary
being' means 'existent being, eternally independent of all others'. And this
insight is of extreme importance, for once it is understood the monogenetic
character of the ontological argument can be demonstrated.
First, there are only two ways in which one could go about showing
that God is a physically necessary being: he could try to do it in an a priori
manner, or via aposteriori means. For those, like Nasser, who seek to establish
God's existence a priori, the latter alternative is ruled out. If one chooses the
former course of action, however, his procedure must be illegitimate, for if
1 I have been extremely liberal in my statement of selected aspects of Madden's theory. I trust,
however, that his intent is fairly represented.