A Just Price
A Just Price
A Just Price
0
By Paul Mueller
F ew economists today ask whether prices are just. This is due in part
to positivism and efforts to remain “value-neutral,” but ultimately,
economists no longer discuss just prices because advances in economic
thinking make such reasoning intractable or irrelevant. For most folks,
however, concerns about just prices still matter—especially regarding
housing and medical prices, which many think unjustly high, and labor
prices that many think unjustly low.
This essay explores the historic debate about what makes prices just
and why economists by and large no longer ask that question. To be
sure, much has been written on this topic over thousands of years. Here
we simply highlight a few of the most important contributions to just
price theory; those of Aristotle and Aquinas, the Spanish Scholastics of
Salamanca, John Locke, and Etienne Condillac.
Aristotle (4th century B. C.)
An example may illustrate why one art is just and the other is unjust for
Aristotle. Suppose you own an olive grove. Your land produces more
than enough olives for you and your family to eat. But you lack grain for
making bread. The art of acquisition involves trading your olives for
grain. Aristotle understands that direct exchange (barter) might be
difficult, and so you may sell your olives for money and then use that
money to buy grain. This accomplishes the same end, exchanging your
surplus olives for grain, more easily.
So things stand in the 13th century. But by the 16th and 17th centuries,
many scholars and philosophers began to challenge the Aristotelian-
Thomist account of just prices and just exchange. Their later
observations on value as well as the importance of market forces—
supply, demand, money, etc.—are much closer to the modern economic
way of thinking.
Spanish Scholastics (16th & 17th centuries AD)
• The value of an article does not depend on its essential nature but on
the estimation of men, even if that estimation be foolish. Thus, in the
Indies wheat is dearer than in Spain because men esteem it more highly,
though the nature of the wheat is the same in both places. (Grice-
Hutchinson, 115).
Luis Saravia de la Calle has an even more penetrating critique of the just
price reasoning we have seen:
• Those who measure the just price by the labor, costs, and risk incurred
by the person who deals in the merchandise or produces it, or by the
cost of transport or the expense of traveling… or by what he has to pay
the factors for their industry, risk, and labor, are greatly in error, and
still more so are those who allow a certain profit of a fifth or a tenth.
For the just price arises from the abundance or scarcity of goods,
merchants, and money… and not from costs, labor, and risk. If we
had to consider labor and risk in order to assess the just price, no
merchant would ever suffer loss, nor would abundance or scarcity of
goods and money enter into the question. Prices are not commonly
fixed on the basis of costs. Why should a bale of linen brought overland
from Brittany at great expense be worth more than one which is
transported cheaply by sea?… Why should a book written out by hand
be worth more than one which is printed, when the latter is better
though it costs less to produce?… The just price is found not by counting
the cost but by the common estimation. (Grice-Hutichinson, 110-111,
emphasis added).
Covarrubias and Saravia, along with Luis de Molina and Martin Navarro
argued that the “common estimation” of market participants
represented the just price. Another Spanish Scholastic, Domingo de
Soto, observed in De Justitia et Jure that if the cost of production
determined value, then producers would have no incentive to provide
goods more cheaply and efficiently because they could justly charge
high prices based upon their costs:
But what if there are not many buyers and sellers around? Locke says:
• But what anyone has he may value at what rate he will, and transgress
not against justice if he sells it at any price, provided he makes no
distinction of buyers, but parts with it as cheap to this as he would to
any other buyer. I say he transgresses not against justice. What he may
do against charity is another case. [emphasis added] (Locke, Wootton,
444)
“Locke asserts, against the conventional wisdom of the day, that it is not strictly a
matter of justice what price a seller sets for the buyer….”
Locke asserts, against the conventional wisdom of the day, that it is not
strictly a matter of justice what price a seller sets for the buyer, even if
the buyer is in dire need of the good but of charity, mercy, or
benevolence. In short, the market price, or as he calls it the “marchand
value,” of a good as opposed to the “natural value” determined by labor,
is always the just price. If there is no market to tell the seller what the
price ought to be, he may set his own so long as that price does not
change from one buyer to the next.
Imagine a man, says Locke, who has a horse but is reluctant to sell it to
a traveler. Upon insistence from the latter, the man sets the price at 40
pounds, which happens to be double what the horse would fetch at the
nearest market. Since the traveler’s need for the horse was less than 40
pounds, he refuses to pay this price. But the next day, a breathless
traveler approaches the same man and begs for the horse because he
stands to lose his business “of much greater consequence” to him.
Knowing the circumstances and willingness to pay of the traveler, the
man sells him the horse for 50 pounds. Locke says this is unjust.
Because the man was willing to part with the same horse for 40 pounds
before, charging 50 pounds now because of the buyer’s circumstances
involves exploitation.
Etienne Condillac (18th century AD)
• Value is not so much in the object as in how we esteem it, and this
estimation is relative to our needs: it grows and diminishes, just as our
need itself grows and diminishes…I say therefore that, even on the
banks of a river, water has value, but the smallest possible, because
there it is infinitely surplus to our needs. In an arid place, by contrast, it
has a huge value, which one assesses according to how far away it is and
the difficulty of getting hold of it. In such a case a thirsty traveler would
give a hundred louis for a glass of water, and that glass of water would
be worth a hundred louis.” (Condillac, Eltis, 192; emphasis added)
We must have valued our olives at less than $20; otherwise we wouldn’t
have sold them. Since we had such an excess of olives, we might have
valued that bushel of olives at $2. If that’s the case, we gained $18 in
value by selling it for $20. Furthermore, we must have valued the grain
more than the $20 we paid for it—let’s say at $28. We gained an
additional $8. Taken altogether, we have gone from having a bushel of
olives we valued at $2 to grain that we valued at $28. Money was only
an intermediate step along the way—it didn’t say anything substantive
about the intrinsic value of the goods involved or how much we gained.
On the other side of the exchange, let’s say the initial owner of the grain
valued it at $15. Selling it for $20 results in a gain of $5. Suppose further
that he values the olives at $24. Buying them at $20 would give him an
additional $4 of benefit. All told, he goes from having grain he values at
$15 to olives he values at $24—a gain of $9.
For more on these topics, see the EconTalk episode Michael Munger on John Locke, Prices, and Hurricane
Sandy and the Econlib article “The Relentless Subjectivity of Value,” by Max Borders, May 3, 2010.
The conclusion to draw here, which also holds true in discussions about
usury, luxury, or price gouging laws, is that neither justice, nor virtue,
nor vice exist in the objects. It exists in the actions and motives of the
people involved. There is no objective economic value, no inherent
quality of a good that we could use as a standard to assess whether the
price it commands on the market is just or unjust. There are of course
objective standards by which we could judge the behavior and motives
of the parties involved—but those standards fall outside the economic
toolbox and into the realm of ethics and philosophy, of norms and
customs. By the end of the just price debate, economics had emerged as
a distinct way of thinking and a proper science with its own application
and scope, leaving its mother philosophy to ask the broader question of
what constitutes just and unjust behavior in the market.
References
Grice-Hutchinson, Marjorie. (1952). The School of Salamanca; Readings
in Spanish Monetary Theory 1544-1605. Oxford University Press:
London.